a professional philosopher.

advertisement
Florida Philosophical Review
Vol. III, Issue 1, Summer 2003
5
Kant’s Thing in itself, or the Tao of Königsberg
Presidential Address of the 48th Annual Meeting
of the Florida Philosophical Association
Martin Schonfeld, University of South Florida and National Taiwan University
Introduction
It is time to take another look at Kant. His philosophy took quite a battering in the past
century. First analytic critics bruised and pummeled it, and then postmodern critics tried to finish it
off. Yet Kant keeps bouncing back. Why is this? Why does he not go away, despite such efforts?
Is it because of his ethical ideas? That, perhaps, universal human rights, the categorical respect for
humanity, are a rule worth remembering? That sustainable development, the replication of a
practice through space and over time, is the only way to go, even though it tends to rub us the
wrong way? Or is it because of Kant’s political claims? That people should be
critical citizens instead of loyal subjects, even if this upsets the patriots? That “the supreme end: the
happiness of all mankind,” as he calls it, requires a United Nations after all? Or, finally, is it because
of Kant’s metaphysical insights? That our two poles are the moral law within and the
starry heavens above? That there is only us, and despite our rational autonomy, we are links in the
Great Chain of Nature? And that, regardless of what fundamentalists want us to believe, proofs of
God and human immortality are over and done with?
Then there is Kant’s context—the Enlightenment. A flower of civilization, this was the
century when the grip of the Churches on reason was broken, when natural philosophy matured into
science, bracketed by Newton at the beginning and insights into electricity and molecular bonds at
the end—and the century that culminated in the Declaration of Independence and the Bill of Rights.
This was an excellent age, and for most generations in Kant’s neighborhood, life was worse before
and after. Before this time, there were witch-hunts and the Thirty Years War. Afterwards, the
French revolution was guillotined, factories produced masses of the poor, slavery became big new
world business, the colonialist land-grab went in overdrive, and the Wild West turned genocidal.
And that was only the prelude to the twentieth century—trenches, flags, gas chambers, soldiers, and
the Bomb. The time under Frederick the Great was better. Calling the Enlightenment “the Age of
Reason” is not exaggerated. People, at least some of them, had their act together. And a few, like
Florida Philosophical Review
Vol. III, Issue 1, Summer 2003
6
Kant, had mind-blowing ideas—ranging from the structure of galaxies to the categorical imperative.
Research in cosmology and ecology reveals an astounding convergence of our knowledge and Kant’s
ideas. What inspired this man? And what was his basic angle—what ties the vast range of his ideas
together? What about the notorious thing in itself? Kant says it is unknowable, but surely he must
have had opinions on it. What were they? Kant keeps bouncing back; his narrative looks fresher
every day; and this makes the questions compelling.
We may never know for certain what Kant’s ultimate inspiration and basic insight were. We
are free to guess, although scholars should not do this. Academics ought to be critics, not artists.
The philosophers, however, did not share our qualms. They wanted to know, and so do I. Thus I
will follow my hunches in this essay; perhaps they will lead somewhere. I will paint a portrait of the
thing in itself based on an unknown root of Kant’s thought.
In the first section, I will speculate on the essence of reality. I argue that Kant’s thing in
itself is a bond of forces in space; that this structural-dynamic pattern governs nature; and that this
perspective not only unifies Kant’s insights but also supplies an ontological narrative that integrates
our scientific knowledge. In the second section, I will interpret the historical record. I argue that
the structural-dynamic perspective was a driving idea in the Enlightenment; that it arrived from
China with the Rites Controversy, and that this idea, mediated by others, informed Kant. In the
third section, I will examine Kant’s first book, Thoughts on the True Estimation of Living Forces (1747). I
argue that this idea is the core of his dynamics, and that (as has only recently become known) the
key claims of his earliest theory have withstood the test of time. I will conclude my conjectures with
questions, as is only fitting: queries about the influence of the structural dynamic perspective on
Kant overall, and about the merit of this idea in general. If my questions are sufficiently reasonable
to provoke further investigations, then I will have reached my aim.
The Consilience of Structural Dynamics
I suspect that Kant’s thing in itself, or the natural essence alluded to from his pre-critical
beginnings to his late Opus Postumum, is an interactive bond of forces in a continuum. As this bond
is not static but dynamic, one could regard it as an energetic activity within its generated field. The
particular form of this activity is interaction.
A consequence of this reading would be that the categorical imperative is the normative
vector of this interactive bond. This would imply that Kant’s imperative reflects the given in
functional practice, as the algorithm of constructive and sustainable interactivity. This would further
mean that the fact-value distinction would have to be qualified. Collapsing this distinction has been
Florida Philosophical Review
Vol. III, Issue 1, Summer 2003
7
called the naturalistic fallacy—but perhaps it is the stance of keeping facts and values apart that is
misguided here: the fallacy of the bifurcation of nature.1 Kant’s case may be subtler than commonly
held. Although his bifurcation of empirical facts and intelligible values leaves the impression that
Kant maintained such a distinction, this ignores two points. First, Kant’s bifurcation arose from an
epistemic context, separating it from ontological dualisms, and second, his early and late ontology
were emphatically monist. Trying to characterize the thing in itself is thus no idle game. It suggests
not only a general description of reality-patterns, but also a reassessment of the quality of value,
because these patterns are not pointless: they are dynamic and often self-organizing.
The verdict of the Critique of Pure Reason (1781/87) is that the thing in itself is not cognitively
accessible, and no verifiable description of its nature can be given. Yet Kant repeatedly suggests
characterizations of a universal matrix. He does so not only in the early works and the late
reflections, but also in the critical texts—even in the Critique itself (A 212-15/B 258-62). What
makes these characterizations intriguing is that they are quite unified and startlingly similar for the
early, critical, and late Kant.2
Kant’s universal matrix seems more than “invention” but less than “discovery”. By
invention I mean something created freely, something that is arbitrary. By discovery I mean
something proven by our standards of justification. Kant’s characterization of essential reality is of
the same type, it appears, as the insights that were his forte: it is an aperçu—it is unsubstantiated and
yet fertile. Its details, primarily the descriptions in his first book, anticipated later discoveries and
informed Kant’s further ideas, those that have been confirmed as well as those that we now accept
as trivially true. Kant characterizes the essence of nature as a sort of dynamic interactivity. This may
well be the keystone of his thoughts, binding his other aperçus together.
Successful scientific aperçus, for example, are Kant’s explanations of the coastal winds
(1:223-4, 1:492-4), of the cycles of the monsoon (1:494-500), of the slow-down of the Earth’s
rotation (1:187-90), of the formation of the solar system (1:263-9), and of the structure of galaxies
(1:248-56).3
Successful philosophical aperçus are Kant’s conclusions that traditional metaphysics is over
(Aviii-x, Axix-xx/Bxiv-xv), and that arguments for God’s existence and the soul’s immortality are
done with (A631-42/B659-70; A395-6/B421-28). Aperçus successful in the interdisciplinary brain
sciences, emerging in good measure from philosophy, are the conclusions in the first Critique that
perception results from interaction, whereby invariant pathways organize affecting data (B1;
A15/B29; A50-1/B74-5; B113; B148-9), and that the subject of organized sense-impressions—the
synthetic unity of apperception—poses, to use Dave Chalmer’s expression, the hard problem of
consciousness (B154-9).
Florida Philosophical Review
Vol. III, Issue 1, Summer 2003
8
Successful historical aperçus, at last, are Kant’s arguments for gender equality (8:35-6), for
the cross-cultural universality of reason (4:428; 8:17-19), for the end of imperialism (8:344-6, 354-7),
for the resilience of tolerant societies whose peoples interact as citizens (8:367), for the Universal
Declaration of Human Rights (4:429), for the emergence of the United Nations (8:355-7), and for
the categorical imperative of sustainable development (4:421). No doubt, Kant was good at
guessing! The identity of the thing in itself, I suspect, binds his lucky guesses together. And if this
royal aperçu is more than an invention, it will explain their extraordinary predictive and explanatory
success.
Crucial for the appreciation of the noumenon is to avoid viewing it as a thing. It is not
shaped like books or people. The Ding an sich is not in any sense thing-like—it is neither blocky nor
solidly inert. Spatially and temporally, it is the opposite of an empirical object. Whereas such
objects are definite and formed, the thing in itself is pure form, thus prior to formation and
accordingly boundless.
More precisely, it is a force knitting its exterior into a field, individuating the original force
into more localized dynamic centers. The “knitting” is essential: the thing in itself is neither force
nor exterior, but instead their interplay. It is an interaction between entities. These are opposites: as
force is “something” (a primal energy), its exterior is “nothing” (a void that is not yet space). The
interplay of “something” and “nothing” is harmonious. It generates nature. Hence the noumenon
can be likened to a dynamic interactivity, which is a harmony of opposites.
The dynamic interactivity or harmony of opposites generates the spatial field. Dynamic
radiation expands into the void exterior to the force-source, thereby structuring the void into a
plenum. This field is in dynamic stasis, but at any instant, it pulses, develops, and structures itself to
ordered wholes. The wholes allocate energy. The more complex the generated systems are, the
more flexible resource allocations become. At higher orders of complexity, the natural systems
manage themselves, some of them evolving to autonomous organisms. The free wills of rational
individuals are bound by a categorical duty to act in line with the natural vector toward sustainable
self-organization.
Kant was not the first to entertain such views. Johannes Kepler (1571-1630), inspired by
Proclus, described a “music of the spheres” in the Harmonice Mundi (1619), a work that has been
called the summa of the Renaissance.4 Kepler’s attempts at modeling nature’s chorded harmonies
and elegant beats resulted in the third planetary law. The Harmonic Law has been fertile, preparing
universal gravitation, and its stated period-distance regularity is accurate. Kepler’s Pythagorean music
is a resonance of the structuring interactivity. Described in the terms of early modern philosophy,
this interactivity is the entelechy’s force in the plenum.
Florida Philosophical Review
Vol. III, Issue 1, Summer 2003
9
In the early Kant, interactivity emerges as the attractive-repulsive coexistence of bodies in
space, explaining the immanent causal development of nature to reason. Ultimately it is a divinely
warranted schema (1:413.1-2, 413-16). In the critical period, Kant warns that it is beyond the
bounds of sense, but nonetheless argues that it is practically intelligible, morally an imperative, and
dynamically a plenum. Later he would explicate it as an ether that sustains physical and cognitive
patterns.
Historically, this perspective originated in the Tao; that is, Laozi’s ontological principle of
the harmony of opposites, and its implied naturalistic ethics. Christian Wolff (1679-1754)
interpreted the principle as a harmony of normative action and factual evolution. Georg Bernhard
Bilfinger (1693-1750) appropriated the harmony of opposites as a heuristic rule for philosophy of
nature. Kant applied Bilfinger’s rule to ontology and cosmology, thereby arriving once more at the
original sense of the Tao.
The Taoist tradition, undergirding Confucianism and abstracted to Chan (Zen), emerged in
tonal languages. When morphemes are sung instead of spoken, it is easier to communicate a
structural-dynamic perspective. Like Kant, Laozi, the author(s) of the Dao De Jing, asserts a
noumenon, the Tao or “way,” which orders nature towards complexity, life, and freedom (e.g. cf.
verses 1, 6, 25, 30, 81).
The Tao Te Ching (verse 4) suggests that Tao “fills” (dao zhong) and, in doing so, becomes
“usable” (yongzhi) “without limit” (bu yin). Translators commonly propose “Tao is empty—its use
never exhausted” or “the Tao is an empty vessel; it is used, but never filled.”5 Although “empty” is
implied in zhong’s connotations (“to make void” or “to neutralize”), zhong is a verb with a dynamic
meaning. In English, it corresponds to “flush,” “soar,” “pour,” “infuse” or “dash against”.6 These
words evoke water, a symbol of Tao because of its life-sustaining force and its properties of
universality and expansion.7 Tao is a primal energy that creates space by structuring it as a presence.
Tao individuates this presence into objects and guides the development of nature. Its initial action is
expressed in the phrase dao zhong, the “flushing” of the Tao into its exterior, a filling of the void that
results in a cosmic plenum.
The “filling” is “usable” to nature. The filling, which initiates self-organization, serves
nature’s goal of viable structures. When the Tao expands, its boundless activity covers or contains
everything; there are no points or interstices not infused by it.8 As a dynamic primum structuring
nature, Tao serves as the cosmic vector which points to unfolded nature. It remains beyond sensible
access, but externalizes itself as the matrix of nature. It is the dynamis, whose realization is the selforganization of the universe.
Moreover, the dynamis is not only the physical thrust of the universe, but also the normative
form of conduct. Good actions, in this view, harmonize with the overall momentum of nature. As
Florida Philosophical Review
Vol. III, Issue 1, Summer 2003
10
Tao orders the cosmic development toward increasing complexity, good actions mirror this process
by benefitting life and freedom. Such conformity is the appropriate response to the given. Laozi
summarizes (v. 25) that people (ren) are patterned (fa) after the Earth (dì), the Earth after (fa) the
cosmos (tian), the cosmos after (fa) Tao, and Tao after (fa) nature (ziran).9
Like Kant’s noumenon, Tao is a pulse—filling space, weaving the cosmos, and branching
into discrete rhythms or things (wan wu; v. 1). The interactive, autonomous, and self-organizing rise
of complexity is its goal (fu mo zhi ming, er chang ziran; v. 51). Instantiations of maximum complexity
are life, sentience, and reason. Their emergence is the descriptive-normative point of the cosmic
vector. Moreover, like the Ding an sich, Tao is an unformed form that is neither blocky nor solid (wu
zhuang zhi zhuang, wu wu zhi xiang; v. 14). Viewed as a dynamic, Tao is a harmony of opposites that
promotes life (tian di xiang he, yijiang gan lu; v. 32). Viewed as an order, Tao is the entelechy of
nature’s self-organization (wan wu jiang zi hua . . . tian xia jiang zi ding; v. 37).
The similarities of Ding an sich and Tao raise the question of why they have not been
discussed. There may be several reasons. Kant research is an ongoing effort. The global
productivity of Kant scholars is reflected in the parallel publication of three leading journals, KantStudien, Studi Kantiani, and Kantian Review. The studies are not done, and our accounts are not graven
in stone.
Language barriers pose a separate problem. The primary sources, of Kant in context, are in
Latin, German, French, and English. Little is available in translation; even the English Kant is
incomplete. Substantial research is published in German, Italian, French, and Spanish. The option
of nonwestern influences throws Chinese into the fray too. The study of Kant is a multilingual
scholarship on a multilingual topic, and accessing the polyglot data is not easy.
Yet doing so is necessary. Heidegger calls language “the house of being” when pondering
the essence of action.10 His simile is poetic but to the point, because languages convey information
while confining it. By “housing” being, languages impose models. Conceptual and formal
frameworks make aspects of reality accessible to us, but any given framework is just one room of a
larger house, as it were. I suspect we will see more if we open doors and survey other rooms as well.
Finally, these claims have not been discussed because ontological syntheses are discouraged.
The humanities are in ironic reserve. Philosophers today are either pragmatic, analytic researchers
who pride themselves on being skeptics in a rigorous way, or postmodern, continental researchers
who pride themselves on being skeptics in a deconstructive way. Skepticism is basic to good
science. But good science is not reducible to it. The colleagues in the sciences puzzle things out and
put stuff together. Recently, with the revolutions in astrophysics, biology, and information
technology, several workers have been trying to put it “all” together, it seems—Hawkings, MurrayGellman, Penrose, Greene, the late S. J. Gould, and Wilson. Edward O. Wilson scolds us scholars
Florida Philosophical Review
Vol. III, Issue 1, Summer 2003
11
for our ironic reserve11—asking us, why aren’t you folks giving us a hand? We are making
connections, we are not sure what they mean, and we are saddened by the loss of life’s diversity; we
need your help! But engaging with ontology and synthesizing tends to make members of our guild
look foolish or naive, all the more so if such pursuits go beyond standard eurocentric discourse.
Hence the trails I explore lead into uncharted territory. Kant scholars are not done; they need many
dictionaries; and the arts are jaded.
I worry Wilson may have a point. Hence I argue for “consilience,” literally a “jumping
together of knowledge”—or simply meaning, as Rodney King, after his beating, said so wisely
(particularly in light of 9-11), “why can’t we just all get along?” Because these ideas define the
Enlightenment and Kant, consilient trails are perhaps not dead alleys after all.
The Transmission of Taoist “Seeing the Nature” (guandao ziran) to Kant
The subtitle of this investigation is “The Tao of Königsberg,” despite the incontrovertible
facts that Kant never refers to Laozi’s Tao Te Ching and had not read it. The questions of how
matters East reached the West, what matters they were, and when they happened, require a closer
look.
The trade routes to Taiwan and Macao had been opened when Copernicus was a young man
and Galileo had not yet been born. The Christian mission began at the end of the sixteenth century.
Matteo Ricci (1552-1610) arrived in 1583, won his green card in 1601, and lived in China until his
death. But Ricci’s efforts backfired. Instead of the Chinese becoming Christian, the Jesuits became
Confucian, including Ricci, who began to dress up like a Mandarin official.12 The sinofied Jesuits
advocated a spiritual synthesis of East and West, organizing an ecumenical worship of Confucian
ancestors and the Christian God. This upset the other missions, staffed by Latin-speaking
Franciscans and Dominicans, Bible-thumpers who did not bother studying the languages of their
hosts. The Rites Controversy began in 1610. Ricci, as well as his successors, wrote texts on China
and mailed them home. The Manchu Emperor Kangxi (r. 1662-1722) protected their freedom with
his famous Edict of Tolerance (1692).13
The Jesuit Philippe Couplet published a translation of three Confucian Classics, the Analects,
Doctrine of the Mean, and Great Learning (1687). The Jesuit François Noël published an edition with
the Mencius (1711). Leibniz supported the Jesuits in the continuing Rites Controversy. Christian
Wolff reviewed Noël’s books in the Acta Eruditorum (1711-12). Completing his term as Halle’s vicepresident (Prorektor), Wolff gave a speech on Chinese philosophy (1721, Oratio de Sinarum philosophia
Florida Philosophical Review
Vol. III, Issue 1, Summer 2003
12
practica). He began and ended his address by declaring that Confucius rocks, and that Confucius is
right.14
The backlash happened immediately. In Germany, the Pietists went on the warpath,
slandering Leibniz (who had died in 1716) and his followers as atheists and spinozists. Wolff was
driven out of Halle in 1723. The presidential address was dynamite. Wolff had explicitly said (7, 13,
65) that oriental pagans ignorant of the Bible comprehensively figured out the difference between
right and wrong. This message questioned authority and had to be suppressed.
In Italy, Pope Clemens XI had already issued an infamous Edict of Intolerance and closed
the flourishing Jesuit China mission in 1715. In China, the Manchu Emperor Yongzheng (r. 172236) responded by banishing Christianity in 1724. The Rites Controversy continued in Europe. Pope
Benedict XIV announced a gag-order, stopping the controversy to the satisfaction of the Biblethumpers in 1742, but this was just a formality, because all missionaries had already been expelled.
The encounter of Confucius and Christ had ended with the defeat of the latter. The Chinese
considered the Holy Trinity contradictory and the Cross, a henchmen tool, barbarian. The
Christians had been embarrassed to find out that Chinese historiography contained no record of the
Biblical Deluge, although this history reached deeper into the past than their own.
In the 1730s the backlash was failing. Wolff’s expulsion from Halle had been a media event.
Wolff was as much leader of German philosophy in the eighteenth century as Hegel would become
later. Wolff’s German Metaphysics (1719) was a runaway bestseller racking up ten consecutive editions.
Halle had aspired to be the Princeton of Europe, and Wolff had been its vice-president. All over the
continent academics were talking about this scandal. More than four hundred treatises were written
on Wolff’s quarrel with the Pietists. The Confucian-Wolffian message—that only reason and observation
are needed to determine the good—was heard loudly and clearly, and Wolff’s students were propagating it.
Add to this the scientific paradigm change happening at the same time. The success of
Newton’s Principia (1687) was proving unstoppable. Its second edition (1713) had been reprinted
twice (1714 and ‘23) in Amsterdam (the freest place on earth). The definitive edition of the Principia
appeared a year after Kant’s birth, in 1725, which is also when John Keill’s physics textbook was
published in the Netherlands (Introductiones ad veram physicam et veram astronomiam). Wolff and his
German students embraced Newtonian physics, and (after Maupertuis’ conversion in 1732) the
French Cartesians followed suit. Once again, all over Europe intellectuals were talking about this.
Newton’s message—that only reason and observation are needed to elucidate nature—was heard loudly and
clearly too.
The Pietists, who had driven out Wolff, rejected Eastern philosophy and Western science,
and insisted that all you need to know is in the holy texts. Their skepticism deflated their own
authority. Galvanized by the encounter with Confucius’ philosophy of the good and the
Florida Philosophical Review
Vol. III, Issue 1, Summer 2003
13
appropriation of Newton’s philosophy of nature, the Age of Reason had come into its own. The
two sets of data now being disseminated—Eastern ethics and Western physics—resonated with each
other, mutually reinforcing the message of the power of the human mind. Now the Enlightenment
had arrived.
Taoism, in one sense, arrived later. A translation of the Tao Te Ching was presented to the
British Royal Society in 1788; it had no effect on Kant. Taoism became better known after his death
(in 1804), as Hegel’s writings show, and a Latin Tao appeared in 1823.15
But in another sense, Taoism arrived already with Couplet (1687) and Noël (1711). It
enjoyed a free ride on the Confucian Classics. Their characteristic feature is a holistic inclusiveness.
Chinese philosophy began with Confucianism and Taoism (5th and 6th C. BCE), followed by
polytheist Buddhism (2nd C. CE). Zen (chán) emerged in the seventh century in China (not Japan).
The spectrum from Confucianism to Taoism to Zen forms a philosophically consilient continuum.
Confucian scholars would have told you then, as they would tell you now, if your concern is
the “ought” for public life, read the Analects and the Mencius. If your concern is the “ought” for
private life, read the Doctrine of the Mean. And if your concern is the “is,” then read Mencius, and
Doctrine of the Mean once more, and study the Great Learning. The is-ought-distinction is a dogma of
Western skeptics and foreign to the East. Like Russian dolls, the Analects and the Mencius nestle in
the causal ontology of the Great Learning, which nestles in the cosmology of the Doctrine of the Mean.
The Doctrine of the Mean explains humanity or benevolence (ren) in terms of integrity (cheng), and
integrity in terms of following the Tao. This was the crucial link. Before Kant’s birth, the Doctrine of
the Mean had been translated twice. The Tao is explicit here; it is the first verse of the Third
Classic:16
What heaven [cosmos] imparts to man is called human nature [vitality]
(tian ming zhi wei xing)
To follow our nature [follow vitality] is called the Way
(shuai xing zhi wei dao)
Cultivating the Way is called education
(xiou dao zhi wei jiao)
The Way cannot be separated from us for a moment
(dao ye zhe, bu ke xuyu li ye)
And what can be separated from us is not the Way
(ke li fei dao ye)
The Jesuit knowledge transfer from China to Germany was a success. Christian Wolff
grasped, appropriated, and defended the essential unit of information. Wolff begins his vicepresidential address by relating the personal importance of the Taoist subtext of the Third Classic,
Florida Philosophical Review
Vol. III, Issue 1, Summer 2003
14
the dynamic resonance of natural structure with normative force. Wolff’s training was in the exact
sciences. Working with forms and functions had not only honed his cognitive abilities, but also
supplied him with the only perspective that makes the Tao intelligible and precise:17
When I took on the arduous business [of applying the geometric method to
philosophy], I had to learn that extraordinary progress is still needed in mathematics
for the sake of its heuristic structure . . . I also understood that the entire
philosophical canon had to be tied to mathematics. . . . Then I developed the
ontological concept of perfection . . . and was blessed (mihi datum fuerat) to see in
metaphysics the perfection of the entire universe . . . Afterwards I thought about the
direction of free actions toward the perfection of the microcosm (directionem actionum
liberarum ad perfectionem microcosmi ). (l. 17-20, 24-6, 32-8)
When applying the heuristic structure of mathematics to philosophy, Wolff saw the limits of
his tools. Still, philosophy must be tied to mathematics. Now Halle’s mathematics professor was a
bit stuck. But then he examined the definition of perfection and the dynamics of moral action—and
had an insight:
I realized that this direction [of free actions] is not different from the one prescribed
by the laws of nature (eam non diversam esse ab illa, quae lege naturali praecepta . . . habetur).
(l. 38-40)
A perfect cosmos is unified. Moral action in such a cosmos is deeply compatible with the
regularity of natural events. In the unified continuum, the overall thrust of beautiful and good deeds
lines up with the overall push of natural events, for the dynamic vectors of the good and nature are
identical:
That is, the same direction that strives for the perfection of the microcosm also
strives for the perfection of the macrocosm (eandemque directionem, quae ad microcosmi
perfectionem tendit, ad ipsam macrocosmi tendere perfectionem). (l. 40-42)
Thus Wolff concludes:
So I was finally convinced that the first principle . . . of decorum itself is the
direction of human activity to the perfection of the microcosm, and consequently to
the perfection of the macrocosm. (l. 42-45)
Wolff’s primum principium decori is the idea that the moral vector in the human sphere is the
same as a putative cosmic vector that governs nature’s development towards “perfection.” Wolff as
well as his eventual follower Kant understood cosmic perfection as nature’s well-ordered abundance.
As Kant would later point out, cosmic perfection is an evolving harmony, a diversity
(Mannigfaltigkeit) according to a rule, or the greatest variety in the greatest order (2:33; cf. also 2:93100). The unfolding (Auswickelung) of organized fruitfulness—what we now call biodiversity—is the
Florida Philosophical Review
Vol. III, Issue 1, Summer 2003
15
hallmark of nature’s growth towards perfection; indeed, the more of it, the better (1:306, 319-21,
347; 2:96). This is the decorum of nature. Well-ordered complexity is its point, and whether one
considers the vector’s astrophysical-ecological momentum or its local moral thrust does not make
any difference.
Although ridiculed in old age, Christian Wolff was a trailblazer in his youth, and Kant was
fortunate to learn from him. Wolff brazenly pushed the ontological envelope. His views were so
innovative because he derived them from outlandish sources:
Attentively studying the Classics . . . I was certain (nullus dubitavi) that the . . . Chinese,
particularly Confucius, had the same notion, albeit confused and vague, a notion that
can therefore be seen only by people who are getting it (ut non agnoscatur nisi a
possidente). (l. 46-49)
Now Wolff had his audience’s attention. His remark was politically incorrect in Pietist Halle,
part of authoritarian Prussia, ruled until 1740 by the pious soldier-king Friedrich Wilhelm I. Wolff
did not care whether his admission of “seeing the nature” (guandao ziran) provoked his listeners—
including the fundamentalist Joachim Lange (1670-1744) who was to be inaugurated as Wolff’s
successor at the end of the speech. Wolff would not pull any punches. Now he would come to the
point, the topic, and the beginning of the scholarly part of his speech:
After I rationally confirmed the doctrines and facts of the Classics, I understood that
my ethics and Chinese ethics match (praxin Sinarum a mea abludere intelligebam).18 (l. 4952)
Wolff’s declaration was intolerable to the Pietist fundamentalists. They plotted revenge and
drove him into exile two years later. In 1723, Wolff fled to Hesse to avoid execution. Halle
University was purged. Wolff’s assistants were fired; his students were dismissed; and his books
were removed from the library shelves, as were the Confucian Classics. An indirect victim of the
fall-out from Wolff’s speech was his student Georg Bernhard Bilfinger (1693-1750); he would be
fired from Tübingen University for standing up for Wolff. Bilfinger published a book on Chinese
philosophy (Specimen doctrinae veterum sinarum moralis et politica, 1724) and a defense of Wolff’s
metaphysics (Dilucidationes philosophicae de Deo, anima humana, mundo et generalibus rerum affectionibus,
1725), both of which were deemed unacceptable by the evangelical administrators of Tübingen’s
university.
Bilfinger engaged with guandao ziran, nature’s dynamic structure and its functional algorithm;
and once again a memetic transfer—now from Wolff to Bilfinger—occurred. Coincidence helped.
Three influences shaped Bilfinger’s views: the entelechy, interpreted by Leibniz as the force of any
substance; substances, defended by Wolff as force points organizing a cosmic grid; and the grid, the
nexus rerum or universal web, which Bilfinger interpreted, in an earlier tract, as the harmony of the
Florida Philosophical Review
Vol. III, Issue 1, Summer 2003
16
entelechies. This tract (De harmonia animae et corporis humani maxime praestabilitate, 1723) wound up on
the Index of Prohibited Books in 1734 as a warning to all Christians. Bilfinger was guided by
entelechies, force points, the web of nature, and the harmony of all things, and he was an expert on
Chinese thought. Such a reader of Confucius, cognizant of the dynamic harmony in the web, could
decode the Taoist subtext —and be helped along by the Third Classic, the speech of his advisor, and
the principle of decorum.
Bilfinger went to St Petersburg in 1725. The Russian Academy was dominated by Leibnizian
dynamics, and when Bilfinger joined in, the ingenious Daniel Bernoulli (1700-82) did so too, the
founder of fluid dynamics. Bilfinger was exposed to the vis viva-problem in natural philosophy. This
was the question of whether there exist “living forces” that govern bodily motion and possibly
everything else, and how to prove their quantity advanced by Leibniz. (This quantity, “mass” times
speed squared, would join science as kinetic energy, the space integral of force.) He turned to the
problem with a treatise called On Forces (w. 1725, p. 1728). It inspired Kant in not-too-distant
Prussia eighteen years later. Now the transmission was complete. Kant states that Bilfinger’s
approach informs his first book, Thoughts on the True Estimation of Living Forces (1747), and he says he
always uses Bilfinger’s research-rule: Truth is to be found in the harmony of opposites. Thus began
Kant’s career.19
Kant’s Force-Space-Bond and the Tao
In the first ten paragraphs of the Thoughts on the True Estimation of Living Forces, Kant lays out
his ontology. Nature consists of force points, whose activities are goal-directed, causal, and
harmonious. The ultimate elements are active forces (§ 1-3; 1:17-18). They govern everything that
happens—not only motions of bodies (§ 2; 1:18.6-8), but also the activities of all objects (§ 3;
1:18.27-36). This includes materially produced ideas as well as mentally intended actions (§ 6;
1:20.35-21.1; 21.14-16). Forces govern mind-body interaction.
Interaction turns out to be fundamental. Interaction governs dynamic action, Kant claims.
In interacting with the outside, a force acts external to itself (§ 4; 1:19.4-11). The capacity for outside
effects associates the presence of force with location (§ 6; 1:20.36-21.1). The force acting external to
itself affects its own vicinity. The vicinity affected by radiation locates the acting source within its
region. That force, in virtue of external action, is put “somewhere,” suggests a bond between force
and space. This bond is productive. Multiple localized forces constitute the world (§ 7) such that
their interaction forms a network (§ 8), which is by definition order (§ 8) and in fact space (§ 9).
Kant concludes that extension results from the external action of force (außer sich wirken, § 9; 1:23.58).
Florida Philosophical Review
Vol. III, Issue 1, Summer 2003
17
From the start (§ 1), Kant insists with Leibniz that “there is something over and above
extension, indeed prior to extension.”20 This “something” is force. Its effect (Wirkung) is radiation
(Ausbreitung). Force spreads, affecting its vicinity. The affected vicinity structures the spread,
shaping force. As the effected shaping occurs through the affecting spread, dynamic action is acted
upon, changing the action. Dynamic action is governed by interaction. As Kant sees it, radiation
and interaction govern each other. He analyzes this interaction in § 10. Force turns “nowhere” into
“somewhere”. A void is structured into a field. This structuring is lawful, Kant insists: substantial
forces, when united by interactions, propagate their strength in inverse proportion to the square of
the distances traversed (1:24.19-23).
Kant may have learned the inverse square from the Principia; as the rule governing gravity, it
is hard to miss. But he does not credit Newton. He uses it in a way that would have made the sober
Brit (dead since 1727), who hated feigning hypotheses on the cause of gravity, dryly turn in his
Westminster grave. For the cause of gravity is now identified: it is space-structuring force—
Aristotle’s entelechy that Leibniz had grasped first (§ 1), and in whose analysis the sinologist
Bilfinger shows Kant the way (§ 20).
Johannes Kepler—founder of celestial dynamics and for Leibniz an incomparable man—
formulated the inverse-square law as the principle of photo measurement. Kepler showed that the
intensity of light decreases with the square of the distance (1604).21 He viewed light as the
primordial living force; he suspected the structural identity of the radiation of light and gravity, and
he qualitatively applied the inverse-square to gravitation (1605).22 Newton tied the inverse-square to
Kepler’s planetary laws (De motu, 1684) and proved it for gravity (Principia, 1687). Kant’s use of the
law is as basic as Kepler’s. It governs the radiation of force, energy, or light. But Kant interprets the
law in a way that put his vision even beyond the ingeniously far-sighted Kepler (who, actually, had
eye problems).
In § 6-10, Kant identifies a force-space bond. Force is the primum, determining space. Once
space is there, the bond is bidirectional. Force fills space, ordering it; space places force, governing
it. Space dynamically expands; force structurally acts. Each needs the other. Without force, space
lacks enframing dimensionality and thus fails to place a world (Abmessungen or Dimensionen; § 9-10,
passim). Without space, force lacks acting location and thus fails to radiate a field (ausbreiten; § 10,
1:24.23). Radiation and continuum are what they are, because force is spaced, and space is forced.
This is their ontological bond. This first aperçu has been confirmed. Today we know that gravitating
mass curves spacetime, and that spacetime grips gravitating mass. Bypassing Newton, Kant
anticipated Einstein.
Then, according to § 10, the inverse square represents force propagation. The law governs
the radiation that structures space (1:24.15-16). Because this law rules the interactivity of substances
Florida Philosophical Review
Vol. III, Issue 1, Summer 2003
18
in general, it accordingly also (auch) determines their accretion and composition (1:24.12-18), which
entails that universal gravitation is subject to the law as well. This second aperçu is correct, just as the
first. The inverse square proportionality of dynamic strength and structural distance marks out
multiple fields. Because Kant found this out, and because it is true (within appropriate limits; his
third aperçu), it deserves to be capitalized as Kant’s Law. We can state Kant’s Law in modern terms:
The pressure of any point source radiation in a free field drops at a rate inversely
proportional to the square of propagated distance.
Kant’s Law governs various instantiations of free point source radiation. The law holds for
light (Kepler), gravity (Newton), sound, electrostatic force (Coulomb), radioactivity (Röntgen), radio
waves, and, with qualifications, for magnetism (Gauss and Ampere). As the history of physics
illustrates, Kant’s Law illuminates the bond of force and space in nature. Gauss’ and Ampere’s work
helped Maxwell and Lorentz, whose work guided Einstein. Kant’s Law also underlines the relevance
of Hawking’s work on black holes, the spikes of the force-space bond. A dramatic application of
the law, in its Keplerian instantiation, was Hubble’s measure of the luminosity of Cepheid variables
in 1924, the first step toward Hubble’s Law of cosmic expansion and the Big Bang.
According to the conclusion of § 10, the inverse-square governs the three-dimensionality of
the continuum (1:24.24-6), but, as Kant insists, this regularity is contingent; other relations between
strength and distance would result in different continua (1:24.26-30). The scientific place of this
aperçu today is not in fertile Minkowski space and solid accounts of the strong nuclear force. Its
place is now in quantum geometry and inchoate approximations to Calabi-Yau spaces, whose
topologies involve fluid regularities of the force-space bond. The final idea of § 10 is not confirmed.
We only know this: Kant’s ontology culminates with the aperçus of the bond, and the claimed
contingency is assumed by superstring theory.
Perhaps superstrings will lead to the master equation of the matrix. Kant implored
Leonhard Euler to read the Living Forces. His effusive praise shows he saw the significance of Euler’s
work. He wished Euler would see that he and Kant were on the same track. Euler’s work in
mathematical dynamics was just as seminal as Kepler’s, and his derivation of force would end the vis
viva-controversy in a formally elegant way. Kant writes that he thinks Euler is the only one able to
resolve the disharmony over force.23 Since Euler coined the beta-function (the trigger of the
superstring revolution), Kant’s hope is prophetic.
The sciences support Kant’s ideas of the bond—and remarkably, even on the deepest,
ontological level. As mentioned, Kant suggests that force is the primum, determining space, and that
force spreads, stretching space out. That is, space is not a void as Newton thought but instead a
dynamic expansion. Space is not empty; the void is energetic, this energy expands, and the more
expanded energy there is, the faster the void keeps expanding. In what has been hailed as “the
Florida Philosophical Review
Vol. III, Issue 1, Summer 2003
19
number one scientific discovery of 1998 in any field of research”, Kant’s odd metaphysical claim has
now been confirmed.24 So Kant is right—but to what extent does his insight correspond to its root?
Bilfinger studied the Classics and formulated a rule, the harmony of opposites, which guides the
Living Forces, as Kant says. To decide whether Kant’s ideas qualify as a Taoist “seeing the nature”
requires comparing his force-space bond to the Tao.
According to the Tao Te Ching, something profound exists (xuan, v. 1 and v. 6), which is
nature’s creative principle (tiandi mu, v. 1 and v. 25). Nature obeys a lawful patterning (fa, v. 25; see
note 8). The cosmic law (tian li, see section 2) is the “law of nature” (dao ji, v. 14). Since it shapes
nature, Toa is form and hence not formed itself (wu zhuang zhi zhuang, v. 14). As unbounded form,
Tao patterns nature by acting external to itself—it “fills” (dao zhong, v. 4; see note 7); it “flows,” “goes
out,” or “reaches” (shi, v. 25). Tao’s dynamic filling is “far reaching” or “flows distant” (shi yuan, v.
25). The distant flow always returns, always comes around (shi yuan fan; zhou xing er bu dai, ibid.).
Elsewhere in the Tao Te Ching, the action or motion of the Tao is described as a reversal (fan zhe dao
zhi dong, v. 40). That is, the unbounded form fills space by pushing outwards and by pulling
inwards—it is a structural-dynamic pulse. Laozi thus likens the plenum (tian di zhi jian, v. 5) to a
bellows (tuo, ibid.).
Because of the continuous character of nature’s unfolding it is a bit arbitrary how finely one
parses the process. A four-step model works for our purposes (cf. v. 1, 40, 42). The first stage of
nature’s self-organization, prior to the cosmic process, is Tao as a plain energy or a nonspatial void
(wu). The second stage, the start of the process, is Tao patterning itself into a plenum, thereby
generating the field between “heaven and earth” (tian dì). The third stage, emerging in the field, is
the existence of placed presences (you) in the fabric. The fourth stage is the progressive ordering of
the places from local charges to discrete objects (wan wu). The totality of objects is empirical reality,
structured by the energetic potential that Laozi calls Tao and Aristotle dynamis.
For Aristotle, dynamis is a potential that, when put in (en) action (ergon), is en-ergon or energeia;
energy. (The standard translations, “actuality” for energeia, and “possibility” for dynamis, fail to retain
the Greek flavor.) Aristotelian energy is dynamis put into operation, or, in the Latinized Aristotle, a
potentia put into agere, a potential acting. This potential has a telos guiding the energeia. Thus it has
(echein) a goal (telos) within (en). If one applies Aristotle’s claim to force points, with Leibniz, the
resulting model involves entelechies that have their goals within, and that are describable in
quantitative and dynamic terms. It is thus understandable why Kant begins his career (§ 1) with
complimenting Leibniz on his useful model of Aristotelian entelechy.
Force creates Ausdehnung (§ 9; cf. Laozi’s zhong) or extension. The “ex” of “extension”
means “out” or “outwards.” The Latin root tensio is reminiscent of “tension” because it derives
from tensum, the participle of tendere meaning “to tighten,” to expand,” or “to stretch.” Thus
Florida Philosophical Review
Vol. III, Issue 1, Summer 2003
20
extension or wu is the result of dynamis or dào, stretched out as a charged void. The result is captured in
the German Ausdehnung, the “out-stretching”. Out-stretching results from the outwards-directed
“filling” of the force (cf. Laozi’s zhong, v. 4, and shi, v. 25). The Ausdehnung of space is due to the
Ausbreitung of force. Kant’s term, Ausbreitung (§ 10), “out-broadening,” conveys Laozi’s dynamic
idea. For Kant, force can stretch out, creating location and place-change (§ 4, 1:19:5, 32). This
initial extension constitutes subsequent interaction. Force out-broadens itself (§ 9-10; cf. Laozi’s shi,
v. 25) such that its grip is inversely proportional to its squared stretch. This lawful out-stretching
creates space (Raum), which is order (Ordnung). Order locates the out-broadening (ausbreiten). Force
then radiates from local presence (Laozi’s you, v.1). Now copresent points act locally.
Because spatial order patterns the pulse to a plurality of local charges, force unfolds to the
set of points. The points act, emitting effects. The effects reach other local charges, affect them,
and pattern them to responses. The process from original extension to eventual response leads to
copresent charges whose radiations mutually pulse. Interaction ensues; like love, the closer, the
hotter. Ongoing interactivity generates lingering webs of pulses and counterpulses. Viable webs of
interactive substance-neighborhoods format themselves into engaged communities. Neighborly
interaction turns into communal “intra-action.” If harmonious, intra-action sustains the
communities as resonating structures, hence as things (Dinge; wan wu).25
A look at the lexical roots of the words clarifies what is meant. Ausdehnung, extensio, or outstretching, derives from dehnen, tendere, “stretch”. At the third stage of the process (when the already
outstretched plenum acquires places), extension does more than stretch. Structuring itself, force is
placed. Through places, extension contains substances; it has and holds them. Laozi uses you for this
stage (v.1). “Have” or “hold” is the basic sense of the morpheme.26
The Latin root of “extension” is tendere’s participle, tentum or tensum. Tendere, “stretch,” shares
its supinum with tenere, which meant originally “to be stretched out” and later “hold” or “grip.”
“Stretch” and “grip” have a familiar resonance in the word “entertain” (derived from the Middle
English entertene, meaning “to hold mutually,” descended through the Middle French entretenir from
intertenere, a medieval compound of tenere). When we entertain an idea, it has hold on us—as we on
it, since the idea and we interact. To get hold of something, we first need to stretch and reach it.
This applies to the force-space bond, organisms, and minds. Extended stretch becomes place when
force reaches, grips, and holds other forces, structuring the fabric.
Laozi and Kant share the same idea. What makes their insight compelling is that the
established scientific description supports it. It is unclear how the cosmos expands (slowing down,
speeding up, or moving at constant speed), but we know that it does. The Big Bang started with a
singularity. In terms of its nature, the singularity was sheer energeia. In terms of its activity, it
Florida Philosophical Review
Vol. III, Issue 1, Summer 2003
21
exploded as a dynamis and then patterned itself to nature. It remains measurable as universal 3-K
background radiation.
Historically, the Living Forces was an embarrassment for Kant. Because of ignorance (he was
young) and irritation (he was passed over by his pious mentor Knutzen, who liked Newton), he
failed to jump on the bandwagon of Newtonian mechanics. By describing force partly as Descartes’
vis mortua (‘mass’ times speed) and partly as Leibniz’s vis viva (‘mass’ times speed squared), he
exposed himself to ridicule, for force is Newton’s product of mass and acceleration. That he
approached force in ontological terms made it worse, because his peers heeded d’Alembert’s
injunction to reduce dynamic discourse to mathematics and experiments. Worst of all, the factual
and logical faults make the book turgid, and Kant was laughed at upon its publication.
But who laughs last, laughs best. Throughout the book Kant studies the harmony of
opposites, dead pressure and living force, trying to marry Cartesian momentum (mv) to Leibnizian
energy (mv2). And he was right. With the Living Forces Kant grasped the fundamental unity of
momentum and energy. And with the interactive spatial beat of § 10, he intuited that momenergy, in
harmony with mass or E/c2, is the conserved pulse of spacetime.27
Conclusion
If my conjectures are plausible, then a curious picture of Kant will have emerged by now.
Over several intermediate steps, Kant had been inspired by a Chinese idea—even though he may
not even have been aware of it. Although he may never have looked into the Classics and certainly
never read the Tao Te Ching (not published during his lifetime), his earliest and decisive inspiration
was an idea he got from the China-expert Bilfinger, who had it from Wolff and Leibniz, and who, in
turn, reacted to the Jesuit translations of the Confucian Classics.
The idea that inspired Kant had several aspects: Nature is energy; energy is a dynamic
interactivity; and dynamic interactivity is a harmony of opposites. These are facets of the Tao. The
Tao was not unique to Laozi’s Tao Te Ching. It haunts the canon of ancient Chinese literature, from
the I Ching to the Book of Rites (two of whose chapters are Confucian Classics, the Doctrine of the Mean
and the Great Learning). It is an element of Chinese culture—as Confucian humanity is the stance
governing ethics and anything social, the Tao is the idea governing the universe and anything
natural.
The information traveled. It was passed on, just like any other commodity. When it arrived
in Königsberg in 1745, it had already traveled a long way, on a journey that had begun in 1601, when
Ricci was admitted to Beijing, trying to preach the Gospel, while absorbing Chinese culture.
Through letters, tracts, and eventually translations, the Tao traveled from the Jesuit mission in
Florida Philosophical Review
Vol. III, Issue 1, Summer 2003
22
Beijing to the Portuguese and Dutch traders at the port of Macao. From there it sailed with the mail
to Lisbon in Portugal and Rotterdam in the Netherlands. Portugal was barren ground; too
conservative and Catholic. The Netherlands, however, was then the freest society on Earth (it
remains so today), and here the information could be communicated. Perhaps it infected Spinoza in
nearby Amsterdam; we do not know. It certainly intrigued Leibniz, who passed by Amsterdam on
his way from Paris to Hanover. The Paris-Hanover road extended to Leipzig, a commercial center
situated at the crossroads with Prussia (Berlin), Bohemia (Prague), and Russia (St. Petersburg).
Thomasius may have been exposed to the idea in Leipzig, his decorum makes one wonder, but once
again, we do not know. But Wolff’s decorum is a different story—we know the Tao fascinated him
in Halle, only ten miles from Leipzig. Wolff’s scandalous speech led to a major infection, and now
the vector spread with Bilfinger first to Tübingen and then to St Petersburg, at whose academy the
Leibnizian researchers on dynamics were gathering. And St Petersburg at the western end of Russia
is not far from Königsberg at the eastern end of Prussia, where Kant studied Bilfinger’s research.
Information spreads, and during the Enlightenment information traveled quickly.
During its travels, the information changed. Communication is inevitably interpretation, and
interpretation is transformation. The Chinese “way” (dao) was rendered as “nature’s reason or
rational nature” (natura rationalis). The Jesuit translators had read it to mean that nature, created by a
benevolent and omnipotent Christian God, is consistent and accessible to reason. At its Eastern
departure, the Tao was paradoxical and elusive; at its Western arrival, it had become uniform and
rational—so much the better for scientific investigation. That things change when the travel is not
limited to ideas, it affects other commodities too. Marco Polo had brought rice noodles from China
to Italy—where one subsequently cooked spaghetti. But as rice noodles and spaghetti are still
noodles, the Tao was still energy. In Kant, in particular, dynamic interactivity had still retained some
its dialectical flavor: the harmony of opposites.
In Kant’s first book, the information—disguised as Bilfinger’s rule of the middle way and as
Leibniz’s dynamic reading of entelechy—blossomed into the ontology of force. Reality is a dynamic
between the bond of energy and continuum, momentum-energy and spacetime. Force pumps out
nature. When concentrated to a focal point (Kant’s “burning point” or Brennpunkt; cf. 2:334.7), the
energy is as hot as it gets. It pulses outward toward complexity. Was this just an odd beginning, a
first false step for Kant?
It seems fitting to end this speculative quest with questions. If his earliest vision, of an
energetic bond flaring out structure, was just a first false step, why would Kant, of all people, earn
his Master’s degree in philosophy (1754), with Meditation on Fire, of all things? Why would he then
turn to investigate anything that moves, shakes, pushes and pulls—from the fate of Earth’s rotation
governed by tidal beats (Spin Cycle essay, 1754) to earthquakes (three tracts, 1756) to winds, storms,
Florida Philosophical Review
Vol. III, Issue 1, Summer 2003
23
and weather pumps like the monsoon (Theory of Winds, 1756; West Wind essay, 1757)? Why would
he, in his second book, Universal Natural History (1755), explain the self-organization of the cosmos
from chaos to complexity with the interplay of pushes and pulls, repulsion and attraction,
antigravity and gravity? And be so certain that he is right that he proclaims proudly, with Voltaire,
to just give him matter, and he would build a world with it (1:229)? While warning Christian zealots
against opposing science—if they did, he declares, they would be defeated (1:222, 225)?
Why would he earn his doctorate (1755) with a dissertation on metaphysical cognition—
while stating, as the first principle of his New Elucidation, an identity-pair of opposites, “whatever is,
is, and whatever is not, is not” (1:389)? Why would he state, as his final principle, an interactive
harmony, the principle of coexistence (1:412)? While, in passing, solving the problem of freedom
in nature dynamically? Why would he harmonize the opposites of freedom and necessity over
force—defining a free will as something that is not being pushed around, but that is a “determining
power” instead, a power that can withstand impulses and remain spontaneous (1:404)?
Furthermore, why would Kant earn his professorial degree (1756) with a habilitation over
elementary particles—that are physical, but energetic monads? While explaining how indivisible
force points can create spatial things by pulsing out active spheres, dynamic spacelets, the tiniest
dimensional spheres of nature (1:481)—thus anticipating the Calabi-Yau spaces in the superstring
and M-theories of today?
Or why would Kant, in his third book, Only Possible Argument (1763), turn to reflect on God,
describing It as a necessary, unified, and constant being, deriving Its existence from possibility,
visible in nature in the design resulting from the “inner possibility of things” (2:91-2)—“possibility,”
which, as we have seen, is Möglichkeit in German, possibilitas in Latin, and dynamis in Greek?
Understandably having second thoughts, knowing he had gone too far (it is one thing to get
from force to fire, tides, and winds, but quite another to get from force to God), he retracted,
became a critic of metaphysics and a geographer of cognition next. So he bifurcated nature, in the
Inaugural Dissertation (1770), into the sensible and the intelligible. But do not these opposites
harmonize, and harmonize over interaction? Why would Kant then account for knowledge, in the
Critique of Pure Reason (1781), by determining it as the result of the interaction of sensory information
and intelligible tools?
And why, even there, would he insist that cognitive interactivity—knowledge—is grounded
in dynamic interactivity, the spatial plenum or force field (A 212-215/B258-262)? And when he
turned to ethics, in the Foundations of Metaphysics of Morals (1785)—why would this foundation with
absolute worth be a good will (4:393)? Why would it be neither a deed nor its outcome, but instead
its intention, its impulse, its dynamic thrust? In its thrust, a conscious force stretches out from the
subjective center. It encounters the other; and pays attention (Achtung; 4:436); and responds, as a
Florida Philosophical Review
Vol. III, Issue 1, Summer 2003
24
good will, interactively and appropriately, granting the other her dignity.
And so the circle closes. Kant set out with the force-space bond when he was young and
forty years later arrived at respect for humanity. A student once asked Confucius what humanity
means. Confucius replied, “Don’t do to others what you don’t want to be done to you”. The
student was not happy. “That’s quite a mouthful,” he said, “isn’t there, like, a shorter version?”
Confucius said: shu! Translated: “reciprocity” or “light-hearted forgiveness.”
Florida Philosophical Review
Vol. III, Issue 1, Summer 2003
25
Notes
1
The phrase is by Shi-Chuan Chen, “How to Form a Hexagram and Consult the I Ching,” Journal of
the American Oriental Society 92 (1972): 248. Explaining non-Western realism, he writes: “There is a
deep conviction of the Chinese that no lines of demarcation exist between man and heaven and
earth [the so-called Principle of the Three Participants] . . . Because of this principle the ancient
Chinese avoided becoming victims of the fallacy of the bifurcation of nature. The derivatives from
the bifurcation, namely, the separation of the subjective from the objective, the distinction of the
primary and secondary qualities, and the confrontation of the ego and non-ego, have not tortured
the Chinese mind.”
2
I am grateful to many colleagues for their ideas. I would like to thank Karl Ameriks for identifying
Kant’s early monism (Karl Ameriks, Kant’s Theory of the Mind, [Oxford and New York: Oxford UP,
1982] 29-30, 85-86); Sidney Axinn and Ivan Marquez for discussions on the dynamics of ethics; Fred
Beiser for fleshing out Kant’s love for metaphysics (Frederick Beiser, “Kant’s Intellectual
Development: 1746-1781,” Cambridge Companion to Kant, ed. P. Guyer [Cambridge and New York:
Cambridge UP, 1992] 26-61); Andrew Carpenter for discussions on Kant’s inverse-square law;
Jeffrey Edwards for discovering the implications of Kant’s Third Analogy (Jeffrey Edwards,
Substance, Force, and the Possibility of Knowledge [Los Angeles and San Francisco: California UP, 2000] 18, 46-7, 165-6); Paul Guyer for pointing to Kant’s reflections on animal souls (Paul Guyer,
“Organisms and the Unity of Science,” Kant and the Sciences, ed. E. Watkins [Oxford and New York:
Oxford UP, 2001] 268; see also Immanuel Kant, Werke, ed. W. Dilthey et al. [Berlin: Reimer, later
De Gruyter, 1902ff] 28:275); Kenneth Westphal for encouraging my Keplerian hunches; Kwasi
Wiredu for stressing the relevance of nonwestern monism; and Manfred Kuehn for discovering
Kant’s disbelief in an afterlife and in a monotheistic God (Manfred Kuehn, Kant: A Biography
[Cambridge and New York: Cambridge UP, 2001] 2-5, 382, 369-78, 385-92). I also thank Jau-Wei
Dan (Taipei Teachers College, Taiwan) for his insights on Zhuangzi; Diane Nai-Yu Schönfeld and
Yung-Ming Shu (Hsinchu Teachers College, Taiwan) for discussions of the Taoist basis of
Confucianism; and Master Jian-Mieng Liu (Zen Center Meinong, Kaoshiung, Taiwan) for most
helpful clarification.
3
I quote from Kant, Werke (1902ff.; Academy edition) by volume and page. If applicable, line
numbers are given. I quote from Kant, Critique of Pure Reason [1781/1787], trans. N.K. Smith (New
York: St. Martins, 1965) by (A) and (B) paginations.
4
Max Caspar, Kepler, trans. C. D. Hellman (London: Abelard-Schuman, 1959) 290.
5
Lao Tzu, Tao Te Ching, trans. S. Addiss and S. Lombardo (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1993) 4; Lao Tsu,
Tao Te Ching, trans. G. Feng and J. English (New York: Vintage, 1997) 4. Compare also verse 25.
Florida Philosophical Review
6
Vol. III, Issue 1, Summer 2003
26
Shi-Qiou Liang and Fang-Jie Zhang, Yuandong Han-Ying Da Chidian/Far East Chinese-English
Dictionary (Taipei: Yuandong Tushu Gongshi, 1999) # 2801, 843-4.
7
Cf. Tao Te Ching, verse 8: “Water benefits all things and does not compete / It flows in lowly places
men reject and is thus close to the Tao;” verse 32: “ Tao in nature is like rivers running into the sea;”
verse 34: “Great Tao flows everywhere /. . . / All beings derive life from it” (my trans.). Water is an
apt symbol of Tao. Astrophysically, water is common in the universe, suggesting Tao’s universality.
Environmentally, water forms the hydrologic cycle, mirroring Tao’s animating pulse. Chemically,
water is the only compound that expands when it crystallizes, thus evoking the spatial swelling of
Tao’s natural self-organization.
8
“Dao . . . yuanshi ji kongxu de, wu suo bu bao, wu wei bu ru;” commentary by Ren-Gong Liang in
Laozi, Dao De Jing, ed. Yu-Tang Lin (Taipei: Wenzhi, 1992) 9. Compare also Lao Tzu, Tao Te Ching,
verse 32. I would like to thank Guan-Xiong Xu, Nangong Taoist Institute, Mucha, Taiwan, for his
assistance.
9
Fa is “institution, law” (as in fajia, Legalism), as well as “method” or “way of doing things.” As a
verb, fa means “to pattern or model after, to emulate”; cf. Liang and Zhang, # 2832, 854-6. The
semantic key of fa, just as the key of zhong (“fill”) is shui—water. For this symbol of Tao, see note 6.
One should not read too much into Chinese characters (not every stroke is there for a reason), but
examining fa is interesting. Given its semantic key, one could conceptualize fa as the water-like
action pattern that mirrors Tao’s pulse. The dynamic aspect of fa is depicted in the character’s main
part, which, sans water-radical, is pronounced in modern Mandarin qu—go. The top segment of the
“go”-part of fa exists as a free graph as well and is pronounced tu—the Earth. Fa, the lawful
patterning, evokes a “going” ruled by “earth”. The patterning, the vector denoted by fa, would thus
be a lawful way, ruled by nature or earth, going “somewhere.” As the second meaning of the “go”component qu is leave, nature’s vector is transcendent, pointing from the rule of the Earth to the
Tao, the highest good (v. 8).
10
Martin Heidegger, “Brief über den Humanismus”[1946], Wegmarken (Frankfurt: Klostermann,
1996) 313. Compare Heidegger, Basic Writings, ed. and trans. D.F. Krell (San Francisco: Harper,
1993) 217.
11
Edward O. Wilson, Consilience: The Unity of Knowledge (New York: Vintage, 1998): 294; see also 1014, 43-8 and 227-8.
12
S. J. Yves Raguin, Ways of Contemplation East and West (Taipei: Ricci Institute for Chinese Studies,
1993-2001) vol. 4, 323. I would like to thank the Ricci Institute, Taipei for its assistance with
documents on the Jesuit China mission.
13
Michael Albrecht, “Einleitung,” Christian Wolff, Oratio de Sinarum philosophia practica, ed. Michael
Albrecht (Hamburg: Meiner, 1985) xvi; compare David E. Mungello, Leibniz and Confucianism: The
Florida Philosophical Review
Vol. III, Issue 1, Summer 2003
27
Search for Accord (Honolulu: Hawaii UP, 1977) 5, 19-20; John K. Fairbank and Merel Goldman, China:
A New History, enlarged ed. (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard UP, 1992) 147-61, 480.
14
The translations are S.J. Philippe Couplet, Confucius sinarum philosophus, sive Scientia Sinensis Latine
exposita (Paris 1687) and S.J. François Noël, Sinensis imperii libri classici sex, nimirum Adultorum Schola
[the Da Xue or “Great Learning”], Immutabile Medium [the Zhong Yong or “Doctrine of the Mean”],
Liber Sententiarum [the Lun Yu or “Analects”], Mencius [the Mengzi or “Book of Mencius”], Filialis
Observantia [the minor Xiao Jing or “Book of Filial Piety”], Parvulorum Schola [the medieval Xiao Xue or
“Youth Learning”], e Sinico idiomate in Latinum traducti (Prague 1711). Wolff reviewed Noël’s Chinahandbook (1708) in the journal Acta Eruditorum in 1711, and Noël’s translation in a two-part essay in
Acta Eruditorum in 1712. His reviews appeared anonymously. Compare Albrecht xxii-xxviii, liii-lxii.
For details on the works mentioned, see Albrecht 305-312. For Wolff’s superlative praise of
Confucius in the Oratio, see Christian Wolff, Oratio de Sinarum Philosophia Practica [1723], ed. M.
Albrecht. (Hamburg: Meiner, 1985) 7-13, 19, 65.
15
For the translation history, see James Legge, “Preface,” The Texts of Taoism [1891], ed. James Legge,
2 vols. (New York: Dover, 1962) xii-xiii.
16
Translation by Wing-Tsit Chan, A Source Book in Chinese Philosophy (New Jersey: Princeton UP,
1969) 98. Additions in brackets are mine. The pinyin transliteration is based on Zhongyong Jiyi
(Taipei: Sangyang, 1985) 2, 6.
17
The subsequent citations are from Wolff 4-6. Line numbers are indicated with “l” followed by
numeral. My translation.
18
The match between Wolff’s and Chinese ethics turns on what Wolff calls the decorum. It helps to
remember that the term derives from Latin decere, “to befit.” Decorum is manners and the same as
Confucian Ritual (li), which gave its name to the Rites Controversy. The Analects (1.12) defines ritual
(li) as harmony (he) or “the fitness of things” (shi zhi yi). See Confucius, The Analects, trans. R.
Dawson (Oxford and New York: Oxford UP, 1993); compare James Legge, ed., The Confucian
Analects, the Great learning, and the Doctrine of the Mean [1893] (New York: Dover, 1971) 143 note, and
Confucius 4. As a fitness of things, decorum is “the Tao of the ancient kings” (lao wang zhi dao;
Analects 1.12); see Legge 143. Neo-Confucianists named it the “decorum of heaven” (tian li).
Confucius defines it as a form of humaneness (ren) and explicates it as the negative Golden Rule,
“do not impose on others what you would not like yourself” (ji suo bu yu, wu shi yu ren; Analects 12.2,
15.23). Christian Thomasius (1655-1728), the father of the German Enlightenment, Halle’s
president (Direktor) in 1721, and probably in Wolff’s audience too, had repeatedly defended the
decorum. Thomasius defines it as the positive Golden Rule (quod vis ut alii tibi faciant, tu ipsis facies) in
Fundamenta Juris Naturae et Gentium. See Christian Thomasius, Fundamenta Juris Naturae et Gentium
[1705] (Aalen: Scientia, 1963) 177. To my knowledge, the historical influence of Confucius on
Florida Philosophical Review
Vol. III, Issue 1, Summer 2003
28
Thomasius, if any, has not been investigated.
19
Bilfinger’s De viribus corpori moto insitis et illarum mensura appeared in the journal of the Russian
Academy at St Petersburg, Commentarii Academicae Petropolitanae in 1728. For Bilfinger’s rule in De
viribus, # 16, see Juan Arana Canedo-Aguelle’s commentary in Immanuel Kant, Pensamientos Sobre la
Verdadera Estimación de las Fuerzas Vivas, ed. and trans. J.A. Canedo-Aguelle (Bern: Lang, 1988) 354.
For Kant’s adoption of Bilfinger’s rule, see Gedanken zur wahren Schätzung der lebendigen Kräfte, # 20, in
Kant, Werke (1902ff.) 1:32.5-7.
20
Gedanken zur wahren Schätzung der lebendige Kräfte, # 1, in Kant, Werke (1902ff) 1:17.22-23. All
further references to this text indicate the pagination of this edition.
21
Johannes Kepler, Astronomia pars optica [1604] prop. 9, Gesammelte Werke, ed. Max Caspar et al.
(Munich: Beck, 1937ff.) 2:22. For the dictum of the “incomparable man” (vir incomparabilis), see Max
Caspar, “Einleitung,” Kepler 1:vii.
22
Astronomia pars optica, ch. 1 “De natura lucis,” margin: “Lucis encomium,” Kepler 2:19.31-9. Kepler
characterizes light as the principle of all that beautifies the world, the instrument of the Creator, the
matrix (matrix) of animal faculties, and the bond (vinculum) of body and mind. For Kepler’s gravityaperçu, see the letter to David Fabricius (11 Oct. 1605), Kepler 15:240-80 (# 358), esp. 241.67-73;
and Astronomia nova (1609), “Introductio,” margin: “Vera doctrina de gravitate,” Kepler 3:25.19-24.
23
See Kant’s letter to Euler, 23. August 1749: “I dare to submit my tract to the judgment of a person,
whose extraordinarily sharp mind is far more adept than others at leading this initial striving (den
Anfang der Bestrebung) in these bad essays to the final and complete resolution of the disharmony
(Uneinigkeit) among such great scholars.” My translation. Not in Kant (1902ff.). For the original, see
Harald-Paul Fischer, “Kant and Euler,” Kant-Studien 76 (1985): 217. Compare Immanuel Kant,
Correspondence, ed. and trans. A. Zweig (Cambridge and New York: Cambridge UP, 1999): 45-6.
24
See Martin Rees, Just Six Numbers. The Deep Forces that Shape the Universe (London and New York:
Phoenix/Basic Books, 2001) 106. Rees refers to a 1999 ranking by the journal Science. The
discovery was the effort of teams by Saul Perlmutter and Brian P. Schmidt, who measured
supernovae, saw that they were dimmer than expected, and concluded that they were more distant
than their redshifts suggest. After eliminating rival hypotheses, Perlmutter and Schmidt recognized
that the cosmos had expanded more slowly in the past than previously assumed: cosmic expansion is
now speeding up. See Saul Perlmutter et al., “Discovery of a Supernova Explosion at Half the Age
of the Universe,” Nature 391 (1998): 51-54 and Adam G. Riess et al., “Observational Evidence from
Supernovae for an Accelerating Universe and a Cosmological Constant,” Astronomical Journal 116
(1998): 1009-1038. Summarizing the discovery, Rees notes, “an unsuspected new force—a cosmic
‘antigravity’—controls the expansion of the universe” (3). John D. Barrow, The Book of Nothing
(London: Vintage, 2001) gives an account of this discovery and its background worth quoting in full:
Florida Philosophical Review
Vol. III, Issue 1, Summer 2003
29
“The quantum revolution [in physics] showed us why the old picture of the vacuum as an empty box
was untenable. Henceforth the vacuum was simply the state that remained when everything that
could be removed from the box was removed. That state was by no means empty. It was merely
the lowest energy state available. . . . Gradually, this exotic new picture of quantum nothingness
succumbed to experimental exploration. . . . Physicists discovered that their defensive definition of
the vacuum as what was left when everything that could be removed had been removed was not as
silly as it sounds. There was always something left: a vacuum energy that permeated every fiber of
the Universe. . . . Last year [1998], two teams of astronomers used Earth’s most powerful telescopes
together with the incomparable optical power of the Hubble Space Telescope to gather persuasive
evidence for the reality of cosmic vacuum energy. Its effects are dramatic. It is accelerating the
expansion of the Universe” (10-12).
25
Laozi’s wanwu, verse 1, is “ten thousand things.” It denotes everything, from noble gases to
biospheres to minds. For Heidegger, wanwu is alles Seiendes, from Zeug to Dasein.
26
Laozi’s you means “to have, to be present, to exist, there is;” see Liang and Zhang # 2315: 727. A
typical usage is in “you meiyou”—“you;” “you have it?”—“I have it.”
27
Momentum and energy are the quantities describing masses moving through space and time. In
collisions, the values of momentum and energy differ before and after impact, but their sum remains
the same. They form a union; momentum and energy (or “momenergy,” a term coined by J. A.
Wheeler) hang together just like space and time do. Put differently, momentum-energy is the
correlate to spacetime. Dynamically, momentum-energy is as fundamental as it gets: it is
proportional to mass, it is conserved in the universe, and it is invariant in relativistic frames of
reference. That matter “somehow” contains energy actually means that mass is momentum-energy.
This is Kant’s force. A weak aspect of momentum-energy is gravity (noticeable only in very large
masses), the organizing force of the cosmos. Kant’s force-space bond, in modern physics, is a bond
of momentum-energy (gravitating mass) and spacetime. As John A. Wheeler puts it: mass grips
spacetime, telling it how to curve; spacetime grips spacetime, transmitting curvature from near to
far; and spacetime grips mass, telling it how to move. See J. A. Wheeler, Gravity and Spacetime (New
York: Scientific American 1990) 3, 11-13, 114.
Florida Philosophical Review
Vol. III, Issue 1, Summer 2003
30
Works Cited
Albrecht, Michael. “Einleitung.” In Christian Wolff, Oratio de Sinarum philosophia practica. 1723. Ed.
M. Albrecht. Hamburg: Meiner, 1985.
Ameriks, Karl. Kant’s Theory of the Mind. Oxford/New York: Oxford UP, 1982.
Barrow, John D. The Book of Nothing. London: Vintage, 2001.
Beiser, Frederick C. “Kant’s Intellectual Development: 1746-1781.” Cambridge Companion to Kant. Ed.
P. Guyer. Cambridge, UK/New York: Cambridge UP, 1992.
Caspar, Max. “Einleitung.” In Johannes Kepler. Gesammelte Werke. 30 vols. Ed. Max Caspar et al.
Munich: Beck, 1937ff.
_____. Kepler. Trans. C. D. Hellmann. London: Abelard-Schuman, 1959.
Chan, Wing-Tsit. A Source Book in Chinese Philosophy. New Jersey: Princeton UP, 1969.
Chen, Shi-Chuan. “How to Form a Hexagram and Consult the I Ching.” Journal of the American
Oriental Society 92 (1972): 237-48.
Confucius. The Analects. Trans. R. Dawson. Oxford and New York: Oxford UP, 1993.
Edwards, Jeffrey. Substance, Force, and the Possibility of Knowledge. Los Angeles and San Francisco:
California UP, 2000.
Fairbank, John King and Goldman, Merel. China: A New History. Enlarged ed. Cambridge, Mass.:
Harvard UP, 1992.
Fischer, Harald-Paul. “Kant and Euler.” Kant-Studien 76 (1985): 214-218.
Guyer, Paul. “Organisms and the Unity of Science.” Kant and the Sciences. Ed. E. Watkins. Oxford and
New York: Oxford UP, 2001.
Florida Philosophical Review
Vol. III, Issue 1, Summer 2003
31
Heidegger, Martin. Basic Writings. Ed. and trans. D. F. Krell. San Francisco: Harper, 1993.
_____. “Brief über den Humanismus” 1946. Wegmarken. Frankfurt: Klostermann, 1996.
Kant, Immanuel. Werke. 29 vols. Ed. W. Dilthey et al. Berlin: Reimer, later De Gruyter, 1902ff.
_____. Critique of Pure Reason. 1781/1787. Trans. N. K. Smith. New York: St Martins, 1965.
_____. Werke: Akademie-Textausgabe. 10 vols. Ed. W. Dilthey et al. Berlin: De Gruyter, 1968.
_____. Pensamientos sobre la verdadera estimación de las fuerzas vivas. Ed. and trans., with commentary, by
J. A. Canedo-Aguelle. Bern: Lang, 1988.
_____. Correspondence. Ed. and trans. A. Zweig. Cambridge, UK and New York: Cambridge UP,
1999.
Kepler, Johannes. Gesammelte Werke. 30 vols. Ed. Max Caspar et al. Munich: Beck, 1937ff.
Kuehn, Manfred. Kant: A Biography. Cambridge, UK and New York: Cambridge UP, 2001.
Lao Tzu. Tao Te Ching. Trans. S. Addiss and S. Lombardo. Indianapolis: Hackett, 1993.
_____. Tao Te Ching. Trans. G. Feng and J. English. New York: Vintage, 1997.
Laozi. Dao De Jing. Ed. Y. T. Lin. Taipei: Wenzhi, 1992.
Legge, James, ed. The Texts of Taoism. 1891. 2 vols. New York: Dover, 1962.
_____, ed. The Confucian Analects, the Great Learning, and the Doctrine of the Mean. 1893. New York: Dover,
1971.
Liang, Shi-Qiou, and Zhang, Fang-Jie. Yuandong Han-Ying Da Chidian: Far East Chinese-English
Dictionary. Second ed. Taipei: Yuandong Tushu Gongshi, 1999.
Mungello, David E. Leibniz and Confucianism: The Search for Accord. Honolulu: Hawaii UP, 1977.
Florida Philosophical Review
Vol. III, Issue 1, Summer 2003
32
Perlmutter, Saul, et al. “Discovery of a Supernova Explosion at Half the Age of the Universe.”
Nature 391 (1998): 51-54.
Raguin, Yves, S. J. Ways of Contemplation East and West. 4 vols. Taipei: Ricci Institute for Chinese
Studies, 1993-2001.
Rees, Martin. Just Six Numbers. The Deep Forces that Shape the Universe. London and New York:
Phoenix/Basic Books, 2001.
Riess, Adam G., et al. “Observational Evidence from Supernovae for an Accelerating Universe and a
Cosmological Constant.” Astronomical Journal 116 (1998): 1009-1038.
Thomasius, Christian. Fundamenta Juris Naturae et Gentium. 1705. Aalen: Scientia, 1963.
Wilson, Edward O. Consilience: The Unity of Knowledge. New York: Vintage, 1998.
Wheeler, John A. A Journey into Gravity and Spacetime. New York: Scientific American, 1990.
Wolff, Christian. Oratio de Sinarum Philosophia Practica. 1723. Ed. M. Albrecht. Hamburg: Meiner,
1985.
Zhongyong Jiyi. Taipei: Sangyang, 1985.
Download