THE INAUGURAL ADDRESS AS CONSTITUTIONAL STATESMANSHIP J. Richard Broughton* I. INTRODUCTION When President Obama delivered his inaugural address on January 20, 2009, he focused on what he described as the dark but recoverable state of the union.' He lamented the Nation's difficult economic conditions but, using the collective "we" and reiterating popular themes of his successful presidential campaign, expressed faith in America's promise and the Nation's capacity to overcome the current challenges"[o]n this day, we gather because we have chosen hope over fear, unity of purpose over conflict and discord.", 2 He emphasized the "indicators of crisis" and the "sapping of confidence across our land," and noted, "[t]he state of our economy calls for action, bold and swift," promising job creation, new infrastructure, lower health care costs, the restoration of science "to its rightful place," and an end to failing programs and poor management.3 He further trumpeted America's opposition to both global terrorism and to official corruption, and promised aid for the impoverished around the globe.4 He also called upon a uniquely American spirit that would help to achieve these goals, invoking founding principles and a fortitude to match the "winter of our hardship." 5 Unlike many other Presidents, however, President Obama failed to discuss one especially notable feature of American government: the Constitution. * Visiting Professor of Law, University of Detroit Mercy School of Law. I am grateful to David Marion, Richard Albert, and Paul Horwitz for their helpful comments. I thank Wendy and Blair for their support. 1. Barak Obama, Inaugural Address (Jan. 20, 2009), in The Address: "All This We Will Do, " N.Y. TIMEs, Jan. 21, 2009, at P2. 2. Id. 3. Id. 4. Id. 5. Obama, supranote 1. QUINNIPIAC LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:265 The omission is not his alone among recent occupants of the presidential office. Modem Presidents, like their early predecessors, have employed the inaugural address to state the present conditions of American life; to highlight important social, political, and economic challenges; and perhaps most importantly, to announce their views on issues of public policy to which they intend to devote their administrations. 6 Unlike the early Presidents, modem chief executives have not, despite the constitutional significance of the oath they took only moments earlier, taken the opportunity in their addresses to articulate or reflect upon their understanding of the nature and scope of constitutional powers. They have not reflected meaningfully upon executive power, the executive's constitutional relationship to the Congress, the extent of permissible judicial intervention in political disputes, or important constitutional rights that they intend to promote or defend that legislative action could jeopardize. Until the twentieth century, Presidents regularly used the inaugural address to reflect on the formalities of the constitutional order, to promise adherence to constitutional forms, and even to offer their interpretations of important constitutional issues.7 Scholars of the American executive have not overlooked the relationship, or the absence of one, between presidential communications and constitutionalism. Jeffrey Tulis's ground-breaking work in political science on what he called "The Rhetorical Presidency" directly confronts the problem of a presidency that operates through popular leadership-that is, contrary to constitutional design and the founding generation's fear of demagoguery, a presidency that eschews the formalities of constitutional governance in favor of direct appeals to the masses for the purpose of gaining popularity and winning public support for a political agenda. 8 Tulis argued that American political 6. See infra Part III. 7. See, e.g., John Quincy Adams, Inaugural Address (Mar. 4, 1825), in INAUGURAL ADDRESSES OF THE PRESIDENTS OF THE UNITED STATES 53, 53-55 (1989) (discussing constitutional principles); William Henry Harrison, Inaugural Address (Mar. 4, 1841), in INAUGURAL ADDRESSES OF THE PRESIDENTS OF THE UNITED STATES, supra, at 79, 79-86 (discussing, for example, his view of the constitutional defect of presidential re-eligibility, of the concentration of constitutional power, and of the veto power); Franklin Pierce, Inaugural Address (Mar. 4, 1853), in INAUGURAL ADDRESSES OF THE PRESIDENTS OF THE UNITED STATES, supra, at 115, 122 (arguing that the Compromise of 1850 is constitutional and that the federal government must respect the rights of southern states to hold slaves just as it would respect any other "legal and constitutional right"). 8. See JEFFREY K. TUL1S, THE RHETORICAL PRESIDENCY (1987). This book followed a 1981 article in PresidentialStudies Quarterly in which Tulis, James W. Ceaser, Glen E. 2010] CONSTITUTIONAL STATESMANSHIP development has witnessed the existence of two presidencies: a constitutional presidency, grounded in the formal institutional arrangements of the constitutional text; and a rhetorical presidency, prominent since Woodrow Wilson, grounded in efforts to shape public opinion in support of a presidential policy agenda through often informal, often extra-constitutional, mechanisms. 9 Wilson announced a revised understanding of the constitutional order, one that identified the President as the singular voice of democratic action and that rejected the formalities of the original constitution that he believed stood in the path of social progress. 10 The "second constitution," as Tulis calls it, satisfies this contemporary impulse for presidential "leadership," understood as directly seeking and securing public support for specific policies that the President wishes to advance and assuming a predominant role for the President in ordinary domestic policy-making and governance it is "a view of statecraft that is in tension with the original Constitutionindeed, is opposed to the founder's understanding of the political system."1 1 Professor Tulis highlights the nineteenth century inaugural addresses as examples of devotion to constitutional form and principle in presidential communications, though he ventures far beyond the inaugural address to consider the historical significance of other forms of presidential rhetoric. 12 Tulis's criticism countered much of the presidential scholarship that has developed since the publication of Richard Neustadt's Presidential Power, a supremely influential work in the modem study of political science and American politics.' 3 Neustadt posited that the American President's real power was one of persuasion and one that ultimately favored the President in conflicts among institutions, (what Tulis Thurow, and Joseph M. Bessette introduce the idea. See James W. Ceasar et al., The Rise of the RhetoricalPresidency, PRESIDENTIAL STUD. Q., Spring 1981, at 158. 9. See TULIS, supra note 8, at 17-23. 10. See Glen E. Thurow, Dimensions of Presidential Character, in BEYOND THE RHETORICAL PRESIDENCY 15, 22-24 (Martin J. Medhurst ed., 1996). 11. TULIS, supra note 8, at 18; see also TERRY EASTLAND, ENERGY IN THE EXECUTIVE: THE CASE FOR THE STRONG PRESIDENCY 29-30 (1992) (observing that Wilson's view of "'constitutional government' was not government according to the original Constitution," and that "Wilson also is the source of problems that have plagued the presidency especially in more recent decades"). For a different perspective on Wilson's impact, see Terri Bimes & Stephen Skowronek, Woodrow Wilson's Critique of Popular Leadership: Reassessing the Modern-Traditional Divide in Presidential History, in SPEAKING TO THE PEOPLE: THE RHETORICAL PRESIDENCY IN HISTORICAL PERSPECTIVE 134 (Richard J. Ellis ed., 1998). 12. TULIS, supra note 8, at 47-51. 13. RICHARD E. NEUSTADT, PRESIDENTIAL POWER (1960). QUINNIPIAC LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:265 describes as "institutional partisanship" 14) institutions that are not actually separated by constitutional function or power but rather share powers even as they are separate.15 Pursuant to Neustadt's paradigm, Presidents exercise their persuasive powers in aggressive ways through personal, as opposed to formal constitutional, bargaining methods, ultimately placing the President in a preferred position among the other institutional bargainers. 1 6 This paradigm further spurred the development of a behavioralist approach to studying the presidency and political institutions more generally; the notion that informal, even extraconstitutional, acts of "leadership" mean more than formal ones in terms of political causation. 7 Subsequently, some, like Samuel Kemell, have distinguished Neustadt's bargaining presidency with another modem, extra-constitutional development: that of appealing directly to the masses for support of a presidential initiative, what Professor Kemell has called "going public." 18 Against these approaches to popular rhetorical leadership in the presidency, Tulis (among others 19) set his sights on restoring presidential devotion to the formal duties of, and limits on, the office. Since The Rhetorical Presidency, scholars in political science and public communication have debated the merits of Tulis's assertions and his description of the two presidencies, and particularly his assertion that the nineteenth-century presidencies (save for Andrew Johnson) best reflect the Framers' design of an executive whose governance would be driven by constitutional formalities rather than popular appeals and advocacy of specific policy preferences. 20 David Nichols, for example, argues that Tulis's construct fails to account for the contentions of constitutional framers like James Wilson and Gouverneur Morris, whose work at the Constitutional Convention reveals the desire for a President who would engage in some form of popular leadership that would be consistent with the constitutional presidency that Tulis identifies.21 14. 15. 16. Id. at 9-13. See generally id. at 33-57. See id. 17. See, e.g., ROBERT A. DAHL, A PREFACE TO DEMOCRATIC THEORY (1956). 18. SAMUEL KERNELL, GOING PUBLIC: NEW STRATEGIES OF PRESIDENTIAL LEADERSHIP 1-2 (4th ed. 2007). In Professor Kernell's view, going public is fundamentally incompatible with presidential bargaining. Id. at 4-5. 19. See, e.g., EASTLAND, supra note 11, at 7 (arguing that although Neustadt proposes a realist understanding of the presidency, the approach "needs to be more securely grounded in the Constitution"). 20. See TULIS, supra note 8, at 27-33. 21. See David K. Nichols, A MarriageMade in Philadelphia:The Constitution and the 2010] CONSTITUTIONAL STATESMANSHIP Other political scientists have suggested that the nineteenth-century Presidents more often engaged in political advocacy to popular audiences than Tulis admits.22 Still others have used Tulis's construct to evaluate trends in presidential rhetoric related to style and usage,23 or cited the construct approvingly to analyze particular instances of contemporary presidential oratory.24 In addition, communication experts, tracing rhetorical theory to Aristotle-including Aristotle's description of the three sources of persuasion that speakers may employ (ethos, logos, and pathos) and of the ways in which rhetoric "is deeply implicated in how human beings come to know and act upon their world" 25-have considered and challenged Tulis's thesis by focusing instead on the broader impact of presidential communications and the ways in which language, rhetoric, and new media shape the presidency and presidential action.2 6 Even if we accept the very plausible notion that the constitutional Rhetorical Presidency, in SPEAKING TO THE PEOPLE: THE RHETORICAL PRESIDENCY IN HISTORICAL PERSPECTIVE, supra note 11, at 16, 19-34. Tulis responds that, in both design and subsequent practice, the American presidency owes more to Hamilton than to Wilson and Morris. See Jeffrey K. Tulis, Reflections on the Rhetorical Presidency in American Political Development, in SPEAKING TO THE PEOPLE: THE RHETORICAL PRESIDENCY IN HISTORICAL PERSPECTIVE, supra note 11, at 211, 212-14. Tulis, in The Rhetorical Presidency, worries that a more robust conception of popular leadership is inconsistent with the Founders' fear of demagogues. See TULIS, supra note 8, at 27-33. 22. See, e.g., MEL LARACEY, PRESIDENTS AND THE PEOPLE: THE PARTISAN STORY OF GOING PUBLIC 122-71 (2002); Richard J. Ellis & Alexis Walker, Policy Speech in the Nineteenth Century Rhetorical Presidency: The Case of Zachary Taylor's 1849 Tour, PRESIDENTIAL STUD. Q., June 2007, at 248. I also note that Professor Tulis asserts in The Rhetorical Presidency that Zachary Taylor did not mention the Constitution in his inaugural address. See TULIS, supra note 8, at 51. This, however, is not accurate; Taylor mentions the Constitution at least four times. See Zachary Taylor, Inaugural Address (Mar. 5, 1849), in INAUGURAL ADDRESSES OF THE PRESIDENTS OF THE UNITED STATES, supra note 7, at 111, 111-14. 23. See, e.g., Chad Murphy, The Evolution of the Modern Rhetorical Presidency: A Critical Response, PRESIDENTIAL STUD. Q., June 2008, at 300; Ryan L. Teten, Evolution of the Modern RhetoricalPresidency:PresidentialPresentationand Development of the State of the Union Addresses, PRESIDENTIAL STUD. Q., June 2003, at 333. 24. See, e.g., George F. Will, Rhetorical Presidency, NEWSWEEK, Feb. 8, 1993, at 74 (evaluating Tulis's work and applying the construct to President Clinton's initial State of the Union Address). 25. Martin J. Medhurst, Afterword: The Ways of Rhetoric, in BEYOND THE RHETORICAL PRESIDENCY, supra note 10, at 218, 221. 26. See, e.g., Thomas W. Benson, Desktop Demos: New Communication Technologies and the Future of the Rhetorical Presidency, in BEYOND THE RHETORICAL PRESIDENCY, supra note 10, at 50; Roderick P. Hart & Kathleen E. Kendall, Lyndon Johnson and the Problem of Politics: A Study in Conversation, in BEYOND THE RHETORICAL PRESIDENCY, supra note 10, at 77. 270 QUINNIPIAC LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:265 framework supports or encourages some limited, moderate form of popular leadership,2 7 the problem against which Tulis and other followers of a constitutionalist presidential construct chiefly inveigh is the more extreme form of popular leadership that is not tethered to constitutional text or structure, or to legitimate efforts at civic education about republican principles. Rather, it is one that Presidents employ in order to persuade, to amass legislative and political achievements, appear sensitive to public needs and desires, and ensure a positive reputation and legacy. Of course, the problem is not limited merely to presidential speech making. It rears its head in other contexts. Modem presidents have used the veto power not simply as a shield to raise constitutional objections to legislation or to protect the prerogatives of the presidency, but as a sword to dictate the content of legislation and to satisfy the President's policy preferences-his "agenda" or "program"-and as leverage to compel obedience to those preferences by Members of Congress who for political reasons may need the public support of the President. 28 The presidency now occupies not just an important role but also a preferred place in the creation, development, and enactment of national legislation, and presidents typically enter office with a detailed legislative agenda that they actively promote by "going public" and by 27. See infra Part II.A. David Nichols's argument concerning a constitutional basis for popular presidential leadership based on the work of Wilson and Morris is persuasive, as far as it goes. See Nichols, supra note 21, at 19-34. To be sure, Nichols is correct that Wilson and Morris were leaders at the Convention and their service on the Committee of Detail gave them some influence in the final wording of the constitutional text. See id. at 28. But Nichols perhaps overstates this influence, and he undervalues important moments at the Convention when their proposals for a much stronger President-and a President more prone to popular leadership-were defeated. For example, Wilson (along with Hamilton) supported an absolute, rather than qualified veto; it was rejected. See 2 THE RECORDS OF THE FEDERAL CONVENTION OF 1787, at 586-87 (Max Farrand ed., 1966). Wilson also supported a proposal for the Council of Revision, which would have joined the president and the judiciary in evaluating legislation before its enactment. See I THE RECORDS OF THE FEDERAL CONVENTION OF 1787, at 97-98, 105 (Max Farrand ed., 1966). This proposal, too, was defeated. Id. at 104, 140; 2 THE RECORDS OF THE FEDERAL CONVENTION OF 1787, supra, at 80. This is not to diminish the significance of Wilson's work at the Convention or his importance to the Founding generation, which is substantial; it is, rather, to say that despite his influence, Wilson did not really get the presidency he sought. Of course, neither did Hamilton, for that matter, but Hamilton did not assert his views nearly as often as Wilson during the Convention, and during ratification and thereafter, it was Hamilton who came to define the character of the American executive. See Tulis, supra note 21, at 212-14. In this sense, then, I think Tulis has the better of the argument. 28. See KERNELL, supra note 18, at 62-65; J. Richard Broughton, Rethinking the PresidentialVeto, 42 HARV. J. ON LEGIS. 91, 131-33 (2005). 2010] CONSTITUTIONAL STATESMANSHIP making the institution appear more democratic than it is. 2 9 The phenomenon has become so powerful that some scholars have referred to the President as the "legislator-in-chief," language that suggests Congress has been displaced in this regard.3 ° Still others have explained the phenomenon as the "deconstitutionalization" of the presidency, attributable in significant part both to the Wilsonian rejection of formal separated powers and to the proclivity for mass appeal to public sentiment that characterizes the modem presidency and distinguishes it from the formal, constitutional presidency that the Framers designed.3 ' Still, particularly in an age in which Presidents can not only travel the Nation and the world easily to speak directly to the public, but can have those speeches made instantaneously available to the remainder of the country through modem technology, it is unlikely that presidential speech making to mass, non-governmental audiences will fade away. This is especially true when one considers the influential role of modem, professional communications and speech-writing staffs in the White House, who carefully craft a democratic presidential "message" to assure its appeal to American voters and to legitimize a President's boast of providing "leadership." '32 The trick, then, is to accept the reality of a rhetorical presidency, and yet to constitutionalize (or perhaps reconstitutionalize) the rhetoric. But it would be a neat trick, for reconstitutionalizing the presidency means making it less democratic, increasing the distance between the President and the Congress and between the President and the people; 33 yet a strategy of mass public communication seems necessarily to close that distance (indeed, closing that distance seems to be among the very purposes of the strategy). Modem Presidents, keen on the allure of public opinion and the anticipated blessings it has in store for their sense of reputations and 29. See generally KERNELL, supra note 18. 30. See Vasan Kesavan & J. Gregory Sidak, The Legislator-in-Chief,44 WM. & MARY L. REV. 1 (2002). 31. See ROGER M. BARRUS ET AL., THE DECONSTITUTIONALIZATION OF AMERICA: THE FORGOTTEN FRAILTIES OF DEMOCRATIC RULE 105-09 (2004). 32. See TULIS, supra note 8, at 184-86. For excellent scholarly coverage of speechwriting and communications in the modem White House, see generally PRESIDENTIAL SPEECH-WRITING (Kurt Ritter & Martin J. Medhurst eds., 2003). 33. Harvey Mansfield describes this as "constitutional space," which is necessary to avoid the extremes and dangers of democracy. See HARVEY C. MANSFIELD, JR., AMERICA'S CONSTITUTIONAL SOUL 16 (1991). In addition, as Glen Thurow writes, "[r]eplacing the Constitution by a direct relationship between the president and the people has been intended to perhaps superficially strengthen the presidential office. In fact, however, it has undermined it." Thurow, supra note 10, at 29. QUINNIPIAC LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:265 success of their preferred program, have forgotten Alexander Hamilton's observation that while republicanism requires "the deliberate sense of the community" to govern the people, "it does not require an unqualified complaisance to every sudden breeze of passion, or to every transient impulse which the people may receive from the arts of men, who flatter their prejudices to betray their interests., 34 Ultimately, only when their leaders have acted upon "cool and sedate reflection," the people may be grateful for men "who had courage and magnanimity enough to serve them at the peril of their displeasure. 35 Tulis, clarifying and revising his original construct, sees possibilities for "reconstitutionalizing political discourse., 3 6 He urges, for example, that Presidents: use their rhetoric to hold Congress accountable for driving a domestic legislative agenda and for engaging in greater deliberation (Tulis suggests that "[t]he State of the Union address would be an especially apt vehicle"); encourage Congress to respond to presidential rhetoric in formal writings; and raise constitutional questions about particular policies or proposals. These suggestions, Tulis explains, are simply a desirable course for pursuing "a new kind of presidential rhetoric and [a] new civic education. 3 8 Indeed they are.39 34. THE FEDERALIST No. 71, at 459 (Alexander Hamilton) (Benjamin Fletcher Wright ed., 1961). 35. Id. at 459-60. 36. Jeffrey K. Tulis, Revising the RhetoricalPresidency, in BEYOND THE RHETORICAL PRESIDENCY, supra note 10, at 1, 13. Kevin Yenerall has also suggested that the rhetorical presidency is not inconsistent with the constitutional presidency, though his analysis is somewhat different from the one I urge here. Professor Yenerall argues that there are events that occur in political life that require the President to marry action with public speech, and cites events that implicate constitutional issues. See Kevin M. Yenerall, Executing the Rhetorical Presidency: William Jefferson Clinton, George W. Bush, and the Contemporary Face of PresidentialPower, in EXECUTING THE CONSTITUTION: PUTTING THE PRESIDENT BACK INTO THE CONSTITUTION 127 (Christopher S. Kelley ed., 2006). More recently, Jedediah Purdy has thoughtfully explained the role of presidential rhetoric in constitutional interpretation. See Jedediah Purdy, PresidentialPopular Constitutionalism,77 FORDHAM L. REv. 1837 (2009). 37. See Tulis, supra note 36, at 10-13. 38. Id. at 13. 39. I am grateful to David Marion for his repeated, sage reminder that leading Founders were in the business of both institution-creation and civic education, as indicated, for example, by George Washington's Farewell Address, John Marshall's biography of Washington, and Ben Franklin's Autobiography. See George Washington, Farewell Address (Sept. 17, 1796), in PRESIDENTIAL DOCUMENTS 18 (J.F. Watts & Fred Israel, eds., 2000); JOHN MARSHALL, THE LIFE OF GEORGE WASHINGTON (Robert K. Faulkner & Paul Carrese, eds., Liberty Fund 2000) (1850); BENJAMIN FRANKLIN, THE AUTOBIOGRAPHY OF BENJAMIN FRANKLIN (Louis P. Masur, ed., Bedford Books 1993) (1793). 2010] CONSTITUTIONAL STATESMANSHIP In light of the reality that modem Presidents speak publicly and often, and in light of the (at least potential) connection between presidential speech-making and constitutionalism, this subject matter ought to have a place not simply in the scholarship of political science and rhetoric but also in legal scholarship, where it deserves greater attention and development. In addition to its consideration in legal scholarship, the literature needs an affirmative call for constitutional reflection, discourse, and even interpretation in the inaugural address, a call that finds justification in the specific provisions of the Constitution that support and compel constitutional deliberation and interpretation by the President, and in a structural theory of the energetic executive. Developing this kind of scholarship related to the rhetorical presidency in the legal literature not only serves to highlight the importance of the connection between rhetoric and constitutionalism, it also serves to put the legal profession in greater touch with the deliberative processes of constitutional reflection and interpretation that occur outside of the judiciary. Although some excellent recent legal scholarship has developed around this notion, 40 American constitutional law remains dominated by a focus on courts and adjudication. This is particularly visible in the constitutional law canon, which overwhelmingly gives its attention to judicial review and the role of courts in determining constitutional meaning. 41 Perhaps this is unremarkable. Perhaps it is a product of the persistence of judicial supremacy theory, or the increasing prevalence of the Supreme Court's unabashed assertions of its core review function, which have diminished the strength of those doctrines 40. See, e.g., NEAL DEVINS & Louis FISHER, THE DEMOCRATIC CONSTITUTION (2004); MARK TUSHNET, TAKING THE CONSTITUTION AWAY FROM THE COURTS (1999); Larry Alexander & Frederick Schauer, On ExtrajudicialConstitutionalInterpretation, 110 HARV. L. REV. 1359 (1997); Scott E. Gant, Judicial Supremacy and Nonjudicial Interpretation of the Constitution, 24 HASTINGS CONST. L.Q. 359 (1997); Neal Kumar Katyal, Legislative Constitutional Interpretation, 50 DUKE L.J. 1335 (2001); Gary Lawson & Christopher D. Moore, The Executive Power of ConstitutionalInterpretation,81 IOWA L. REV. 1267 (1996); Robert Post & Reva Siegel, Popular Constitutionalism, Departmentalism, and Judicial Supremacy, 92 CAL. L. REV. 1027 (2004); Purdy, supra note 36, at 1838-39. 41. A review of the leading casebooks in Constitutional Law shows that although some of the texts now devote a small portion of materials to constitutional interpretation by nonjudicial actors (perhaps as a response to the increased literature in this area), this treatment still does not approximate the frequency with which the political branches engage in constitutional review. See generally, e.g., DANIEL A. FARBER ET AL., CASES AND MATERIALS ON CONSTITUTIONAL LAW: THEMES FOR THE CONSTITUTION'S THIRD CENTURY (4th ed. 2009); RONALD D. ROTUNDA, MODERN CONSTITUTIONAL LAW: CASES AND NOTES (9th ed. 2009); JONATHAN D. VARAT ET AL., CONSTITUTIONAL LAW: CASES AND MATERIALS (13th ed. 2009). QUINNIPIAC LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:265 designed to limit judicial review.42 Alternatively, perhaps it is simply a reflection of Tocqueville's dictum that in America all political questions ultimately become judicial ones.43 Yet many important issues of constitutional meaning are analyzed and debated in the political branches long before they ever appear in the four comers of a judicial opinion or case reporter. A court-centered canon may ultimately be appropriate, but lawyers and law teachers must better appreciate and convey to new generations of lawyers the ways that political actors deliberate, and reach conclusions, about the Constitution and about the allocation of constitutional power. This Article seeks to add this new dimension to the scholarship on this subject and place it within the lawyer's scholarly toolbox, where it ought to command greater attention. This Article therefore argues that, in light of its connection to the presidential oath and the conferring of formal constitutional power, the presidential inaugural address can serve as an important constitutional moment in the life of a presidency. Drawing on literature from the fields of political science and public communication, this Article seeks to engage the construct of The Rhetorical Presidency, and the plausible constitutionalism of the presidential inaugural, within the realm of legal scholarship by advocating a constitutionalized and constitutionalist model for these unique moments. Presidents should seize the opportunity at the outset of their administration, through the inaugural address, to reflect on formal constitutional arrangements and articulate their understanding of the nature and scope of their constitutional powers, and of the President's institutional relationship to the other branches of government and to the people. In this way, the inaugural address becomes more than just a national rhetorical exercise designed to arouse public support for an administration's priorities or to employ historically significant language. 42. I have referred elsewhere to the Court's sense of its own "omnipotence" in connection with aggressive judicial review in some prominent areas of constitutional adjudication. J. Richard Broughton, JudicializingFederativePower, 11 TEX. REV. L. & POL. 283 (2007); see Rachel E. Barkow, More Supreme Than Court? The Fall of the Political Question Doctrine and the Rise of JudicialSupremacy, 102 COLUM. L. REv. 237, 335 (2002) (arguing that the Court's diminution of the political question doctrine threatens to "disrupt our constitutional order and turn the Framers' vision of a constitutional conversation among three coordinate branches into a monologue by the Supreme Court"); Richard A. Posner, Foreword: A Political Court, 119 HARV. L. REv. 31, 56 (2005) (remarking on the lack of judicial modesty in the contemporary Court). 43. See I ALEXIS DE TOCQUEVILLE, DEMOCRACY IN AMERICA 248 (J.P. Mayer & Max Lemer eds., George Lawrence trans., Harper & Row 1966) (1835) ("There is hardly a political question in the United States which does not sooner or later turn into a judicial one."). 2010] CONSTITUTIONAL STATESMANSHIP Rather, it becomes a highly public and highly visible institutional tool for instantiating executive energy and for engaging in a responsible form of civic education. Consequently, though not itself a formal power identified in or required by the constitutional text, the inaugural address can invigorate the modem presidency's devotion to the forms of the Constitution, transforming the address from an important rhetorical moment into a constitutional one and demonstrating that constitutional discourse is compatible with the rhetorical realities of modem political life. II. CONSTITUTIONAL DISCOURSE IN THE INAUGURAL ADDRESS It is hardly remarkable to observe that Presidents ought to deliberate, and offer conclusions about, the meaning of the Constitution (even if some do it better and more often than others), or that the presidency should be energetic. These characteristics of the presidency are core features of my proposal here, because they are core features of a constitutional presidency that I (and other like-minded scholars) seek to reinvigorate; but they are not the sum of it. Rather, when we talk about an energetic executive and about constitutional deliberation, reflection, and interpretation in the presidency, we tend to talk about them in terms of official presidential action, for example, when the President exercises the veto, or asserts executive privilege, or makes decisions concerning the exercise of war or foreign affairs power. We tend not to talk about this aspect of presidential structure and function, at least not substantively, in the context of presidential rhetoric or communication. We should, and we should start with the first and one of the most significant of all rhetorical moments in the life of a presidency: the inaugural address. Constitutional deliberation in the inaugural address can demonstrate the President's understanding of his powers, as well as those of the coordinate branches, and thus publicly acknowledge formal constraints on presidential power, as well as formal bases for robust presidential action. History, as I explain later, provides ample precedent." More importantly, elevating presidential inaugural rhetoric to constitutional discourse promotes the President's obligation to preserve, protect, and defend the Constitution, instantiates the kind of energetic executive that leading Framers contemplated, and enhances the public's understanding and appreciation of constitutional government. 44. See infra Part III.A. 276 A. QUINNIPIAC [Vol. 28:265 LAW REVIEW The InauguralAddress as a ConstitutionalMoment Although Bruce Ackerman has described "constitutional moments" as rare, extraordinary occasions in American political life (the Founding, the Civil War and Reconstruction, and the New Deal),45 Paul Horwitz challenged that notion by concluding that constitutional moments are "momentous, but they are not irregular. 4 6 Professor Horwitz identifies presidential transitions as constitutional moments, whereby the new President takes the constitutional oath and thus creates "a moment in which at least one branch of the federal government must consider anew what the Constitution means and what it demands, and ratify or rescind the constitutional readings that have come before., 47 Although he concedes that Professor Ackerman may have been describing a different kind of phenomenon-one transformative of constitutional meaningHorwitz explains that the distinctions between his understanding of presidential transitions and the rare Ackermanian moments exist but do not undermine his conclusions.48 Perhaps, then, we can simply call them what we will: constitutional moments, constitutional minimoments, or constitutional momentettes. Descriptive labels aside, Professor Horwitz's point is well taken: instances of constitutional significance are frequent in American political life. I would add the following contributions to this important conversation: those instances should occur even more frequently, they should occur more frequently in the political branches, and Presidents can contribute to such increased frequency by using the inaugural address-one of these moments-as an initial statement of constitutional understanding and principle that will guide that President's administration. Unlike the oath, the Constitution does not require the inaugural address. But every President who has held a formal inauguration has joined an address to the taking of the oath, at which point constitutional power is vested in the oath-taker. As Jedediah Purdy has recently described the inaugural addresses, they "form a genre-specific time-slice of presidential popular constitutionalism as old as the Constitution 45. 1 BRUCE ACKERMAN, WE THE PEOPLE: FOUNDATIONS ACKERMAN, WE THE PEOPLE: TRANSFORMATIONS (1998). (1991); 2 BRUCE 46. Paul Horwitz, Honor's Constitutional Moment: The Oath and Presidential Transitions, 103 Nw. U. L. REV. COLLOQUY 259, 259 (2008). 47. Id. 48. Id. at 260-61. 2010] CONSTITUTIONAL STATESMANSHIP itself."49 William Henry Harrison said he was about to give a speech "in obedience to a custom coeval with our government." 50 His grandson Benjamin Harrison famously said that although the Constitution does not require a public oath, "there is so manifest an appropriateness in the public induction to office of the chief executive officer of the nation that from the beginning of the Government the people ... have been called to witness the solemn ceremonial.' Hamilton, in a letter to George Washington dated just after Washington's inauguration, described a plan for presidential entertainment that highlights the significance of the event. He wrote that the President should "give formal entertainments" only two or four times a year, and if twice, to include Independence Day and Inauguration Day "which completed the organization of the Constitution."5 2 Although Hamilton makes no reference to a presidential speech, and it is unremarkable today that he viewed Inauguration Day as a special ceremonial time, what is noteworthy is that his letter connects the inauguration ceremony to the Constitution. Given its temporal connection to an oath that substantively requires the President to "preserve, protect and defend the Constitution, '5 3 and its historical place in a formalized process of conferring constitutional power, then, we can say that the inaugural address, though not a constitutional mandate, ought at least to be viewed as a constitutional, as well as political, tradition-and a constitutional moment, as scholars like 54 Professor Horwitz understand the notion. In this context, a highly public one, the inaugural address represents a unique opportunity for the President to assert his understanding of constitutional prerogatives and limits. It is televised to the Nation and world, delivered before hundreds of thousands of onlookers in Washington, and perhaps most importantly, represents the culmination of a public constitutionalprocess by which the newly elected President obtains the full force of his constitutional powers. Following on the heels of completing the oath, there is no better time-indeed, this is the ideal time-for the President to clarify his understanding of the governing instrument he has just sworn to preserve, protect, and defend. 49. Purdy, supra note 36, at 1844. 50. Harrison, supra note 7, at 79. 51. Benjamin Harrison, Inaugural Address (Mar. 4, 1889), in INAUGURAL ADDRESSES OF THE PRESIDENTS OF THE UNITED STATES, supra note 7, at 175, 175. 52. Letter from Alexander Hamilton to George Washington, President (May 5, 1789), in ALEXANDER HAMILTON: WRITINGS 515, 516 (Library of America 2001) (1961). 53. U.S. CONST. art. II, § 1, cl. 8. 54. See Horwitz, supranote 46. QUINNIPIAC LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:265 In other words, the inaugural address is the ideal time for the President to clarify his understanding of the powers the Constitution has now conferred upon him and those that belong to the other branches of government with which he will work and against whose encroachments he will fight. A constitutionalized inaugural address would also serve the interests of responsible civic education, in the sense that it could cultivate the public's attachment to constitutional rule and inform the citizenry of the necessity of formal arrangements designed to avoid the pitfalls of democracy.5 5 This is not to say that the inaugural address is the only way for a President to assert a constitutional vision or engage in the process of constitutional interpretation. There are other methods, as well. Some occur in the course of official acts-for example, exercising the veto power,56 presidential signing statements,57 delivering messages to Congress,5 8 asserting executive privilege,5 9 and appointing judges.60 55. See BARRUS ETAL., supra note 31, at 7-8. As I have previously argued, the veto is an especially important institutional tool for presidential constitutional interpretation and must be employed when a President objects to legislation as unconstitutional. See Broughton, supra note 28, at 110-15. Article I, Section 7 explicitly requires the president to give his reasons for the return of legislation, so the veto operates naturally as an example of how presidential constitutional interpretation can occur in the course of fulfilling an official institutional function. See U.S. CONST. art I, § 7, cl. 2. 57. For excellent discussions of signing statements and their constitutional significance, see Curtis A. Bradley & Eric A. Posner, Presidential Signing Statements and Executive Power, 23 CONST. COMMENT. 307 (2006); Neal Devins, Signing Statements and Divided Government, 16 WM. & MARY BILL RTS. J. 63 (2007); Christopher S. Kelley, The Significance of the Presidential Signing Statement, in EXECUTING THE CONSTITUTION: 56. PUTTING THE PRESIDENT BACK INTO THE CONSTITUTION, supra note 36, at 73. The Constitution does not direct the President to give his reasons for signing a bill. See U.S. CONST. art I, § 7, cl. 2. Yet the presidential signing statement, which Presidents of both the Republican and Democratic parties, and Presidents since James Monroe, have employed as a regular part of the presidency, has become the subject of much controversy in recent years. See, e.g., Bradley & Posner, supra, at 308, 312-13. This controversy has derived chiefly from using the signing statement to identify portions of the signed legislation that the president will not enforce either because he objects to them as a matter of policy or because he believes them to be unconstitutional. See, e.g., id. at 313. Putting aside the ongoing debate over the propriety of this practice, what is significant for our purposes here is that the signing statement has become a modem device for active presidential assertion of constitutional meaning. 58. Primarily I have in mind here the annual State of the Union message. See TuLIS, supranote 8, at 55-59. 59. See Mark J. Rozell, Executive Privilege in an Era of Polarized Politics, in EXECUTING THE CONSTITUTION: PUTTING THE PRESIDENT BACK INTO THE CONSTITUTION, supra note 36, at 91. 60. See generally HENRY J. ABRAHAM, JUSTICES, PRESIDENTS, AND SENATORS: A HISTORY OF THE U.S. SUPREME COURT APPOINTMENTS FROM WASHINGTON TO CLINTON (1999) (explaining how Presidents express constitutional views though judicial appointments). 20101 CONSTITUTIONAL STATESMANSHIP Others, as Jedediah Purdy has elegantly explained, occur in the ordinary, and sometimes extraordinary, courses of presidential communication in modem America.6 1 Constitutional deliberation and interpretation by non-judicial actors has been the subject of substantial scholarly attention in the last two decades, particularly after Attorney General Edwin Meese's speech and law review article in 1987 that rejected the notion of judicial supremacy in the enterprise.62 Today scholars often refer to the phenomenon as "popular constitutionalism. ' 63 Of course, it is "popular" only in the sense that it is performed by actors in the elected branches of the government, not in the sense that it is subject to plebiscite. How well those actors in the political branches reflect upon and interpret the Constitution is an important question, but one for another time, and one that other scholars have addressed.64 For present purposes, the more important observation here is that the Constitution provides a basis for presidential constitutional interpretation, that the President has a special constitutional obligation to do it, and that the inaugural address is, and ought to be, a unique platform for performing it. The Constitution provides in the Take Care Clause that the 65 President shall "take care that the laws be faithfully executed., Writing as Pacificus in defense of President Washington's declaration of neutrality in the war between France and England, Hamilton posited that, "[t]he President is the constitutional executor of the laws .... He who is to execute the laws must first judge for himself of their ,,66 wsi meaning. Hamilton was, in this context, referring specifically to international law and treaties, but his contention applies equally to any other "law of the land," including the Constitution. 67 Perhaps, though, the Oath Clause provides the most important source of authority for 61. See Purdy, supra note 36, at 1842-63 (giving examples of constitutional discourse in presidential rhetoric beyond the inaugural). 62. See Edwin Meese III, The Law of the Constitution, 61 TUL. L. REv. 979 (1987). For a thoughtful account of the scholarly and political responses to Meese's view, see DEVINS & FISHER, supra note 40, at 3-7, 26-28. 63. See, e.g., Purdy, supra note 36, at 1839. 64. See, e.g., Louis Fisher, ConstitutionalInterpretationby Members of Congress, 63 N.C.L. REv. 707 (1985); Katyal, supra note 40, at 1335. 65. See U.S. CONST. art. II, § 3. 66. See Alexander Hamilton, Pacificus No. 1 (June 29, 1793), reprinted in ALEXANDER HAMILTON: WRITINGS, supra note 52, at 801, 809 (emphasis omitted). 67. See Saikrishna Bangalore Prakash, The Executive's Duty to Disregard UnconstitutionalLaws, 96 GEO. L.J. 1613, 1617 (2008) (stating that the Constitution is a law for Take Care Clause purposes, as it is elsewhere recognized as "the Supreme Law of the Land"). QUINNIPIAC LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:265 presidential constitutional deliberation and interpretation. To put it more accurately, perhaps the Oath Clause read in conjunction with the Take Care Clause signifies fully the justification for a President's efforts to understand and articulate the meaning of the Constitution.68 Some worthwhile scholarship on the meaning of the presidential oath exists, and commentators have ascribed diverse purposes to it. Robert Blomquist has neatly surveyed the competing visions of the oath, explaining that scholars had concluded, for example, that the oath: gives the President special responsibility to preserve the Union; represents a limit on presidential power, as opposed to an affirmative grant of power; permits the President to protect the institution of the presidency from encroachments; and, gives the President a limited power to refuse enforcement of federal laws. 69 More recently, Professor Horwitz thoughtfully analyzed the competing visions of the oath, including the view that it enables the President to preserve the nation even by the use of prerogative and the alternative view that the oath does not permit suspension of the Constitution in order to save it. 70 Horwitz concludes that the presidential oath "like all constitutional oaths, ties [the President's] personal and professional honor to the Constitution, individually and indefeasibly., 71 Whatever the precise function of the oath, though, leading scholars now agree that it offers a textual justification, indeed obligation, for Presidents to grapple with constitutional meaning. 72 Moreover, there does not appear to be any scholarly commentary to suggest that it is to occur only in the course of the President's official acts. Constitutional forms, then, justify discourse and reflection about constitutional forms. Just as the inaugural address is connected in time 68. See id. 69. Robert F. Blomquist, The PresidentialOath, the American National Interest, and a Callfor Presiprudence,73 UMKC L. REV. 1, 37-41 (2004). 70. See Horwitz, supra note 46, at 261-62 (comparing the views of Michael Stokes Paulsen with that of Sai Prakash and Thomas Crocker). 71. Id.at 271. 72. See id. at 264; Gary Lawson, Everything I Need to Know About Presidents I Learnedfrom Dr. Seuss, 24 HARV. J. L. & PUB. POL'Y 381 (2001); Lawson & Moore, supra note 40, at 1287; Sanford Levinson, ConstitutionalProtestantism in Theory and Practice: Two Questionsfor Michael Stokes Paulsen and Onefor His Critics, 83 GEO. L.J. 373 (1994); Michael Stokes Paulsen, The Constitution of Necessity, 79 NOTRE DAME L. REv. 1257 (2004). The conclusion may seem pedestrian today, but it is worth recalling, as do Professors Lawson and Moore, that not so long ago a defense of presidential constitutional interpretive power (which was Attorney General Meese's view) was ridiculed as inconsistent with the rule of law and the special province of the judiciary to decide the Constitution's meaning. See Lawson & Moore, supra note 40, at 1268. 20101 CONSTITUTIONAL STATESMANSHIP and space to the constitutional oath of office, so, too, can it be connected to the very authority that the oath confers. In addition, like official presidential acts and other presidential speeches, the inaugural address ought to command the same recognition as a moment of constitutional deliberation and interpretation pursuant to the Oath and Take Care Clauses. Through a constitutionalized inaugural address, the President can tell the other institutions and the American public how he understands the word "faithfully" in the oath he just took and in the Constitution's provision that he execute federal laws. He can elaborate upon his view of what it means to "preserve, protect and defend" the Constitution.73 He can articulate his understanding of the limits on Congress's legislative powers, or his understanding of the scope of those powers and the circumstances under which his Administration will stand behind the constitutionality of a particular congressional enactment, or alert the Congress as to the justifications he may find for refusing to enforce a particular enactment. Just as a constitutionalized, constitutionalist inaugural address serves to make real the kind of executive energy that both supports and moderates presidential action, so too does constitutional discourse in the inaugural address give public rhetorical dimension to a President's understanding of his duty to safeguard the Constitution and to faithfully execute the laws. Of course, in light of these other instances of presidential constitutional interpretation, one may therefore object to the instant proposal on the ground that the inaugural address is unremarkable as a vehicle for constitutional discourse, no more significant than any of these other moments in which the President articulates his understanding of the Constitution. Therefore, the argument goes, the inaugural is better spent on important policy goals, and promoting amity with political rivals, and in inspiring public confidence in the new administration. The response to this critique is two-fold. First, the timing (contemporaneously with the taking of the constitutional oath) and modem ubiquity (thanks to mass communication technology) of the inaugural address set it apart from most other moments of constitutional significance. Although many presidential communications today are televised or otherwise instantly available to members of the public who are not necessarily present when the communication occurs, most of these moments are far less formal and less public, and do not gamer, or 73. U.S. CONST. art. II, § 1, cl. 8; see Horwitz, supra note 46, at 271 (concluding that "the new President must decide for himself what the oath means and what it requires of him"). QUINNIPIAC LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:265 command, the same popular attention that the inaugural does. Under these circumstances of publicity, the constitutionalized-inaugural-ascivic-education model takes on special significance. Second, these Employing constitutional moments are not mutually exclusive. discourse in the inaugural does not mean the President should not employ it in other venues, and employing it in other instances does not preclude its employment in the inaugural. The President should engage in constitutional deliberation and reflection in all of his formal speeches and communications, where appropriate to the occasion and subject matter. If the modem presidency is to remain an institution that is characterized by mass public communication that serves the rhetorical presidency (as I believe it will) then Presidents should employ those public communications more often to serve the interests of the constitutional presidency, as well.74 Still, by acknowledging and affirmatively conducting a dialogue about the formal institutional arrangements of the presidency and of the constitutional system, and by beginning that dialogue from the outset of the Administration in the highly public setting of the inaugural, the President sets a tone and a theme for his presidency that is less likely to undermine those arrangements or that system. Therefore, my proposal is that the inaugural address marks an important beginning of a constitutionalized presidential rhetoric, not an end. Another objection to this proposed inaugural model is one of style, or perhaps tone, rather than substance. One might argue that the inaugural address is meant to be humble, conciliatory, and diplomatic. Particularly when a new President is elected, the taking of the oath and presentation of the inaugural address highlight the peaceful transfer of power. This, one may argue, is hardly the moment for bold assertions on weighty and usually debatable constitutional questions that may alienate, even offend, the coordinate branches, and thereby spoil whatever goodwill the newly elected President has amassed during the campaign and transition. Better, the argument goes again, to leave those battles for another day. The model I propose here, however, need not be offensive or confrontational toward the other branches, the opposing party, or a prior administration. As previous executives have shown, the President can use language that is respectfil of the Congress, the judiciary, and the previous administration while still articulating his own understanding of 74. See Tulis, supra note 36, at 5-6. 2010] CONSTITUTIONAL STATESMANSHIP constitutional principles, his constitutional role, and theirs.7 5 Indeed, such a model places the other branches on notice of the President's intentions and enables the Congress-the Nation, no less-to reflect upon and ultimately respond to the President's assertions. There is no intrinsic constitutional value in merely avoiding conflict between Congress and the President for the sake of avoiding conflict or in promoting amity simply for the sake of promoting amity; because it seeks equilibrium among the powers and promotes, as Madison described it, ambition counteracting ambition, the Constitution actually encourages conflict between them and does not regret a stalemate.76 Therefore, under the proposed model, a respectful but open dialogue about constitutional forms can begin, and it can begin at the appropriate moment-upon the President's highly public affirmation of his duty to faithfully execute his office and to preserve, protect, and defend the Constitution. It is a model for civic education on a grand scale. B. Forms, Leadership, and the Civic Virtues of Constitutional Discourse In calling for a constitutionalized and constitutionalist inaugural address, I do not mean to say that the act becomes part of the Constitution or that the Constitution demands it, but rather that it invokes, that it is grounded in, the Constitution and the President's particular vision of constitutional meaning. Of course, I defend the notion that the address has become a constitutional tradition, and thus stands apart from other presidential addresses (except the State of the Union) in the sense that it is connected to the constitutional oath and is highly public. This is not the same, however, as arguing that the Constitution requires the address in the first instance, which, of course, it does not. Thus, it is constitutionalized in the sense that it invokes the language of the Constitution, and constitutionalist in the sense that it advocates formal constitutional authority and restraint as bases for political action and decision-making. While I have in mind primarily the President's invocation of and 75. See infra Part 111. 76. See THE FEDERALIST No. 51 (James Madison), supra note 34, at 356-57. As Professor Mansfield describes the notion, Madison's argument demonstrates that ambition is "useful, perhaps indispensible" to republican government, and that ambition actually vies with, but does not try to thwart, ambition in the constitutional scheme. See MANSFIELD, supra note 33, at 123. QUINNIPIAC LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:265 reliance upon formal institutional powers and arrangements, and of the republicanism that the Constitution explicitly protects,7 7 this model may certainly also encompass a defense of certain rights that a President understands to be protected by the Constitution, for these also are constitutional forms. President Jefferson, for example, devoted his first inaugural to recognizing rights as well as to republican virtue. 78 Why are forms so important? The law, Justice Scalia reminds us, is about form. 79 Despite this, legal scholarship, political science, and constitutional adjudication have debated for years the competing notions of formalism and functionalism in separation of powers theory.8 ° Students of constitutional law are, in fact, introduced every year to the leading "formalist" cases and the leading "functionalist" cases as described in the constitutional law canon. 81 I propose not (so much) that the President actively articulate and defend the formalist theory of separation of powers, as that theory has been developed among lawyers and legal scholars. Rather the President's focus should be upon giving meaning to, and an understanding of, the hard powers with which the Constitution invests his office (as opposed to the soft powers of public advocacy and bargaining). Why defend the formal in constitutionalism, and in presidential rhetoric in particular, at all? Tocqueville offers a persuasive explanation. Forms, Tocqueville explains, stand in the way of the immediate satisfaction of human wants and, for this reason, men tend to look at forms with skepticism, even 83 rejection. 82 It slows, even prevents, the processes of gratification. "Forms," Tocqueville says, arouse the "disdain" and "hatred" of people 77. 78. See U.S. CONST. art. IV. See Thomas Jefferson, First Inaugural Address in the Washington, D.C. (Mar. 4, 1801), in INAUGURAL ADDRESSES OF THE PRESIDENTS OF THE UNITED STATES, supra note 7, at 13. 79. ANTONIN SCALIA, A MATTER OF INTERPRETATION 25 (1997). 80. Compare Harold H. Bruff, PresidentialPowers and Administrative Rulemaking, 88 YALE L.J. 451 (1979) (advocating functionalist theory), and Martin S. Flaherty, The Most DangerousBranch, 105 YALE L.J. 1725 (1996) (same), with Steven G. Calabresi & Kevin H. Rhodes, The Structural Constitution:Unitary Executive, PluralJudiciary, 105 HARV. L. REV. 1153 (1992) (advocating formal theory), and Gary Lawson, The Rise and Rise of the Administrative State, 107 HARv. L. REV. 1231 (1994) (same). 81. These cases traditionally tend to include, for example, Clinton v. City of New York, 524 U.S. 417 (1998); Mistretta v. United States, 488 U.S. 361 (1989); Morrison v. Olson, 487 U.S. 654 (1988); Bowsher v. Synar, 478 U.S. 714 (1986); and IN.S. v. Chadha, 462 U.S. 919 (1983). 82. TOCQUEVILLE, supra note 43, at 673. 83. Id. at426-31. 2010] CONSTITUTIONAL STATESMANSHIP in democratic societies. 84 "As they usually aspire to none but facile and immediate pleasures, they rush straight at the object of each of their desires, and the slightest delay exasperates them., 85 And yet, Tocqueville understands, "it is just this inconvenience, of which democracies complain, which makes formalities so useful to freedom. For their chief merit is to serve as a barrier between the strong and the weak, the government and the governed. 8 6 Thus, he concludes, "democracies by their nature need formalities more than other peoples and by nature have less respect for them.",87 Following Tocqueville's premise, Professor Harvey Mansfield further reflects on the importance of form to constitutionalism. Institutions like the presidency are forms that "give characteristic dignity, or plain stubbornness, to whomever their incumbents may be." 8 8 These forms promote, among other things, what Mansfield calls "constitutional space," the distance between institutions and between institutions and the people. 89 That distance is necessary for the preservation of safe government in a republic. 90 By elevating extreme versions of popular leadership--the modem presidency's persistent bargaining, legislative maneuvering, and direct appeals to the public to satisfy both public wants and the President's legislative agenda-the presidency eschews forms and narrows the distance between itself, the people, and the legislature. David Nichols identifies the President as legislative agenda-setter, a role that requires the President to not only articulate constitutional principles "but also a set of policies that respond to the problems of contemporary society." 9' There is both historical evidence, which Nichols persuasively describes, and textual evidence for the proposition that a constitutional presidency can support some kind of presidential popular leadership. 92 Perhaps the State of the Union and Recommendation Clauses of Article II and the veto power described in Article I provide a formal constitutional basis for this. These provisions, however, should not be read in isolation; they 84. 85. 86. 87. 88. Id. at 673. Id. TOCQUEVILLE, supra note 43, at 673. Id. See MANSFIELD, supra note 33, at 16. Mansfield's further reflections on the formal in American politics are brilliant, and well worth study by scholars and jurists alike. See, e.g., id. at 137-54. 89. 90. 91. 92. Id. at 16. See id. See Nichols, supra note 21, at 33. Id. at 33-34. QUINNIPIAC LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:265 are only a portion of a larger constitutional structure that seems not to prefer presidential dominance in determining the content of federal legislation, yet the extreme modem form of popular presidential leadership (of which legislative agenda setting is an important component) accomplishes just that. The founding generation understood that legislative power would predominate in a republic. 93 Of course, they feared legislative encroachments and the danger that Congress would draw the other branches into its "impetuous vortex." 94 The answer, however, was not to provide for presidential dominance in setting and carrying out legislative agendas. Rather, it was to create a divided Congress with distinct electoral systems and distinct responsibilities, as well as a constitutional presidency that would counter potential legislative domination in order to give the scheme of government equilibrium (toward the end of promoting competent government). The Framers cared little about efficiency and functionality for the sake of solving the problems of the day; rather, they wanted safety and competence, which is provided by creating institutions with distinct spheres of authority and by cultivating in institutional actors the kind of ambition that would find expression in those spheres and culminate in the responsible use of power. 95 The constitutional text and structure thus provide for barriers against legislative encroachment without inviting presidential dominance in determining the content of national legislation: the division of legislative power into two distinct houses of Congress, the qualified veto, the absence of the Council of Revision, the vesting of enumerated legislative powers in Congress (including power to make all laws "necessary and proper" to carrying constitutional powers into execution), and the vesting of "executive" power (the power to carry out) in the President, along with limited quasi-legislative authority. This is a far cry from a regime in which the President would have predominance in legislative affairs or even in determining the course that legislation should take in Congress. 96 The State of the Union, 93. See, e.g., THE FEDERALIST No. 51 (James Madison), supra note 34. 94. THE FEDERALIST NO. 48 (James Madison), supra note 34, at 343. 95. See I.N.S. v. Chadha, 462 U.S. 919, 958-59 (1983). 96. See Michael B. Rappaport, The President's Veto and the Constitution, 87 Nw. U. L. REv. 735, 759 (1993) (arguing that the Constitution does not favor the president in creating national legislation "as he was not even given equal legislative power with the houses of Congress"). 20101 CONSTITUTIONAL STATESMANSHIP recommendation, and veto powers are thus important exceptions to the general form of legislative predominance (including "agenda-setting") in the Congress, exceptions designed to promote executive energy, stability, and ultimately safety in the government. And because the Framers understood that the Congress would serve as the deliberative branch while a unitary president would have the capacity to act quickly, it is only sensible that they would have given favorable position to Congress in setting legislative agendas, a process that seems to require some significant measure of deliberation. 97 Finally, there is an argument that if the President's "agenda-setting" and other quasi-legislative powers, combined with the use of informal power that could be used to persuade Members of Congress not only to support him but also to squelch a veto override, came to predominate by allowing him to dictate the content of national legislation, he could virtually destroy the essential role of the Congress in the constitutional scheme. One could argue that it is no more legitimate for the President to accomplish this than for the Congress to destroy the essential role of the Supreme Court in the constitutional scheme pursuant to the 98 Exceptions Clause of Article 1II. The President is no clerk of the Congress, but the Congress is no errand boy of the President, either. As I have argued elsewhere, we need not choose between a strong president and a weak Congress, or a weak president and strong Congress; each branch can robustly assert its constitutional prerogatives as well as its understanding of constitutional limits. 99 Again, conflict between the political branches is no vice. So perhaps the better understanding here is to say that the constitutional scheme (and particularly its devotion to energy in the executive), 10 0 supports a moderate form of popular leadership in the presidency, but one always anchored to constitutional text and structure and mindful of the excesses that characterize the problem of demagoguery in a democracy.10 1 If we are to rescue the presidency from 97. See THE FEDERALIST No. 70 (Alexander Hamilton), supra at 34, at 451. 98. This is Henry Hart's famous formulation concerning congressional power to take jurisdiction from the federal courts. See Henry M. Hart, Jr., The Power of Congress to Limit the Jurisdictionof Federal Courts: An Exercise in Dialectic, 66 HARV. L. REV. 1362, 1365 (1953). 99. See Broughton, supra note 42, at 315. 100. 101. excellent CEASER, See infra Part II.C. See TULIS, supra note 8, at 27-33. Professor Tulis describes James Ceaser's account of demagogues, which Ceaser categorizes as soft and hard. See JAMES W. PRESIDENTIAL SELECTION: THEORY AND DEVELOPMENT (1979); TULIS, supra note QUINNIPIAC LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:265 the authoritativeness with which modernity has imbued the extreme version of popular presidential leadership, with its presidential dominance in bargaining, law-creation, and law-making-the soft powers of the modem presidency-while still acknowledging the realities of modem presidential rhetoric in a government whose legitimacy depends upon consent, then we must restore a presidential rhetoric that invokes and meaningfully reflects on the hard powers that the Constitution provides for the presidency and other institutions, powers that make the process of governing more deliberate, less democratic, and less likely to hastily satisfy the instinct for immediate satisfaction and public approbation.10 2 Such a rhetoric may be unappealing to those who prefer such gratification, as well as the comfort and sense of control that comes with an increasingly intimate relationship with elected officials. Yet it is far more likely to serve the interest of responsible civic education by reminding the people of the fragility of democracy and the virtue of constitutional forms that mitigate democratic dangers and provide for safe government. This kind of civic education is not one in which political authority attempts to shape the moral character of citizens in order to assure their obedience to law. Rather, it is one that, to preserve stability and order in a democratic society, soberly assesses human nature, the necessity of institutional arrangements, and the responsible exercise of authority. Moreover, it requires a President who sets an example of, and who publicly articulates, devotion to constitutional rule. C. InstantiatingEnergy in the Executive To understand the presidency, it is most important to understand Hamilton. 103 Ron Chernow's excellent biography of Hamilton rightly 8, at 28. As Tulis reads Ceaser, the common characteristic of all demagogues "seems to be an excess of passionate appeals." TuLIs, supra note 8, at 28. Tulis's understanding of Theodore Roosevelt's presidency arguably reflects the kind of moderate version of popular leadership that avoids demagoguery, although Tulis concedes that Theodore Roosevelt set a precedent that has devolved into the more extreme version. See id. at 114-16. 102. For Professor Tulis's suggestions as to how this can happen, see Tulis, supra note 36, at 5-6, 10-13. Cf Yenerall, supra note 36, at 134-48 (disagreeing that the rhetorical presidency is always detached from constitutional moorings, and describing how recent presidents have used the rhetorical presidency to fulfill institutional duties). 103. On this point, I agree with Karl Walling, who also identifies Edward Corwin and Clinton Rossiter as others who share this view of Hamilton's significance to the presidency. See KARL-FRIEDRICH WALLING, REPUBLICAN EMPIRE: ALEXANDER HAMILTON ON WAR AND FREE GOVERNMENT 123 (1999). 2010] CONSTITUTIONAL STATESMANSHIP asserts that "[i]f Washington was the father of the Country and Madison the father of the Constitution, then Alexander Hamilton was surely the father of the American government."'' 0 4 Hamilton not only authored all of the essays in which Publius explains and defends the executive in the new Constitution, he penned numerous other noteworthy writings on executive power, including the Pacificus essays and advice to Washington on the Whiskey Rebellion. 105 In many of these moments, Hamilton was also President Washington's voice, a kind of Federalistera communications manager. Hamilton thus is an ideal figure to consult in studying the confluence of constitutional structure, presidential rhetoric, and civic education. In Federalist 70, Hamilton makes his famous call for "energy" in the executive, which he says is "a leading character in the definition of good government." 106 While Hamilton was keenly aware of the colonial experience with monarchy and of the objections that were raised to a powerful executive, he was also aware of the failures of the Articles of Confederation, which lacked a national executive. 107 Hamilton therefore seeks to show how an energetic, or "vigorous," executive is consistent with the "genius of republican government."10 8 The key ingredients for an energetic executive are unity (a single executive), duration (substantial time in office and reeligibility), adequate provision for support of the executive (compensation), and competent powers (formal institutional authority vested in the President). 10 9 Hamilton thus sees a vigorous executive as essential to avoiding feeble administration (bad government), but must be careful not to place the President beyond the reach of prudent limits (which Hamilton accomplishes by repeatedly assuring readers that the American President is easily distinguishable from the British monarch). 110 104. RON CHERNOW, ALEXANDER HAMILTON 481 (2004). 105. See id. at 243-69; WALLING, supra note 103, at 123; Letter from Alexander Hamilton to George Washington (Aug. 2, 1794), in ALEXANDER HAMILTON: WRITINGS, supra note 52, at 823. As Professor Walling states, Hamilton "wrote more of enduring relevance about the theory and practice of the presidency than any other Founder." WALLING, supra note 101, at 123. 106. See THE FEDERALIST NO. 70 (Alexander Hamilton), supra note 34, at 451. 107. Consider, for example, Hamilton's many essays critical of the Articles of Confederation, see, e.g., THE FEDERALIST NO. 22 (Alexander Hamilton), supra note 34, at 143-52, as well as his defense of the new executive against charges of monarchism, see, e.g., THE FEDERALIST NO. 73 (Alexander Hamilton), supra note 34, at 444. 108. 109. Id. Id. at451-52. 110. See id. at 451, 456-57. QUINNIPIAC LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:265 What, exactly, does Hamilton's energetic executive look like? What does he mean by "energy" (or "vigor")? With "energy," Hamilton is using the language of natural science, in which "energy" would be understood as action or alacrity. Hamilton, however, is applying the language of natural science to politics, which suggests that its application is more nuanced than the dictionary definition of the term. David F. Epstein elaborates on the scientific origins of energy in Federalist 70, explaining that "its scientific flavor suggests less the aweinspiring omnipotence of a king or god than the application of a certain quantity of force to create a specific motion.""'' But what quantity is sufficient to be truly energetic? Also recognizing Publius's placement of science's "energy" in political discourse, Harvey Mansfield argues that energy "is not something good in itself; it is not virtue," not a claim to rule.112 Rather, it, along with stability, serves as a mode of governing that is regime neutral--"it answers the necessities that any government must face."' 1 3 Still, in our constitutional scheme energy leads to virtue because it helps to make republican government good, as opposed to feeble, as Hamilton describes a government without an energetic To ensure this kind of energetic executive, the executive. 114 Constitution creates an executive that can protect the Constitution in times of emergency and act independently to counter the ambitious encroachments of the other branches (which is to say, the Congress), thus guaranteeing not merely separated political power but safe, stable, and competent government. A certain kind of energy used in a certain kind of way, then, helps to "republicanize" the executive, in Mansfield's words.' 15 Consistent with the idea that there is a close connection, rather than a tension, between constitutionalism and energy, Karl Walling offers an even more comprehensive explanation of Hamilton's energetic executive. Professor Walling explains how Hamilton's defense of an energetic executive--one that had to respond to and answer the complaints of the Anti-Federalists, who feared the new executive would be indistinguishable from a monarch-is consistent with constitutional 111. DAVID F. EPSTEIN, THE POLITICAL THEORY OF THE FEDERALIST 171 (1984). Epstein also offers a compelling look at the way that Publius used "energy" in other contexts, outside of reference to the executive. See id. at 35-58. 112. MODERN 113. 114. 115. See HARVEY C. MANSFIELD, JR., TAMING THE PRINCE: THE AMBIVALENCE OF EXECUTIVE POWER 267 (1989). Id. See THE FEDERALIST NO. 70 (Alexander Hamilton), supra note 34, at 451. MANSFIELD, supra note 112, at 274. 2010] CONSTITUTIONAL STATESMANSHIP limits, with republican safety: energy, understood in this context, is not 16 aggression or vigorous action at the extremes, but moderation.' Drawing on Machiavelli's prescription for a robust executive capable of responding to the dictates of necessity, but careful to note that Hamilton did not endorse Machiavelli's preference for a Roman-style dictatorship, Walling explains that Hamilton joined with Machiavelli in understanding that in a republic executive power must avoid the extremes of constitutional weakness and unrestrained prerogative.'7 "Executive energy was the mean between impotence and usurpation, the extremes that Hamilton believed would necessarily result from a strict construction of executive power."1 1 8 Although Professor Walling uses Hamilton's perspectives on war and foreign affairs-Locke's federative power 9-to clarify this understanding of executive energy," 2 the theory certainly applies in other presidential contexts, particularly when we understand Hamilton's explanation of the ingredients of executive energy. Unity, for example, helps to produce moderation in the executive by enabling the President to protect the Constitution without acting ultra vires. Because action is more important in the executive than in the legislature, Hamilton explains that executive vigor requires decisionmaking by a single individual.12 1 A plural executive would create the danger of differences of opinion, dissent, even civil war. 122 Ever the shrewd student of human nature, Hamilton understood the "danger of personal emulation and even animosity" among men given equal responsibilities, the danger that their sense of personal honor and personal interest would lead them to interfere with the success of the other man. 123 Hamilton calls this a "despicable frailty, or rather detestable vice, in the human character," but one that could frustrate the executive branch in times of necessity. 124 In addition, as Professor Walling explains Hamilton's argument, although in republican government power is generally safer in the hands of many men than of 116. 117. See WALLtNG, supra note 103, at 125. Id. 118. Id. 119. See JOHN LOCKE,THE SECOND TREATISE OF GOVERNMENT 74 (J.W. Gough ed., Macmillan Co. 1980) (1690). 120. See WALLING, supra note 103, at 141-53. 121. THE FEDERALIST NO. 70 (Alexander Hamilton), supra note 34, at 452. 122. 123. 124. Id.at 452-53. Id. at 453. Id. at 454. QUINNIPIAC LAW REVIEW (Vol. 28:265 one, the executive required a different theory: "[w]hen there is only one executive, there is only one to watch. He therefore cannot hide in the anonymity of a crowd."' 125 The President's responsibility, and thus his accountability both to the people and to the Constitution, increases when there is only one. 126 Therefore, unity enhances the "due dependence" that Hamilton described as necessary to republican safety "because it enables the people to hold the executive accountable for the public 27 welfare." 1 Like unity, substantial duration in office is also an ingredient of a moderated, republicanized, constitutionalized executive. Duration, according to Hamilton, connects ambition to the great public purposes of the presidency. 28 The longer the term, the more likely that the person holding the office will dedicate themselves to significant achievements that serve the public interest, projects that will require time to develop, manage, and blossom. 129 "To attract energetic statesmen capable of building America's republican empire, national office had to become13a prize worthy of extraordinary political ambition," Walling writes. 0 This same stability, though, which promotes great action and ambition, also promotes moderation and respect for the Constitution and laws. First, duration promotes executive independence, and here Hamilton invokes the forms of the Constitution. Because in republican government, the tendency is for legislative power to absorb all other power, an executive truly independent of the legislature is necessary to supply the kind of ambition that will be necessary to check that of the legislature, the kind of ambition that animates the formal separation of powers. 131 Second, if ambitious men are unable to remain in office, they 13 2 may seek their achievements in illegitimate or unlawful ways. Hamilton wonders whether peace and stability would be best served by many highly accomplished men, former presidents, "wandering among the people like discontented ghosts, and sighing for a place which they were destined never more to possess?" ' 133 Such a man might convince the people that it is in their interest to give him power in any event, even 125. WALLING, supra note 103, at 130. 126. Id. 127. 128. Id. THE FEDERALIST No. 71 (Alexander Hamilton), supra note 34, at 458. 129. Id. at 458-59. 130. 131. 132. WALLING, supra note 103, at 131. THE FEDERALIST No. 71 (Alexander Hamilton), supra note 34, at 460. THE FEDERALIST No. 72 (Alexander Hamilton), supra note 34, at 466. 133. Id. at 465. 2010] CONSTITUTIONAL STATESMANSHIP 34 unlawfully or in corrupt ways. 1 Finally, Professor Walling describes how the provision for competent powers serves to constitutionalize executive energy, a state of moderation. The Constitution seeks a balance that avoids the extremes of a President who is completely independent of Congress, and thus unaccountable, and one who is completely dependent, and thus unable to act responsibly in asserting his powers, checking congressional ambition, and protecting the Nation in times of emergency or necessity. 135 The qualified veto power, for example, allows the President to exercise independent judgment as to the legality or constitutionality of legislation, and thus to act as a restraint upon popular will and defective or inadequate deliberation; yet his judgment is not absolute and 1is 36 subject to congressional override and makes him publicly accountable (recall that Congress went so far as to censure President Jackson over his exercise of the veto137 ). In giving the pardon power to the President, to cite another example, the Constitution gives additional support to the virtues of unity, as a single person is, according to Hamilton, "better fitted, in delicate conjunctures, to balance the motives which may plead for and against the remission of the punishment."' 38 Because, as Walling observes, Hamilton believed that the pardon power was designed to put an end to revolts, a single executive would be in the best position to "act quickly to end a revolt and thereby restore the rule of law."' 139 Walling then cites the Whiskey Rebellion in western Pennsylvania as an example: President Washington employed a show of force to quell the rebellion, granted a general amnesty for those who pledged their allegiance to the American government, and pardoned the two insurgents who were not protected by the amnesty and who were subsequently convicted of treason, thus ending the rebellion. 40 The pardon power thus gives the President authority to promote, not subvert, reverence for law and civil social order. 134. Id. at 467. 135. See WALLING, supra note 103, at 134. 136. See THE FEDERALIST No. 73 (Alexander Hamilton), supra note 34, at 468-69. 137. See 10 REG. DEB. 58-59 (1834) (statement of Sen. Henry Clay). The censure was later expunged on constitutional grounds. 13 REG. DEB. 503-04 (1837). 138. THE FEDERALIST No. 74 (Alexander Hamilton), supra note 34, at 474. 139. WALLING, supra note 103, at 138. 140. Id. at 138-39. Hamilton's advice to Washington regarding the Whiskey Rebellion is worth careful reading. See Letter from Alexander Hamilton to George Washington, supra note 105, at 823-26. QUINNIPIAC LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:265 In addition, with regard to the powers of war and foreign relations, the Constitution emphatically does not adopt the Lockean taxonomy of power which distinguished federative and executive power yet placed them both in the hands of the executive-some of Locke's federative power was placed in the hands of Congress, such as the power to declare war, to grant letters of marque and reprisal, and to ratify treaties. 141 Yet, as I have previously argued elsewhere, Article II is more Lockean than it may appear at first blush, allowing the President sufficient latitude to act in response to the vicissitudes of chance and necessity and to do so within the framework of republican legality. 142 Hamilton's Pacificus essays demonstrate that he understood this aspect of political and constitutional theory, and give us a much greater window into his understanding of the core meaning of "executive power" than did any of his essays in The Federalist. Countering Madison's fear that Hamilton's understanding of executive (which included federative) power might be used to swallow the powers of war and peace given explicitly to the Congress, and thus was simply a recipe for prerogative or lawlessness, 143 Hamilton grounds his defense of executive powers not on Lockean prerogative but on constitutional text, structure, and theory.' 44 When we examine the ingredients of executive energy, then, and evaluate the presidency in the context of existing forms and institutional responsibilities, we see strong and persuasive support for Professor Walling's conclusion that a truly energetic executive is consistent with Hamilton's (one prone to) constitutionalism, not prerogative. explanation of the ingredients for executive energy "showed that executive energy and republican safety are mutually dependent. No republic can be safe without an energetic executive ....45[Hamilton] made executive energy both constitutional and republican." 1 What, then, is the connection between executive energy, properly understood, and executive rhetoric, particularly in the form of the inaugural? "For the sake of preserving the constitutional rule of law," Walling explains, "one often wishes presidents would not only act but also speak like Hamilton, who preferred for the president to act 141. Compare JOHN LOCKE, Two TREATISES OF GOVERNMENT (Peter Laslett, ed., Cambridge Univ. Press 1993) (1690), with U.S. CONST. art. I, § 8. 142. See Broughton, supra note 42, at 314-16. 143. James Madison, Letters of Helvidius No. 1 (Aug. 24, 1793), reprinted in THE POWER OF THE PRESIDENCY: CONCEPTS AND CONTROVERSY 59, 64 (Robert S. Hirschfield ed., 3rd ed., 1982). 144. See Hamilton, supra note 66, at 803-09. 145. WALLING, supra note 103, at 152-53. CONSTITUTIONAL STATESMANSHIP 2010] energetically within rather than outside the law."' 146 The Constitution's support for executive energy enables Presidents to simultaneously use their energy to act aggressively in fulfilling specific duties and in protecting the Nation, and to assert limits on their own power, and to bolster the enumerated powers of the Congress. The inaugural address offers a unique opportunity to employ executive energy understood in this way, as enabling vigorous action but doing so within the framework of formal proscriptions and arrangements; indeed, to sound like, and to be, constitutionalists. The need for energy in the executive, in fact, arguably supports an inclination toward some moderate form of rhetorical leadership. 147 Again, the question today is not whether Presidents will or ought to speak about their actions. Rather the question is how will they speak? The inaugural address presents an opportunity for the President to be active, to directly assert his independence from the Congress, the projects he will pursue, the legislation he will recommend, and the kind of administration he will direct, and yet to place those aspects of his presidency in the context of constitutional authority. Just as certain aspects of executive energy (such as secrecy and dispatch) are especially useful in meeting the necessities that accompany war and foreign affairs, Presidents can emphasize these characteristics of the office in articulating an approach to issues of federative power, such as by explaining the President's understanding of his commander-in-chief authority, or the extent of his responsibility to defend the Constitution. Moreover, through use of the language of the Constitution, the President can make clear that his view of the office is not unrestrained or lawless, but anchored by specific limitations or grants of power. In this way, the inaugural address can instantiate the energetic executive that the Constitution formalizes and republicanizes, an independent executive who demonstrates both by action and by his popular rhetoric that he takes seriously the formalities of the office. III. THE INAUGURAL ADDRESS IN HISTORICAL PERSPECTIVE It is no fantasy to suggest that the inaugural address can support constitutional discourse and promote a certain kind civic education. The early presidencies, through the Civil War, managed to do so to varying degrees. Of course, some Presidents simply referred to the Constitution 146. Id. at 152. 147. See supra Part II.B. QUINNIPIAC LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:265 briefly or invoked it solely for the purpose of making a general observation about American government or to laud the mechanism for the transfer of power, rather than offer serious reflections on the nature and scope of powers that the Constitution confers. Still, a terse invocation of the Constitution is better than none at all. Moreover, whether Presidents ultimately live up to their constitutionalist rhetoric, or follow their own initial interpretations, remains a different matter. Having advocated a model for the inaugural address that is predicated upon a return to a more faithful commitment to formal constitutional arrangements, it is useful at this point to briefly examine the historical uses of the inaugural address and to highlight the ways in which Presidents have employed, or failed to employ, constitutional discourse in their inaugural addresses. A. The Early Inaugurals and Constitutional Rule as Inspiration and Anchor Quite apart from the mass public delivery of most inaugurals, President Washington delivered his first inaugural address to a joint session of Congress at Federal Hall in New York. 148 After a few moving remarks about the honor that had been bestowed upon him, and in light of the circumstances of his address, Washington referred to his constitutional obligation to recommend legislation to the Congress and to the Constitution's description of legislative powers vested in Congress, demonstrating his understanding of the boundaries that separate executive and legislative power in the Constitution. 149 Rather than take the opportunity to recommend any specific measures, he reiterated his deference to the character and talents of the Congress and expressed hope and confidence that Congress would act to protect the "characteristic rights of freemen" and to promote "the public harmony." 150 Glen Thurow, who has evaluated the relationship of the early and modem inaugurals to presidential character, notes "Washington's first inaugural may be said to contain the most open display of character and virtue of any inaugural address."1 51 Notably, 148. See George Washington, First Inaugural Address in the City of New York (Apr. 30, 1789), in INAUGURAL ADDRESSES OF THE PRESIDENTS OF THE UNITED STATES, supra note 7, at 1, 1. 149. 150. 151. See id. at 1-4. Id. at4. Thurow, supra note 10, at 18. 20l1 CONSTITUTIONAL STATESMANSHIP Professor Thurow sees a connection between Washington's portrayal of virtue and his commitment to constitutional arrangements. Indeed, Thurow explains, Washington wholly subordinates himself to the Constitution and, in so doing, shows the Constitution is the basis for presidential power and obligation, not the virtue of the individual occupying the office. 152 The claim to rule is formal, not personal. So "Washington seeks to transfer the esteem in which he is held to the new Constitution" and to make the new Constitution stronger by elevating its 53 forms. Washington's second inaugural address was considerably shorter and actually preceded the oath.15 4 Yet Washington took the opportunity to state, at the outset, "I am again called upon by the voice of my country to execute the functions of its Chief Magistrate."' 155 Note the use of the phrase 'functions of its Chief Magistrate"-a direct reference to the formal constitutional duties of the institution, with no mention of the accomplishments of his first administration, no detailed political agenda, and no public appeals regarding his goals for the second administration. He went on in the next paragraph of the address to mention that the Constitution requires the oath and explained, "if it shall be found during my administration of the Government I have in any instance violated willingly or knowingly the injunctions thereof, I may (besides incurring constitutional punishment) be subject to the upbraidings of all who are now witnesses of the present solemn ceremony."' 156 This concluded the speech, yet even in such a brief address, Washington was able to remind listeners of his constitutional obligations and the constitutional consequences for violating them. Washington's inaugurals do not possess the historic impact of some of his other speeches and writings, most notably the Farewell Address. 157 They do, however, set an early precedent for an inaugural address devoted meaningfully to elevating the formal arrangements of the constitutional system, particularly formal institutional powers of the 152. Id. at 19. 153. Id. Professor Tulis explains that Washington had prepared a lengthy set of recommendations for Congress, which was his original inaugural draft, but thought the occasion inappropriate for such a presentation. TULIS, supra note 8, at 48. 154. George Washington, Second Inaugural Address in the City of Philadelphia (Mar. 4, 1793), in THE INAUGURAL ADDRESSES OF THE PRESIDENTS OF THE UNITED STATES, supra note 7, at 6, 6. 155. Id. 156. Id. 157. See Washington, supra note 39. QUINNIPIAC LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:265 presidency. Some, like President Jefferson, followed a somewhat different model. Jefferson's references to the Constitution in each of his inaugurals are relatively few but, when they occur, they tend to concern individual rights rather than structures or specific governmental powers, executive or otherwise. Following the bitter and divisive election of 1800, President Jefferson's famed first inaugural is best known for its conciliatory spirit ("We are all Republicans, we are all Federalists" and "peace, commerce, and honest friendship with all nations, entangling alliances with none") and libertarian spirit ("a wise and frugal Government... shall leave [men] otherwise free to regulate their own pursuits of industry and improvement, and shall not take from the mouth of labor the bread it has earned").1 58 Still, Jefferson explains what he deemed "the essential principles of our Government, and consequently those which ought to shape its administration," and included in his list "a jealous care of the right of election by the people," "freedom of religion; freedom of the press, and freedom of [the] person under the protection of the habeas corpus, and trial by juries impartially selected." 159 Therefore, although Jefferson is not chiefly devoted to explaining his understanding of executive or other constitutional powers (an explanation that could have proven useful in light of Jefferson's subsequent enlargement of federal power), his speech nonetheless respects the constitutional formalities of individual rights and republican virtue. As Thurow describes it, the Jefferson first inaugural expressed virtue "as a result of 160 Constitution."' the serves it because noble be to and the Constitution As the nineteenth century presidents emerged, it became common to invoke the Constitution during the inaugural as a way of reassuring listeners that the constitutional text and its forms would bind the President. Of course, some did not elaborate upon their view of its meaning but instead referred to it, or its specific provisions, only generally, leaving at least the impression of respect for constitutional forms, though without adding much to the substantive constitutional understanding regarding the scope of political powers. President Madison, for example, vowed in his first inaugural to "support the Constitution, which is the cement of the Union, as well in its limitations as in its authorities."' 6 1 President Monroe's first inaugural, which 158. Jefferson, supra note 78, at 15-16. 159. Id. at 16. 160. See Thurow, supra note 10, at 21. 161. James Madison, First Inaugural Address (Mar. 4, 1809), in INAUGURAL ADDRESSES OF THE PRESIDENTS OF THE UNITED STATES, supra note 7, at 25, 27. CONSTITUTIONAL STATESMANSHIP 2010] toasted the "happy state" of affairs in the country and which was the first to be given outdoors, reminded listeners that internal improvements would always proceed "with a constitutional sanction."' 162 President Jackson, whose assertions of his own understanding of the Constitution engendered great controversy during his two terms, stated in his first inaugural that "[i]n administering the laws of Congress I shall keep steadily in view the limitations as well as the extent of the Executive power, trusting thereby to discharge the functions of my office without transcending its authority." 163 Like Monroe, Jackson, whose address appears to be deliberately vague about the constitutional concerns he raises, also advocated internal improvements but only insofar "as they can be promoted by the constitutional acts of the Federal Government."' 164 Indeed, the language of constitutional limitation is useful to observe here because both Monroe and Jackson ultimately exercised a constitutional veto of internal improvements legislation, declaring the legislation to exceed congressional authority.' 65 President Van Buren declared "that the principle that will govern me in the high duty to which my country calls me is a strict adherence to the letter and 166 spirit of the Constitution as it was designed by those who framed it.' Van Buren further explained that he would refer to the Constitution for "direction in every action," and that he would "zealously devote" himself to those domestic and foreign affairs governed by the Constitution, yet "beyond those limits I shall never pass."' 167 Finally, John Quincy Adams was somewhat more elaborate in his invocation of the Constitution than his predecessors or immediate successors. He actually devoted the first several paragraphs of his inaugural to citing the general operation and purposes of the constitutional scheme, acknowledging the role of the judiciary in interpreting the Constitution consistent with "legislative will" and asserting that the Constitution was "founded upon the republican principle of equal rights."' 168 He saved 162. James Monroe, First Inaugural Address (Mar. 4, 1817), in INAUGURAL ADDRESSES OF THE PRESIDENTS OF THE UNITED STATES, supra note 7, at 33, 36, 38. 163. Andrew Jackson, First Inaugural Address (Mar. 4, 1829), in INAUGURAL ADDRESSES OF THE PRESIDENTS OF THE UNITED STATES, supra note 7, at 61, 62. 164. Id. at 63. According to Robert Remini, Jackson's first inaugural "was a model of political adroitness. It was short, vague, and contained nothing to frighten his friends." ROBERT V. REMINI, ANDREW JACKSON 107 (1966). 165. See Broughton, supra note 28, at 120-22. 166. Martin Van Buren, Inaugural Address (Mar. 4, 1837), in INAUGURAL ADDRESSES OF THE PRESIDENTS OF THE UNITED STATES, supra note 7, at 69, 76. 167. Id. at 76-77. 168. Adams, supra note 7, at 53-55. QUINNIPIAC [Vol. 28:265 LAW REVIEW room toward the end of his speech for a more specific discussion of internal improvements, which, Adams says, precipitated "[r]epeated, liberal, and candid discussions" about whether Congress enjoyed constitutional authority to enact provisions for such improvements, hoping that "all constitutional objections will ultimately be removed" and that "[t]he extent and limitation of the powers of the General Government in relation to" internal improvements will be finally 69 1 settled. One of the most noteworthy of the constitutionalized presidential inaugurals, but one neglected by legal scholars, is that of William Henry Harrison. His inaugural address is best known not for its content but for its length: an eight thousand five hundred word speech delivered with neither hat nor coat for nearly two hours in the bitter cold and snow of Washington in March of 1841.170 Infamously, President Harrison developed pneumonia and died a month later. 7 1 If, however, we dismiss Harrison as foolish and ignore his remarks simply because he served only thirty-one days as President, we miss a meaningful discussion about the Whig view of the presidency and the Constitution in an intriguing but under evaluated speech, one that differs in important ways from its predecessors. Indeed, Harrison's inaugural is largely a lesson in constitutional theory and interpretation; though he differs with Publius in some particulars (such as duration in the office of the President), and does not hesitate to identify flaws in the Constitution's text,' 72 the address reads much like Publius's defense of the new Constitution. In addition, it begins with a simple statement about the role of the address in the life of a constitutional presidency: "I proceed to present to you a summary of the principles which will govern me in the 173 perform."' to upon called be shall I which discharge of the duties Harrison spends considerable time throughout the address drawing lessons from Roman political history and explaining generally that the American Constitution imposes limits on governmental power to assure the protection of personal liberty. 74 His assertions for the first few paragraphs are unremarkable, but then Harrison notes that "disputes 169. Id. at 59. 170. See Harrison, supra note 7, at 79. 171. William Henry http://www.whitehouse.gov/about/presidents/willianbenryharrison 2009). 172. Harrison, supra note 7, at 83-84. 173. Id. at 79-80. 174. Id. at 80, 81, 88, 94, 96. (last Harrison, visited Nov. 21, 2010] CONSTITUTIONAL STATESMANSHIP have arisen as to the amount of power which [the Constitution] has actually granted or was intended to grant," and acknowledges the difficulty in ascertaining the intentions of the Constitution's framers. 175 Harrison states that the problem with the abuse of power in American government is not chiefly that institutions exercise power they have not received; rather, the chief danger is that the formal separation of powers have not been observed, resulting in the accumulation of the powers in one branch that belong to another branch. 76 He then explains that he is determined "to arrest the progress of that tendency if it really exists and restore the government to its pristine health and vigor"'177 and later states the "necessity of keeping the respective 8 departments of the 17 Government ...within their appropriate orbits." To achieve this end, Harrison offers both a critique and defense of the Constitution's formal arrangements. Notably, he first promises he will serve only a single term. 179 He argues that the Constitution defectively permits Presidents to serve a second term, thus creating the danger that the President will, over time, be corrupted by his power and forget that "he is the accountable agent, not the principal; the servant, not the master."' 180 Harrison next explains his whiggish view of the President's role in legislative affairs under the Constitution. He rejects the notion that the Recommendation Clause is a legislative power and explains his view that the veto is a "conservative power" to be employed in only three instances: "to protect the Constitution," to prevent the enactment of "hasty legislation," and to protect the rights of minorities.18 1 "To assist or control Congress, then, in its ordinary legislation could not, I conceive, have been the motive for conferring the veto power on the President."'8 2 Next, Harrison states that the executive has become too dangerous because of both excesses in patronage, claiming that the Constitution should have made certain government officials, such as the Treasury Secretary, independent and removable only upon request of Congress; and because Presidents now not only recommend legislation to Congress, they have become the source of legislation, particularly public finance bills: "the delicate duty of 175. Id.at 82. 176. 177. Harrison, supra note 7, at 82. Id. 178. 179. Id.at 91. Id.at 84. 180. Harrison, supra note 7, at 83-84. 181. 182. Id. at 86. Id.at 85. QUINNIPIAC LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:265 devising schemes of revenue should be left where the Constitution has 1 83 people."' the of representatives immediate the placed it-with The next portion of the address is devoted to general observations about another formal constitutional arrangement: American federalism (and clearly, though slavery is not mentioned by name, the remarks constitute an expression of concerns about domestic violence regarding slavery). Harrison advocates the importance of a united confederacy of the states and of respect for the sovereignty of each, fearing that if their sovereignty is not respected, the result will be "disunion, violence, and civil war." 184 Afterward, Harrison devotes a single paragraph to foreign affairs in which he simply gives his assurance to "preserve the friendly ' 85 intercourse which now so happily subsists with every foreign nation."' Finally, Harrison concludes with a criticism of parties, or factions, vowing that "[a]ll the influence that I possess shall be exerted to prevent the formation at least of an Executive party in the halls of the legislative 18 6 ' body." The Harrison inaugural is arguably excessive not only in its length but in the detail that Harrison devotes to constitutional theory. My proposal does not go as far as Harrison does. Still, even when he is critical of the constitutional text, Harrison is at least engaged in the serious business of discussing constitutional meaning. Moreover, he is doing so publicly, to a mass audience, conveying an earnest effort at civic education. In this context, it is also interesting that Harrison devotes so much time to the ancients. The Framers understood the tragedies that befell the ancients and were careful to construct a system with forms that would avoid the problems of popular government that plagued, and ultimately destroyed, ancient regimes like Athens. 187 By invoking the ancients as he does, Harrison, like Publius and others of the founding generation, invites a deeper contemplation of the significance of our constitutional formalities and the ways in which they are designed 188 to avoid the dangers of democracy and republican government. 183. Id. at 88, 89-90. 184. Harrison, supra note 7, at 92. 185. Id. at95. 186. 187. 188. Id. at 97. See BARRUS ET AL., supra note 31, at 2-7. See, e.g., THE FEDERALIST No. 9 (Alexander Hamilton), supra note 34, at 124 (stating "[i]t is impossible to read the history of the petty republics of Greece and Italy without feeling sensations of horror and disgust at the distractions with which they were continually agitated, and at the rapid succession of revolutions by which they were kept in a state of perpetual vibration between the extremes of tyranny and anarchy"); THE FEDERALIST No. 63 2010] CONSTITUTIONAL STATESMANSHIP Again, this enhances the Harrison inaugural address as a civic education model. The Harrison inaugural address thus remains a historically meaningful effort to employ the inaugural address for purposes chiefly related not to policy preferences and self-serving political advocacy, but to reflection about the forms of the Constitution and to engaging in public dialogue about the significance of those forms. Though its detail perhaps sits at the extreme, and its view of executive power more whiggish than the one I would endorse, it is an early example of how a President can reconcile mass public oratory with the constitutional presidency. After Harrison's, (President Tyler did not give an inaugural address, nor did President Fillmore, who ascended to the presidency upon Zachary Taylor's sudden death 189 ) the mid-nineteenth century inaugural addresses continued to invoke the Constitution but tended to focus on the Constitution's federalism, which was significant in light of westward expansion and the effort to emphasize national unity despite the discord over slavery. At times, these inaugural addresses plainly fail to acknowledge the moral, political, and legal consequences of defending slavery or rationalizing its perpetuation through an often vague defense of federalism. Yet, it is worthwhile to study each of these speeches, some of which are useful examples of what may charitably be described as the sometimes ugly side of employing constitutional discourse in the inaugural to define the expectations and priorities of the new administration-ugly in the sense that Presidents, like courts, can view the Constitution in unfortunate, even mistaken, ways. President Polk, whose lengthy address did not hesitate to announce policy preferences, particularly those related to the annexation of Texas and his obsession with Manifest Destiny and the development of western territory, combined his policy advocacy with substantial constitutional rhetoric. 90 Polk stated that "[t]he Constitution itself, plainly written as it is, the safeguard of our federative compact, the offspring of concession and compromise, binding together in the bonds of peace and union this great and increasing family of free and independent States, will be the (James Madison), supra note 34, at 415 (stating that "history informs us of no long-lived republic which had not a senate"); THE FEDERALIST No. 70 (Alexander Hamilton), supra note 34, at 452 (stating that the experience of other nations "teaches us not to be enamoured [sic] of plurality in the Executive"). 189. at iv. 190. INAUGURAL ADDRESSES OF THE PRESIDENTS OF THE UNITED STATES, supra note 7, James Knox Polk, Inaugural Address (Mar. 4, 1845), in INAUGURAL ADDRESSES OF THE PRESIDENTS OF THE UNITED STATES, supra note 7, at 99. QUINNIPIAC LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:265 chart by which I shall be directed."' 9' He followed by promising that "[i]t will be my first care to administer the Government in the true spirit of that instrument, and to assume no powers not expressly granted or clearly implied in its terms."' 92 His successor, President Taylor, a military hero (like Polk) who was a poor public speaker, similarly invoked the Constitution and the significance of precedent in the search for constitutional meaning: "[i]n the discharge of these duties my guide will be the Constitution" and "[f]or the interpretation of that instrument I shall look to the decisions of the judicial tribunals established by its authority and to the practice of the Government under the earlier Presidents, who had so large a share in its formation."193 Polk went on to discuss the importance of a limited national government and the sovereignty of the states, the attachment of the people to the union and the "moral treason" that would accompany any efforts to dissolve the union, but also warned that the states had only limited powers reserved to them as well. 194 He also, like William Henry Harrison, noted his view that the executive's veto was a "conservative" power that he would exercise against "hasty, inconsiderate, or unconstitutional legislation." 195 Even his discussion of westward expansion was qualified by his acknowledgement of constitutional constraints (as to the receipt of Texas into the union and the acquisition of lands "beyond the Rocky Mountains," Polk promises these will occur only by "constitutional means"), and near the conclusion of his remarks he quotes the Take Care Clause in promising the accountability of public 96 officials, especially those who manage public money. 1 Taylor, whose whiggish view of the presidency more readily complements that of Harrison, discussed the importance of American neutrality in foreign affairs and also emphasized a few preferred domestic policies-agriculture, commerce, and manufacturing; internal improvements related to waterways; elimination of public debt; accountability of public officials-but noted "it is for the wisdom of Congress itself, in which all legislative powers are vested by the Constitution, to regulate these and other matters of domestic policy." 197 191. 192. Id. at 100. Id. 193. 194. Taylor, supranote 22, at 111-12. Polk, supra note 190, at 100, 104. 195. 196. Id. at 102. Id. at 109. 197. Taylor, supranote 22, at 113. 2010] CONSTITUTIONAL STATESMANSHIP 305 Taylor's reference to potential discord among the states over slavery was limited to a single vague line: "I shall look with confidence to the enlightened patriotism of [Congress] to adopt such measures of conciliation as may harmonize conflicting interests and tend to perpetuate [the] Union .... ,,198 In contrast, the invocation of the Constitution as a formal means of protecting the union was much stronger in Franklin Pierce's address. Moreover, Pierce's references to his views on slavery, troubling though they are, are stated with much greater clarity. His address warns generally, seemingly benignly, against an omnipotent central government: "[y]ou have a right, therefore, to expect your agents in every department to regard strictly the limits imposed upon them by the Constitution of the United States."' 199 Pierce, who was a Northerner, continually sought to appease Southern interests, and his address distinctly employs the Constitution for this purpose: The great scheme of our constitutional liberty rests upon a proper distribution of power between the state and federal authorities .... If the Federal Government will confine itself to the exercise of powers clearly granted by the Constitution, it can hardly happen that its action upon any question should endanger the institutions of the States or interfere with their right 2 0 0to manage matters strictly domestic according to the will of their own people. Pierce then becomes clear: I believe that involuntary servitude, as it exists in different States of this Confederacy, is recognized by the Constitution. I believe that it stands like any other admitted right, and that the States where it exists are entitled to efficient remedies to enforce the constitutional provisions. I hold that the laws of 1850, commonly called the "compromise measures," are strictly constitutional and to be unhesitatingly carried into effect. I believe that the constituted authorities of this Republic are bound to regard the rights of the South in this respect as they would view any other legal and constitutional right .... 201 Whether Pierce truly misunderstood the moral, political, and legal consequences of his unfortunate construction of the Constitution with regard to slavery, or whether his articulation of this construction was 198. 199. 200. 201. Polk, supranote 190, at 113. Pierce, supra note 7, at 121. Id. Id. at 122. QUINNIPIAC LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:265 designed simply to appease southern interests in an effort to stave off further conflict, the Pierce address-like those of his predecessors who broached the subject with less clarity-serves as a model for the ways in which Presidents can use the inaugural address to articulate and defend even a misguided or objectionable interpretation of the Constitution, rather than deferring constitutional deliberation and construction to the courts or the Congress. Even President Buchanan, who noted in his address that the Kansas-Nebraska Act was a "judicial question" pending before the Supreme Court and appeared convinced that the slavery matter ought no longer to pose a reason for discord in the union,2 °2 repeatedly offers his views on constitutional meaning and theory. As to slavery, he says, "all agree that under the Constitution slavery in the States is beyond the reach of any human power except that of the respective States. 20 3 As to the method of discerning constitutional meaning, he explains, "I desire to state at the commencement of my Administration that long experience and observation have convinced me that a strict construction of the powers of the Government is the only true, as well as the only safe, theory of the Constitution', 20°4 As to the policy of adopting military roads through the territories to California, he concludes "[i]t is impossible to conceive that whilst the Constitution has expressly required Congress to defend all the States it should yet deny to them, by any fair construction, the only possible means by which one of these states can be defended. 2 °5 When Abraham Lincoln took the oath, it was not immediately clear from his first inaugural precisely how aggressive his administration would be in acting to preserve the Union and to eradicate slavery. Indeed, Lincoln stated explicitly in the address that he did not have a "lawful right" to interfere with the institution of slavery and had "no inclination to do so. '' 2° 6 Later in the speech, he even states that he has no objection to a constitutional amendment that would prevent federal interference with "domestic institutions of the States, including that of persons held to service. ,,207 His many invocations of the Constitution 202. James Buchanan, Inaugural Address (Mar. 4, 1857), in INAUGURAL ADDRESSES OF THE PRESIDENTS OF THE UNITED STATES, supra note 7, at 125, 126. 203. Id. at 127. 204. Id. at 130. 205. Id. 206. Abraham Lincoln, First Inaugural Address (Mar. 4, 1861), in INAUGURAL ADDRESSES OF THE PRESIDENTS OF THE UNITED STATES, supra note 7, at 133, 134. 207. Id.at 140. CONSTITUTIONAL STATESMANSHIP 2010] appeared to reflect caution in his understanding of the scope of his authority, and the authority of the federal government with respect to the states, but Lincoln's first inaugural was still a substantial foray into presidential constitutional deliberation that demonstrated an effort to assure constitutional equilibrium by avoiding the language of weakness on the one hand and prerogative on the other. Apart from its assurance not to interfere in the South's domestic policies, Lincoln's speech is devoted chiefly to his highest priority of saving the Union, and the listener cannot help but feel that Lincoln's tone suggests he would take extraordinary measures to do so. Yet the address that Lincoln gives is somewhat softer than his original draft, a result of suggestions he received from William Seward, who feared that a more confrontational address would only exacerbate secession.20 8 Thus, not unlike his speech to the Young Men's Lyceum at Springfield in 1838 in which he argued that reverence for the Constitution and laws should be our political religion, 20 9 Lincoln's first inaugural address is impressive in its ability to strike the proper tone, all while remaining faithful, indeed absolutely committed, to constitutional forms. Moreover, it is an example of a President employing the inaugural to express the national-preservation view of presidential power under the oath. "[T]he intention of the lawgiver is the law," Lincoln announced in referencing the Fugitive Slave Clause. 210 He recalled that "[a]ll members of Congress "swear their support to the whole Constitution," and indicated that this ought to ensure that fugitive slaves be delivered, whether by state or federal enforcement.2 1 Lincoln then asks, rhetorically (and surely with the DredScott case in mind), whether a free man should be delivered as a slave, and whether the law should provide for the enforcement of the Privileges and Immunities Clause of Article 1I.212 At this point, his attention turns from reassuring listeners that he would respect the Fugitive Slave Clause to his concerns for the preservation of the Union and, more broadly, for preservation of the Constitution. He sees a connection between respecting the forms of the Constitution and protecting the Union, which existed before the 208. See DAVID HERBERT DONALD, LINCOLN 283-84 (1995). 209. See Abraham Lincoln, The Perpetuation of Our Political Institutions (Jan. 27, 1838), in SELECTED WRITINGS OF ABRAHAM LINCOLN 10, 15 (1992). 210. Lincoln, supra note 206, at 135. 211. Id. 212. Id. QUINNIPIAC LAW REVIEW (Vol. 28:265 Constitution.2 13 Lincoln declared: I hold that in contemplation of universal law and of the Constitution the Union of these States is perpetual.... Continue to execute all the express provisions of our National Constitution, and the Union will endure forever, it being impossible to destroy it except by some action not provided for in the 214 instrument itself. Consequently, no state can escape the Union and any effort to do so is void, for in this case, the Union would be less perfect because not perpetual. 215 Lincoln continued: I therefore consider that in view of the Constitution and the laws the Union is unbroken, and to the extent of my ability, I shall take care, as the Constitution itself expressly enjoins upon me, that the laws of the Union be faithfully executed in all the States .... I trust this will not be regarded as a menace, but only as the declared purpose of the Union that it will constitutionally defend and maintain itself. Lincoln says that "[a]ll profess to be content in the Union if all constitutional rights can be maintained" and says no one has been deprived of his rights.217 The Constitution, Lincoln explains, does not answer every question and it is in the Constitution's silence, rather than its express provisions, that constitutional controversy arises, for it is in these moments that majority and minority factions appear and divide over the unanswered questions.2 18 To prevent anarchy, we must retain the constitutional form, with the majority governed by constitutional checks; secession is, Lincoln explains, tantamount to anarchy.2 19 Lincoln then completes his defense of constitutional forms by turning his attention from federalism and rights to the separation of powers and his understanding of constitutional limits on those powers, particularly those of the judiciary. He agrees that the Supreme Court decides constitutional questions in specific cases and its decisions are worthy of "very high respect and consideration" by the political branches, even when the Court errs and even when the error produces an evil (for the 213. 214. 215. 216. 217. 218. 219. Id. at 135-36. Lincoln, supra note 206, at 135-36. Id. at 136. Id. Id.at 137. Lincoln, supra note 206, at 138. Id. 20101 CONSTITUTIONAL STATESMANSHIP error can be corrected in future cases). 220 Lincoln, though, rejects the notion that the Court's view renders an issue "irrevocably fixed"; he says he does not mean this as an "assault upon the court or the judges," and "it is no fault of theirs if others seek to turn their decisions to political purposes. ' '2 Here Lincoln appears to imply that others can discern the Constitution's meaning as well, but he stops short of asserting this. Rather, his speech constantly raises ongoing constitutional controversies without expressly urging an interpretation that would cause discord between his administration and the other branches of government. His caution seems to be a deliberate effort, consistent with his theme and with the changes he made from the original draft, to avoid provocation and confrontation, preferring instead to speak generally of respect for existing institutions and constitutional forms, perhaps even as a reminder of the need for unity and of the principles that bind Americans. 222 "We are not enemies, but friends. We must not be enemies," Lincoln says.223 "Though passion may have strained it must not break the bonds of our affection., 224 He concludes with hope that the memory of those bonds will "yet swell the chorus of the Union, when again touched, as surely 225 they will be, by the better angels of our nature. Although the post-Civil War presidencies were hardly monuments to executive energy, Lincoln's was not the last inaugural to delve substantially into the meaning of the Constitution and the scope of constitutional powers. To be sure, most of his immediate successors certainly referenced the Constitution, but those references tended to look very much like those of most nineteenth century presidents who invoked the Constitution to reassure listeners that the President would be anchored and not prone to the sense of prerogative that many feared when the American presidency was created. President Hayes, for example, whose controversial election itself raised constitutional concerns, announced his view that the government must submit "loyally and heartily to the Constitution and the laws-the laws of the nation and the laws of the States themselves-accepting and obeying faithfully the 220. Id. at 138-39. Lincoln, of course, publicly rejected the Supreme Court's decision in the Dred Scott case, most notably in his Senate campaign against Stephen Douglas in 1858. See BARRUS ET AL., supra note 31, at 36-42. 221. Lincoln, supra note 206, at 139. 222. See DONALD, supra note 208, at 283-84. 223. Lincoln, supra note 206, at 141. 224. Id. 225. Id. QUINNIPIAC [Vol. 28:265 LAW REVIEW whole Constitution as it is. ' ' 22 6 He further expressed his view that the American South "now needs and deserves the considerate care of the National Government within the just limits prescribed by the Constitution and wise public economy., 227 Similarly, President Cleveland's first inaugural explained that he would "endeavor to be guided by a just and unstrained construction of the Constitution," by observing the distinction between federal and state powers, and by a "cautious appreciation of those functions which by the Constitution and laws have been especially assigned to the executive branch of the Government., 228 Of all the nineteenth century president who followed Lincoln, it was President Garfield who elaborated somewhat further on constitutional meaning. He stated that it is the "paramount duty of the executive" to interpret and execute the people's will "in accordance with the Constitution"; 229 assured Americans that the Supremacy Clause of the Constitution binds the States and the people but does not "disturb the autonomy of the States nor interfere with any of their necessary rights of local self-government," though, harkening back to Lincoln, it does establish the Union's "permanent supremacy"; 23° and explained that with regard to blacks, "[s]o far as my authority can lawfully extend they shall enjoy the full and equal protection of the Constitution and the laws.",23 1 Garfield further expressed his support for the right of black suffrage (as did Cleveland); acknowledged the constitutional question regarding Congress's power to make paper money legal tender; and explained, in referring to the Mormon Church's support of polygamy, that although "[t]he Constitution guarantees absolute religious freedom," Congress had a duty to "prohibit within its jurisdiction all criminal practices, especially of that class which destroy the family relations and endanger social order., 232 Nearing the conclusion of his remarks, Garfield assured his audience that he would always act "within the authority and limitations of the Constitution. 23 3 226. Rutherford B. Hayes, Inaugural Address (Mar. 5, 1877), in INAUGURAL ADDRESSES OF THE PRESIDENTS OF THE UNITED STATES, supra note 7, at 153, 153, 155. 227. 228. Id. at 156. Grover Cleveland, First Inaugural Address (Mar. 4, 1885), in INAUGURAL ADDRESSES OF THE PRESIDENTS OF THE UNITED STATES, supra note 7, at 169, 171. 229. James A. Garfield, Inaugural Address (Mar. 4, 1881), in INAUGURAL ADDRESSES OF THE PRESIDENTS OF THE UNITED STATES, supra note 7, at 161, 162-63. 230. 231. 232. 233. Id. at 163. Id. at 164. Id. at 164-167. Garfield, supra note 229, at 168. 20101 CONSTITUTIONAL STATESMANSHIP From these early inaugural addresses we see popular presidential rhetoric that is at once designed to promote action (or at least to reserve the authority to act), either by the President himself or by the Congress, while commanding respect for constitutionalism, and most often for formal constitutional arrangements related to the allocation of powereither the horizontal allocation of power among the three branches of the federal government or the vertical allocation of powers among the states and the federal government. Of course, this is not to say that the early inaugurals were wholly, or even overwhelmingly, devoted to constitutional discourse. Rather, Presidents increasingly saw the inaugural address as a way not simply to discuss general principles of government but to promote particular domestic or foreign policy concerns. Yet, even this kind of rhetoric was usually presented in the broader context of a formal constitutional system that either supports or forbids political action to meet those concerns. The most notable common theme among the pre-twentieth century inaugurals, then, is not advocacy of a particular policy or even an assertion of presidential leadership in the making of public policy; rather, it is a moderate form of leadership invoking some measure of reflection, however general, upon the scope of constitutional authority for the political action that presidents contemplated. These addresses thus show that even as later Presidents were increasingly advocating their policy preferences they were at the same time acknowledging and contemplating the significance of the Constitution's provisions for both executive and legislative power. That a President articulates a disagreeable, even morally repugnant, vision of the constitutional order is a matter worthy of considerable study but another matter still; after all, Presidents are no different from courts in this regard. Rather, what is significant about these speeches for present purposes is that they employ the rhetoric of a presidency anchored by the formal constitutional arrangements and, particularly as to those in the middle and latter years of the nineteenth century, that they demonstrate that a President need not forego constitutional reflection even as he promotes a domestic or foreign political agenda. B. The Modern Inauguralsand Wilsonian Theory in Practice It takes considerably less time to survey the constitutional discourse in the inaugural addresses beginning in the twentieth century. That is because modern Presidents have increasingly avoided invoking the Constitution during their addresses. Instead, the inaugural addresses QUINNIPIAC LAW REVIEW (Vol. 28:265 since 1901 have been overwhelmingly devoted to the political objectives of the new administration and to describing national conditions, without placing those discussions in the context of constitutional forms. The first address of the century was President McKinley's second inaugural, which briefly cited the words of the oath and the Take Care Clause in expressing McKinley's encouragement that he had support of the public. 234 President Taft used his inaugural address to advocate a number of new policies, and particularly to discuss foreign affairs, but devoted a portion of his address to the progress of racial integration into American society in light of the Reconstruction Amendments. 23 5 Most pressing for Taft was enforcement of the Fifteenth Amendment, which, he observed, had not been adequately enforced but was slowly becoming a reality as more Southern states enacted laws regarding voter qualifications.236 Taft expressed his view that the Fifteenth Amendment "never ought to be repealed," but as long as southern legislation satisfied the Constitution and federal law, "it is not the disposition or within the province of the Federal Government to interfere with the regulation by Southern States of their domestic affairs. 237 President Harding refers to "[o]ur fundamental law" as recognizing "no class, no group, no section .... The supreme inspiration is the common weal. 23 8 He went on to add that "[o]urs is a constitutional freedom where. .. minorities are sacredly protected., 239 Calvin Coolidge, urging tax reform and security for property rights, stated that "[u]nder this republic the rewards of industry belong to those who earn them. The only constitutional tax is the tax which ministers to public necessity., 240 He subsequently explained that "[i]t is ... the right to hold property, both great and small, which our Constitution guarantees,, 24 1 and, in urging obedience to the law, stated that "[t]hose who want their rights respected under the Constitution and the law ought to set the example themselves of 234. See William McKinley, Second Inaugural Address (Mar. 4, 1901), in INAUGURAL ADDRESSES OF THE PRESIDENTS OF THE UNITED STATES, supra note 7, at 203, 203. 235. See William Howard Taft, Inaugural Address (Mar. 4, 1909), in INAUGURAL ADDRESSES OF THE PRESIDENTS OF THE UNITED STATES, supra note 7, at 213. 236. Id. at 222. 237. Id. at 222-23. 238. Warren G. Harding, Inaugural Address (Mar. 4, 1921), in INAUGURAL ADDRESSES OF THE PRESIDENTS OF THE UNITED STATES, supra note 7, at 237, 243. 239. Id. 240. Calvin Coolidge, Inaugural Address (Mar. 4, 1925), in INAUGURAL ADDRESSES OF THE PRESIDENTS OF THE UNITED STATES, supra note 7, at 247, 253-54. 241. Id. at 254. 20101 CONSTITUTIONAL STATESMANSHIP observing the Constitution and the law., 242 In addition, President Hoover, who devoted most of his inaugural address to crime, invoked the Constitution when discussing federal regulation of monopolies, as well as later in the speech when he listed "maintenance of the integrity of the Constitution" as the first in a list of mandates flowing from his election. 243 Perhaps the most notable of the twentieth century inaugural addresses are those of Theodore Roosevelt, Woodrow Wilson, and Franklin Roosevelt, each of whom has contributed, in varying degrees, to the development of modem presidential leadership. Professor Tulis identifies Theodore Roosevelt's administration as beginning a shift in presidential power toward popular leadership, but both Tulis and the Deconstitutionalization scholars maintain that Theodore Roosevelt differed from Wilson in the important sense that Theodore Roosevelt anchored his "stewardship theory" of the presidency in constitutional forms. 244 Still, his single inaugural address did not mention the Constitution. 245 Wilson's impact on presidential leadership, described earlier, is to some extent reflected in his two inaugural addresses, both of which charted his new vision for the government and the Nation's future 246 but neither of which mentioned the Constitution. In faimess, Wilson's first inaugural was an example of constitutional reflection, but in the sense that it announced a revised understanding of the President's role in American political life, one in which "[t]he President was to be a kind of democratic oracle, tasked with giving voice to the people's power to redefine public life through democratic action-a power which, he implied, would remain mute unless it found its presidential voice. 247 His understanding, however, explicitly rejected the formal arrangements of the constitutional text and structure. Franklin Roosevelt, facing dire economic conditions in the country, was the first President of the last century to use the inaugural as a 242. Id. at 255. 243. Herbert Hoover, Inaugural Address (Mar. 4, 1929), in INAUGURAL ADDRESSES OF THE PRESIDENTS OF THE UNITED STATES, supra note 7, at 257, 260-61, 265. 244. See BARRUS ET AL., supra note 31, at 105; TULIS, supra note 8, at 113-16. 245. See Theodore Roosevelt, Inaugural Address (Mar. 4, 1905), in INAUGURAL ADDRESSES OF THE PRESIDENTS OF THE UNITED STATES, supra note 7, at 209. 246. See Woodrow Wilson, First Inaugural Address (Mar. 4, 1913), in INAUGURAL ADDRESSES OF THE PRESIDENTS OF THE UNITED STATES, supra note 7, at 227; Woodrow Wilson, Second Inaugural Address (Mar. 5, 1917), in INAUGURAL ADDRESSES OF THE PRESIDENTS OF THE UNITED STATES, supra note 7, at 232. 247. Purdy, supra note 36, at 1849. QUINNIPIAC LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:265 platform for invoking the Constitution to advocate enhanced presidential powers. "Our Constitution is so simple and practical that it is possible always to meet extraordinary needs by changes in emphasis and arrangement without loss of essential form," Roosevelt explained.24 8 According to Roosevelt, the existing balance between legislative and executive power could prove inadequate in light of national conditions and the administration's ideas for improving them. 249 So Roosevelt claimed he was "prepared under my constitutional duty to recommend the measures that a stricken nation in the midst of a stricken world may 250 require" and to adopt them "within my constitutional authority., Roosevelt went on to make clear that if Congress failed to work with the administration to adopt measures necessary to meet national exigencies, "I shall ask the Congress for the one remaining instrument to meet the crisis-broad Executive power to wage a war against the emergency, as great as the power that would be given to me if we were in fact invaded by a foreign foe., 251 Roosevelt's frank assertion of the need for greater presidential authority seems at once innovative and audacious. Moreover, students of law and political history know well the constitutional controversies that emerged because of Roosevelt's New Deal, cases that created conflict with the Court that lasted until 1937 and precipitated Roosevelt's proposal to increase the number of Justices on the Court.2 52 Still it is important to remember that Roosevelt forecasted these momentous constitutional controversies in his first inaugural address, thus demonstrating the power of popular presidential rhetoric to not only assert a need for exercising a particular kind of constitutional authority but to employ that rhetoric to advocate a change in our understanding of the existing constitutional order. After Roosevelt, however, presidential inaugural addresses have barely referenced the Constitution or otherwise reflected on federal powers. For example, President Reagan's first inaugural address referenced federalism and the Tenth Amendment by "demand[ing] recognition of the distinction between the powers granted to the Federal Government and those reserved to the States or to the people, 25 3 while 248. Franklin D. Roosevelt, First Inaugural Address (Mar. 4, 1933), in INAUGURAL ADDRESSES OF THE PRESIDENTS OF THE UNITED STATES, supra note 7, at 269, 272-73. 249. 250. 251. 252. Id. at 273. Id. Id. For a good summary, see BERNARD SCHWARTZ, A HISTORY OF THE SUPREME COURT 231-38 (1993). 253. Ronald Reagan, First Inaugural Address (Jan. 20, 1981), in INAUGURAL ADDRESSES 20101 CONSTITUTIONAL STATESMANSHIP his second inaugural address proposed to "make it unconstitutional for the Federal Government to spend more than the Federal Government takes in," a reference to the proposed balanced budget amendment to the 25 Constitution. 25 More commonly, modem inaugural addresses tend overwhelmingly to invoke soaring language to capture a distinctly American spirit (for example, Bill Clinton's "[t]here is nothing wrong with America that cannot be cured by what is right with America" 255 and John Kennedy's "ask not what your country can do for you-ask what you can do for your country" 256). They describe national conditions and offer promises of improvement through new policies, or they speak generally about the role of government in satisfying public needs and desires (Reagan's "[i]n this present crisis, government is not the solution to our problem").25 7 They even commonly invoke an appeal to religion.258 The modem inaugural addresses, like the early ones, is conciliatory, friendly both to the Congress with (or against) whom the President must work as well as to the opposing political party. 25 9 The modem inaugural addresses, though, tend not to invoke or rely upon constitutional premises for presidential and other political action. They do not even offer the traditional reassurance to be bound by the Constitution that we see in so many of the nineteenth century inaugural addresses.26 ° Instead, they assume Wilson's style, the more extreme OF THE PRESIDENTS OF THE UNITED STATES, supra note 7, at 331, 333. 254. Ronald Reagan, Second Inaugural Address (Jan. 21, 1981), in INAUGURAL ADDRESSES OF THE PRESIDENTS OF THE UNITED STATES, supra note 7, at 339, 341. 255. William J. Clinton, First Inaugural Address (Jan. 20, 1993), in "We Force the Spring": Transcript ofAddress by President Clinton, N.Y. TIMES, Jan. 21, 2007, at A 15. 256. John F. Kennedy, Inaugural Address (Jan. 20, 1961), in INAUGURAL ADDRESSES OF THE PRESIDENTS OF THE UNITED STATES, supra note 7, at 305, 308. 257. See, e.g., Reagan, supra note 254. 258. See Dwight D. Eisenhower, First Inaugural Address (Jan. 20, 1953), in INAUGURAL ADDRESSES OF THE PRESIDENTS OF THE UNITED STATES, supra note 7, at 293, 293-94; Richard Milhous Nixon, Second Inaugural Address (Jan. 20, 1973), in INAUGURAL ADDRESSES OF THE PRESIDENTS OF TE UNITED STATES, supra note 7, at 321, 325; George Bush, Inaugural Address (Jan. 20, 1989), in INAUGURAL ADDRESSES OF THE PRESIDENTS OF THE UNITED STATES, supranote 7, at 345, 346. 259. See, e.g., Bush, supra note 258, at 348; William J. Clinton, Second Inaugural Address (Jan. 20, 1997), in Transcriptof President Clinton'sSecond InauguralAddress to the Nation, N.Y. TIMES, Jan. 21, 1997, at A14. 260. The first inaugural addresses of Richard Nixon and Ronald Reagan, and the second inaugural address of George W. Bush may be considered exceptions, although none of them engaged in deeper reflection about constitutional forms or anchored their programs to constitutional powers. Nixon recalls that he has taken an oath "to uphold and defend the Constitution of the United States," to which he adds "this sacred commitment: I shall consecrate my office, my energies, and all the wisdom I can summon, to the cause of peace QUINNIPIAC LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:265 form of popular leadership, invoking the language of vigorous action, presidential dominance, and, most notably, intimacy with the electorate, but not within the context of constitutional rules or forms. As Elvin Lim has written upon studying presidential rhetoric, including the inaugural addresses, the rhetoric has become more informal (Lim describes this as 61 anti-intellectual), abstract, assertive, democratic, and conversational. This is not a trend that bodes well for the constitutional presidency, constitutional discourse, or responsible civic education. C. A Short Critique of the Obama InauguralAddress Much ink has been spilled concerning President Obama's 2 62 considerable rhetorical gifts, of his eloquence and his skillful delivery. Nevertheless, it is important to separate articulateness and skill from content and message, at least for purposes of refining the rhetorical presidency and reconciling it with the constitutional presidency. President Obama's inaugural alludes to constitutional principles, though only in the most general and vague ways and never by name: he refers to "a charter" and "founding documents. ' ' 263 Moreover, his nameless references to founding documents and principles do not approach the kind of constitutional reflection and assertiveness that the presidential oath justifies and that would be worthy of executive energy under these among nations." Richard Milhous Nixon, First Inaugural Address (Jan. 20, 1969), in INAUGURAL ADDRESSES OF THE PRESIDENTS OF THE UNITED STATES, supra note 7, at 315, 320. Reagan began his first inaugural address with his observation of the "orderly transfer of authority as called for in the Constitution." Ronald Reagan, supra note 254, at 331. Finally, President George W. Bush began his second inaugural address-the first inaugural address after the September 11 th attacks on America-with a reminder that "[o]n this day, prescribed by law and marked by ceremony, we celebrate the durable wisdom of our Constitution and recall the deep commitments that unite our country." George W. Bush, Second Inaugural Address (Jan. 20, 2005), in The InauguralAddress: "The Best Hopefor Peace in Our World is the Expansion ofFreedom in All the World, " N.Y. TIMES, Jan. 21, 2005, at A12. 261. See Elvin T. Lim, Five Trends in PresidentialRhetoric: An Analysis of Rhetoric from George Washington to Bill Clinton, PRESIDENTIAL STUD. Q., June 2002, at 328. 262. See, e.g., Caren Bohan, A Gifted Orator,Obama is on an Historic Path, RUETERS, Oct. 31, 2008 (noting Obama's reputation for "stirring eloquence"); Dean Reynolds, Obama: Extremely Gifted and Also Very Lucky, CBS NEWS, Nov. 5, 2008, http://www.cbsnews.com/blogs/2008/l 1/05/politics/fromtheroad/entry457271 1.shtml (noting descriptions of Obama as "gifted and inspiring speaker"); Michael Useem, The Gifted Speaker, WASH. POST, Jan. 12, 2009, http://views.washingtonpost.com/ leadership/panelists/2009/01/the-gifted-speaker.html (describing President Obama's speaking style); Peter Wehner, The Wright Stand, NAT'L REV. ONLINE, Mar. 20, 2008 (stating that Obama is a "gifted writer and speaker"). 263. See Obama, supra note 1. 2010] CONSTITUTIONAL STATESMANSHIP circumstances. It is an excellent but unfortunate example of the extreme form of popular presidential leadership that has prevailed in the modem presidency. President Obama's constant use of the term "we" in advocating particular political goals is, at least potentially, troublesome. As a rhetorical device, "we" is most useful when referring to those goals or aspirations reasonably understood as common to Americans. It conveys a kind of unity and public spiritedness appropriate for a moment that transcends political affiliation. The use of "we" or "our" also suggests an inclusiveness and intimacy with the listener that is inconsistent with the distance that constitutional formalities provide for the President, even when he is speaking to the public.2 6 Moreover, does his repeated use of "we" refer always to Americans broadly, or to the Obama Administration? "We," then, becomes especially problematic when describing specific policies; vowing that "we" will enact some policy assumes the support of the Congress and the people, and implies that the President is the de facto architect of all national policy. Nevertheless, this seems contrary to the formal arrangements of the Constitution, which give the President a role in formulating national legislation but a role that is neither primary nor preferred. Institutionally, the President's use of "we" appears to suggest that the Congress either has no say in the particular matter or will simply blindly follow the President's preferences. President Obama's is a distinctly Wilsonian approach to defining the scope of presidential responsibility, for it is not one that he attempts to defend on any formal constitutional ground. 265 Moreover, the use of "'we" to enumerate specific policy preferences captures a sense of closeness between the President and the people that assumes they are complicit in his political endeavors. This further complicates the formal features of the constitutional presidency, which, as I explained earlier, aims to increase, not decrease, the distance between the President and the public.266 In addition, even when President Obama uses "we" in referring to more general or aspirational notions, the listener is left to wonder whether "we" really would agree. For example, President 264, See Lim, supra note 261, at 339-43. Professor Lim's research indicates that "contemporary presidential rhetoric contains five times as many references to the inclusive self than the rhetoric of the patrician presidents." Id. at 341. Therefore, the practice is certainly not unique to President Obama, though it was emphatic in his address. 265. See Thurow, supra note 10, at 22. 266. See supra part II.B. QUINNIPIAC LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:265 Obama says "we... have chosen... unity of purpose over conflict and discord., 267 What purpose, exactly, have "we" chosen? Perhaps he is referring to broader purposes more readily identified as the common good, as republican virtue, or perhaps something akin to "a more perfect union," but the catalogue of more specific policies he promotes later in the speech suggest that he may see little difference between the "purposes" "we" have chosen and the legislation and regulations his Administration intends to seek: among other things, to build roads and bridges; "restore science to its rightful place"; use alternative fuels for automobiles and factories; "responsibly leave Iraq"; and "roll back the 268 specter of a warming planet. The problem is not that President Obama highlights preferred public policies-all Presidents have their preferences, and as described here, many have used the inaugural address to articulate those preferences. Rather, it is that he offers no reflection on the constitutional basis for the leadership he asserts, possibly leaving the listener, the citizenry, with the unexplained impression that the Constitution and its provisions for the exercise of federal power offer no constraints on the fulfillment of his promises. President Obama exacerbates the problem by closing the distance between him and the public, distance that is necessary to ensure safe government and deliberate, sober judgment about the public good. Yet even as he becomes closer to the people, he is not forthright with the people about the constitutional contours of federal power to do what he is so passionate about doing. This is precisely the kind of problem that drives the need for a new political education through presidential rhetoric.269 Quite apart from President Obama's collectivism and democratic appeals, perhaps the chief indication of the problem-his inattention to formal constitutional arrangements-is that President Obama never once mentions the Congress in his address. One might imagine that a President, "true to our founding documents," committed to a "charter [that] assure[s] the rule of law," with previous experience teaching constitutional law, and a former Senator and state legislator with no prior executive branch experience, would, at a minimum, acknowledge Congress. 270 That is to say, recognize the governmental branch constitutionally responsible for deliberating upon and enacting the very 267. 268. 269. 270. Obama, supra note 1. See id. See Tulis, supra note 36, at 13. See Obama,supra note 1. CONSTITUTIONAL STATESMANSHIP 2010] proposals that the President claims "we" need so desperately, those things he maintains "we will do.", 271 (Again, to whom is he referring when he emphasizes "we"?) This is particularly true where, as here, the President faces a politically friendly Congress. Constitutionalizing this rhetoric would not take a great feat of speech-writing acumen. President Obama could simply have listed his desired policy goals, explained that it is within his constitutional power to recommend these measures to Congress, and stated his fervent hope that the Congress would join him in making them a reality, or that he would use all of his constitutional power to bring them to fruition, all while being mindful of the Constitution's limits and of Congress's importance in the constitutional scheme. In a speech heavily-laden with policy aspirations, his failure even to acknowledge Congress's constitutional role in the policy-making process raises concerns about his views of the presidency, more generally, and more specifically, about his intention to use popular rhetoric to undermine formal constitutional arrangements and the filters of congressional, and constitutional, deliberation. President Obama's predecessor in the office was subjected to substantial criticism for what was perceived as a grandiose, even "unprecedented," vision of presidential power, and for failing to acknowledge constitutional limits and congressional prerogatives. 272 President Obama's inaugural address, however, provides no evidence that he views the presidency as more constrained, that he views the Congress as the institution with primary responsibility for deliberating upon and crafting national legislation, or what he views as the precise constitutional bases for 271. See id. 272. See, e.g., Dan Froomkin, White House Watched, WASH. POST, June 26, 2009, http://voices.washingtonpost.com/white-house-watch (describing President Bush's "fundamentally cancerous expansion of executive power that led to violations of our laws and our principles"). Some of this kind of criticism came from President Obama himself. See Editorial, Promises, Promises;Is Obama Backsliding on His Pledges, or is He Just Balancing Politics and Principle?, L.A. TIMES, Mar. 22, 2009, at A27 (noting Obama's criticisms of President Bush on executive power); Charlie Savage, Candidates On Executive Power: A Full Spectrum, BOSTON GLOBE, Dec. 22, 2007, at Al (quoting Senator Obama's responses in survey on presidential powers, including "[t]he American people need to know where we stand on these issues before they entrust us with this responsibility-particularly at a time when our laws, our traditions, and our Constitution have been repeatedly challenged by [the Bush] administration") (internal quotations omitted); Wendell Goler, Obama'sArmy of Czars Raises Concerns About Executive Power, FOX NEWS, July 16, 2009, http://www.foxnews.com/politics/2009/07/16/obamas-army-czars-raises-concerns-executivepower (stating that "Barack Obama criticized President Bush for trying to increase executive power"). 320 QUINNIPIAC LAW REVIEW [Vol. 28:265 asserting the president's dominance, in the alternative. His rhetorical skill and inspiring language do not overcome these deficiencies, nor do they sufficiently mask his failure to remain mindful of the sober realities of governing a democratic republic. IV. CONCLUSION Rhetoric can be-indeed, has become-a powerful tool of the presidential office. It is used to persuade political actors and the citizenry, to define the goals of an administration, and to assert the interests of the United States government. Presidential rhetoric can be a force for shaping both the substance and procedures of presidential governance. To a large extent, however, it has become a weapon to enable the president to creep closer to the public and, ultimately, to get what he wants. Presidents do not employ their rhetoric in a vacuum. They speak within the context of a political system of rules, of lines, of divided institutional responsibilities and guarantees for certain individual rights. In such a system, it is not only desirable that Presidents do not always get what they privately want; it is also desirable that they do not always publicly seek those wants. In addition, when they do, it is desirable that they place their interests within the framework of responsible use of authority (which also requires good judgment, or Lockean right reason, about the use of authority). In such a system, then, presidential rhetoric can be an equally powerful tool for articulating the contours of a constitutional presidency, and thus contributing to the civic education of the public by promoting the peoples' attachment to constitutional rule while mitigating their expectations of direct influence on official action. The President can assert a vision of his constitutional duties that clarifies his own views of the powers that the Constitution confers upon him, but he can also clarify his understanding of the limits on his power and of the prerogatives of other institutions in the system. The inaugural address, unique in the world of presidential rhetoric, allows the President to do this to an enormous public audience and to do it contemporaneously with the conferral of his constitutional authority. Consequently, even in a time when presidential rhetoric and oratory is subject to the carefully orchestrated and all-too-democratic strategies of communications professionals in the White House, modem presidential rhetoric can be compatible with the constitutional presidency the founding generation created, and with a sober civic education mindful of leading founders' trepidation toward democratic rule and human nature.