Book Reviews KIVY, PETER. The Possessor and the Possessed: Handel, Mozart, Beethoven, and the Idea of Musical Genius. Yale University Press, 2001, xiv + 287 pp., 9 b&w illus., $35.00 cloth. Peter Kivy is a philosophical raconteur. As well as analyses and arguments, his books contain narratives that aim to create a unifying framework. Because he writes elegantly and intelligently, Kivy’s stories are always engaging and interesting. The Possessor and the Possessed is no exception. The book is in two parts. On my view, it would have been better had they been inverted. In the second, Kivy provides an account of the genius composer: he or she is disposed to create works of the highest caliber. This requires a musically fecund imagination and the talent, concentration, and motivation to get the most of the musical ideas he or she comes up with. One theory of genius, deriving from Plato, provides a metaphor for the role of the creative imagination: the genius is possessed by the muses and is a passive conduit for the transmission of their ideas. A second theory, dating from a first-century book on the sublime, misattributed to Longinus, emphasizes instead the centrality of the genius’s talent. The genius is a naturally gifted individual who is active and in control of what he or she creates. According to Kivy, the first view is needed to account for “one off” masterpieces; cases in which an artist produces a single tour de force for which there is no precedent in their oeuvre. The second is required to accommodate those singular individuals, such as Beethoven, who repeatedly and consistently produce masterworks. As this makes clear, Kivy regards the concept of genius as possessing content and explanatory power. He resists attempts to deconstruct or dismiss it. It is not reducible merely to a socially fabricated reputation, as has been argued by Tia DeNora. (Kivy’s pen must have slipped when he wrote, “For what is important to us is . . . what was taken for truth by those who were in the process of constructing the concept of musical genius” [p. 38].) Also, because women are no less capable than men of genius when given the same opportunities, the absence of women from the canon shows the extent to which they have been discriminated against, not that the notion of genius should be dismissed as a tool of masculinist bias, as has been recommended by Christine Battersby. Meanwhile, psychoanalytic explanations cannot account for the rarity of genius, because they deal with widely shared experiences, and the portrayal of Mozart in Peter Shaffer’s Amadeus, by implying that the genius need never labor, study, or practice in perfecting his art, so that genius might be one hundred percent inspiration and zero percent perspiration, represents an unrealizable extreme. I found much to enjoy in these later chapters, but it is in the first part of the book that Kivy sets up and develops his narrative. According to it, there has been an alternation over time between the two models of genius outlined above. Handel was a genius in the Longinian mold. Mozart’s genius was characterized by the Platonic view. With Beethoven, the Longinian model again became dominant and remained so for more than one hundred years. Only under the influence of Shaffer’s recent portrayal of Mozart has the Platonic picture of genius reasserted itself. Although there were geniuses before Handel, Handel was the first composer who could be recognized by his contemporaries as such, because it was only in the eighteenth century that the composer qualified as an artist (as opposed to a mere craftsperson) and that philosophers developed the theory of artistic genius. Indeed, it is part of Kivy’s thesis that philosophical developments played a key role in each swing of the pendulum between the two conceptions of genius. Addison, Burke, and Young laid the philosophical ground for Handel’s elevation to the status of genius. They built on the Longinian model, by variously emphasizing the importance of natural talent and originality, by associating genius with the sublime, and by suggesting not only that geniuses break the rules but also that this is a virtue and not a fault in what they produce. In his 1760 biography of Handel, Mainwaring describes the composer in a fashion that accords with this picture. For instance, he interprets The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 61:1 Winter 2003 74 the musical ability displayed by Handel in his childhood as evidence of his natural talent, and he intimates that what some regarded as defects in the music are in fact strengths. Schopenhauer favors the Platonic view of genius. To the idea that genius is associated with madness, loss of ego, and the appearance of possession (as a result of the absence of “common sense,” not godly visitation), he adds the image of the genius as perpetual child, citing Mozart as an example. Mozart’s early biographers, such as Niemetschek (1798), stress the achievements of his childhood years and describe the adult as game loving, naively affectionate, impractical, and distracted. When Schopenhauer argued for the elevation of music above all the arts and set out his account of genius (1819), Mozart was the inevitable paradigm. The account of genius provided by Kant in his Critique of Judgment (1790) is Longinian, except that he connects it to the creation of the beautiful rather than the sublime. Kant’s major contribution to this view was an argument to show that genius cannot be constrained by rules: since the beautiful is without concept, the production of beauty is not susceptible to methodization, so the producer must be original. The genius, he says, gives the rule to art; that is, it is only after the fact of creation that scholars can derive from masterpieces rules or principles that then can become guides for lesser artists. Meanwhile, Beethoven is described by his contemporaries as oblivious to his surroundings, as heroic, and as a political and social rebel. It is the account they offer of the music—as grand, sublime, and terrifying—that reveals these personal traits as illustrating the Longinian view. Above all, Beethoven is identified as someone who must overturn musical conventions. Kivy repeatedly insists that he is interested in the myth, not facts, and he uses as evidence for the predominance of one or the other model some accounts known to be false of the composers they purport to describe. That may be acceptable, given his purposes. But there are two kinds of facts he cannot afford to ignore, and I have reservations for both as regards his discussion of Mozart. In the first instance, Kivy must be correct in his description of the contemporary view as inclining to one or other theory of genius. As he frequently acknowledges in the discussion of Beethoven and subsequently, many descriptions of behavior could be consistent with either model. Childhood skill is as likely to be evidence of natural talent as of divine inspiration; distractedness in ordinary conduct is as liable to indicate intense concentration on other, musical matters as to show the madness of possession. It seems to me that much of what is cited by Kivy from Mozart’s contemporaries is neutral between the Longinian and Platonic views and that Kivy exaggerates the extent to which Mozart the composer was seen The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism as “a perpetual child.” Moreover, just as Beethoven was described by some of his contemporaries as possessed by divine inspiration, Mozart was described also as possessing prodigious natural talent and as authoring powerful, grand music. Second, Kivy must respect the facts of musical genius as such, since he argues for the concept’s reality. And recall that it is their genius as composers, not performers, in terms of which Kivy is supposed to discuss Handel, Mozart, and Beethoven. My view is that Mozart did not begin producing masterpieces of the highest caliber until adulthood, and he did not do so consistently before the age of twenty-five, with works (in the K. 360s) such as Idomeneo and the Sinfonia Concertante for Violin and Viola. Had he died at twenty, he would have been rated, qua composer, as a largely unfulfilled genius. Mozart’s contemporaries (and Kivy) focus more on the child who was a prodigy as a performer. Where composition is mentioned in this connection, it is not because the childhood works are masterpieces but because it is extraordinary that anyone could write music of such technical competence—that is, in accord with the rules—at such an early age. No one who concentrates on Mozart as a composer is likely to see him as childlike or as displaying more effortless facility than other composers of the time. Those of his contemporaries who knew how he worked did not. Recall Kivy’s claim that the Platonic model of genius best fits the composer who seems to transcend the limits of their own basic talent by producing a single masterpiece. That composer, obviously, is not Mozart. Kivy allows that Haydn and Bach do not clearly fit either of his models of genius. It seems to me the same is true of Mozart. I think Kivy’s two models of genius are complementary, not competing. The Platonic view addresses the fact that geniuses get wonderful ideas seemingly from thin air and the Longinian model explains that they need to shape, explore, and develop those ideas in producing an artwork of quality. A composer who comes up with only banal ideas will not write a masterpiece and neither will one who is unable to tame, make the most of, and satisfactorily integrate the good ideas she has. Kivy’s models stress the two different aspects of creation where both are essential to the composition of masterworks. STEPHEN DAVIES Department of Philosophy University of Auckland PILLOW, KIRK. Sublime Understanding: Aesthetic Reflection in Kant and Hegel. MIT Press, 2000, vi + 377 pp., $37.95 cloth. Kirk Pillow’s Sublime Understanding: Aesthetic Reflection in Kant and Hegel accentuates Kant’s aesthetics of Book Reviews sublimity for the purposes of developing a wellknown insight into the nature of interpretation, namely, that it tends to be open-ended and nonrigidlystructured. The book’s originality resides in its use of Kant’s aesthetic judgments of the sublime as a model for interpretation in general. With this innovative extrapolation, Pillow shows how Kant’s theory of the sublime can fit in well with contemporary hermeneutics and postmodern sensibilities. Overall, the study is coherently organized and consistently well-written, moving from Kant’s aesthetics, to Hegel’s aesthetics, and finally to contemporary theories of metaphor and interpretation. The enjoyable book is grounded upon a controversial and disadvantageous assumption, though, which I will articulate and criticize below. The first section of Sublime Understanding focuses upon Kant’s theory of reflective judgment with a view toward highlighting the nature of judgments of the sublime. Here, the particular formulation of Kant’s distinction between “reflective” [reflectirend] and “determinative” [bestimmend] judgment is foundational. According to Pillow, reflective judgment “seeks out a purposive unity—the appearance of intentional organization—among the diversity of presentations, or features of objects or situations, upon which it reflects” (p. 18). In contrast, determinative judgment arises when “a concept or universal . . . is available to judgment, and judgment need only subsume a particular under it” (p. 19). For Kant, when one judges reflectively, one starts with an individual and seeks a concept in terms of which the individual can be understood, and when one judges determinately, one starts with a concept and seeks an individual to which the concept can be applied. Kant famously claims that all aesthetic judgments are reflective and, thus, are fundamentally searching. Pillow emphasizes that in reflective aesthetic judgment the “search for purposive unity among a diversity of parts” (p. 31)—a search that, most importantly, has no determinate conclusion in cases of beauty and sublimity—is the key to understanding the significance of judgments of sublimity as they bear on interpretation in general. For when we likewise interpret a work of art, there is (as many have argued) a search for meaning accompanied by an inexhaustibility and endlessness to the enterprise. Later in the book, Pillow cites Stephen David Ross’s theory of interpretation as “inexhaustibility by contrast” and Nelson Goodman’s “ways of worldmaking” to illustrate the hermeneutic vision he has in mind. Within this context, Pillow makes inventive and highly perceptive use of Kant. His interpretation becomes extreme when he distinguishes rigidly between the form-focused (formalist) and meaningfocused (interpretive) aesthetic spheres, and associates Kant’s theory of beauty exclusively with the 75 former, Kant’s theory of sublimity exclusively with the latter. Supposedly, Kantian beauty is only about formal unity of an indeterminate sort, and Kantian sublimity is only about semantic unity of an indeterminate sort. With this separation of the waters, Pillow offers an “alternative solution to the long-standing debate in the literature concerning the respective roles of ‘form’ and ‘expression’ in Kant’s aesthetics” (p. 88). His solution is an eye-opener, given how often Kant refers to beauty (and not sublimity) in connection with meaning-exuding “aesthetic ideas” in the later sections of the Critique of Judgment. Kant states, “We may describe beauty in general (whether natural or artificial) as the expression of aesthetic ideas” (Critique of Judgment, §51). He also claims that aesthetic ideas enliven (beleben) the cognitive faculties (Critique of Judgment, §49). Pillow notes Kant’s claim that beauty is the expression of aesthetic ideas, but he chooses radically to reconstruct Kant’s view in a way that disintegrates the intriguing fusion (or remove the confusion) of beauty and sublimity that pervades Kant’s characterization of aesthetic ideas. Pillow consequently associates aesthetic ideas exclusively with sublimity. With this, he grounds upon Kant’s theory of aesthetic ideas an account of what he calls “sublime understanding.” This is a kind of indeterminate “understanding” (i.e., it is not “understanding” in Kant’s technical sense) that remains illuminating, just as an effective and ingenious metaphorical coinage is illuminating. Aesthetic ideas are associated with metaphor, and via the concept of metaphor, Pillow links Kant’s theory of aesthetic ideas with those contemporary theories of interpretation that emphasize metaphorical thought. These connections are apt and well traced in the third part of the book. The intermediary section of Sublime Understanding focuses on Hegel’s discussion of imaginative styles (viz., Einbildungskraft and Phantasie), and on his triad of “symbolic,” “classic,” and “romantic” art. The classical-art center of Hegel’s aesthetics is mostly bypassed, however, because the expository goal is to emphasize how the symbolic and romantic forms of art illustrate the account of reflective judgments of the sublime to be found in Kant. The purpose of introducing Hegel is to add detail to the structure of the Kantian aesthetic ideas. Hegel is useful here, for during the course of his encyclopedic hierarchicalization and systematization of almost everything significant that he can identify, Hegel mentions various styles of imagination and association that can be used to help specify how our “webs of meaning” are structured. As a pendant to the discussion of Hegel, a brief survey of some antecedent British empiricist associationist thinkers reveals how imagination and wit play a crucial role in constructing our interpretations. 76 This discussion, along with that of Hegel’s views on imagination, is positively contributory as a matter of scholarship because it opens up an area that tends to be neglected in most accounts of Hegel’s aesthetics, namely, Hegel’s views on the mental processes involved in artistic creation. Just as one can refer to Hegel’s Logic as a way to understand Hegel’s theory of aesthetic judgment, Pillow helpfully directs us to Hegel’s Encyclopedia as a way to understand Hegel’s rarely thematized theory of artistic creativity. At various points throughout the book, aesthetic ideas are described as “shared webs of meaning,” as “networked meanings,” as “shared connectivity,” as “world-making webs of meaning,” as “meaninggiving webs of relation-building,” as “indeterminate webs of shared meaning,” as “sense-making network[s],” as “localized patterns of intelligibility,” as “fields of shared connection,” as “relational affinities,” as “shared field[s] of social meanings,” as “network[s] of affinities,” as “web[s] of interrelation,” as “networks of indeterminate unity,” as “visions of intelligibility,” and as “’unifying’ set[s] of relations.” The array of locutions is impressionistically impressive, but they largely remain as uniformly indeterminate as the phrase “unity amidst diversity.” In any case, these “webs” are strictly opposed to systems of classification of a determinate sort, as one might find in a system of biological taxonomy. This is the basic contrast Pillow wishes to draw—he distinguishes between determinate and indeterminate structures of meaning— and his book valuably emphasizes how indeterminate and open-ended meaning-formation plays a role in our conscious life and being in the world. With respect to the scholarly interpretation of Kant, Pillow identifies “determinative” judgment (viz., when one starts with a concept and seeks an object to which it can be applied) with “logical” (or “cognitive”) judgment (viz., when a determinate concept and an individual are brought together to judge “S is P”), and collapses the two kinds of judgment into one. Taxonomically, it can nonetheless be argued that the generic distinction is between determinative and reflective judgment, and that the more specific distinction is between logical and aesthetic judgment, because Kant’s definitions of reflective judgment comprehensively include those cases where an individual is given and a concept is sought and not found (reflective aesthetic judgment), and those cases where an individual is given and a concept is sought and found (reflective logical judgment). Pillow’s identification of “determinative” and “logical” judgment is based on a subtle assumption regarding the phenomenology of logical awareness, which is that whenever “subsumption” of an individual under a determinate concept occurs, the concept must first be thought about before the individual to which it applies is thought about. Every judgment The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism involving “subsumption” is thus considered to be determinative (pp. 25, 31). But Kant says that in certain cases, “reflective judgment must subsume [subsumiren] under a law which is not yet given” [Kant’s italics in original] (Critique of Judgment, §69). He also states that reflective judgment “makes concepts possible” and that concepts “result” (or are “attained,” or “reached,” or are “gained” [erlangen]) by it (First Introduction to the Critique of Judgment, §5). If we accept these statements, then reflective judgment can include among its processes determinate concept formation in addition to subsumption under determinate concepts. The mere presence of a determinate concept in a judgment does not render the judgment “determinative,” in other words. This is not a point of technical insignificance, because Pillow’s nonacknowledgement of reflective logical judgment leads him to deemphasize most of the discussions in Kant’s aesthetics that involve the association of beauty with determinately meaningful content, such as Kant’s account of dependent beauty and his account of the ideal of beauty. In other words, the book’s one-sided definition of reflective judgment generates a historically misleading submergence of the neoclassical content in the presentations of both Kant’s and Hegel’s aesthetics in order to elevate postmodern indeterminacy of meaning. Moreover, owing to the markdown of logical judgment, the hermeneutical role of reflective judgment is reduced to the single-minded enterprise of constructing “webs of meaning” that lack an overridingly determinate structure. There is, admittedly, an open-endedness in the meaning-constructs involved in interpretation, but reflective judgment, as reflective logical judgment, helps to construct determinate concepts that can provide a strong measure of stability to interpretations. This, too, is part of our “making sense” of works of art and our general activity of world-making. Pillow’s own quote from Nelson Goodman confirms this important role of reflective logical judgment. As can be readily seen, Goodman’s words carry a definitively taxonomic and logical air that is foreign to the hermeneutics of sublime understanding: Much but by no means all worldmaking consists of taking apart and putting together, often conjointedly: on the one hand, of dividing wholes into parts and partitioning kinds into subspecies, analyzing complexes into component features, drawing distinctions; on the other hand, of composing wholes and kinds out of parts and members and subclasses, combining features into subclasses, and making connections. (pp. 305–306) Sublime Understanding: Aesthetic Reflection in Kant and Hegel is in many ways a fine book. The intellectually fruitful emphasis upon judgments of the sublime might have been grounded, though, upon a wider characterization of reflective judgment. Had this Book Reviews been done, it might not have been necessary to set aside the distinctive neoclassical features of Kant’s and Hegel’s aesthetics proper. Also, a more complicated and realistic account of reflective thought processes as they operate in interpretation—an account that includes both aesthetic and logical forms of judgment and that does not so easily and fashionably grant hermeneutical hegemony to metaphorical thought—might have been consequently articulated. ROBERT WICKS Department of Philosophy The University of Auckland IRWIN, WILLIAM. Intentionalist Interpretation: A Philosophical Explanation and Defense. Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1999, 152 pp., $62.95 cloth. The intentionalist view of interpretation holds that the proper aim of a text’s interpreter is to discover the meaning its author intended, since a text just means what its author meant by it. Examples such as malapropism, where the text seems to mean something other than what the speaker meant, have made strict intentionalism unattractive; even E. D. Hirsch Jr., among the most steadfast intentionalists, came to hold that linguistic convention plays an independent role in fixing textual meaning. But with Intentionalist Interpretation, William Irwin aims to show why Hirsch was wrong to abandon strict intentionalism and offer a supplement to restore its viability. On my view, Irwin’s defense of intentionalism is unsuccessful, but this book remains a useful philosophical resource. Written in a clear and engaging style, the text unites several discussions relevant to its thesis: The distinction between normative and descriptive approaches to interpretation (Chapter 1); Michel Foucault’s and Roland Barthes’s rejection of the author, and Jorge Gracia’s and Alexander Nehamas’s proposals to redeem author-based interpretation (Chapter 2); the debate over intentionalism between Hirsch and Monroe Beardsley (Chapter 3, where Irwin defends his own view); Hans-Georg Gadamer’s views regarding the hermeneutic circle and the fusion of horizons (Chapter 4); and contemporary approaches to legal interpretation (Chapter 5, where Irwin argues that intentionalism is appropriate to all kinds of texts). Most of these topics are treated rather briefly, but the book provides a helpful survey of the relevant terrain. Irwin’s recent anthology, The Death and Resurrection of the Author? (Greenwood Press, 2002), collects many of the relevant texts and might serve as a companion to the present volume. I will focus on Irwin’s defense of his own view, urinterpretation, an extension of Hirsch’s intentional- 77 ism. Hirsch originally held that “meaning is an affair of consciousness and not of physical signs or things” (Validity in Interpretation, Yale University Press, 1969, p. 23) and, thus, denied that texts, in themselves, could bear meaning. The question, then, was whose consciousness determines a text’s meaning: the reader’s or the author’s? Hirsch chose the latter, for reasons to be discussed below. Eventually, he softened his stance to allow that linguistic conventions limit the meanings an author can intend. Irwin differs from Hirsch in two important respects: he resists Hirsch’s concession that convention restricts textual meaning, and he introduces an author construct, the urauthor, as an interpretative tool. Irwin is a strict intentionalist, since he holds that a text’s meaning is determined exclusively by its author’s intentions. “Meaning is . . . in the mind” (p. 57), and an author is free to intend any meaning whatever for a given text. Even if her meaning is unlikely to be conveyed successfully, the text means just what she means by it (pp. 57–58). Irwin’s defense of strict intentionalism stems from two Hirschian arguments. First, the interpreter’s ethical duty is to seek out the author’s intended meaning: to do otherwise is to use the text “merely as grist for one’s own mill” (Hirsch, The Aims of Interpretation, University of Chicago Press, 1976, p. 91) and, thus, treat the author as a means only, in the Kantian sense. The categorical imperative applies to texts, Hirsch says, “because speech is an extension and expression of men in the social domain” (Aims, p. 90). Perhaps Hirsch has more to say on the subject, but Irwin fails to show that Kant’s imperative leads to intentionalism. We sometimes punish an agent for effects produced as a result of her action, though contrary to her intention. Do we then fail to treat her as an end in herself? No: to hold someone responsible for effects foreseeable to, but not intended (and perhaps not foreseen) by, her is to take her seriously as a rational agent capable of evaluating courses of action and choosing appropriately. Why, then, should an interpreter consider only the meaning an author intended, rather than also, or instead, the meanings she should have expected her audience to understand from her text? Interpretation based on reasonable audience expectations may, in fact, conduce to seeing her as an end in herself, since it treats her as a rational communicator. The second argument for strict intentionalism is based on the view that a text cannot “speak for itself” (p. 47); to interpret, we must make certain defeasible assumptions about the author, such as that she is rational and uses language conventionally (p. 32). When these assumptions prove false, Irwin suggests, this shows “how reliant upon the author we actually are” (p. 32) and demonstrates that appeal to actual intentions is required. 78 But in Irwin’s own examples, the data we use to overturn such assumptions often seem to be found within the text. As an instance of unconventional word usage that requires intentionalist interpretation, Irwin offers E. E. Cummings’s concrete poem r-p-op-h-e-s-s-a-g-r, which ends: .gRrEaPsPhOs) to rea(be)rran(com)gi(e)ngly ,grasshopper; Irwin asserts that “the words mean what the author intended to communicate by them” (p. 57), even if the usage is unconventional. Tellingly, though, Irwin offers no explanation of what Cummings meant. The text is presented on its own, without appeal to the poet’s intentions. Other examples receive similar treatment. There is nothing distinctively intentionalist in Irwin’s approach to this case: as he acknowledges elsewhere, the anti-intentionalist can appeal to authorial intention “as long as it is inferred from the text itself” (p. 34). In a way, Irwin is right that interpreting Cummings’s poem requires looking beyond the text. We must appeal to facts about linguistic context and convention: the fact that “rea(be)rran(com)gi(e)ngly” is not a word, but “rearranging” and “become” are words; the fact that “gRrEaPsPhOs,” rearranged, becomes “grasshopper”; and facts about the conventional meanings of “rearranging,” “become,” “grasshopper,” and the suffix “-ly.” Irwin regards his approach as intentionalist because these facts are included in his author construct, the urauthor, which is “composed of relevant available biographical information, likely intentions, use of language in the text itself, information concerning the author’s context and audience, and other texts of the same author” (p. 61). The urauthor is required, Irwin points out, because of problems with the author’s availability: “We can never even hope to ‘have’ the real historical author. All we ever have is a more or less accurate version of him as related to his text” (p. 29). If I understand Irwin correctly, the urauthor is a tool to maximize our probability of ascertaining the author’s intentions (which, as mental states, are in principle inaccessible [pp. 49–50]), though we will never be sure we have succeeded in a given case. The information included in the urauthor seems likely to lead us toward the author’s intention. This does not mean, however, that all appeals to such information are intentionalist. Linguistic convention may be used to ascertain authorial intentions; but it might be used, instead, to fix textual meaning independent of the author’s mental states. When I appeal to the conventional meaning of “grasshopper,” I fix an aspect of the poem’s meaning: it is about grasshoppers and not, say, woodchucks. Irwin The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism would have us believe that whether “grasshopper” means “woodchuck” in Cummings’s poem depends entirely on some private mental state experienced by Cummings as he wrote the poem. If Cummings had woodchucks in mind—if, knowingly or unknowingly, he used “grasshopper” unconventionally to refer to woodchucks—then, on Irwin’s view, his poem is about woodchucks. Unlike Irwin, I hold the anti-intentionalist intuition that the text is not about woodchucks, even if Cummings knowingly used “grasshopper” to refer to woodchucks. (Had he given us some intratextual clues to his unconventional usage, that might be another matter.) But my point is not about intuitions. I mean only to show that linguistic convention need not be used to ascertain private authorial intentions. It may be used, instead, to determine textual meaning independently— and perhaps in contravention—of the author’s intention. If linguistic convention can do what Irwin needs it to do, namely, supply evidence of authorial intent, it can also do what the anti-intentionalist needs it to do: make texts into bearers of meaning. The same goes for the urauthor’s other features, including biography, information about audience, and so on. Why not take Irwin’s method further and say that these aspects of the urauthor fix textual meaning? This might yield a hypothetical intentionalist view, on which textual meaning is determined by the intentions of a hypothetical author with the urauthor’s characteristics (including rationality, to the extent compatible with other features). The real author’s private, epistemically inaccessible intentions would then be irrelevant. I find in Intentionalist Interpretation no compelling reason to accept that interpretation should be a chase after the unknowable, so I remain unconvinced by Irwin’s case for strict intentionalism. But if we read Irwin as a hypothetical intentionalist, his view succeeds at fixing textual meaning, and thereby secures its epistemic availability. An editorial note: The book contains many (usually minor) inaccuracies in direct quotations from other authors, along with occasional failures to note that a short passage is a direct quote (although citations are provided). SHERRI IRVIN Departments of Philosophy Princeton University and University of Ottawa CARLSON, ALLEN. Aesthetics and the Environment: The Appreciation of Nature, Art, and Architecture. New York: Routledge, 2000, xxi + 247 pp., 10 b&w illus., $90.00 cloth, $15.99 paper. This is unquestionably the most important book to have appeared in the burgeoning field of environmental Book Reviews aesthetics. Carefully argued and clearly expressed, broad in scope but patient with details, passionate without being romantic, it is an elegant demonstration of what philosophical analysis can achieve in regard to the appreciation of nature and its various aesthetic qualities. It sets the bar very high for all subsequent work in the field. As its subtitle indicates, the book deals with more than the aesthetics of nature. It also takes up a range of subjects that might be regarded as artifactual interventions in natural settings, such as works of architecture, landscape art, and agriculture. Carlson’s reflections on these latter topics are characteristically insightful and informative, but clearly subsidiary to the main thrust of the book, which is the development and defense of what he calls the “natural environmental model” of the appreciation of nature, a species of what he more generally styles “the objectivist approach.” This project takes up the first seven chapters out of fourteen. Eleven of the chapters have been previously published in journals or reference works; three of them first appeared in this journal. Of the three new chapters, two are designed chiefly to serve as overviews of the six chapters to follow (one introduces the theme of the appreciation of nature, the other presents the framework for thinking about a set of issues in which appreciation straddles the fence between nature and art). The third new chapter analyzes relations between understanding and aesthetic experience, addressing the questions of whether natural objects can be experienced aesthetically without (much, if any) knowledge about them, and whether knowledge, once had, can interfere with or even destroy the aesthetic experience of nature. Carlson’s objectivist natural aesthetics has been debated and defended for two decades now, and although there have been refinements and amendments from time to time, the general contours of his approach have remained intact. Briefly stated, these include the following ideas: (1) (With apologies to Bishop Butler) nature is what it is and not another thing; accordingly, any responsible form of appreciation of nature must take it for what it is rather than some other thing (for example, something we see it as a sign, reflection, or embodiment of); (2) Natural objects are connected to their matrix environments in “organic unity”; what they are is inseparable from the conditions of their creation and development; (3) Just as in the field of art, where certain aesthetic categories have been shown (most persuasively by Kendall Walton) to be requisite to our making of informed aesthetic judgments, so in the field of nature we need categories to marshal our judgments and ensure that what we appreciate is seen as what it really is and as organically unified with its environment; (4) The correct categories of nature are those provided by the natural sciences; (5) Thus, the appropriate aesthetic 79 appreciation of nature must proceed hand in hand with scientific knowledge about the natural environment; (6) Because art is created, while nature is discovered, “in science, unlike in art, creativity plays its major role in the determinations of categories and their correctness; and considerations of aesthetic goodness come into play at this creative level” (p. 93); (7) Thus, it follows analytically that the natural environment has mainly positive aesthetic qualities, a vindication of the view that “positive aesthetics” holds in the world of nature. These are bold and powerful ideas. Here, Carlson makes an impressive case for them, patiently (and repeatedly) working through both supportive arguments and challenges to his position. It is only now that the various components of this position (which appeared at various times and in various places) have been assembled in a single volume, that the structure and coherence of this position become apparent. If you buy the basics—Carlson’s initial perspective on the nature of nature and the enterprise of appreciation—everything that follows falls into place with a sense of commonsensicality, even inevitability. Readers of Plato and Kafka are familiar with this effect, and with its residual worries. Everything goes smoothly if you assume that there is a world of forms, or if you assume that people are sometimes transformed into cockroaches while they sleep. We find a foothold from which to reject the denouement only when we retrace our footsteps and reject these initial assumptions. Critical response to Carlson’s natural aesthetics has usually taken the shape of an attack on one or more of the seven key ideas mentioned above. But the true thrust of much of the criticism is really a rejection of certain assumptions that shape and animate the theory as a whole. “Nature” is a notoriously ambiguous term, and Carlson’s deployment of it follows one, but only one, perspective. Nature, as he speaks of it, is not the dust mote tumbling down across my study window, not the wen on my mother’s cheek, not the grain on my old pipe. It is, instead, the big outside. It is the buzzing, blooming, sprawling environment in which all manner of things grow, interact, and develop (largely) independent of the hand of man. This way of thinking of nature has the advantage of taking stock of any particular in the context of its complex matrix of interdependency, the interconnected web of natural process. But it sees it only in that context; it is oblivious to any aspects of the nonartifactual world not woven into that web. Arguably, many objects and features of objects are sufficiently detachable from the environmental matrix that their aesthetic appreciation can be made largely, if not wholly, independent of environmental considerations. At least, so it seems to some other aestheticians. 80 Equally subject to challenge is the assumption that there is some brute, basic reality about nature, some way of taking it that shows it to be what it “really is,” and that this reality is made available to us by the natural scientist. There are, of course, times when aesthetic judgment is a matter of taking particular things as specimens—good, bad, or indifferent—of their categorial types. And here the categories of science may be helpful, even indispensable. But, equally, there are times when aesthetic attention seems to cut across types, or abandon them altogether, as when I see as beautiful a certain interplay of leaves and clouds moving in a breeze. The fact that the leaves are alder or oak, the clouds cumulus or cirrus, has no bearing on the aesthetic experience; the fact that these are trees and clouds may itself have only the slightest bearing. For what the perceiver may be responding to in this instance is an interplay of rhythm, form, and color as divorced from the identities of its sources as the delight one may experience in a Mahler symphony may be from the identity of instruments that are performing it. It would be a mistake, however, to take these challenges to be winning points against the theory as a whole. They merely point up different paths the aesthetics of nature might take. Any alternative path chosen will demand its own, confining assumptions and encounter its own obstacles. In this book, Carlson achieves something that simply had not been done before. He begins with the groundwork and builds upward until he has a full-scale philosophical analysis of the enterprise of aesthetic appreciation as it encompasses natural phenomena in their native environment. If his assumptions are open to challenge, they are at least as respectable as most alternatives proposed; if the scope of his attention seems restricted, it covers what it covers methodically and perspicuously, without pretending to cover more. It remains to his critics to do as much if they have serious counterproposals. Two themes in Part 2 deserve special attention. The first is Carlson’s response to what he (admittedly casually) calls the “postmodern approach to aesthetic relevance,” the view that whatever observers happen to bring to an object will be relevant to its aesthetic appreciation. Carlson’s rejoinder to this approach turns on shifting the conceptual focus from the observer to the object of appreciation. Objects of appreciation “make demands,” so that not just any and everything that might be in the mind of the observer can count toward its appreciation. Recognizing this fact, Carlson claims, holds significant implications for applied aesthetics, making certain historical, cultural, and artistic information necessary. He goes on, in the final chapters, to show how this idea plays out in relation to roadsides, cornfields, formal Japanese gardens, landscape in literature The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism (taking Tony Hillerman’s descriptions as a telling example), various buildings, and even graffiti. The second notable theme is Carlson’s response to the claim that certain environmental works of art (e.g., Smithson’s Asphalt Rundown and Heizer’s Double Negative) are, because of the disruption to prior natural conditions they bring about, affronts to the natural environment. His answer to this challenge flows directly from the categorial tenet (number 3, above) in his general natural aesthetic: Whether a given object is an affront or not is a function of the determination of that object’s kind, and of whether that kind has been changed. A change in kind would result in an alteration of the object’s appreciable aesthetic qualities. On both of these themes, as well as the other miscellaneous topics in the later chapters, Carlson’s comments both illustrate the applicability of his theory of aesthetic appreciation and provide a sensible commentary on often-overlooked topics that is informative whether or not you accept the theory. In complimenting this book for its manifest strengths, I do not mean to suggest that it is without evident weaknesses. The arguments for requiring contextual appreciation, for example, seem far more plausible than the neo-Kantian claim that this form of appreciation leads (through the lemma that science creates categories of art in light of aesthetic goodness) to the conclusion that, within the scope of the scientific worldview, the natural world is throughand-through aesthetically good. Whatever should prove to be the basis of scientific category-making, it is hard to see why that basis should ensure aesthetic goodness in appreciations that deploy the categories. Science gave us the category “cat,” but didn’t thereby ensure that all cats are beautiful; and indeed you’d have to be a Panglossian zealot to insist that no cat is ugly. The new chapter on “Understanding and Aesthetic Experience” has its problems, too. Here, Carlson trains his analysis on Mark Twain’s famous remark, in Life on the Mississippi, that once he had mastered “the language of this water,” that is, gained knowledge about it, the river lost for him its aesthetic charm: “All the grace, the beauty, the poetry had gone out of the majestic river!” The success of Carlson’s objectivism depends on the compatibility, at some level, of cognitive and aesthetic experience; but what Twain reports here seems to indicate a potential rivalry between the two. Knowledge, he seems to be saying, can get in the way of aesthetic appreciation. Carlson’s way around this claim is first to show that what Twain says does not actually commit him to the incompatibility of aesthetic and cognitive elements in his experience and, second, to show that reflection on formalist theory reveals an incoherence in the incompatibility claim. But both of these responses are suspect. Twain makes it clear that it was not only his apointment to riverboat piloting (and all the attendant Book Reviews knowledge that required) that caused the change in his perception. And the formalist theory, by restricting the range of aesthetic experience to form without any eye to content, provides too easy a target. The important question is not whether pure form is the exclusive source of aesthetic experience but whether some aesthetic experience can be so wedded to perception that knowledge—categories, background information, history—can impede that experience. And that question just doesn’t get answered. I could point to other apparent defects; but there would be no point in doing so. All the criticisms I might make are small potatoes. The book as a whole is excellent, and will be mandatory reading for anyone who takes a serious interest in the aesthetic qualities of the natural environment. A final note. Readers who persist in judging books by their covers will, in this instance, make a big mistake. The book’s cover illustration, a detail from Tom Thomson’s Autumn Foliage (1916), is its worst feature. Its colors (gray, black, and a sort of chartreuse) are arguably uglier in their combination than anything to be found in nature. Its loose, messy design gives no hint of the clarity and coherence of the book’s contents. The illustration was printed upside-down on the hardback edition; but this mistake has been corrected in the paperback edition. RONALD MOORE Department of Philosophy University of Washington GROSZ, ELIZABETH. Architecture from the Outside. MIT Press, 2001, 218 pp., $20.00 paper. LEATHERBARROW, DAVID. Uncommon Ground: Architecture, Technology, and Topography. MIT Press, 2000, 297 pp., 87 b&w illus., $37.95 cloth. Reading this pair of books together is a bracing experience. One is written by an architectural authority with a decidedly philosophical turn of mind. The other is written by a philosopher with interest in issues that bear heavily on architecture. The play between the two is most stimulating, moving the reader from detailed analysis of the thinking of particular architects and their buildings to broad theoretical issues that should be addressed in architectural theory and practice. The big themes that both authors address include a rethinking of space and the buildings that help articulate it; the role of time and praxis in architecture; and the importance of undermining or overcoming such traditional boundaries (in building and thinking) as in/out and front/back. Having said this, let me address Grosz’s work more specifically. 81 To begin, Grosz’s book is both much more than a discussion of architecture and, unfortunately, a good deal less. The use of the term “architecture” in the title will seriously mislead readers thinking to be taken on a sustained architectural investigation of buildings or even space. Rather, Grosz reflects on culture with emphasis on the body, spatiality, cyberspace, and other decidedly Continental issues. And indeed, Grosz apologizes several times for stopping short of what the title seems to promise. In the midst of her insightful discussion of cyberspace and virtuality, she says, “Rather than explore technological potential and its relevance to architectural practice— something I am unfortunately unable to do—I hope to see, more broadly and philosophically, how conceptions of virtuality, simulation, computer reproduction and rendering transform our understanding of the real, matter, space, the body, and the world” (p. 76). You get the idea. Grosz’s style and substance should suit readers who like their philosophical ideas laid on with broad brush strokes, preferably with a Gallic palette. But perhaps the book should be read as something like a manifesto, a call to radical reappraisal of culture from the standpoint of bodies in space. With different expectations, Grosz’s thought is more a refreshing provocation than a disappointing treatise on architecture. Thus does she say, “These technologies [that make possible global computerization] have served not to transform bodies . . . but to fundamentally transform the way that bodies are conceived, their sphere of imaginary and lived representation” (p. 51). Regrettably, Grosz does not provide very specific analysis of how bodies have been reconceived, except to dismiss allegedly phallocentric hopes that cyberspace will enable us to think ourselves, and perhaps our (male) sexuality, as disembodied (e.g., pp. 82–85). As Grosz remarks (p. 61), she is primarily raising questions “inspired by [Gilles] Deleuze”—who seems to have replaced Derrida as the Continental philosopher du jour. Where exactly does Grosz provoke most interestingly? I found her discussions of virtuality versus virtual reality and lived spatiality more helpful than some of the other chapters. In Chapter 2, “Lived Spatiality,” Grosz does a good job of explaining how the sense of “psychical integrity” depends upon a developed body image that includes placing oneself in space. She explores pathologies resulting from the inability of people to anchor subjectivity in their bodies, for such anchoring “is the condition of a coherent identity” (p. 37). Indeed, representing space as such requires that individuals be able to locate themselves as the physical/spatial point of origin. But this discussion is largely a reprise of the work of Roger Caillois. Where Grosz makes original inroads is in moving from this sense of embodiment to questions of virtual 82 space and virtuality raised by computer-generated cyberspace. Grosz asks important questions about the relationship between the computer and virtual space and architecture: Will computers change how buildings are designed, how space is rethought, how we understand our connection to place or displacement? She teases us with assertions such as the following without doing very much to explain or develop them: “The virtuality of the space of computing, and of inscription more generally, is transforming at least in part how we understand what it is to be in space (and time)” (p. 86). To give Grosz her due, she smoothly, almost imperceptibly, glides from a discussion of the “virtual” to the notion of “virtuality,” and then goes on to speak at great length (and redundancy because the essays were written separately and not revised for the sake of streamlining or integration) about virtuality. And virtuality is about how the future infects the present, about the indeterminate or open-endedness of the future. She daringly, and I think correctly, asserts that “the challenge that virtual reality poses to architecture cannot be reduced to the question of technology” (p. 87). This is because the challenge as Grosz sees it is a matter of rethinking architecture in terms of the rich notion of virtuality rather than the more prosaic idea of virtual reality. Grosz’s investigation of virtuality dovetails most neatly with Leatherbarrow’s orientation when it links the future with our potential for action in space, emphasizing the “possibilities of my action on and being acted on by matter in space and time” (Grosz, p. 118). Space and the objects in it must be understood in terms of potential for bodily movement. We will see how Leatherbarrow translates into concrete architectural decisions and details Grosz’s claim that once space is opened up to time, “space becomes amenable to transformation and refiguring; it becomes . . . individualized” (Grosz, p. 116). Leatherbarrow takes up Grosz’s challenge that we temporize our conceptualization of space and architecture, focusing on “relations of nearness and farness, relations of proximity and entwinement, . . . rather than of numerals or geometry” (Grosz, p. 129). The title of Leatherbarrow’s book, Uncommon Ground, refers to the indeterminate areas overshadowed by the more prominent aspects of buildings, what Grosz and Gilles Deleuze call the “in between” (Grosz, p. 64). Leatherbarrow casually alludes to his title when he notes the importance of the “gaps or unclaimed areas, a discontinuous field, an uncommon ground, a horizon no longer dominated by a constructed vista” (p. 19). Thus does he align his repeated emphasis on horizontals (floors, ceilings, shelves, terraces, benches, halls, paths, and the like) with the notion of horizon. Horizon has several meanings for Leatherbarrow, and he seems to want to The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism think them all at once: perceptual horizon where sky meets land or sea; visible boundary of what we are able to see from wherever we happen to be; horizon as topographical field; horizon as practical context of options for movement and acting; cultural/traditional ways of doing things. What is common to the way these horizons work and speak to architecture is that they capture the “unnoticed underside” of what we pay most attention to, such as the connections between building and terrain. And this underside, full of latency and tacit meaning, is akin to what Grosz understands by virtuality. For it is full of potential, and good building design works with it as a liberating force. Leatherbarrow gives architectural definition to Grosz’s notion that what matters most is “difference and discontinuity” (Grosz, p. 115). Leatherbarrow writes with a flair and dexterity that is all the more remarkable for its grounding in the details of buildings, sites, and materials. Here is a schematic rendition of how Leatherbarrow contrasts his approach to more typical architectural theory and practice. The standard view emphasizes verticals (walls and partitions): the front or facade of buildings; hierarchical arrangements; pictorial effect; seeing buildings as isolated, stable objects. Leatherbarrow’s approach emphasizes horizontality: site sectionality; accommodation to use and context; networks of spaces; bodies in motion; intersection of praxis with tradition and site. Horizontality is Leatherbarrow’s conceptual wedge into the web of relationships that ideally structure the work of architecture. Instead of the building as a complete object to look at and admire, defined most clearly by the facade that separates it from environing conditions and interior walls that segment the spaces within, Leatherbarrow proposes the horizontality of levels, sections, lateral movement, and interface with vicinity. Horizontality and horizons focus attention on a field of circumstances and terrain of cultural practices (p. 172). This is why he directs our attention to what is usually taken for granted, tacit, and implicit, such as the backs of buildings rather than their conspicuous faces. The back of a building is like a horizon, full of latent meaning for praxis—human activity within a topographical, built, and cultural context. When we shift our attention to the sectional and lateral, we see how the backs of buildings are indirect and sustaining of the activities that make up residence. To illustrate this, Leatherbarrow analyzes several of Adolf Loos’s buildings, which effectively blur the front-back distinction. In Loos’s Winteritz Villa, the entrance is itself placed on the side of the house, adapted to plot configuration, bend in the street, and practical needs (p. 93). More generally, the back of buildings is emblematic for Leatherbarrow of that which is inconspicuous, ready-for-use, and connected with environment. Book Reviews We usually lack the needed distance to have a nice picture of the back, so it slides beneath our visual awareness and is that much better adapted to accommodate practical life. The front of the building is all show, crying out for attention, but that attenuates the true purpose of building design—to sustain everyday practice through interaction within and between dwelling and surrounding conditions. The distinctiveness of facades “disintegrates ensembles” (p. 158), and for Leatherbarrow, “The building is essentially an ensemble of preparations for the typical practices of residing” (p. 209). Leatherbarrow analyzes in depth the designs of Neutra’s buildings to illustrate how varying levels of the lateral elements of floors and ceilings, rather than walls and partitions, can create discrete settings and direct movement. For example, in the Tremaine House ceilings change levels five or six times with accompanying change in surfaces (p. 35). At the same time, these different levels provide natural ventilation and indirect lighting. But the emphasis on strata does not stop at the building’s edge for Leatherbarrow (or for Neutra). Three distinct horizons are interwoven: land as it slopes into valley, sunken reflecting pool and rock garden, and entry space. Sections of the house correspond to or open on to different levels in the surrounding topography. The rooms are set off from one another by upward and downward shifts that define paths, steps, landings, floors, decks, terraces, and pools. This yields what Leatherbarrow calls a “field of articulation” as the site section cuts through surrounding terrain (p. 51). By minimizing verticality, earlier architects, such as Frank Lloyd Wright, pioneered the effort to “break open the box.” Such architects freed interior space for multiple arrangements and dwelling options while connecting the inside of the building with its surroundings. However, Leatherbarrow supplants Wrightian “flow” with “reciprocation” and “knotting” between different spaces, such as inside and outside. Not only does the notion of flow tend to obliterate needed territorial definition and demarcation, but it promotes the goal of assimilating building to site (p. 202)—as in Wright’s famous house, Fallingwater (Bear Run, PA). Instead of Wrightian isomorphism between architecture and terrain, Leatherbarrow offers a more dialectical interpretation of lateral interface—transaction and reciprocation. This is reminiscent of John Dewey’s pragmatism, as is much of Leatherbarrow’s emphasis on praxis over mere appearance. Leatherbarrow insists on capitalizing on the difference between built form and land form: “This contrast gives both amplitude and dramatic tension to the field of articulation within any given site” (p. 55). Leatherbarrow notes with approval how the buildings of Aris Konstantinidis in Greece transform the 83 outside as it penetrates the dwelling: warm air is cooled in summer and cool air is warmed in winter by virtue of the modulating design of windows, apertures, colonnades, roofline, and shades. Leatherbarrow’s idea is a dynamic one—to use the resistance nature (or a building tradition) affords to invent modes of interactions that connect building with topography and climate in practically efficacious ways. The question of how to integrate mass-produced building ingredients so as to individualize design is also answered by Leatherbarrow’s dialectic of difference. How can we design so that standardized, repetitive furnishings and building constituents (e.g., windows) can be site-specific—adapted to topography, culture, and practice (p. 122)? If architects merely select from catalogues, the homogeneity of the ready-mades will yield homogeneity in construction and style by stripping from a situation the irregularities that give it particular definition. A new kind of creativity is needed to mix from different product lines and the prefabricated with the handcrafted. The irony for Leatherbarrow is that local constraints can instigate freedom from the tyranny of product lines by forcing the architect to innovative use of standardized elements (p. 127). Design can adapt prefabricated constituents to topographic and practical specifics by shifting attention from “objects [such as furnishings] as objects to the actions they were meant to accommodate” (p. 154). Only when we focus on their performative role can we tell whether factory-made artifacts can be appropriately combined with crafted materials. When architecture successfully mediates between something unique (location, tradition, use) and standardized products, it effects the “recuperation of the same by virtue of the different” (p. 168). Thus do the Japanese dwellings built by Antonin and Noemi Raymond effect the traditional design and function of bamboo curtains and awnings with factory-made materials (Chapter 4). Ready-made objects can become “absorbed into the situation” (p. 282) precisely because they are so anonymous. Their potential to “accumulate” nontechnical relationships exists because they are themselves “unsaturated” with references. The erstwhile sterility or uniformity of factory-made products actually gives them the potential to be adapted anywhere: to meet territorial exigencies and to be appropriated for practical life. Leatherbarrow’s book should appeal to a wide range of readers. Readers with varying degrees of familiarity with architectural theory can be engaged because Leatherbarrow presents an overview of his position and proceeds to analyze particular buildings in ever-increasing depth. As mentioned, his approach has much in common with American pragmatism, but easily consorts with Continental treatments of 84 themes descended from Heideggerian “dwelling.” Perhaps most importantly, Leatherbarrow expresses his philosophy of design and building in writing that is both clear and poetic, at once useful and elegant, like the best architecture. JOSEPH KUPFER Department of Philosophy and Religious Studies Iowa State University PICART, CAROLINE JOAN S. Thomas Mann and Friedrich Nietzsche: Eroticism, Death, Music, and Laughter. Atlanta: Rudolpi, 1999, 151 pp., 1 b&w illus., $30.50 paper. PICART, CAROLINE JOAN S. Resentment and the “Feminine” in Nietzsche’s Politico-Aesthetics. Pennsylvania State University Press, 1999, 206 pp., 1 b&w illus., $49.95 cloth, $19.95 paper. Caroline Picart has written two well-crafted scholarly books that add nicely to the vast literature of Nietzsche studies. Both have some relevance to aesthetics, as well as to other topics. The specific object of the first is the influence of Nietzsche on Thomas Mann. This book will be of special interest to Mann scholars and to those who are curious about the history of Nietzsche’s influence. Picart’s method is to pair several of Nietzsche’s texts with several of Mann’s. She seeks to make up for a lacuna in the literature on Nietzsche and Mann, having discovered that the themes of eroticism, death, music, and laughter, although explored separately, have never been addressed as an interweaving group in the works of Nietzsche and Mann. Although Mann was an early enthusiast, in his later writings he became increasingly critical of Nietzsche, associating him with Wagnerian decadence and worse. Picart sees even the later Mann, however, as close to Nietzsche in the themes he covered, and in his methodology. In the first chapter, Picart colorfully associates the above mentioned four themes with the magic square found in Dürer’s etching, Melancholia I. She finds a fundamental ambiguity in this work: it both symbolizes deep sadness and higher intellectual pursuits. She also finds this Faustian ambiguity in both Nietzsche and Mann. This is consistent with her criticism of Nietzsche that he is a decadent romantic despite his intentions. Unfortunately, Mann misreads Nietzsche. And reading Nietzsche by way of Mann, as Picart does, may overemphasize his connections with decadence and romanticism. Picart observes that in A Death in Venice, Mann eliminates Nietzsche’s distinction between the Asiatic Dionysus (noted by Nietzsche The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism for its “witches’ brew” of pain and pleasure) and the Greek Dionysus, and reduces the latter to the former. For Mann, but not for Nietzsche, the Dionysian is associated with death and sterile exhaustion. Reading Nietzsche in this way would put him squarely in the camp of Wagner and romanticism. However, Nietzsche’s adulation of Wagner and Schopenhauer, even at the time of The Birth of Tragedy, was not consistent with his overall position, evident even then, and developed in later works, that one ought to say “yes” to life. What Mann misses, and oddly Picart too, is that the Greek Dionysus is itself synthesized with the Greek Apollo to achieve Nietzsche’s ideal art form, thus becoming transformed once again against decadence. Moreover, although eroticism, music, and laughter play important roles in Nietzsche’s thought, the only role death plays is as something that leads to rebirth. The best part of both books is Picart’s analysis of the development of Nietzsche’s political thought with respect to modernity. She argues that Nietzsche begins with a political aesthetic antidote to modernity (before Zarathustra), then moves to aesthetic political inoculation (in Zarathustra), and then advocates a crude political amputation of modernity in the postZarathustra period. Generally speaking, this is a decline. The second book under review develops this theme in relation to the concerns of contemporary feminism. “Resentment,” or “ressentiment,” is Nietzsche’s term for a stance he abhors. Yet Picart believes that a “will-to-resentment” (against his own romantic tendencies, against the herd) drives his entire philosophy and that his approach to women is an example of this. This book is a very careful and well-researched analysis of the development, or rather devolution, of Nietzsche’s concepts of the “feminine” and of “woman” throughout his career. He begins with a usually positive attitude toward the “feminine,” as exemplified by his use of various female mythological characters to represent valuable traits. However, he becomes progressively misogynistic toward the end. Picart believes that issues of gender, politics, aesthetics, and myth are deeply intertwined in Nietzsche’s thought, although less so in his last period, which is more crudely political. “Aesthetics” in the phrase “politico-aesthetics” refers not only to Nietzsche’s philosophy of art, but also, and perhaps mainly, to his approach to myth. Politico-aesthetics, as far as I understand it, is the use of myth to promote a certain future. We learn more about this idea in the last chapter. There, Picart advocates a postNietzschean, postmodernist, and feminist version of political aesthetics, inspired by Cixous and Trin Minh-Ha, that seeks to move beyond resentment and beyond the master-slave dialectic. This is a political multiculturalist aesthetics of resistance against Book Reviews traditional hierarchies and dichotomies. Picart ends her book by discussing these issues in relation to a drawing of her own titled Nurturance? and various responses to it. The idea of politico-aesthetics might be best understood in terms of Picart’s analysis of Nietzsche’s changing use of myth. She argues that his early use of myth, as in The Birth of Tragedy, is “benign” and even “empowering.” Unlike the Mann book, here she takes into account the role of Apollo as well as Dionysus in mediating the tension between politics and aesthetics and between the “masculine” and “feminine.” She then argues that myth’s function is transformed in Zarathustra, where it becomes a noble lie designed to save the polis. There, Nietzsche weaves together the myths of Dionysus, Zeus, and Apollo in an attempt to harness the feminine power of fertility to a “phallic mother.” This involves mythologizing Zarathustra’s body as supermasculine, able to give birth itself. Following Irigaray, and drawing on her interpretation of Book 4 as ironizing his central doctrines, Picart sees this as expressing Nietzsche’s own “womb envy.” She further argues that the idea of the übermensch is presented by Nietzsche as a “noble lie” designed to help “the many” face the nightmare of eternal recurrence. Picart then reads the post-Zarathustran period as Nietzsche’s attempt at birthing the Übermensch. She characterizes these attempts as stillbirths rooted in resentment. His resentment is based on his inability to rebirth himself in disciples. In his final writings, Nietzsche’s own body becomes the Dionysian body that must be dismembered to bring a resurgence of life after modernity. Here the body of “woman” must be harnessed and destroyed so as not to contaminate Nietzsche’s own body. Picart’s overall story concerning Nietzsche’s descent into misogyny is well argued. Her analysis of Thus Spoke Zarathustra, however, is problematic and confusing. (Is the noble lie for the few [p. 151] or the many [p. 152]?) I agree that the Overman as a future race of man is a myth that is superceded by the doctrine of eternal recurrence later in the book. The end point, however, is not a deep pessimism (at least about life), or even a rejection of the Overman as an ideal. I also find Picart’s idea that the Übermensch is a noble lie for the ordinary man implausible. For 85 those few who confront the idea of eternal recurrence the experience is nightmarish only at first: the Overman is someone who is able to say “yes” even to the eternal recurrence of the most despicable. “The many” do not even encounter the idea of eternal recurrence. Why would Nietzsche want to provide a noble lie for them? Picart thinks it is needed to lure them back to life to hasten their destruction. But there is no need for this, as they are never going to question life anyway. Although Nietzsche promotes a distinction between exoteric and esoteric doctrine, this is between what Zarathustra says to his disciples and what he says to himself, the point being that the deepest levels of insight are extremely difficult, and actually impossible for all but a very few. Picart’s analysis of Book 4 (as Nietzsche’s confession of residual unhealthiness) fails to capture the point of the last chapter of that book. Here we learn that Zarathustra’s final sin is his pity for the “higher men,” which Picart correctly describes as representing distortions of aspects of his doctrine. He recognizes here that these are not his “proper companions.” His true children are to come, although they are “near.” Contra Picart, Nietzsche is not, here, ironizing Zarathustra’s dream of birthing the Übermensch in Book 4, but reaffirming it, while recognizing its great difficulty. This, then, poses problems for the womb envy thesis. There are many fine things in these two books, particularly Picart’s analysis of the development of Nietzsche’s attitudes toward women and the feminine and her general attitude that one cannot separate Nietzsche’s aesthetics from his politics. Although I am not convinced of some of the central claims, her detailed analysis contributes to deepening our understanding of Nietzsche’s philosophy in general and his aesthetics in particular by forcing us to look at it from a different perspective. For the most part these books are clearly written, however, I protest the frequent use of parentheses and dashes within words, as in “(dis)empowered and dis-eased” (p. 5, Resentment), which, although a common postmodern practice, is just plain confusing. THOMAS LEDDY Department of Philosophy San Jose State University