International Journal of Applied Psychoanalytic Studies Int. J. Appl. Psychoanal. Studies 3(4): 299–307 (2006) Published online in Wiley InterScience (www.interscience.wiley.com) DOI: 10.1002/aps.113 Root Values for a Global One-world: Darwinian Biology and Social Etymology* ELLIOTT JAQUES AND KATHRYN CASON ABSTRACT Global terrorism can harm anyone anywhere. It is imperative that we shift to a commonly shared system of powerful primary values which will determine basic behavior so as to enable us to live together in mutual trust. The untestable belief systems that have created terrorism and other divisive wars must be replaced by a testable sciencebased, trust-inducing system of values. Copyright © 2006 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd. Key words: belief systems, evolution theory, global terrorism, social values, mutual trust, good society We shall take up the fundamental question of ways in which we value others and the values (good and bad) we place upon the ways in which we behave towards each other. Our aim is to get to a scientific foundation for deciding such values. Our goal was taken forward with the absolute basis provided by Darwinian evolutionary theory (Darwin, 1859). This is followed by a scientific hypothesis that is an immediate derivative from that theory, and then followed further by some recent findings from the behavioral sciences. Such a scientific achievement being objectively established should help to overcome the widespread social divisiveness caused by the conflicting values based upon conflicting belief systems that have always existed all over the world. The urgent need for such an objective scientific foundation is that scientific findings are universally meaningful and shareable, and are not influenced by the religious or philosophical or culture-bound biases and conflicts that cause so much trouble, especially in the currently emerging one-world. It is fortunate that * Edited extract from unpublished A Scientific Foundation for Ethics, Economics, and Government (2003). Copyright © 2006 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd Int. J. Appl. Psychoanal. Studies 3: 299–307 (2006) DOI: 10.1002/aps 300 Jaques and Cason Darwinian theory and a developing true science of human behavior became available in the same century as a potentially troubled and troublesome oneworld began to arrive. In order to discuss these issues we shall have recourse to the following three concepts because our relationships with the people in the groups they define are so very different. All of them have to do with relationships between members of the same species. • • • Familiars: a concept, the opposite of strangers, for which we have had no single label, which includes everyone we know: family members, friends, acquaintances, neighbors, people we meet regularly in the course of our daily living, associates, etc. This group may include anywhere from a few hundred to perhaps a thousand or more people. Connected strangers: people we do not know personally, but with whom we interact in the course of our daily lives in everything from seeing them from time to time on the street, or in a shop, or whatever, to members of our community, or city, or nation, with whom we interact in voting, or hear about, or know about anywhere. Potentially connected strangers: people anywhere in the world with whom we might personally interact, or be affected by, which since the events of 9/11 have come to comprise anyone, anywhere, in the whole world – our present day one-world. VALUES FROM RELIGION AND PHILOSOPHY Up until the nineteenth century the prime formulation of societal values had been set by the common culture as influenced by the dominating religion or religions in any given society, and by philosophers. In this sense, prime social values were literally either god-given or philosopher-given. The gods, of course, and the philosophers varied widely among themselves. They went from the anthropomorphic gods of primitive peoples to the more sophisticated multiplicity of gods of the early Greek, Chinese, Egyptian, Indian, and Mesopotamian civilizations, to the emergence of the single all-powerful world-creating gods of the Hebrew, Christian, Islamic, and Buddhist religions, which pretty much took over the world. It was probably somewhere in the period between 5000 BC and 3000 BC that the first social values were set out in written documents, of which the first books of the Hebrew bible are a good example of the process. This early bible sets out both what would be the appropriate – positively valued – behavior, and what would now be the legislated laws that set the context for such behavior, mainly in the form of “thou shalt not” behavioral constraints. These constraints were of three kinds: those related to how to deal with familiars; those related to how to deal with connected strangers, this need being occasioned by the emergence of the large conurbations that developed at that Copyright © 2006 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd Int. J. Appl. Psychoanal. Studies 3: 299–307 (2006) DOI: 10.1002/aps Root Values for a Global One-world time, along with the development of writing; and, to a very small extent, those related to how to deal with unconnected strangers, to do mainly with how to handle captives-in-war, these being the only unconnected strangers they would encounter. By 500 BC these religious rules were joined by the written outputs of the philosophers, who added to the written behavioral injunctions. However, the main problem then was that the few monotheistic religions not only dominated the world, but were in conflict with each other, as were the accumulating philosophical belief systems. Nonetheless, it was these conflicting religious ideas which largely promoted the value systems within which there lived the great sectors of society made up of their adherents, since the philosophers had less impact. Among the worst conflicts that occurred were those in which there were warring parties each of which represented a different religion seeking to dominate the governmental outlook of the same territories. For example, in Northern Ireland, or as between Islamic and Christian/Hebrew groups in different parts of the world. God-given values and philosophical ideas are explicitly founded upon beliefs. Belief systems can be argued about endlessly, with no hope of resolution, because there are no objective testable criteria with which to establish the advantages of one set of beliefs above another. Our argument is that our societal arrangements now need to be founded upon scientifically established criteria of the good society, criteria that can be shared globally. Given a scientific foundation for establishing worldwide testable and shareable societal values, it would no longer be the role of religion and belief in God, and philosophy, to set the standards of behavior for the world. Having churches, belonging to churches, having different religions or different philosophies, would become a matter of individual faith, interest, and concern. Every individual must have the continuing right and freedom to believe in and to worship the God of his or her choice, or not to do so, or to adhere to a particular philosophical or political outlook. But no such beliefs must be allowed to displace the worldwide system of scientifically established values found to be necessary for the achievement of a secure and peaceful one-world. No church, no system of beliefs must be allowed to have priority over scientifically established unconditional world values which can be applicable to a one-world, because they are testable. It would appear then, that the ways in which familiars should value each other, have been well-laid down in the evolving genetic development of all species. This finding includes humans, in whom there is a further elaboration in terms of the sophisticated understanding which we can bring to our formulations of these values. Our values are displayed not just in behaviors but in statements about the ethics and morals and appropriate behaviors that we expect from each other, even though we do not always behave in those ways. Thus everyone knows that children and parents should love each other, behave warmly and helpfully to extended family members. Friends should respect and be helpful to each other. Acquaintances should treat each other politely and Copyright © 2006 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd Int. J. Appl. Psychoanal. Studies 3: 299–307 (2006) DOI: 10.1002/aps 301 302 Jaques and Cason helpfully, and so on. It is not always possible to carry out such behaviors, or under various circumstances, even to want to do so or feel like doing so. But we do not need legislated laws and regulations to require us to behave in these positive ways. Unless abuses are involved we do not need the police or a judge to decide that we have not carried out the optimum positive behavioral “requirements” and therefore to set punishment. THE BASIC VALUE OF SPECIES SURVIVAL Let us begin with the fundamental unconditional, absolute, scientifically given, prime value, from which all other values may be scientifically derived in the sense of being objectively stated and testable: All of our regulated social arrangements will set a context for ensuring that any behavior if universally applied will enhance the survival of the human species, in accord with the Darwinian principle of the survival of the fittest. This value applies to all living species. It is played out in a social context in that all species function in terms of clusters, or colonies, or swarms, or hives, or flocks, or herds, or families, or extended families, or in humans, more extended tribes, or cities, or nations. It is in these social arrangements that individuals collaborate to ensure the survival, if not of everyone, at least of enough, and especially enough of the best, to keep the species in existence. In the evolutionary development of non-human species there has been a persistence of genetically inbuilt mechanisms that prevent them from harming each other. Thus we find in wolves, elks, goats, and others, when there is a combat for leadership of a pack the loser will show the neck, or turn and run off, as signs of giving in, and preventing the fight from ending in the death of the loser. Of the same ilk are the methods that a pack leader will use – urinating, or marking trees, for example – to mark off his territory and prevent fighting with other packs of the same species. Humans somehow have lost, or perhaps never had, such automatic behavioral mechanisms. Instead, we have learned to use our higher levels of capability, especially our ability to communicate in disengaged intangible language of high orders of complexity, to formulate laws in the form of constraints against such harm backed by legal punishments if we behave outside the limits that they set. The universality of such laws would point to a strong genetic foundation for their establishment once population growth reached the level where families no longer lived together and controlled behavior in small family or extended family groups. Instead, in large populations – conurbations – where members of family groups become dispersed across wide areas, behavioral constraints must be legislated, backed by legal punishments, in order to protect all world citizens from the tyranny of fear of harm. In all of these arrangements, it is in no way necessary to assume some kind of genetic source of altruistic self-sacrifice for familiars; Copyright © 2006 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd Int. J. Appl. Psychoanal. Studies 3: 299–307 (2006) DOI: 10.1002/aps Root Values for a Global One-world just ordinary good loving, or at least compassionate and mutually sustaining behaviors. This general value of species survival is all very well. It does not, however, tell us what these socially collaborating individuals are phylogenetically driven to do in order to achieve the foundation goal of ensuring species survival. What values must individual members of these social communities have that will enable them to live and to collaborate to overcome any forces that might undo the ability of the species to survive, especially against the depredations of other species who are also engaged in the competition to survive? Let us turn to some of the clues we sought in our examination of the underlying primitive roots of the language of prime values. INDIVIDUAL VERSUS SOCIAL VALUES IN HUMANS Humans, too, are genetically endowed with what are regarded and valued as good behaviors with familiars. Even values such as freedom and liberty are not freedom and liberty from others, but freedom and liberty with others, despite the fact that we often formulate them as individual values, as, for example, in the right of free speech. Are we then to suppose that we are the only living organisms who have a sense of things being worth more or less, or perhaps nothing at all? Not unless we assume that we are the only living organisms that have intentions. And we are assuming precisely the opposite; namely, that the prime distinction between animate and inanimate is that animate “things” are intentionally goal-directed, whereas inanimate things move only under the impact of external physical forces. And you cannot have goals or intentions without having a sense of the worth of everything, in the process of deciding what it is worthwhile to intend to do or not to do, and then to do or not to do it. From this point of view then, we are justified in describing the values of all living organisms in terms of what they choose to do. Richard Dawkins’ (1990) “selfish gene” does not take us far enough. As he recognizes, selfish genes can survive only to the extent that they are organized into successfully surviving organisms. We would add that these organisms must be organized into successfully functioning and mutually supportive social groups and organizations. There must be a strong genetic underpinning to all of these arrangements. In the context of this argument the sociological concept of the selfish gene as explaining all living behavior is an emaciated concept for describing and explaining the behavior of living organisms in relation to familiars in well established permanent social groups. THE KEY SOCIAL VALUES: HYPOTHESES We have been emphasizing that the operative basic values that are necessary for species survival should be stated in terms of constraints and objectives that Copyright © 2006 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd Int. J. Appl. Psychoanal. Studies 3: 299–307 (2006) DOI: 10.1002/aps 303 304 Jaques and Cason leave us free to behave however we choose within the limits set rather than in terms of wide open unlimited freedoms that allow unrestrained license. Are there then any specific values that are absolutely fundamental in the sense of being directly connected with species survival? We will put forward the hypotheses that there are two such basic sets of constraints and objectives that we derived from the outcome of our etymological analysis. These two sets of values are hypotheses. They are stated in terms of concepts that are rigorously and unequivocally articulated and labeled so as to constrain propositions that allow for objective testing. The two values are first, fundamental survival constraints that apply to relationships between everyone in the world, strangers and persons known to each other alike. And, second, evolving genetic development of behavioral objectives that apply only to those whom we know, whether related in kinship, or friendship or various degrees of acquaintanceship. The constraints that apply to absolutely everyone, from worldwide strangers in distant foreign lands to our closest kin and friends are that: No person or group of persons acting on their own behalf and not as agents of government carrying out governmental policies and programs should intentionally injure or cause injury or do anything injurious to anyone else. The foundation of this new value system can be readily stated: universally accepted criterion for judging our primary social constructions – our laws, political organizations, economic policies and regulations, social arrangements, educational systems – will be constructed in terms of a common basic context, constraining our behaviors regardless of our personal values and beliefs. In order for the human species to survive successfully, we will have to design international, national and local laws, regulations, and practices that we can all rely upon. Meaning being able to trust that no one, including utter strangers, will do you intentional physical, economic, or psychological harm or injury, and indeed will do their best to help you if they see that you are being harmed or injured, or at risk of being so threatened. Because we have lost much of our genetic endowment (30 000 or so genes found in both genome studies rather than the expected 90 000–100 000 genes), the human species is required to substitute the creation of universally applicable laws and regulations that we can rely upon to substitute for genetic instinctual behaviors. We have failed to do so until now because we have always been divided by religious and philosophical differences. Recourse to scientific, or at least testable, global constraints, might just make it possible for us to better work with our global neighbors through organizations such as the United Nations. The scientific route is the best and really the only route to take to a credible arrangement of secular values that we can rely upon in our global one-world, and yet allow everyone to engage in their own interests with respect to religion and philosophy. Copyright © 2006 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd Int. J. Appl. Psychoanal. Studies 3: 299–307 (2006) DOI: 10.1002/aps Root Values for a Global One-world VALUES IN OUR RELATIONSHIPS WITH PEOPLE WE KNOW Here we come into the world of enriched language and a multiplicity of relationships based upon positive requisite obligations. They range from the IndoEuropean and Greek, Latin, and Germanic word roots, concerned with obligations spanning love for family and kinship relations; compassion, warmth, and concern for friendship; good feelings and positive regard for colleagues, acquaintances; and the wide variety of others whom we know. At bottom, of course, even in these relationships, we must be able to rely upon well established and effective constraining limits to our behavior to enable us to trust each other not to do us harm. Without that all possibility of relationships is erased. Thus, for example, if the members of a family cannot rely upon each other not to do harm to any other member, then the family will cease to exist. The difference between the two groups is striking. We value being able to trust everyone in the world, far-off strangers and those we know, not to take it upon themselves to injure us. And in addition, if there is anything they can do, to do what they can to help us if we are in danger of being injured – but not the altruistic self-sacrifice called upon by some sociobiologists. On the other hand, our constraints in relation to those we do know are in various degrees of personal values and obligations that have been instilled in us, to do good things for them, depending upon the closeness of the relationship, but not upon the requirements of legal constraints. THE RELEVANCE OF MELANIE KLEIN’S PSYCHOANALYTICAL THEMES There has been a post-Freudian development in psychoanalysis connected with the work of Melanie Klein that can give some scientific support to the two sets of values: legal constraints against harm, on the one hand, and positive personal obligations, on the other. Mrs Klein’s clinically based conception of early infant development sets out two phases, which she calls “positions.” The first is the phase, roughly from birth to six months of age, which she calls the “paranoid-schizoid position.” During this period, the infant is not mature enough to handle ambivalence and mixed feelings. If it experiences a good breast feed, the breast is idealized as a “good breast,” that is, pure perfection. If, on the other hand, it experiences a feed as unsatisfactory, it feels persecuted by a “bad breast”, is in a rage, and projects into the breast its own rage and destructive impulses, and experiences a relationship with a bad breast split away from the good breast, that is, the essence of the worst kind of persecuting and damaging object. Strangers anywhere in the world arouse such feelings if we do not create shared constraints that prevent any and every stranger from doing harm to anyone else. Copyright © 2006 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd Int. J. Appl. Psychoanal. Studies 3: 299–307 (2006) DOI: 10.1002/aps 305 306 Jaques and Cason There is a sense here that because the infant is engaged in dealing with split-apart objects and is unable to deal with the breast and mother as whole objects, they become potentially persecuting strangers. These primal fantasies and anxieties are re-awakened in a world of strangers who cannot be relied upon not to injure you. Nothing can be more frightening. On the other hand, as the infant matures into the second half of the first year, it matures into what Mrs Klein has called the “depressive position,” that is to say, to the point where it can experience and deal with whole objects – with the whole mother, and the whole breast – partly good and partly bad, but no longer split into good and bad part objects, with a persecutory undertone. It is able to deal with the ambivalence of love, of good experience, and depressive reactions when the same good mother or breast turns out to do frustrating or bad things. We now get to the foundation of obligation for feeling and expressing positive feelings, for overcoming the feelings of ambivalence, and for maintaining a good loving relationship with a mother whom the infant is now able to know as an integrated whole object, a real person, no longer idealized, but it is hoped with a preponderance of good feeling. It is this position that underlies the personal obligation to behave with varied strengths of positive feelings and behavior towards those whom we know. TRUST AND PARANOID MISTRUST UNDERLIE LOVE AND HATE IN HUMAN RELATIONS In the early development of human beings anxiety about being harmed by bad objects and idealization of the good in relation to a breast and mother is experienced as good and bad parts. The whole mother, still perceived as a stranger, precedes and underlies the ability to experience ambivalence in love and anger for a whole recognizable mother and other family members, to whom there are experienced obligations to express good feelings. Against this background, in order for the human species to hold together and to be among the fittest for survival, we must arrange for the most primitively grounded experiences to be catered for; namely, to eliminate the paranoid feelings that are generated with inability to trust strangers in the absence of internationally agreed and reliable constraints or harmful and injurious paranoigenic behaviors. An important but developmentally secondary requirement is to provide for a sense of personal obligation on family members to love each other, on friends to have compassion and mutual support for each other, on colleagues to be able to rely upon each other for mutual support, on acquaintances or those we encounter in day-to-day relationships for a reasonable regard and polite treatment. The difference between the consequences of the two sets of values is a matter of interest and considerable importance. The more primitive and paranoigenic relationships that include countless millions of strangers worldwide need to be Copyright © 2006 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd Int. J. Appl. Psychoanal. Studies 3: 299–307 (2006) DOI: 10.1002/aps Root Values for a Global One-world made the subject of internationally legislated constraints that constrain individuals from behaving in ways that can harm others, strangers, and non-strangers alike. Without such clear social constraints the human world is driven to tear itself apart because we lack the genetically instinctual constraints possessed by all other living organisms against such behaviors. Besides the obligations to have positive feelings and to carry out positive behaviors of various degrees of intensity toward those we know, it seems to be left to the individuals concerned to feel free to decide upon the nature of their obligations to possess and express good feelings and behaviors to anyone else in the world at large. Externally imposed constraints against harmful behaviors to everyone and cultivated personal values inducing personally determined positive behaviors in relation to those we know seem to be the order of the day for the one-world species of humankind to rank high in the survival-of-the-fittest competition. REFERENCES Darwin C (1859) The Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection. London: Senate, 1994. Dawkins R. The Selfish Gene. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990. Kathryn Cason Requisite Organization International Institute 1101 St Paul Street, Suite 1112 Baltimore MD 21202 USA (Kcason@requisite.org) Copyright © 2006 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd Int. J. Appl. Psychoanal. Studies 3: 299–307 (2006) DOI: 10.1002/aps 307