Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 1 UTIL V DEONT UTIL BAD = DESTROYS HMN DIGNITY ................................................................................................................2 UTIL BAD = DECREASES VALUE OF HMN LIFE..................................................................................................5 UTIL BAD = DILUTES QUAL OF LIFE ....................................................................................................................7 UTIL BAD = JUSTIFIES DEATHS OF MILLIONS ...................................................................................................8 UTIL BAD = FOUNDATION FOR WAR ...................................................................................................................9 UTIL BAD = JUSTIFIES SLAVERY.........................................................................................................................11 UTIL BAD = TYRANNY...........................................................................................................................................12 UTIL BAD = 4 REASONS (1/2).................................................................................................................................13 UTIL BAD = ANTHROCENTRIC.............................................................................................................................15 UTIL BAD = IMPOSSIBLE .......................................................................................................................................16 UTIL BAD = SPILLS OVER......................................................................................................................................18 UTIL BAD = JUSTIFIES HOLOCAUST...................................................................................................................19 UTIL BAD = SCHELL INDICT.................................................................................................................................22 DEONT GOOD = BETTER POLICY MAKING .......................................................................................................23 DEONT GOOD = INT HMN RTS..............................................................................................................................24 DEONT GOOD = PRECEDES UTIL (1/2) ................................................................................................................25 DEONT GOOD = OUTWEIGHS UTIL .....................................................................................................................30 DEONT GOOD = PREVENTS TORTURE ...............................................................................................................31 DEONT GOOD = FW INDEPENDENT OF UTIL ....................................................................................................32 DEONT GOOD = MORAL IMPERATIVE ...............................................................................................................33 DEONT GOOD = BEST POLICY OPTION, PREVENTS GENOCIDE ...................................................................35 DEONT GOOD = INCREASES VALUE OF WORLD .............................................................................................36 DEONT GOOD = PREVENTS GENOCIDE/TORTURE ..........................................................................................37 A2: DEONT DISMISSES CONSEQUENCES ...........................................................................................................38 A2: UTIL CAN SOLVE DEONT (1/3).......................................................................................................................39 Util good – Public Policy.............................................................................................................................................42 Util good – Values life.................................................................................................................................................45 Util good – Best Justice ...............................................................................................................................................47 Util good – Solves morality.........................................................................................................................................48 Util good – Utility best FW for individual advocacy 1/2 ............................................................................................50 Util good – Solves cultural relativism .........................................................................................................................52 Util good – solves equality ..........................................................................................................................................53 Util good – Scientifically backed ................................................................................................................................54 Util good – Universially applicative............................................................................................................................55 Consequentialism good – Weigh benefits/consequences.............................................................................................56 Consequentialism good – Evaluating Catastrophic Consequences..............................................................................57 Consequentialism good – Solves morality...................................................................................................................58 Consequentialism good – Solves genocide in policy making......................................................................................60 Nuclear War Outweighs ..............................................................................................................................................61 Consequentialism = Inevitable ....................................................................................................................................64 Deontology bad – Lacks humanity / morality..............................................................................................................65 Deontology Bad – Contridicts itself ............................................................................................................................66 Deontology bad – Justifies killings..............................................................................................................................67 A2: Util and freedom mutally exclusive......................................................................................................................68 A2: Utilitarianism kills human rights. .........................................................................................................................69 A2: Util doesn’t account for separateness ...................................................................................................................70 A2: util= suffering .......................................................................................................................................................71 Survival outweighs in African Morality ......................................................................................................................72 Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 2 UTIL V DEONT UTIL BAD = DESTROYS HMN DIGNITY The utilitarian viewpoint is flawed. It is impossible for society to be viewed as a single entity without sacrificing the human dignity of the individual. Will Kymlicka, 1988 (Prof. of Philosophy at Queen’s U, Press, Philosophy and Public Affairs, Vol. 17, No. 3., pp. 172-190, ‘Rawls on Technology and Deontology” JSTOR) According to Rawls, then, the debate over distribution is essentially a debate over whether we should or should not define the right as maximizing the good. But is this an accurate characterization of the debate? Utilitarians do, of course, believe that the right act maximizes happiness, under some description of that good. And that requirement does have potentially abhorrent consequences. But do utilitarians believe that it is right because it maximizes happiness? Do they hold that the maximization of the good defines the right, as teleological theories are said to do? Let us see why Rawls believes they do. Rawls says that utilitarianism is teleological (that is, defines the right as the maximization of the good) because it generalizes from what is rational in the one-person case to what is rational in many-person cases. Since it is rational for me to sacrifice my present happiness to increase my later happiness if doing so will maximize my happiness overall, it is rational for society to sacrifice my current happiness to increase someone else's happiness if doing so maximizes social welfare overall. For utilitarians, utility-maximizing acts are right because they are maximizing. It is because they are maximizing that they are rational. Rawls objects to this generalization from the one-person to the many person case because he believes that it ignores the separateness of persons.? Although it is right and proper that I sacrifice my present happiness for my later happiness if doing so will increase my overall happiness, it is wrong to demand that I sacrifice my present happiness to increase someone else's happiness. In the first case, the trade-off occurs within one person's life, and the later happiness compensates for my current sacrifice. In the second case, the trade-off occurs across lives, and I am not compensated for my sacrifice by the fact that someone else benefits. My good has simply been sacrificed, and I have been used as a means to someone else's 2. John Rawls, A Theory ofJz~stice(Cambridge: Harvard University Press, rg71), p. 31 3. Ibid., p. 27. Philosophy G Public Affairs happiness. Trade-offs that make sense within a life are wrong and unfair across lives. Utilitarians obscure this point by ignoring the fact that separate people are involved. They treat society as though it were an individual, as a single organism, with its own interests, so that trade-offs between one person and another appear as legitimate trade-offs within the social organism. Utilitarians view society as a single entity, which devalues the rights and human dignity of the individual. Will Kymlicka, 1988 (Prof. of Philosophy at Queen’s U, Press, Philosophy and Public Affairs, Vol. 17, No. 3., pp. 172-190, ‘Rawls on Technology and Deontology” JSTOR) Scott Gordon echoes this interpretation of utilitarianism when he says that utilitarians adopt the view "that 'society' is an organic entity and contend that its utility is the proper objective of social policy." This view, he says, "permits flirtation with the grossest form of anti-individualistic social philosophy."4 This, then, is Rawls's major example of a "teleological" theory which gives priority to the good over the right. His rejection of the priority of the good, in this context, is just the corollary of his affirmation of the separateness of persons: promoting the well-being of the social organism cannot be the goal from which people's rightful claims are derived, since there is no socialorganism. Since individuals are distinct, they are ends in themselves, not merely agents or representatives of the well-being of the social organism. This is why Rawls believes that utilitarianism is teleological, and why he believes that we should reject it in favor of a deontological doctrine. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 3 UTIL V DEONT UTIL BAD = DESTROYS HMN DIGNITY Utilitarianism belittles the value of a human life, reducing it to nothing more than a number. Germain Grisez and Russel Shaw 1988 (Catholic Moral Theologian, Beyond the New Morality: The Responsibilities of Freedom p. 28) One arrives at a different judgment of how one ought to proceed in such circumstances if human life is regarded not as one of the things of relative value which a person has, but as an intrinsic component of the person, and so as a value which shares in the dignity of the person. In denying that we can choose to kill one person for the sake of two, we really are denying that two persons are "worth" twice as much as some other real person. On this view it is simply not possible to make the sort of calculation which weighs persons against each other (my life is more valuable than John's life, John's life is more valuable than Mary's and Tom's combined, or vice versa) and thus to determine whose life shall be respected and whose sacrificed. The value of each human person is incalculable, not in any merely poetic sense, but simply because it is not susceptible to calculation, measurement, weighing, and balancing. Traditionally this point has been expressed by the statement that the end does not justify the means. This is a way of saying that the direct violation of any good intrinsic to the person cannot be justified by the good result which such a violation may bring about. What is extrinsic to human persons may be used for the good of persons, but what is intrinsic to persons has a kind of sacredness and may not be violated. Utilitarianism quantifies the value of a human being and thus destroys the value to life Germain Grisez and Russel Shaw 1988 (Catholic Moral Theologian, Beyond the New Morality: The Responsibilities of Freedom p. 26) If there are no ethical absolutes, human persons, rather than being the norm and source from which other things receive their value, become simply items or commodities with a relative value-inviolable only up to the point at which it is expedient to violate them in order to achieve an objective. It would then make no sense at all to speak of the immeasurable value of the human person. Far from being immeasurable-that is, beyond calculation-the value of a person would be quite specific and quantifiable, something to be weighed in the balance against other values. Utilitarianism belittles the right to life, reducing the value to human life to nothing more than a number. Sanford Levy, 2000 (Prof of Philosophy @ Montana State, Morality, Rules, And Consequences: A Critical Reader, "The Educational Equivalence of Act and Rule Utilitarianism", 2000 p. 28) At the same time, act utilitarianism is clearly an extremist view from the commonsense perspective of 'ordinary morality', which consists of the intuitions which most people in our social context share about right and wrong acts. On the one hand, act utilitarianism is overly permissive because it doesn't recognize ordinary moral constraints against doing or allowing serious harm (including death) to others. Because it doesn't recognize these constraints, it denies that individuals have corresponding fixed rights not to be harmed. To save the lives of five patients who need different organ transplants, for example. a surgeon will be permitted to seize and chop up the innocent Chuck to harvest his healthy heart, liver, lungs and so on, if these organs happen to be matches for the respective patients. 'After all, if everyone counts equally then it is simply a matter of five versus one. Obviously, it is a horrible result that Chuck will end up dead; but it would be an even worse result if five people end up dead. So the right thing to do - according to [act] utilitarianism -is to kill Chuck.'6 There isn't any thought that Chuck has a 'deontological right' not to be killed for his organs. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 4 UTIL V DEONT UTIL BAD = DESTROYS HMN DIGNITY Utilitarianism is not a moral ideal. The individual is second to the good of the whole, which belittles their human value. Will Kymlicka, 1988 (Prof. of Philosophy at Queen’s U, Press, Philosophy and Public Affairs, Vol. 17, No. 3., pp. 172-190, ‘Rawls on Technology and Deontology” JSTOR) But if that duty is, as seems most plausible, the duty to treat people with equal consideration, then we are back at the first interpretation of utilitarianism as a way of treating people as equals. And then we need not double the population, since we have no obligation to conceive those who would constitute the increased population. If we nonetheless accept that maximizing utility is itself the goal, then it is best seen as a nonmoral ideal, akin in some ways to an aesthetic ideal. The appropriateness of this can be seen by looking at the other example Rawls gives of a teleological theory, namely, Nietzsche's.13 In Nietzsche's theory, the good which the theory seeks to maximize is available only to the special few. Others are useful only insofar as they promote the good of the special few. In utilitarianism, the value being maximized is more mundane, something that every individual is capable of partaking in or contributing to (although the maximizing policy may well result in the sacrifice of the good of many). This means that in utilitarian teleology, unlike Nietzsche's, every person's preferences must be given some weight. But in neither case is the fundamental principle to treat people as equals. Rather it is to maximize the good. And in both cases, it is difficult to see how this can be viewed as a moral principle. The goal is not to respect people, for whom certain things are needed or wanted, but rather to respect the good, to which certain people may or may not be useful contributors. If people have become the means for the maximization of the good, morality has dropped out of the picture, and a nonmoral ideal is at work. A Nietzschean society may be aesthetically better, more beautiful, but it is not morally better (a description that I think Nietzsche himself would not have rejected; his theory was "beyond good and eviln).14 And if utilitarianism is interpreted in this "teleological" way, it too has ceased to be a moral theory.'5 This form of utilitarianism does not merit serious consideration as a political morality.. Making decisions based on the evaluation of consequences belittles individual dignity. Richard Warner, 1995 (Professor of Law at Chicago-Kent College of Law, Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, “Excluding Reasons: Impossible Comparisons and the Law”, JSTOR) Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 5 UTIL V DEONT UTIL BAD = DECREASES VALUE OF HMN LIFE The individual person has an intrinsic value and is an end in himself or herself; the Utilitarian use of people solely for others is thus immoral. Alan Gewirth in 91 (prof. of philosophy @ University of Chicago, Ethics, “Can Any Final Ends Be Rational?”, issue 102, p. 69) The meaning of "final" will obviously vary according to whether the ends it modifies are subsistent or desiderative. First, as to subsistent final ends, the finality of persons who are such ends means that it is always for the sake of these persons that actions ought to be done, so that the persons ought never to be used only for the sake of other persons. For this principle, Kant's doctrine is the model: "Man and, in general, every rational being exists as an end in himself and not merely as a means to be arbitrarily used by this or that will. . . . Such a being is thus an object of respect."' From this, Kant derives the second main version of his categorical imperative: "Act so that you treat humanity, whether in your own person or in that of another, always as an end and never as a means only."* The idea of persons' being treated as ends in themselves is not inherently problematic. One of the most direct clarificatory counterpoises is provided by Aristotle's doctrine that it is morally right to treat certain human beings as mere means or "living instruments" (the so-called natural slaves) for the benefit of other^.^ The thesis of exploitation as intended by Marx, and the totalitarian ideologies that regard persons as objects to be used for the benefit of the state, are also negative illustrations of Kant's idea. Put affirmatively, the thesis that each human being should be treated as a final end is conveyed by the principle of human rights: that all human beings have rights to freedom and wellbeing as their personal due, as what they are entitled to for their own sakes and not simply as means to the maximizing of overall good, or for any other separate purpose. What has to be shown is that this principle is itself rational in that it can be proved or established by the use of reason Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 6 UTIL V DEONT UTIL BAD = DECREASES VALUE OF HMN LIFE Consequentialism destroys the value of the person, giving value only to the some arbitrary consequentialist ideal; only deontology recognizes the individual human as an end in itself. F. M. Kamm in 92 (Philosophy and Public Affairs, “Non-consequentialism, the person as an end-in-itself, and the significance of status.”, p. 361) With these provisos in mind, we might try justifying options by concern for personal autonomy, most often where significant personal concerns are at state. (But note that autonomy itself may be a significant concern.) Kagan argues that to try to justify options by concern for autonomy is merely to assert again the definition of "option”-that is, it is to argue that we should give people a choice (an option) because then they would have choice (autonomy). But such an argument is not without merit if it draws attention to the intrinsic significance of being able to choose, especially when significant concerns besides concern for autonomy are at stake. Ultimately, however, I believe that options are justified by the view that persons are not mere means to the end of the best state of affairs, but ends-in-themselves, having a point even if they do not serve the best consequences. (This is stronger than saying their interests must be served as they serve the greatest good.) This idea of a person as an end-in-itself goes beyond and helps justify autonomy, understood as permissible choice between personal and impersonal points of view. It is this idea of persons as ends-in-themselves who deserve autonomy in action that options help capture. (Note that this is a very different argument for options from the one given by Scheffler.) Further, it need not be that having a strongly motivating personal point of view makes one an end-in-itself, for those whose reasons are never out of synchrony with the impartial point of view could be ends-in-themselves, entitled to an option they would never in fact use. Rather, certain factors that loom large from the personal points of view of those who are ends-in-themselves can become legitimate reasons for action. Suppose that choice is important because it is tied to the view of the person as an end-in-itself. Would it not express greater concern for this conception of the person if we minimized the number of occasions on which people were not permitted to choose, even if this meant occasionally depriving someone of choice by obliging him to make a big sacrifice that ensured that others might choose? My view is that permitting this means to minimization, even if it involved no physical coercion by others and even if no one ever actually had to make the obligatory sacrifice, would defeat the very ideal of the person as an end-in-itself that was supposedly the object of concern. For if such an obligation were appropriate, the individual would no longer be someone who was not "for" the greater good, as he would be available for minimizing interference with the value of choice. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 7 UTIL V DEONT UTIL BAD = DILUTES QUAL OF LIFE Utilitarianism views people as locations of utilities, whose purpose is to bring good to the whole, even if that entails the lower standard or life for the individual. Will Kymlicka, 1988 (Prof. of Philosophy at Queen’s U, Press, Philosophy and Public Affairs, Vol. 17, No. 3., pp. 172-190, ‘Rawls on Technology and Deontology” JSTOR) There is, however, another interpretation of utilitarianism, one that seems more in line with Rawls's characterization of the debate. On this second interpretation, maximizing the good is primary, and we count individuals equally only because that maximizes value. Our primary duty is not to treat people as equals, but to bring about valuable states of affairs. Rawls on Teleology and Deontology As Bernard Williams puts it, people are viewed merely as locations of utilities, or as causal levers for the "utility network": "the basic bearer of value for Utilitarianism is the state of affairs. . . . as a Utilitarian agent, I am just the representative of the satisfaction system who happens to be near certain causal levers at a certain time."Io Utilitarianism, on this view, is primarily concerned not with persons, but with states of affairs. This second interpretation is not merely a matter of emphasizing a different facet of the same theoretical structure. Its distinctiveness becomes clear if we look at some utilitarian discussions of population policy, like those of Jonathan Glover and Derek Parfit. They ask whether we morally ought to double the population, even if it means reducing each person's welfare by almost half (since that will still increase overall utility). They think that a policy of doubling the population is a genuine, if somewhat repugnant, conclusion of utilitarianism. But it need not be if we view utilitarianism as a theory of treating people as equals. Nonexistent people have no claims-we have no moral duty to them to bring them into the world. As John Broome says, "one cannot owe anyone a duty to bring her into existence, because failing in such a duty would not be failing anyone."" So what is the duty here, on the second interpretation? The duty is to maximize value, to bring about valuable states of affairs, even if the effect is to make all existing persons worse off than they otherwise would have been. To put the difference another way, if I fail to bring about the best state of affairs, by failing to consider the interests of some group of people, for example, then I can be criticized, on both interpretations, for failing to live up to my moral duty as a utilitarian. But, on the second interpretation, those whose interests are neglected have no special grievance against me. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 8 UTIL V DEONT UTIL BAD = JUSTIFIES DEATHS OF MILLIONS Adapting the consequentialist viewpoint justifies the deaths of millions of innocents in order to bring about an ends. Thomas Donaldson, 1995 (Prof. of Business Ethics at Georgetown U, Ethics and International Affairs, “International Deontology Defended: A Response to Russell Hardin”, pg. 147-154) The supposed “unrealism” of deontology also seems to lie behind Hardin’s concerns over nuclear deterrence. After noting that Kantians typically have condemned the indiscriminate destruction implicit in a policy of deterrence, he adds that “it therefore seemed [to Kantians] profoundly immoral to destroy cities full of children merely for the sake of the theory of deterrence.” The word “seemed” is surprising. Shouldn’t most people, not only Kantians, be appalled by the prospect of destroying cities full of children? To not be appalled, I submit, is the result of either having been swept away by the morality of consequences or having studied too much political science. It is noteworthy that the reason we are appalled relies on a Kantian-style explanation. If we were to adopt an exclusive consequentialist view, if the ends were always capable of justifying the means, then the death of millions of innocents should be trivial—mere fluff in the face of moral truth. The idea that there are some things that should not be done is precisely a deontological notion. The idea that, no matter how powerful a deterrent it may be, the strapping of babies to the front of tanks is nonetheless wrong, cannot be understood entirely in consequentialist terms. It does not follow that the policy of nuclear deterrence is wrong from the viewpoint of deontology. Some deontologists accept nuclear deterrence while others do not. But deontologists insist correctly that not only the assessment of the consequences, but an assessment of the means used to achieve consequences, must be factored into the moral evaluation of nuclear deterrence. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 9 UTIL V DEONT UTIL BAD = FOUNDATION FOR WAR Utilitarianism taken alone allows unjustified war; full weight must be given to deontological analysis in order to achieve the best policy option. Eric Heinze in 99 (assistant prof. of polisci @ University of Oklahoma, Human Rights & Human Welfare, “Waging War for Human Rights: Towards a Moral-Legal Theory of Humanitarian Intervention”, http://www.du.edu/gsis/hrhw/volumes/2003/heinze-2003.pdf, p. 5) By itself, this “utilitarianism of rights” test has serious problems when employed as a threshold level of human suffering that triggers a humanitarian intervention. This is because it suggests that aggregate human suffering is the only moral concern that should be addressed (Montaldi 1985: 135). If we are to accept the general presumption against war as enshrined in Article 2 of the UN Charter, we do so because of war’s inherent destructiveness and its detrimental effect on international security. The use of force, including humanitarian intervention, will always result in at least some loss of life. The principle of utility ameliorates this effect of intervention, but once an intervention is employed to halt such widespread suffering, a pure utilitarian ethos would sanction the pursuit of this primary end (achieving the military and/or humanitarian objective) without exception, so long as fewer people are killed than are rescued in an intervention. Not only does this reduce the moral relevance of the individual, it opens up the door for aggression disguised as humanitarian intervention, as long as there are individuals who are suffering and dying within a state—even if their suffering is entirely accidental. Taken as part and parcel of the utilitarian framework, therefore, military intervention must only be sanctioned when it is in response to violations that are intentionally perpetrated Thus, as Fernando Tesón eloquently explains in his chapter, “The Liberal Case for Humanitarian Intervention,” the best case for humanitarian intervention contains a deontological element—that is, a principled concern for the respectful treatment of individuals (not intentionally or maliciously mistreating them)—as well as a consequentialist one—the utilitarian requirement that interventions cause more good than harm (Holzgrefe and Keohane: 114). Consider NATO’s intervention in Kosovo, where a significant number of Serbian civilians were killed by NATO bombs in the process of coercing the Milosevic regime to stop its ethnic cleansing of Kosovars. Regardless of whether more lives were saved than lost, in accidentally killing noncombatants, NATO was in essence accepting the notion that human rights are not absolute. This is despite the fact that such killing was done in order to save the lives of other innocent civilians. The moral difference between NATO’s killing and Milosevic’s ethnic cleansing lies in the intent and purpose of the agent, and the ends he hopes to achieve and the conditions he intends to create beyond the mere frustration of an individual’s ability to enjoy a right Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 10 UTIL V DEONT UTIL BAD = FOUNDATION FOR WAR The calculation of utilitarianism is the foundation of war. Kateb, 1992. (George, Professor of Politics, Princeton, The Inner Ocean, page 11.) I do not mean to take seriously the idea that utilitarianism is a satisfactory replacement for the theory of rights. The well-being (or mere preferences) of the majority cannot override the rightful claims of individuals. In a time when the theory of rights is global it is noteworthy that some moral philosophers disparage the theory of rights. The political experience of this century should be enough to make them hesitate: it is not clear that, say, some version of utilitarianism could not justify totalitarian evil. It also could be fairly easy for some utilitarians to justify any war and any dictatorship, and very easy to justify any kind of ruthless-ness even in societies that pay some attention to rights. There is no end to the immoral permissions that one or another type of utilitarianism grants. Everything is permitted, if the calculation is right. No, an advocate of rights cannot take utilitarianism seriously as a competing general theory of political morality, nor any other competing general theory. Rather, particular principles or considerations must be given a place. A theory of rights may simply leave many decisions undetermined or have to admit that rights may have to be overridden (but never for the sake of Social well-being or mere policy preference). Also, kinds of rights may sometimes conflict, and it is not always possible to end that conflict either by an elaboration of the theory of rights or by an appeal to some other. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 11 UTIL V DEONT UTIL BAD = JUSTIFIES SLAVERY Utilitarianism justifies slavery. H. L. A. Hart in 79 (former principal of Oxford University, Tulane Law Review, “The Shell Foundation Lectures, 1978-1979: Utilitarianism and Natural Rights”, April, 53 Tul. L. Rev. 663, l/n) It is most important that Mill conceived that these fundamental rights described by him as a special kind of Utility should be respected by society in the case of each individual. The principles at stake, he says, "protect every individual from being harmed by others," 27 and he adds that "it is by a person's observance of these [moralities] that his fitness to exist as one of the fellowship of human beings, is tested and decided." 28 Mill therefore recognises an equal distribution as vital where these fundamental rights are concerned: all are to have them respected. Yet he nowhere demonstrates or even attempts to demonstrate the doctrine that general utility, as Bentham conceived it, is the basis of such individual rights, since he does not show that general utility treated as an aggregate would be maximised by an equal distribution to all individuals in society of these fundamental rights. There is therefore nothing to counter the sceptic who would argue that if general utility had any meaning it must be [*672] logically possible that the total net balance of ease, pleasure and happiness of a society over pain or unhappiness might be greater, not where those fundamental rights were equally distributed to all members alike, but where a minority, say a small slave population, or even a few individuals, were denied these essentials of human wellbeing in order that the vast majority should receive increments in the means of pleasure or happiness, each small in themselves but large in the aggregate. The difficulty for Mill arises from the possibility that a society might protect the vast majority of its members by rules which made exceptions for a small oppressed minority. Utilitarian principles as ordinarily understood might be satisfied by this, but a doctrine of Natural Rights could not be. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 12 UTIL V DEONT UTIL BAD = TYRANNY Utilitarianism allows tyranny and the absolute oppression of the minority, yet identifies value in a democratic society that increases the welfare of a population; in order to achieve this society, political morality such as deontology must precede consequentialist evaluations. H. L. A. Hart in 79 (former principal of Oxford University, Tulane Law Review, “The Shell Foundation Lectures, 1978-1979: Utilitarianism and Natural Rights”, April, 53 Tul. L. Rev. 663, l/n) The first fundamental criticism of this central maximising principle is again to be found implicit in John Stuart Mill's work. It is implicit in his account of Justice already mentioned, but even more importantly in his influential reflections on Liberty, in the essay of that name. Bentham, it will be recalled, in making his own slow transition from a Tory supporter of the unreformed British Constitution to radical democrat, though that Utilitarianism provided entirely adequate reasons for preferring democracy with manhood suffrage to any other form of government, because only a government dependent on popular election could have sufficient incentive to work for the general interest rather than the sinister interest of a governing few. So his critique of constitutional or political structures was rather like that of a business efficiency expert on a grand scale examining the structure of a firm, and political theorists of our own day have produced some highly sophisticated versions of this type of quasieconomic approach to political theory. But Mill valued democracy for quite other reasons: not merely as the protection of the majority against exploitation by the few and against the inefficiency of governments, but as affording the opportunity to all to develop their distinctive human capacities for thought, choice and self-direction by partaking in political decisions, even in the minimal form of voting at intermittent elections. But Mill also thought that the tyranny of the majority over a minority was as great a danger as the tyranny of a minority government or despotism against which Bentham thought democracy the best protection. So a political morality which like Utilitarianism places political power in the hands of the majority is not enough to secure a good, liberal society. It matters very much what the majority do with the power which is put in their hands; so there is need for constraints in the form of distinct principles of political morality whether or not they are translated into law in the form of a Bill of Rights. "The limitations of the power of government over individuals," said Mill, "loses none of its importance when the [*675] holders of power are regularly accountable to the community--that is to the strongest party therein." Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 13 UTIL V DEONT UTIL BAD = 4 REASONS (1/2) Utilitarianism is bad – ignores individual human value, H. L. A. Hart in 79 (former principal of Oxford University, Tulane Law Review, “The Shell Foundation Lectures, 1978-1979: Utilitarianism and Natural Rights”, April, 53 Tul. L. Rev. 663, l/n) [*676] (i) The first is this: Classical maximising Utilitarianism, in focusing on the aggregate or total of pleasure or happiness, ignores not only distributive principles but something of greater moral importance from which the need for distributive principles arises, namely the simple and obvious fact that humanity is divided into separate persons. Maximising Utilitarianism ignores this because, in its perspective, separate individuals are of no intrinsic importance but only important as the points at which fragments of the total aggregate of pleasure or happiness are located. It is as if we were concerned to collect the greatest possible amount of water in a number of different receptacles and were indifferent, as long as that were achieved, how it was distributed among the receptacles, whether they were full, half full or empty. Individual persons, for maximising Utilitarianism, are therefore merely the locations where what is of value is to be found. It is for this reason that as long as the totals are thereby increased, one individual's happiness or pleasure, however innocent he may be, may be sacrificed to procure a greater happiness or pleasure located in other persons. Such replacements of one person by another are not only allowed but required by Utilitarianism when unrestrained by distinct distributive principles. (ii) Secondly, Utilitarianism is not, as sometimes it is said to be, an individualistic and egalitarian doctrine, although in a sense it treats persons as equals, or of equal worth. For it does this only by, in effect, treating individual persons as having no worth, since not persons for the Utilitarian, but the experiences of pleasure or satisfaction or happiness which persons have are the sole items of worth or elements of value. It is of course true and very important that, according to the Utilitarian maxim, "everybody is to count for one, nobody for more than one," 37 in the sense that in any application of the greatest happiness calculus the equal preferences or pains or pleasures, satisfactions or dissatisfactions of different persons are given the same weight, whether they be Brahmins or Untouchables, Jews or Christians, black or white. But since Utilitarianism has no direct or intrinsic concern, but only an instrumental concern with the relative levels of total wellbeing enjoyed by different persons, its form of equal concern and respect for persons embodied in the maxim that "everybody is to count for one, nobody for more than one," licenses the grossest form of inequality in the actual treatment of individuals, if [*677] required to maximise aggregate or average welfare. So long as that condition is satisfied, the situation in which a few enjoy great happiness while many suffer is as good as one in which happiness is more equally distributed. Of course in comparing the aggregate economic welfare produced by equal and unequal distribution of resources, account must be taken of factors such as diminishing marginal utility and also envy. These factors favour an equal distribution of resources but by no means always favour it conclusively. For there are also factors pointing the other way, such as administrative and transaction costs, loss of incentives and failure of the standard assumption that all individuals are equally good pleasure or satisfaction machines and derive the same utility from the same amount of wealth. (iii) Thirdly, the modern critique of Utilitarianism asserts that there is nothing selfevidently valuable or authoritative as a moral goal in the mere increase in totals of pleasure or happiness abstracted from all questions of distribution. The collective sum of different persons' pleasures or the net balance of total happiness of different persons (supposing it makes sense to talk of adding them) is not in itself a pleasure or happiness which anybody experiences. Society is not an individual experiencing the aggregate collected pleasures or pains of its members; no person experiences such an aggregate. (iv) From this point of view maximising Utilitarianism, if it is not restrained by distinct distributive principles, seems to proceed on a false analogy between the way in which it is rational for a single prudent individual to order his life and the way in which it is rational for a whole community to order its life through government. The analogy is this: it is rational for one man as a single individual to sacrifice a present satisfaction or pleasure for a greater satisfaction later, even if we discount somewhat the value of the later satisfaction because of its uncertainty. Such sacrifices are amongst the most elementary requirements of prudence and are commonly accepted as a virtue and of course any form of saving is an example of this form of rationality. But it is of course a common feature of life even where saving and money are not in -------------- (continues on next page)-------------- UTIL BAD = 4 REASONS (2/2) Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 14 UTIL V DEONT -------------- (continues from previous page)-------------question. For example I decided some time ago to put aside the then present pleasures of idleness to write this lecture so as to have later this greater pleasure of appearing before you here. In this case the later, greater pleasure for the sake of which the lesser, earlier pleasure of idleness is sacrificed is really enjoyed [*678] by me, the same human being who made the earlier sacrifice. By a misleading analogy with an individual's prudence, maximising Utilitarianism treats not merely one person's pleasure as replaceable by some greater pleasure of that same person, but it also treats the pleasure or happiness of one individual as similarly replaceable by the greater pleasure of other individuals. So it treats the division between persons as of no more moral significance than the division between times which separates one individual's earlier pleasure from his later pleasure. But the analogy is false because there is no one person who sacrifices the lesser pleasure but enjoys the greater pleasure later, and the separate identity of different persons is accordingly a division quite different from the merely temporal division between different experiences of a single person, and has a moral claim on our attention of a quite different order. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 15 UTIL V DEONT UTIL BAD = ANTHROCENTRIC Utilitarianism is anthocentric. F. Neil Brady in 85 (assistant prof. of management @ San Diego State University, Journal of Business Ethics, “A Defense of Utilitarian Policy Processes in Corporate and Public Management”, issue 23-30, p. 24) Even if the widely recognized procedural difficulties of applying utilitarian theory to decision-making in public and corporate policy were overcome, it does not follow that a perfected technique which encompasses all manifestations of human preference will prove satisfactory. Laurence Tribe (1974) has argued that utilitarian techniques in the law and in public policy systematically suppress certain kinds of values which express some individuals’ concern for natural objects and non-human life. That is, utilitarianism as a system of public decision-making tends to suppress the expression of sympathy and other felt obligations toward animal life and, instead, distorts those feelings by translating them into mere expressions of human interest. Any obligations or feelings of intrinsic worth, apart from human selfinterest, are comparatively unimportant in the policy game. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 16 UTIL V DEONT UTIL BAD = IMPOSSIBLE Consequentialism is impossible because categories or instances of good cannot be measured against each other. Germain Grisez and Russel Shaw 1988 (Catholic Moral Theologian, Beyond the New Morality: The Responsibilities of Freedom p. 24-25) But, the objection goes, the way of proceeding which we have just described is reasonable-indeed, it is the morally right way to act in many cases-if the quantity of good in the instance preferred out- weighs the quantity in the instance treated as a means to the end. Is it not rational and ethically correct to choose the way of acting which promises to bring about the greater good? This is the line of reasoning recommended by those who subscribe to the ethical system known as "consequentialism" or "proportional- ism." But their recommendation is mistaken. Instances of basic human goods are incommensurable: they cannot be measured against one another as the proportionalist calculus requires. There is a twofold incommensurability. First, it is impossible to measure different categories of human good against one another, since the basic human goods are not reducible to one another or to some ultrabasic category of good underlying all the rest. Comparing categories of good is rather like dividing apples by oranges. Choices, though, are not between or among categories of goods , but instances of goods, so this incommensurability is not precisely what renders the calculus impossible. ... Second, however, it is no less impossible to measure different instances of the same good against one another and determine that one instance outweighs the others. Each instance, each real possibility for choice, has some appeal not found in its competitors. Where shall I go on vacation, the mountains or the seashore? I find both possibilities appealing, but in somewhat different ways, and that is precisely why I must choose between them; if the seashore had all the appeal of the mountains and its own besides, there would be no choice to make-it would simply tumble spontaneously and without choice for the clearly superior alternative. Consequentialism is impossible because each choice results in a unique outcome making it impossible to weigh options. Germain Grisez and Russel Shaw 1988 (Catholic Moral Theologian, Beyond the New Morality: The Responsibilities of Freedom p. 24-25) Artificial as the example is, it makes the crucial point that whenever we have a real choice to make, it is because we are confronted with various possibilities, each embodying a diverse mix of human goods. Consequentialism or proportionalism requires that one weigh and measure the good as represented in the various possibilities and opt for the instance promising more good. But each of the several possibilities comprises, not merely so much (on an imaginary scale) of a certain human good, but a unique "package" of instances of various goods whose very uniqueness makes it impossible to measure it against other, similarly unique "packages" competing to be chosen. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 17 UTIL V DEONT Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 18 UTIL V DEONT UTIL BAD = SPILLS OVER Acceptance of utilitarian arguments in one area creates a gateway for the acceptance of morally repugnant actions in other areas of life to achieve an ends. Germain Grisez and Russel Shaw 1988 (Catholic Moral Theologian, Beyond the New Morality: The Responsibilities of Freedom p. 28) This points to yet another possible element to explain the prevalence of the attitude we are describing: the nuclear deterrent strategy of the United States and other countries. It is a central element of this strategy that, if pressed to the wall in war, the United States and other nuclear nations would rain down nuclear bombs on enemy cities. Leaving aside the question whether such a course of action would make sense (although it would in fact be senseless), the strategy is built on the presumption that the United States and the other nations involved would really do what they say they are prepared to do. Otherwise the deterrent would not be credible. For years then, Americans and the people of other nations which have nuclear deterrents have been living with the knowledge and intention that this is how their countries would, in certain circumstances, act. In subtle but real ways this fact-of nuclear deterrent strategy and all it implies-has helped to undermine the foundations of moral perception and moral thought in our society. This is a broad statement, and one whose truth it is impossible to demonstrate. Yet it stands to reason that this appalling fact has, like a sort of moral disease, infected national life, deadened ethical sensitivity, and poisoned many aspects of our society. It has accustomed us to the idea that it is morally right to will evil for the sake of good. We do not propose a solution. We only suggest that the nuclear deterrent strategy represents a frighteningly logical application of the principle that the end does justify the means. Having willingly although regretfully accepted this principle in one critical area of national life, we can hardly expect to be immune from its influence in many others. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 19 UTIL V DEONT UTIL BAD = JUSTIFIES HOLOCAUST Philosophies of utilitarianism allowed the Germans to employ acts of murder, torture, and mutilation upon anyone assumed to be a ‘threat’ to the state. Arthur L. Kaplan, 2005 (The Emanuel and Robert Hart Professor of Bioethics and Chair of the Department of Medical Ethics and Director, Center for Bioethics, University of Pennsylvania, Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law Online, Too Hard to Face, http://www.jaapl.org/cgi/content/full/33/3/394) Crude utilitarianism is a position that sometimes rears its head in contemporary bioethics debates. For example, some argue that we ought not to spend scarce social resources on certain groups within our society, such as the elderly, so that other groups, such as children, may have greater benefits. Those who want to invoke the Nazi analogy may be able to show that this form of crude utilitarian thinking does motivate some of the policies or actions taken by contemporary biomedical scientists and health care professionals, but they should do so with great caution. In closely reviewing the statements that accompany the six major moral rationales for murder, torture, and mutilation conducted in the camps—freedom was a possible benefit, only the condemned were used, expiation was a possible benefit, a lack of moral expertise, the need to preserve the state in conditions of total war, and the morality of sacrificing a few to benefit many—it becomes clear that the conduct of those who worked in the concentration camps was sometimes guided by moral rationales. It is also clear that all of these moral arguments were nested within a biomedical interpretation of the danger facing Germany. Physicians used utilitarian morals to justify lethal experiments for the greater good of the German state. Their skewed view of what was for ‘the greater good’ led them to eliminate various minority groups. Arthur L. Kaplan, 2005 (The Emanuel and Robert Hart Professor of Bioethics and Chair of the Dept of Medical Ethics and Director, Center for Bioethics, UPenn, Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law Online, Too Hard to Face, http://www.jaapl.org/cgi/content/full/33/3/394) Physicians could justify their actions, whether direct involvement with euthanasia and lethal experiments, or, merely support for Hitler and the Reich, on the grounds that the Jew, the homosexual, the congenitally handicapped, and the Slav posed a threat, a biological threat, a genetic threat, to the existence and future of the Reich. The appropriate response to such a threat was to eliminate it, just as a physician must eliminate a burst appendix by means of surgery or a dangerous bacterium by using penicillin.5 Viewing specific ethnic groups and populations as threatening the health of the German state permitted, and in the view of those on trial demanded, the involvement of medicine in mass genocide, sterilization, and lethal experimentation. The biomedical paradigm provided the theoretical basis for allowing those sworn to the Hippocratic principle of nonmaleficence to kill in the name of the state. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 20 UTIL V DEONT UTIL BAD = JUSTIFIES HOLOCAUST Utilitarianism works on an “end justifies the means” mentality. This practice justifies the holocaust, Stalin’s slaughtering of millions to attain a communist state, slavery, and practices that subjugate minorities. Kerby Anderson, 2004 (National Director of Probe Ministries International, , Probe Ministries, Utilitarianism: The Greatest Good for the Greatest Number, http://www.probe.org/theology-and-philosophy/worldview--philosophy/utilitarianism-the-greatest-good-for-thegreatest-number.html) One problem with utilitarianism is that it leads to an "end justifies the means" mentality. If any worthwhile end can justify the means to attain it, a true ethical foundation is lost. But we all know that the end does not justify the means. If that were so, then Hitler could justify the Holocaust because the end was to purify the human race. Stalin could justify his slaughter of millions because he was trying to achieve a communist utopia. The end never justifies the means. The means must justify themselves. A particular act cannot be judged as good simply because it may lead to a good consequence. The means must be judged by some objective and consistent standard of morality. Second, utilitarianism cannot protect the rights of minorities if the goal is the greatest good for the greatest number. Americans in the eighteenth century could justify slavery on the basis that it provided a good consequence for a majority of Americans. Certainly the majority benefited from cheap slave labor even though the lives of black slaves were much worse. A third problem with utilitarianism is predicting the consequences. If morality is based on results, then we would have to have omniscience in order to accurately predict the consequence of any action. But at best we can only guess at the future, and often these educated guesses are wrong. A fourth problem with utilitarianism is that consequences themselves must be judged. When results occur, we must still ask whether they are good or bad results. Utilitarianism provides no objective and consistent foundation to judge results because results are the mechanism used to judge the action itself. UTIL BAD = JUSTIFIES HOLOCAUST Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 21 UTIL V DEONT Genocide can be justified if it is in the interest of the majority Irrational Knowledge, 2006. (Practical Ethics - A Critical Review, August 13, 2006. http://www.irrationalknowledge.com/08-13-2006/practical-ethics-a-critical-review/) Utilitarianism fails the test for beauty and goodness because it could potentially justify genocide on an ethnic or religious minority. Realize that nothing is intrinsically good or bad according to Singer's principle of the equal consideration of interests. Instead, an action is deemed good or bad based on how many people hold a given interest. If most people have an interest in favor of genocide, then utilitarianism says that genocide is the good. To paraphrase Benjamin Franklin, utilitarianism is two wolves and a lamb voting about what to have for dinner. Of course, there are utilitarian protections that make genocide more difficult than simply holding a vote. Strongly held interests count for more than weakly held interests (page 21), and the principle of declining marginal utility (page 24) further elevates the interests of the threatened minority group. But declining marginal utility is not a substitute for an unalienable right to life; it still places a finite value on a life, which can then be "outvoted" by the majority. A utilitarian justification of genocide is difficult, but by no means impossible. Even if the interests of a member of the minority group count ten times as much as that of the oppressors, it just means that the minority group must make up less than 10% of the population for genocide to be justified. If the minority group starts to internalize the hatred directed towards them, their interests to keep living will weaken, making genocide even more likely. For those with a background in modal logic, there is a possible world in which Singer's utilitarianism justifies genocide. Singer tacitly recognizes this; on page 94 he explains that the type of utilitarianism that results from maximizing interests is called preference utilitarianism, and on page 99 he says "if we are preference utilitarians we must allow that a desire to go on living can be outweighed by other desires." Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 22 UTIL V DEONT UTIL BAD = SCHELL INDICT EVEN SCHELL, THEIR OWN AUTHOR SAYS THAT IT DOESN’T TAKE PRECEDENCE OVER EVERYTHING NOR THAT ANY ACTION IS JUSTIFIED SO LONG AS IT SUPPORTS PREVENTION OF EXTINCTION. Cheshier, 2001. (David M., Assistant Professor of Communications, Director of Debate at Georgia State University, “IS IT MORE IMPORTANT TO PROTECT HUMAN RIGHTS OR AVERT WAR?”, p. 1-2, debate.uvm.edu.) These are powerful words, with an obvious utility in debates where nuclear risks are being assessed. Of course one must be careful not to misuse Schell's argument. He cannot be saying that any risk a policy decision might culminate in eventual nuclear usage has to weighted as a 100% certain extinction risk. Such a claim is on the face of it unsustainable since any and every conceivable action might entail an infinitesimally small heightening of nuclear risk. To treat Schell as implying this would produce genuine decisional paralysis ("if I put my left shoe on first, then there's a 0.0000000.1% chance of nuclear war, which is infinite; but if I put my right shoe on first..."). Schell implicitly recognizes this by acknowledging that from his argument "it does not follow that any action is permitted as long as it serves the end of preventing extinction" (130). And in a literal mathematical sense Schell's formulation seems to provide little guidance when it comes to comparing relative nuclear risks (since it implies that a 1% chance of nuclear war should count as infinitely large as a 99% chance,when surely we would prefer the former to the latter). The calculation does have direct relevance to debates where rights are counterposed to nuclear risks, and Schell devotes a section of his essay to thinking through the ethical issues arising from his position. He spends some time refuting, for example, the argument of Karl Jaspers that because there are some principles and circumstances warranting self-sacrifice ("some things worth dying for"), total self-destruction is not necessarily implausible or unreasonable (with Jaspers we have an eloquent articulation of what was once called the "better dead than Red" argument). Schell finds this point of view unsustainable. But Schell does not reject all ethical considerations, nor does he subordinate everything to survival. Rather, he defends a more nuanced ethical position of relevance to those defending rights against war. Conceding that there is "nothing in the teachings of either Socrates or Christ that could justify the extinction of mankind," he also adds that "neither is there anything that would justify the commission of crimes in order to prevent extinction" (134). And, by way of an analogy to the death camps of World War II, Schell makes clear that even a preeminent concern with survival does not "take precedence over the obligation to treat others decently" (136). Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 23 UTIL V DEONT DEONT GOOD = BETTER POLICY MAKING Policy makers cannot depend solely on economics, but need to apply ethics to make efficient policies Pinstrup-Andersen, Per. 2005. (Ethics and economic policy for the food system. General Sessions, 01DEC-05, American Journal of Agricultural Economics.) Economists seldom address ethical questions as they infringe on economic theory or economic behavior. They (and I) find this subject complex and elusive in comparison with the relative precision and objectivity of economic analysis. However, if ethics is influencing our analyses but ignored, is the precision and objectivity just an illusion? Are we in fact being normative when we claim to be positive or are we, as suggested by Gilbert (p. xvi), ignoring social ethics and, as a consequence, contributing to a situation in which we know "the price of everything and the value of nothing?" The economists' focus on efficiency and the Pareto Principle has made us less relevant to policy makers, whose main concerns are who gains, who loses, by how much, and can or should the losers be compensated. By focusing on the distribution of gains and losses and replacing the Pareto Principle with estimates of whether a big enough economic surplus could be generated so that gainers could compensate losers, the socalled new welfare economics (which is no longer new) was a step toward more relevancy for policy makers (Just, Hueth, and Schmitz). Another major step toward relevancy was made by the more recent emphasis on political economy and institutional economics. But are we trading off scientific validity for relevancy? Robbins (p. 9) seems to think so, when he states that "claims of welfare economics to be scientific are highly dubious." But if Aristotle saw economics as a branch of ethics and Adam Smith was a moral philosopher, when did we, as implied by Stigler, replace ethics with precision and objectivity? Or, when did we as economists move away from philosophy toward statistics and engineering and are we on our way back to a more comprehensive political economy approach, in which both quantitative and qualitative variables are taken into account? I believe we are. Does that make us less scientific, as argued by Robbins? I am not questioning whether the quantification of economic relationships is important. It is. In the case of food policy analysis, it is critically important that the causal relationship between policy options and expected impact on the population groups of interest is quantitatively estimated. But not at the expense of reality, context, and ethical considerations, much of which can be described only in qualitative terms. Economic analyses that ignore everything that cannot be quantified and included in our models are not likely to advance our understanding of economic and policy relationships. Neither will they be relevant for solving real world problems. The predictive ability is likely to be low and, if the results are used by policy makers, the outcome may be different from what was expected. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 24 UTIL V DEONT DEONT GOOD = INT HMN RTS Deontology is essential for the maintenance of international human rights because it restricts the practice of justifying the actions of the government by the ends achieved, creating what is essentially a humane international order. Thomas Donaldson, 1995 (Prof. of Business Ethics at Georgetown U, Ethics and International Affairs, “International Deontology Defended: A Response to Russell Hardin”, pg. 147-154) It may appear that I am defending Kantian deontology as a comprehensive moral language to use in interpreting international events. But I mean not to assert that Kantian deontology is sufficient, only that it is necessary. Such a perspective contributes fundamental, often neglected, insights. First it provides a moral grounding for any rights-based approach to international affairs. This includes not only the general interpretation of international policy through broad notions of human rights, but also the application of specific rights such as those found in the UN Universal Declaration of Human Rights. Indeed, most contemporary rights-based theories are deontological theories. Rights are principles that assign claims or entitlements to someone against someone and are usually interpreted as “trumping” or taking precedence over consequential claims made in the name of collective welfare.4 Hence, both in their similarity of form (as a principle universally applicable to relevantly similar situations) and in their similarity of function (as taking precedence over collective, consequential considerations), rights satisfy two key Kantian-deontological criteria. Second, Kantianism entails clear restrictions on the general behavior of states. Of greatest importance is the fact that these restrictions alert us to the danger of letting the ends justify the means. Whatever the flaws of the Kantian deontological tradition, and no matter what verdict we finally reach on the comprehensiveness of deontological moral logic, the insistence on principle over mere calculation of future consequences stands as deontology’s practical raison d’etre. Deontology may not be sufficient, but it is necessary for a humane international order. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 25 UTIL V DEONT DEONT GOOD = PRECEDES UTIL (1/2) Certain premises have an intrinsic moral value that comes before consequences of actions. Evaluating consequences first puts our fate and the fate of the masses in the hands of belligerent others. Igor Primoratz in 05 (Principal Research Fellow @ Center for Applied Philosophy amd Public Ethics, The Philosophical Forum, Volume 36, No. 1, “Civilian Immunity in War”, Spring, p. 44-46) Consequentialist thinkers usually present their view on civilian immunity against the background of a critique of attempts of philosophers and legal thinkers to account for civilian immunity in deontological terms. Having satisfied themselves that those attempts have been unsuccessful, they put forward the claim that civilian immunity has nothing to do with civilians’ acts or omissions, guilt or innocence, responsibility or lack of it, but is merely a useful convention. It is useful since it rules out targeting a large group of human beings, and thus helps reduce greatly the overall killing, mayhem, and destruction in war. The consequentialist view of civilian immunity is exposed to two objections: the protection it offers to civilians is too weak, and the ground provided for it indicates a misunderstanding of the moral issue involved. The protection is too weak because civilian immunity is understood as but a useful convention. This makes it doubly weak. First, if it is merely a useful convention, if all its moral force is due to its utility, then it will have no such force in cases where it has no utility. This is a familiar flaw of consequentialism. It denies that moral rules have any intrinsic moral significance, and explains their binding force solely in terms of the good consequences of acting in accordance with them. Therefore it cannot give us any good consequentialist reason to adhere to a moral rule in cases where adhering to it will not have the good consequences it usually has, and where better consequences will be attained by going against the rule.6 This means that we should respect civilian immunity when, and only when, doing so will have the good consequences adduced as its ground: when it will indeed reduce the overall killing, maiming, and destruction. On the other hand, whenever we have good reasons to believe that, by targeting civilians, we shall make a significant contribution to our war effort, thus shortening the war and reducing the overall killing and mayhem, that is what we may and indeed ought to do. Civilian immunity is thus made hostage to the vagaries of war, instead of providing civilians with iron-clad protection against them. This is not a purely theoretical concern. As Kai Nielsen has pointed out, systematic attacks on civilians in the course of a war of national liberation can make an indispensable contribution to the successful prosecution of such a war. That was indeed the case in Algeria and South Vietnam, and may well have been the case in Angola and Mozambique as well. Then again, if civilian immunity is merely a useful convention, that weakens it by making it hostage to the stance taken by enemy political and military leadership. They may or may not choose to respect the immunity of our civilians. If they do not, on the consequentialist view of this immunity, we are not bound to respect the immunity of their civilians. Being a convention, it binds only if, or as long as, it is accepted by both parties to the conflict. As an important statement of this view puts it, “for convention-dependent obligations, what one’s opponent does, what ‘everyone is doing,’ etc., are facts of great moral importance. Such facts help to determine within what convention, if any, one is operating, and thus they help one discover what his moral duties are.”8 To be sure, even if no such convention is in place, but we have reason to believe we can help bring about its acceptance by unilaterally acting in accordance with it and thereby encouraging the enemy to do the same, we should do that. But if we have no good reason to believe that, or if we have tried that approach and it has failed, our military are free to kill and maim enemy civilians whenever they feel they need to do that. Thus our moral choice is determined, be it directly or ultimately, by the moral (or immoral) choice of enemy political and military leaders. So is the fate of enemy civilians. The fact that they are civilians, in itself, counts for nothing. This brings me to the second objection: The consequentialist misses what anyone else, and in particular any civilian in wartime, would consider the crux of the matter. Faced with the prospect of being killed or maimed by enemy fire, a civilian would not make her case in terms of disutility of killing or maiming civilians in war in general, or of killing or maiming her then and there. She would rather point out that she is a civilian, not a soldier; a bystander, not a participant; an innocent, not a guilty party. She would point out that ----------CONTINUES ON NEXT PAGE---------------- DEONT GOOD = PRECEDES UTIL (2/2) Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 26 UTIL V DEONT ----------CONTINUED FROM PREVIOUS PAGE---------------she has done nothing to deserve, or become liable to, such a fate. She would present these personal facts as considerations whose moral significance is intrinsic and decisive, rather than instrumental and fortuitous, mediated by a useful convention (which, in different circumstances, might enjoin limiting war by targeting only civilians). And her argument, couched in personal terms, would seem to be more to the point than the impersonal calculation of good and bad consequences by means of which the consequentialist would settle the matter. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 27 UTIL V DEONT DEONT GOOD = PRECEDES UTIL Recognizing rights and putting them before a utilitarian calculus is the only rational and moral option. H. L. A. Hart in 79 (former principal of Oxford University, Tulane Law Review, “The Shell Foundation Lectures, 1978-1979: Utilitarianism and Natural Rights”, April, 53 Tul. L. Rev. 663, l/n) Accordingly, the contemporary modern philosophers of whom I have spoken, and preeminently Rawls in his Theory of Justice, have argued that any morally adequate political philosophy must recognise that there must be, in any morally tolerable form of social life, certain protections for the freedom and basic interests of individuals which constitute an essential framework of individual rights. Though the pursuit of the general welfare is indeed a legitimate and indeed necessary concern of governments, it is something to be pursued only within certain constraints imposed by recognition of such rights. The modern philosophical defence put forward for the recognition of basic human rights does not wear the same metaphysical or conceptual dress as the earlier doctrines of the seventeenth and eighteenth-century Rights of Man, which men were said to have in a state of nature or to be endowed with by their creator. Nonetheless, the most complete and articulate version of this modern critique of Utilitarianism has many affinities with the theories of social contract which in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries accompanied the doctrine of natural rights. Thus Rawls has argued in A Theory of Justice that though any rational person must know that in order to live even a minimally tolerable life he must live within a political society with an ordered government, no rational person bargaining with others on a footing of [*679] equality could agree to regard himself as bound to obey the laws of any government if his freedom and basic interests, what Mill called "the groundwork of human existence," were not given protection and treated as having priority over mere increases in aggregate welfare even if the protection cannot be absolute. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 28 UTIL V DEONT DEONT GOOD = PRECIDES UTIL Rights precede other concerns; their protection is key to moral legitimacy and any form of morality that does not put them first suffers moral indeterminacy and deficiency. Alan Gewirth in 86 (prof. of philosophy @ University of Chicago, Oxford University Press, “Why Rights are Indespensible”, p. 343-344) Nevertheless, human rights, as explicated above, are basic to morality, in that they are the necessary even if not the sufficient condition of all moral values. For all moral precepts deal, directly or indirectly, with how persons ought to act, especially towards one another. Where the precepts deal only indirectly with actions, as in the case of the virtues, there is still an important reference to action, since virtues are dispositions to act in certain ways. Now, since the human rights are rights to the necessary goods of action and successful action in general, it follows that without the objects of the human rights the actions with which morality is concerned are either impossible or deficient, and the abilities and conditions needed for the actions are not securely possessed. Without rights to these objects, the individual's personal dignity as an agent who can justifiably claim these goods on his own behalf is seriously threatened. And without social recognition of these rights-and, regarding the most important rights, their legal enforcement- the individual's possession of the necessary goods of action and successful action is rendered precarious. In addition, as we have seen, the universality of human rights provides the essential basis for linking together each individual's possession of the necessary goods of action in a context of social solidarity. For all these reasons, recognition and protection of human rights is a necessary condition of the moral legitimacy of societies. The human rights can account for the value both of supererogatory actions and of the moral virtues. Although supererogatory actions go beyond the duties required by rights, the direction of this 'beyond' is itself indicated by the human rights, in one of two ways. Supererogatory actions may aim at assuring that other persons' freedom and well-being will be promoted or protected in certain dire circumstances where the agent puts his own freedom and well-being at risk, as in saintly or heroic actions. Alternatively, supererogatory actions may provide benefits that reflect the same civility and mutuality of consideration as are required by the human rights, but go beyond the needs of freedom and well-being, as, for example, in actions of generosity or courtesy. Moral virtues add to morally right actions the important qualifications that persons who have the virtues tend to do what is morally right from deep-seated habitual motivations, with knowledge that it is right and because it is right. But since actions in accord with human rights are morally the most important kinds of actions because they promote or tend to support other persons' freedom and well-being, the human rights underlie the moral virtues and serve to explain why they are morally valuable. Attempted accounts of the moral virtues that do not ground them in human rights can be shown to suffer from moral indeterminacy.27 DEONT GOOD = PRECEDES UTIL Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 29 UTIL V DEONT We have a prima facia duty to certain entities due to special relationships with those entities, preceding consequentialist concerns. These relationships justify action based on claims of morality and precede Utilitarian values. David McNaughton and Piers Rawling in 98 (profs. Of philosophy @ Keele University and the University of Missouri-St. Louis, Ratio, “On Defending Deontology”, issue 11, p. 42-43) We begin with duties of special relationship. In a telling paragraph, Ross contrasts his view with consequentialism thus: [Consequentialism] says, in effect, that the only morally significant relation in which my neighbours stand to me is that of being possible beneficiaries by my action. They do stand in this relation to me, and this relation is morally significant. But they may also stand to me in the relation of promisee to promiser, of creditor to debtor, of wife to husband, of child to parent, of friend to friend, of fellow countryman to fellow countryman, and the like; and each of these relations is the foundation of a prima facie duty (1965, p.19). The various relationships in which we stand to other people generate a variety of agent-relative reasons: one can be required, say, to keep a promise, even if by breaking it promise-keeping as whole would thereby be increased. On the direct-act consequentialist view, on the other hand, if promises should be kept, that can only be because promise-keeping is valuable, and hence should, ceteris paribus, be maximized. Accepting Ross’s view of duties of special relationship entails that what is right is not solely determined by considerations of agent-neutral value. At this point, the consequentialist may rightly claim that no account has been given of why certain relationships are morally basic in a way that does not permit their violation whenever such violation would increase value. But it is hard to see how this is a complaint, unless it is also a complaint that the consequentialist has not explained why morality’s sole concern is the increase of value – on the consequentialist view, it is apparently taken to be selfevident that all moral reasons ultimately rest on considerations of agent-neutral value. Justification has to stop somewhere, and it is not clear that the intuitionist’s stopping place is less defensible than that of the consequentialist. The thought that others have direct moral claims on us that are not explicable in terms of agent-neutral value is a familiar one in everyday moral thinking. Intuitionism accepts this thought at face value and thereby rejects the consequentialist perspective. In addition to agent-relative reasons generated by duties of special relationship, of course, Ross also takes as basic those generated by constraints. He is silent, however, on the subject of whether his line on the former can be extended to cover the latter. There is an obvious disanalogy between constraints and duties of special relationship: constraints do not depend on the specific nature of the relationships we have. I should not treat anyone in the way that constraints forbid, whether I have a relationship with them or not. Note, however, that the usual objection that is raised to justifying constraints – how could it ever be that we are required not to maximize the good? – has already been met. For Ross’s account of duties of special relationship has already shown that we can make sense of this once we get away from the consequentialist picture of value determining what is right. Fulfilling the duties which stem from special relationships may require us not to maximize the good. Others can have direct moral claims on us, claims that are not routed via thoughts about the maximization of the good. So we can already make formal sense of the thought that other agents have a claim on us not to be treated in certain ways; a claim we standardly express by saying that they have a right not to be harmed, tortured or killed. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 30 UTIL V DEONT DEONT GOOD = OUTWEIGHS UTIL Rights come first – they have an intrinsic value that outweighs utilitarian imperatives. David McNaughton and Piers Rawling in 98 (profs. Of philosophy @ Keele University and the University of Missouri-St. Louis, Ratio, “On Defending Deontology”, issue 11, p. 48-49) Nagel effectively accepts the consequentialist view that a system of moral rules can only be defended by showing that their adoption brings about some good that could not otherwise be realized, and then seeks to show that deontology is such a system. The claim is not, of course, that agent-relative reasons rest directly on considerations of value in a manner obviously susceptible to the CVC; rather, the grounding is indirect – the notion is that worlds in which there are agent-relative reasons are better than worlds in which there are not. Nagel argues that an agent relative morality, qua moral system, is intrinsically valuable. Thus we concur with Hooker (1994), then, pace Howard-Snyder (1993), that rule consequentialism is not a 'rubber duck'. Thus rights (the obverse of constraints) have value, and are, therefore, part of the basic structure of moral theory. ‘A right is an agent-relative, not an agent-neutral, value’, says Nagel (1995, p.88). This is precisely because it is supposed to resist the CVC (one is forbidden to violate a right even to minimize the total number of such violations). So Nagel faces the Scheffler problem: ‘How could it be wrong to harm one person to prevent greater harm to others? How are we to understand the value that rights assign to certain kinds of human inviolability, which makes this consequence morally intelligible?’ (p.89, our emphasis – note the presumption inherent in the question). The answer ‘focuses on the status conferred on all human beings by the design of a morality which includes agent-relative constraints’ (p.89). That status is one of being inviolable (which is not, of course, to say that one will not be violated, but that one may not be violated – even to minimize the total number of such violations). A system of morality that includes inviolability encapsulates a good that its rivals cannot capture. For, ‘not only is it an evil for a person to be harmed in certain ways, but for it to be permissible to harm the person in those ways is an additional and independent evil’ (p.91). So there is a sense in which we are better off if there are rights (they are a ‘kind of generally disseminated intrinsic good’ (p.93)). Hence there are rights. In short, we are inviolable because inviolability is intrinsically valuable. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 31 UTIL V DEONT DEONT GOOD = PREVENTS TORTURE Recognizing moral impartives is necessary to prevent the worst forms of torture. Henry Shue in 71 (prof. of ethics and public life @ Cornell, Philosophy and Public Affairs, Vol. 7, No. 2. (Winter), “Torture”, p. 132) Terroristic torture, as we may call this dominant type, cannot satisfy the constraint of possible compliance, because its purpose (intimidation of persons other than the victim of the torture) cannot be accomplished and may not even be capable of being influenced by the victim of the torture. The victim's suffering-indeed, the victim-is being used entirely as a means to an end over which the victim has no control. Terroristic torture is a pure case-the purest possible case of the violation of the Kantian principle that no person may be used only as a means. The victim is simply a site at which great pain occurs so that others may know about it and be frightened by the prospect. The torturers have no particular reason not to make the suffering as great and as extended as possible. Quite possibly the more terrible the torture, the more intimidating it will be-this is certainly likely to be believed to be so. AND torture is morally worse than slavery. Henry Shue in 71 (prof. of ethics and public life @ Cornell, Philosophy and Public Affairs, Vol. 7, No. 2. (Winter), “Torture”, p. 124) Torture is indeed contrary to every relevant international law, including the laws of war. No other practice except slavery is so universally and unanimously condemned in law and human convention. Yet, unlike slavery, which is still most definitely practiced but affects relatively few people, torture is widespread and growing. According to Amnesty International, scores of governments are now using some torture-including governments which are widely viewed as fairly civilized-and a number of governments are heavily dependent upon torture for their very surviva1. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 32 UTIL V DEONT DEONT GOOD = FW INDEPENDENT OF UTIL A defense of deontology’s assumptions regarding the moral value of certain acts is unnecessary; its framework for evaluation has a value independent of utilitarianism. David McNaughton and Piers Rawling in 98 (profs. Of philosophy @ Keele University and the University of Missouri-St. Louis, Ratio, “On Defending Deontology”, issue 11, p. 44) These observations do not constitute, of course, an argument for deontology. It is simply supposed that the prohibition on treating people in certain ways is basic. This is a demand that the existence of other agents makes upon us. The deontological intuition can be spelled out in greater detail and illustrated, but it cannot, on our view, be justified, in the sense of being deduced from or supported by some more basic intuition. Every moral theory, as Mill justly remarked, will have its fundamental principles. Deontology has a greater number of basic principles than consequentialism, and that might be a ground of complaint, but that it has them at all cannot be held to its discredit. Ross’s main contention, then, is remarkably simple. He claims that the deontic cannot, and need not, be justified by appeal to yet more basic considerations. And, in particular, he insists that the deontic is largely independent of the evaluative: thoughts about what is required, forbidden, or permitted, are not identical to, reducible to, or derivable from, thoughts about what will produce the most good. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 33 UTIL V DEONT DEONT GOOD = MORAL IMPERATIVE We must act in accordance with the generic rights of others; the fulfillment of these rights is a precursor to any action and their protection a moral imperative. Alan Gewirth in 86 (prof. of philosophy @ University of Chicago, Oxford University Press, “Why Rights are Indespensible”, p. 338-340) In Reason and Morality I have developed in considerable detail an argument for a principle that provides a determinate ground for moral, and especially human, rights: a ground that derives from the necessary conditions of action and successful action in general. The argument undertakes to establish two main theses. The first is that every agent logically must accept that he has rights to freedom and well-being, which are the generic features and necessary conditions of action and generally successful action. (I omit here the requisite analyses of the concepts of freedom and well-being that bear on such purposive action). The second thesis is that every agent logically must also accept that all other actual or prospective agents have the same rights he claims for himself, so that in this way the existence of universal and equal moral rights, and hence of human rights, must be accepted within the whole context of action or practice.22 I also call them generic rights, because they are rights to the generic features of action and successful action in general. From these two theses, there follows a supreme moral principle that every agent logically must also accept. I call it the Principle of Generic Consistency (PGC), and its main precept, addressed to every actual or prospettive agent, is: Act in accord with the generic rights of your recipients as well as of yourself. It is this principle that grounds the specific human rights to freedom and well-being in the spheres both of individual action and of social institutions. For reasons of space, I must here confine myself to a brief outline of the argument. Reduced to its barest essentials, the argument for the first main thesis is as follows. Since freedom and well-being are the necessary conditions of action and successful action in general, every agent must regard these conditions as necessary goods for himself, since without them he would not be able to act for his purposes, either at all or with general chances of success. Hence, every agent has to accept (I) 'I must have freedom and well-being.' This 'must' is practical-prescriptive in that it signifies the agent's advocacy of his having the necessary goods of action. Now, by virtue of accepting (I), every agent also has to accept (2) 'I have rights to freedom and well-being.' For, if he rejects (2), then, because of the correlativity of claim-rights and strict 'oughts', he also has to reject (3) 'All other persons ought at least to refrain from removing or interfering with my freedom and well-being.' By rejecting (3), he has to accept (4) 'Other persons may (i.e. It is permissible that other persons) remove or interfere with my freedom and wellbeing.' And by accepting (4), he also has to accept (5) 'I may not (i.e. It is permissible that I do not) have freedom and well-being.' But (5) contradicts (I). Since every agent must accept (I), he must reject (5). And since ( 5 ) follows from the denial of (2), every agent must reject that denial, so that he must accept (2) 'I have rights to freedom and well-being.' This, in outline, is my argument for the first main thesis stated above. I shall give an even briefer summary of my argument for the second main thesis, that every agent logically must accept that all other actual or prospective agents also have rights to freedom and well-being. This generalization is an application of the logical principle of universalizability. Since every agent must hold that he has the generic rights because he is a prospective purposive agent, he also logically must hold that all prospective purposive agents have the generic rights. And from this generalization the PGC directly follows. Many questions may be and have been raised about this argument. I have dealt with them elsewhere.23 In the present context I shall confine myself to two observations. Firstly, if the above argument is sound, it shows that, contrary to the justificatory objection, belief in moral, and especially human, rights is not only warranted but logically mandatory for all actual or prospective agents because of the argument's justification or proof of the principle that grounds the rights. Secondly, the argument establishes a decision procedure for ascertaining what moral rights persons have, since all justified moral rights consist in one or another segment, individual or institutional, of the rights to freedom and well-being. For example, the right to have promises to oneself kept is an instance of a 'nonsubtractive right' to well-being, because broken promises tend -to diminish the promisees' capabilities of successful action in the particular circumstances affected by the promise. Similarly, the right to an education is an example of an 'additive right' to well-being, because it serves to increase one's capabilities for successful purpose-fulfilling actions. Political and economic rights, including rights to civil liberties and to relief of large-scale starvation, are justified on the basis of 'indirect', i.e. institutional, applications of the PGC. Thus, as I have tried to show elsewhere, the general moral theory which has the above argument as its Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 34 UTIL V DEONT centrepiece provides determinate contents for the concepts of freedom and well-being and for the human rights to these goods of agency. A further argument also yields criteria for resolving conflicts of rights, where one right is overridden by another.24 Hence, a theory upholding moral human rights can avoid the appeals to intuition which the justificatory objection held to be inevitable. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 35 UTIL V DEONT DEONT GOOD = BEST POLICY OPTION, PREVENTS GENOCIDE A deontological approach to international policy is imperative for the selection of the best policy option; Utilitarianism fails to recognize the difference between intended and accidental death and fails to recognize the value of humans, allowing genocide. Eric Heinze in 99 (assistant prof. of polisci @ University of Oklahoma, Human Rights & Human Welfare, “Waging War for Human Rights: Towards a Moral-Legal Theory of Humanitarian Intervention”, http://www.du.edu/gsis/hrhw/volumes/2003/heinze-2003.pdf, p. 6-7) Another practical implication of this understanding of humanitarian intervention has to do with its deontological element—proscription of the intentional, malicious murder and abuse of innocents that is instrumental to achieving an end. A deontological approach ensures that there is always an identifiable, responsible agent against whom the use of force may be directed. This view permits intervention when authorities knowingly and willingly cause great harm to their citizens, through for example, outright killing, ethnic cleansing, mass expulsion, or intentional starvation. Further, to the extent that the authorities knowingly tolerate such abuse or fail to take steps to curb it—such as Milosevic’s “toleration” of atrocities committed by Serb paramilitaries—they are the legitimate subjects of intervention. The same could be said for the government of Ethiopia in 1984, as Rony Brauman has portrayed it in his chapter in Hard Choices. According to Brauman, Ethiopia’s policy of land collectivization and its irrational taxation system—in addition to the wanton destruction of crops, confiscation of livestock, and forcible recruitment of manpower into the army to fight a civil war—was done knowingly and maliciously, and could have been subject to forcible intervention (Moore: 182-183). Of equal relevance for the deontological element of humanitarian intervention are the instances of human suffering that eschew the use of force. We generally would not consider unleashing a war against a state that failed to install a tsunami early-warning system, for example, even if it could have afforded to do so and thousands subsequently perished. Such an instance would be appropriate for humanitarian aid (and perhaps even legal liability) but not humanitarian intervention as defined here. This is an important distinction that the contributors to Hard Choices fail to make. Had this same government summarily starved or executed its own citizens to preserve their rule or create an ethnically pure state, there would be an extremely strong case for intervention. The moral difference lies in the perpetrator’s treatment of his victims as entirely disposable means to an end (Montaldi 1985: 137-140). It is certainly possible for governments to endeavor to achieve sinister ends by “mismanaging” such crises, in which case they would presumably reject outside assistance, thereby provoking suspicion toward their behavior and making the case stronger for forcible intervention. These are critically important empirical considerations that are vital to any theory of humanitarian intervention. Nevertheless, one can reasonably regard outright murder as morally worse than accidental death, despite their empirical reducibility to “instances of death.” In this way, human welfare is more than simply aggregate human rights enjoyment; it is to be treated as deserving of respect in the original Kantian sense of regarding human beings as ends and not means. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 36 UTIL V DEONT DEONT GOOD = INCREASES VALUE OF WORLD The idea that rights must precede utilitarian values increases the value of humans and thus increases the value of the world; this is necessary to give a meaning to the service of humanity. F. M. Kamm in 92 (Philosophy and Public Affairs, “Non-consequentialism, the person as an end-in-itself, and the significance of status.”, p. 390) If we are inviolable in a certain way, we are more important creatures than violable ones; such a higher status is itself a benefit to us. Indeed, we are creatures whose interests as recipients of such ordinary benefits as welfare are more worth serving. The world is, in a sense, a better place, as it has more important creatures in it.3' In this sense the inviolable status (against being harmed in a certain way) of any potential victim can be taken to be an agent-neutral value. This is a nonconsequential value. It does not follow (causally or noncausally) upon any act, but is already present in the status that persons have. Ensuring it provides the background against which we may then seek their welfare or pursue other values. It is not our duty to bring about the agent-neutral value, but only to respect the constraints that express its presence. Kagan claims that the only sense in which we can show disrespect for people is by using them in an unjustified way. Hence, if it is justified to kill one to save five, we will not be showing disrespect for the one if we so use him. But there is another sense of disrespect tied to the fact that we owe people more respect than animals, even though we also should not treat animals in an unjustified way. And this other sense of disrespect is, I believe, tied to the failure to heed the greater inviolability of persons. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 37 UTIL V DEONT DEONT GOOD = PREVENTS GENOCIDE/TORTURE Deontology is essential in establishing limits on the behavior of the state in order to avoid the consideration of genocide and torture as tools of political power. Thomas Donaldson, 1995 (Prof. of Business Ethics at Georgetown U, Ethics and International Affairs, “International Deontology Defended: A Response to Russell Hardin”, pg. 147-154) Of the consequentialists, I regard Hardin as the most articulate spokesperson. He combines formidable philosophical skills with political erudition. Both talents, unfortunately, make his mistaken conclusions on the matter of international deontology surprising. As I will show, agreeing with Hardin to banish deontological justifications from international discussion amounts to abandoning the power of deontology to interpret political intent and to establish hard limits on political behavior. States may not be human individuals, but they often behave with foresight and must be accountable to certain moral principles. Genocide and torture are not to be weighed up by states on the scale of future consequences; rather, states simply must not engage in them. The moral language of deontology may not be sufficient for the moral interpretation of international affairs, but it turns out to be necessary. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 38 UTIL V DEONT A2: DEONT DISMISSES CONSEQUENCES Deontology does not dismiss the evaluation of consequences; good consequences are merely derived from the categorical imperative. Thomas Donaldson, 1995 (Prof. of Business Ethics at Georgetown U, Ethics and International Affairs, “International Deontology Defended: A Response to Russell Hardin”, pg. 147-154) When discussing nuclear deterrence or intervention it is common to exaggerate the nonconsequential nature of Kantianism. It is a false but all-too common myth that Kant believed that consequences were irrelevant to the evaluation of moral action. In his practical writings Kant explicitly states that each of us has a duty to maximize the happiness of other individuals, a statement that echoes Mill’s famous principle of utility. But Kant’s duty to promote beneficial consequences is understood to be derived from an even higher order principle, namely, the categorical imperative that requires all of us to act in a way that respects the intrinsic value of other rational beings. Kant does not dismiss consequences. He simply wants them in their proper place. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 39 UTIL V DEONT A2: UTIL CAN SOLVE DEONT (1/3) Trying to reconcile human rights and utilitarianism results in cultural relativism. Heard in 1997 (Andrew, professor of political science at Simon Fraser University, The Challenges of Utilitarianism and Relativism <http://www.sfu.ca/~aheard/417/util.html>) Perhaps the most telling critique of attempts to reconcile utilitarianism with human rights is that the solutions proposed may end up leading not to universal human rights but to cultural relativism. Whether one refers to constrained utilitarianism or rule utilitarianism, the basic premise is that certain fundamental norms are said to frame utilitarian calculations, and these norms may be human rights. Utilitarianism is, in my view, a society-centred notion of policy choices - in another words the calculations for Canadians can only be made by Canadians, or for Fijians by Fijians. In order to accommodate universal human rights, one has to assert that each society must logically deduce that human rights benefits are as essential to their own. Thus, universalism might only be ascribed to human rights if each society recognizes their inherent value, or if they are necessary to the functioning of a complex human society. John Stuart Mill laid the groundwork for such a possibility, in his arguments that certain basic rights or liberties are essential for utilitarianism to function; freedom of expression and representative government, for example, are necessary for a society to debate and determine what the greatest happiness for the greatest number entails. However, this position is debateable, and one could argue that a benign sovereign may determine the greatest happiness without the trappings of representative democracy; traditional societies and even Marxist societies in the transitional socialist phase might be viewed in this light. Moreover, there still remains the nagging question of what norms each society will end up adopting as the rules that must be considered. The very real possibility exists that societies will differ on just what benefits their citizens should enjoy in order to enhance the greatest happiness. Notions of equality will be expressed in very different benefits and circumstances for citizens of a non-theistic, liberal society than they will be in a traditional Islamic or Hindu society. In the end, rule or constrained utilitarianism may simply lead one down the path to cultural relativism, where each society determines for itself what basic norms must be protected and what sort of benefits may or may not be traded off in determining the greatest good for that society. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 40 UTIL V DEONT A2: UTIL CAN SOLVE DEONT (2/3) Cultural relativism allows for rights to be denied to repressed groups. Heard in 1997 (Andrew, professor of political science at Simon Fraser University, The Challenges of Utilitarianism and Relativism < http://www.sfu.ca/~aheard/417/util.html>) Human rights face a serious challenge to their universality from cultural relativism. Since morality is inextricably linked to the general cultural values of a society, it is very difficult to argue that the moral standards arising from one society can be imposed on another. In its most extreme form, cultural relativism leads to the conclusion that each culture is equally valid and the ethical norms of any society are just as legitimate as those found in another society. Cultural relativism, therefore, poses a serious hurdle to global human rights standards: with the variety of political, religious, economic, and cultural values across the world, how can one set of 'human rights' bind all societies? The challenge raised by cultural relativism undermines the two dimensions of universalism: that all humans possess human rights, and that all humans enjoy roughly the same benefits from those rights. There are several aspects of the cultural relativist challenges to all humans holding human rights. One fundamental question is whether all societies would agree on who is meant by 'humans' to which rights apply. However, different societies will draw different conclusions about who is 'human', and thus entitled to the protection of human rights. A number of cultures and religions have at times in their past viewed certain, or even all, outside groups as essentially sub-human barbarians who could never enjoy the status or rights of a member of that culture. Several societies have held that a member could lose whatever rights they held by some act of heresy or communication with the undesirables. But the issues of who is human or who can hold rights re-emerges in modern contexts in debates over the right to life of a foetus, deformed newborn, unwanted female baby, a murderer, comatose patient, and - in some societies - even those who renounce their religion. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 41 UTIL V DEONT A2: UTIL CAN SOLVE DEONT (3/3) Cultural relativism puts rights at the complete discretion of individual states. Ayton-Shenker in 1995 (Diana, author who has written extensively on culture and politics and worked with the United Nations, and taught at colleges and universities in New York and Paris; The Challenge of Human Rights and Cultural Diversity, <http://www.un.org/rights/dpi1627e.htm>) Cultural relativism is the assertion that human values, far from being universal, vary a great deal according to different cultural perspectives. Some would apply this relativism to the promotion, protection, interpretation and application of human rights which could be interpreted differently within different cultural, ethnic and religious traditions. In other words, according to this view, human rights are culturally relative rather than universal. Taken to its extreme, this relativism would pose a dangerous threat to the effectiveness of international law and the international system of human rights that has been painstakingly contructed over the decades. If cultural tradition alone governs State compliance with international standards, then widespread disregard, abuse and violation of human rights would be given legitimacy. Accordingly, the promotion and protection of human rights perceived as culturally relative would only be subject to State discretion, rather than international legal imperative. By rejecting or disregarding their legal obligation to promote and protect universal human rights, States advocating cultural relativism could raise their own cultural norms and particularities above international law and standards. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 42 UTIL V DEONT Util good – Public Policy Utilitarianism is vital to any policymaking paradigm. Bentley in 2000 (Kristina A., has an MA in political theory from Rhodes University and completed a PhD in the Department of Government at the University of Manchester in 2001. From 1996–1998, Dr Bentley was a lecturer in political theory in the Department of Political Studies and International Relations at Rhodes University. Her areas of research interest are theories and concepts of rights, the rights of vulnerable persons, rights and multiculturalism, and the enforceability of social and economic rights; Suggesting a “Separate” Approach to Utility and Rights: Deontological Specification and Teleological Enforcement of Human Rights, Sapientia, September, < http://www.abdn.ac.uk/pir/postgrad/vol1_issue3/issue3_article1.pdf>) Firstly, utilitarianism is an impersonal doctrine leaving no room for subjective considerations such as loyalty, personal relationships, or commitments - it assumes perfectly “free-floating” individuals. This is of course completely inappropriate to decisions about personal morality, as “[p]eople have, and upon reflection we think they should have, principled commitments and personal attachments of various sorts” (Goodin, 1995: 8). However, quite the reverse may be said of the moral decisions of public officials, and indeed individuals acting in their public capacity as citizens. Of course, in such instances these individuals are not “free-floating” but rather have a whole raft of baggage of personal attachments, commitments, principles and prejudices. In their public capacities, however, we think it only right and proper that they should stow that baggage as best they can ... [because] ... [i]t is the essence of public service as such that public servants should serve the public at large. Public servants must not play favourites (Goodin, 1995: 9). The second vice of utilitarianism that is transformed into a virtue at the level of public policy is that it is “a coldly calculating doctrine” and once again while this is repugnant in personal ethical matters, the opposite 6 is true of normative matters at the public level. This is because public officials have responsibilities (voluntarily undertaken and which are thought to give rise to moral obligations) and those responsibilities imply that they are obliged “not to let their hearts rule their heads” as “it is the height of irresponsibility to proceed careless of the consequences” (Goodin, 1995: 9). This especially so when it is considered that the consequences in such a case will impact on the whole society which the public official has undertaken to serve. This relates to the third criticism of utilitarianism as a consequentialist doctrine, which considers that “the effects of an action are everything” (Goodin, 1995: 9) and that it is outcomes which ought to dictate a particular course of action. However, while this may run counter to the personal ethics of an individual, it seems that this is the only way in which decisions of public policy ought to be made, as public officials cannot possibly (nor should they) take into account all of the personal ethics and beliefs of the people affected by a particular decision. They should however, in all instances, take heed of the possible consequences of particular course of action. Finally there is the criticism that “there is something necessarily crass about whatever utilitarians take as their maximand” and consequently it is difficult for utilitarianism to take account of any “‘higher’ concerns” (Goodin, 1995: 10-11). Once again, however, while this would “diminish private life” quite the reverse is true of the sort of considerations relevant to public life. Public officials are obliged to inquire into the usefulness of particular courses of action for the society taken as a whole and make their decisions accordingly. Furthermore, “it seems transparently wrong for public officials to impose ... sacrifices upon any who refuse to undertake them voluntarily” even though personal sacrifices are perfectly morally acceptable, and sometimes even may be morally required in so far as personal ethics are concerned (Goodin, 1995: 11).iii Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 43 UTIL V DEONT Util good – Public Policy Utilitarianism should be the deciding factor in determining what is important in public debate. Bentley in 2000 (Kristina A., has an MA in political theory from Rhodes University and completed a PhD in the Department of Government at the University of Manchester in 2001. From 1996–1998, Dr Bentley was a lecturer in political theory in the Department of Political Studies and International Relations at Rhodes University. Her areas of research interest are theories and concepts of rights, the rights of vulnerable persons, rights and multiculturalism, and the enforceability of social and economic rights; Suggesting a “Separate” Approach to Utility and Rights: Deontological Specification and Teleological Enforcement of Human Rights, Sapientia, September, < http://www.abdn.ac.uk/pir/postgrad/vol1_issue3/issue3_article1.pdf>) In addition to the above four vices of utilitarianism which are transformed into virtues at the level of public deliberation, Goodin argues that “the public, rather than private application of utilitarian precepts helps us evade some of the most standard practical and practicality objections to the doctrine” (Goodin, 1995: 18- 19). Primary among these sorts of objection is that utilitarianism cannot be implemented, as it requires us to make impossible comparisons of utility among individuals, and of course in addition to the problem that this is impossible to determine with any certainty, it may not even be desirable to do so. Furthermore, even where utilitarianism proves indeterminate, it sets the terms of ... public debate. It tells us what sorts of considerations ought to weigh with us, often while allowing that how heavily each of them actually weighs is legitimately open to dispute. (Goodin, 1995: 21). Any legitimate government has to follow the general will by acting in the public goodgovernment policy must be utilitarian Hill in 1998 (R.A., Ph.D, Department of Anthropology, Virginia State University, Government, Justice and Human Rights, < http://www.bu.edu/wcp/Papers/Poli/PoliHill.htm>) Rousseau writes that a "legitimate" government should obey the general will. The formation of laws, administration of laws, and dispensation of justice in the courts should all conform to this general will. The wills of subsections of the populace are only particular; one does not reach the general will until one takes into account the will of the largest possible group (the more inclusive the group the more just the will): in the case of citizens of a country the general will is made up of the combined will of all the citizenry. (1) Rousseau answers the question, "How does one know that one is following the general will?" by writing that the most general will is always aligned with the public interest, which is characterized by fairness. If the rulers want to follow the general will, they have only to act justly in order to accomplish it (1987, p. 371). Again justice is introduced. Rousseau maintains that a legitimate government follows the general will, whose earmark is justice. The social compact, which establishes this just government, ensures that all citizens are equitably and impartially treated - no actions guided by the general will are individual or unfair. At such time that the general will, the collective will of the citizenry, should be overruled by the "executor of the laws," the government ceases to exist (1955, p. 64). Rousseau, then, feels that legitimate government is tied very closely to justice: the legitimate government is guided by the general will, which is just; when the government is no longer guided by the just general will, it is no longer legitimate. Justice is introduced into government as a quality of the general will and of the actions resulting therefrom. "What is most necessary, and perhaps most difficult, in government, is rigid integrity in doing strict justice to all..." (1987, p. 375). Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 44 UTIL V DEONT Util good – Public Policy Utilitarians are supporters of legal and political rights because of the effectiveness in practice Ian Montgomerie, 2000. (Software Engineer, A Utilitarian FAQ, July 1, 2000, http://www.ianmontgomerie.com/manifesto/utilitarianfaq.html#WHYACCEPT) The real reason for "our commitment to rights" (the commitment of modern Westerners at any rate - rights were not always such a strong idea) is that they have been prescriptively useful. Legal and political rights in the real world have had very positive results. Unfortunately, rights have often been supported on the grounds that they are inherently right in themselves. Their success in the real world has tended to reinforce that perspective, even though people would not have found it very appealing if the concept made everyone worse off. Humans have a great history of taking concepts that are prescriptively useful, and coming to believe that those concepts are inherently right (rather than useful because they promote welfare). This may be, in part, because humans tend to believe in something more strongly if they think it is inherently right, than if they think it is merely useful in practice. There is, in fact, a natural tendency among many people to believe that whatever conventional wisdom holds to be good is good because of some inherent correctness, rather than because it is "merely" very useful in promoting the welfare of people. Utilitarians tend to be strong supporters of legal and political rights. This is because, rather than wasting time trying to determine which rights are to be preferred based on their inherent merits, Utilitarians recognize that many rights are very effective at promoting welfare. In the real world, things like crime, abuse of power, and intolerance are very real problems and legally protected rights are effective and efficient safeguards against them. It is important to recognize that those who criticize Utilitarianism for not having a sufficient regard for rights are either doing so on entirely theoretical grounds, or are missing how useful rights are in practice. Rights are certainly not so lacking in justification that they cannot stand on evidence, but must appeal to being moral requirements in themselves. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 45 UTIL V DEONT Util good – Values life Utilitarians do not believe that people come with arbitrary structures- they believe that each person acts and thinks alike, and all have similar needs Ian Montgomerie, 2000. (Software Engineer, A Utilitarian FAQ, July 1, 2000, http://www.ianmontgomerie.com/manifesto/utilitarianfaq.html#WHYACCEPT) This particular objection is often raised from the perspective of economic theory. Various theoretical results based on certain preference structures suggest that it can be quite difficult to compare arbitrary sorts of preferences. Theorists investigating such issues are looking for a rigorous and exact comparison between the full preferences of different individuals. Finding the "weighting" of preferences so that one person's preferences can be quantitatively compared to those of another is a daunting task. It's not insoluble in theory, but it's certainly not the kind of thing that you would want to try in practice. Fortunately for Utilitarianism, there is no need to try it in practice. Real humans do not come with arbitrary structures of preferences, we come with goals and desires that are reliably similar in important ways. We are all part of the same species, with very similar brains and thus similar minds. Our differences are outweighed by our similarities. Real preferences can often be compared in a sensible, straightforward manner. The basics such as food, shelter, and good health, for example, are of similar importance to most people. We can be confident that the effect of factors such as these on the welfare of different people is substantial, and similar. We can even safely assume that people benefit to a similar extent from money, at least up to a reasonable amount which allows comfortable living. This is not to say that all people actually do benefit equally. The point is that the benefits to different people are similar enough that we can assume they are the same, and not be too far off. Not all goods can be compared in such a way, and that is also important. We have no reasonable basis to compare how much welfare benefit different people gain from activities such as going to the opera (or a rock concert), walking in a pristine forest, or living in a society which promotes their religious beliefs. Although we might be able to establish the benefits of these to specific individuals, given extensive testing, it is not practically possible to compare them across the population in general. The fact that welfare benefits for different people can be compared easily for some goods, but not for others, has important policy implications for Utilitarians. A government can reliably estimate the welfare benefits of such basics as food, shelter, health, and a minimal income. This gives it an effective basis on which to design policies to supply, regulate, or redistribute such goods. It cannot effectively redistribute arbitrary goods, however, because there is too much room for people to misrepresent their interests. If the government cannot reasonably know what the welfare benefits of a good are except by asking, and the people it asks are not reliable because they are promoting their own interests, that will not lead to effective redistribution of the good. These practical concerns indicate that governments should focus on redistributing basic goods and money, rather than on trying to manage the distribution of a wide variety of goods. In fact, the government should support policies such as free speech, and free choice in the realm of hard-to-compare goods. Free speech allows accurate information about the welfare benefits of goods to be distributed. Free choice allows consumers to promote their own interests when it comes to the many goods which cannot be effectively redistributed. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 46 UTIL V DEONT Util good – Values life "Utility" is nothing more than a measurement of a person's well-being. Utilitarians regard people as valuable and important. Ian Montgomerie, 2000. (Software Engineer, A Utilitarian FAQ, July 1, 2000, http://www.ianmontgomerie.com/manifesto/utilitarianfaq.html#WHYACCEPT) Many people focus on the Utilitarian credo to "maximize utility", an overall quantity, and come to the impression that Utilitarians think utility is a "thing" which is important independently of people. Utilitarianism has been accused of treating people as "vessels of utility", as if they were only important because they contained utility. A bit of reflection quickly shows the error of this criticism. "Utility", or welfare, is nothing more than a measurement of a person's well-being. When Utilitarians talk of utility, this is a conceptual shorthand for the well-being of people - their satisfaction of preferences, achievement of goals, and so on. Utility is the exact opposite of a concept valuable "in itself", independent of individual people - it is a measure of what is good for individual people. Utility is valuable precisely because it is not independent of the well-being of people, it is that very well-being. It can sometimes be easy to forget this for people not used to using an abstract concept to represent a complex reality. Regardless of the fact that Utilitarians talk of utility in abstract terms, as a single thing, utility is not a thing. It is a concept referring to the well-being of all. People are not "vessels of utility", worthwhile only because they possess utility. Utility is a measure of the good of people, who are what Utilitarianism regards as valuable and important. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 47 UTIL V DEONT Util good – Best Justice Morality is not based on consequences, but on the concept of justice which is apart of utility Eugene Lee in 2000. (University Scholars Program, National University of Singapore, An Introduction to Utilitarianism. 6 November 2000. http://www.victorianweb.org/ philosophy/utilitarianism.html) Critics of utilitarianism argue that unlike the suppositions of the utilitarians, morality is not based on consequences of actions. Instead, it is based on the fundamental concept of justice. Mill sees the concept of justice as a case for utilitarianism. Thus, he uses the concept of justice, explained in terms of utility, to address the main argument against utilitarianism. Mill offers two counter arguments. First, he argues that social utility governs all moral elements in the notion of justice. The two essential elements in the notion of justice are: punishment, and the violation of another's rights. Punishment results from a combination of revenge and collective social sympathy. As a single entity, revenge has no moral component, and collective social sympathy is equal to social utility. Violation of rights is also derived from utility, as rights are claims that one has on society to protect us. Thus, social utility is the only reason society should protect us. Consequently, both elements of justice are based on utility. Mill's second argument is that if justice were foundational, then justice would not be ambiguous. According to Mill, there are disputes in the notion of justice when examining theories of punishment, fair distribution of wealth, and fair taxation. Only by appealing to utility can these disputes be resolved. Mill concludes that justice is a genuine concept, but it must be seen as based on utility. Utilitarianism promotes justice and exactly as far as its benefits justify. Ian Montgomerie, 2000. (Software Engineer, A Utilitarian FAQ, July 1, 2000, http://www.ianmontgomerie.com/manifesto/utilitarianfaq.html#WHYACCEPT) There are two senses in which "justice" can be used. The first is that of a system which ensures results that are morally good and "deserved" according to ethical theory. The second is that of a system which enforces law effectively in practice. In the sense of ethical theory, Utilitarians argue that utility maximization provides the optimal tradeoff between the values of different people. A concept of what people "deserve" which is not derived from the values of the people requires placing an objective, inherent value in some concept of justice. That would be fundamentally contrary to the basis of Utilitarianism, and Utilitarians argue that there is no good reason to claim that some form of justice is inherently good independently of the welfare of people. Such a concept of justice would require that, under some circumstances, justice should be promoted even if it was not in fact what anyone involved wants. People do seem to feel that justice should be considered valuable in itself, but this is because justice has tended to be practically useful. The practical usefulness of justice means that beliefs that it is a good thing thrive, since they tend to lead to outcomes which further their spread. The prevalence of modern belief in justice should be understood not as evidence that justice is good in itself, but as evidence that belief in justice has produced good results in practice. Utilitarianism establishes why justice is a good thing (it often promotes welfare), and then promotes it exactly as far as its benefits justify. Promoting justice is an effective way of maximizing utility Ian Montgomerie, 2000. (Software Engineer, A Utilitarian FAQ, July 1, 2000, http://www.ianmontgomerie.com/manifesto/utilitarianfaq.html#WHYACCEPT) Utilitarianism also indicates that justice is useful in practice, to deter and rectify various forms of undesirable, welfare-reducing behavior. Utilitarianism leads to a strong commitment to an effective justice system, and argues that promoting justice in the real world is an effective way of maximizing utility. This is especially true because it is not practically feasible to attempt to directly apply Utilitarian principles to every decision. The social order recommended by Utilitarianism must be able to deal effectively with a non-Utilitarian majority, and with every failure and abuse to which humanity will inevitably subject it. A consistently enforced and fair set of laws and system of government are effective at maximizing utility under such circumstances. Utilitarians often suggest a sort of justice system that many people find quite attractive, and which does not differ radically from that present in modern society. Utilitarianism does not recommend sacrificing the real world justice system to hopes that individuals will come up with more expedient behavior on their own. While perfect Utilitarians would not need to bother with a justice system, actual people will often respond to a highly permissive system by abusing it for personal gain. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 48 UTIL V DEONT Util good – Solves morality Utilitarianism doesn’t deny the importance of motives for action-immoral behaviors will be condemned because they are associated with negative consequences Ian Montgomerie, 2000. (Software Engineer, A Utilitarian FAQ, July 1, 2000, http://www.ianmontgomerie.com/manifesto/utilitarianfaq.html#WHYACCEPT) There are two senses in which the motive behind an action can be important - theoretical and practical. Utilitarianism recognizes that motivations have great practical importance. Even if the direct effects of two actions are the same, the motivations behind it can make a great deal of difference in how we should respond to the action. In theory, however, absolutely all effects of an action can be considered. Two acts which have the same consequences for welfare cannot be distinguished as better or worse than each other, because all of their direct and indirect results taken together are equivalent. When Utilitarian theory says that a "bad" motivation is not morally inferior to a "good" motivation, it is necessarily because the "bad" motivation does not produce any consequences whatsoever that would make it more harmful. Utilitarians recognize that motives are important in practice because they are important to future behavior. Future behavior is an indirect and difficult to predict consequence of the present. This means that if a given motivation is known to be a good predictor of future undesirable behavior, that knowledge should be taken advantage of. When that motivation is seen in action, it provides an excellent opportunity to criticize and discourage it. Such an opportunity may often outweigh the importance of the immediate consequences of the action, even if they are positive. As an example, if someone publicly helps another only because they want to grab the spotlight for political advantage, the opportunity to condemn such a negative motivation may outweigh the short term benefits of the act. It may be beneficial to discourage using others for political advantage in general, even if the consequences of some such actions happen to be positive. In reality we cannot always be certain about specific consequences, but we can know that certain motivations are usually associated with negative consequences. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 49 UTIL V DEONT Util good – Solves morality Utilitarianism can preserve morality because immoral actions have bad consequences Bentley in 2000 (Kristina A., has an MA in political theory from Rhodes University and completed a PhD in the Department of Government at the University of Manchester in 2001. From 1996–1998, Dr Bentley was a lecturer in political theory in the Department of Political Studies and International Relations at Rhodes University. Her areas of research interest are theories and concepts of rights, the rights of vulnerable persons, rights and multiculturalism, and the enforceability of social and economic rights; Suggesting a “Separate” Approach to Utility and Rights: Deontological Specification and Teleological Enforcement of Human Rights, Sapientia, September, < http://www.abdn.ac.uk/pir/postgrad/vol1_issue3/issue3_article1.pdf>) Secondly, it is objected that utilitarianism might give rise to policies that are morally outrageous (examples which Goodin uses are feeding Christians to lions, distributing the body parts of one person among many others and hanging an innocent person to appease a mob), but of course if utilitarianism is an exclusively public philosophy, it “spares us the burdens associated with maximising at the margins in each and every case” (Goodin, 1995: 22). This is the case because public policies by their very nature have to be durable, and a policy which allowed any of the above things to occur would necessarily be an unstable one, because of the fear it would engender. The worry over who is to be next to be fed to the lions, forced to donate their organs, or wrongly executed would quickly undermine the utility of such a policy and lead to its replacement. Consequently “[u]tilitarianism, employed as a public philosophy, must by its nature adopt institutions and practices and policies suited to recurring situations and standard individuals” (Goodin, 1995: 23). Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 50 UTIL V DEONT Util good – Utility best FW for individual advocacy 1/2 ALL ACTIONS ARE DISCRIMINATED BY THEIR OUTCOME AS BEING GOOD OR BAD ACTIONS. THE ULTIMATE GOAL IS TO ACHIEVE UTILITY – THE ULTIMATE HAPPINESS. Mill, 1863. (John Stuart, Lord Rector of University of St. Andrews, “Utalitarianism.”) It is true that similar confusion and uncertainty, and in some cases similar discordance, exist respecting the first principles of all the sciences, not excepting that which is deemed the most certain of them, mathematics; without much impairing, generally indeed without impairing at all, the trustworthiness of the conclusions of those sciences. An apparent anomaly, the explanation of which is, that the detailed doctrines of a science are not usually deduced from, nor depend for their evidence upon, what are called its first principles. Were it not so, there would be no science more precarious, or whose conclusions were more insufficiently made out, than algebra; which derives none of its certainty from what are commonly taught to learners as its elements, since these, as laid down by some of its most eminent teachers, are as full of fictions as English law, and of mysteries as theology. The truths which are ultimately accepted as the first principles of a science, are really the last results of metaphysical analysis, practised on the elementary notions with which the science is conversant; and their relation to the science is not that of foundations to an edifice, but of roots to a tree, which may perform their office equally well though they be never dug down to and exposed to light. But though in science the particular truths precede the general theory, the contrary might be expected to be the case with a practical art, such as morals or legislation. All action is for the sake of some end, and rules of action, it seems natural to suppose, must take their whole character and colour from the end to which they are subservient. When we engage in a pursuit, a clear and precise conception of what we are pursuing would seem to be the first thing we need, instead of the last we are to look forward to. A test of right and wrong must be the means, one would think, of ascertaining what is right or wrong, and not a consequence of having already ascertained it. The difficulty is not avoided by having recourse to the popular theory of a natural faculty, a sense or instinct, informing us of right and wrong. For — besides that the existence of such — a moral instinct is itself one of the matters in dispute — those believers in it who have any pretensions to philosophy, have been obliged to abandon the idea that it discerns what is right or wrong in the particular case in hand, as our other senses discern the sight or sound actually present. Our moral faculty, according to all those of its interpreters who are entitled to the name of thinkers, supplies us only with the general principles of moral judgments; it is a branch of our reason, not of our sensitive faculty; and must be looked to for the abstract doctrines of morality, not for perception of it in the concrete. The intuitive, no less than what may be termed the inductive, school of ethics, insists on the necessity of general laws. They both agree that the morality of an individual action is not a question of direct perception, but of the application of a law to an individual case. They recognise also, to a great extent, the same moral laws; but differ as to their evidence, and the source from which they derive their authority. According to the one opinion, the principles of morals are evident a priori, requiring nothing to command assent, except that the meaning of the terms be understood. According to the other doctrine, right and wrong, as well as truth and falsehood, are questions of observation and experience. But both hold equally that morality must be deduced from principles; and the intuitive school affirm as strongly as the inductive, that there is a science of morals. Yet they seldom attempt to make out a list of the a priori principles which are to serve as the premises of the science; still more rarely do they make any effort to reduce those various principles to one first principle, or common ground of obligation. They either assume the ordinary precepts of morals as of a priori authority, or they lay down as the common groundwork of those maxims, some generality much less obviously authoritative than the maxims themselves, and which has never succeeded in gaining popular acceptance. Yet to support their pretensions there ought either to be some one fundamental principle or law, at the root of all morality, or if there be several, there should be a determinate order of precedence among them; and the one principle, or the rule for deciding between the various principles when they conflict, ought to be self-evident. To inquire how far the bad effects of this deficiency have been mitigated in practice, or to what extent the moral beliefs of mankind have been vitiated or made uncertain by the absence of any distinct recognition of an ultimate standard, would imply a complete survey and criticism, of past and present ethical doctrine. It would, however, be easy to show that whatever steadiness or consistency these moral beliefs have, attained, has been mainly due to the tacit influence of a standard not recognised. Although the non-existence of an acknowledged first principle has made ethics not so much a guide as a consecration of men's actual sentiments, still, as men's sentiments, both of favour and of aversion, are greatly influenced by what they suppose to be the effects of things upon their happiness, the principle of utility, or as Bentham latterly called it, the greatest happiness principle, has had a large share in forming the moral doctrines even of those who most scornfully reject its authority. Nor is there any school of thought which refuses to admit that the influence of actions on happiness is a most material and even predominant consideration in Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 51 UTIL V DEONT Util good – Utility best FW for individual advocacy 2/2 many of the details of morals, however unwilling to acknowledge it as the fundamental principle of morality, and the source of moral obligation. I might go much further, and say that to all those a priori moralists who deem it necessary to argue at all, utilitarian arguments are indispensable. It is not my present purpose to criticise these thinkers; but I cannot help referring, for illustration, to a systematic treatise by one of the most illustrious of them, the Metaphysics of Ethics, by Kant. This remarkable man, whose system of thought will long remain one of the landmarks in the history of philosophical speculation, does, in the treatise in question, lay down a universal first principle as the origin and ground of moral obligation; it is this: "So act, that the rule on which thou actest would admit of being adopted as a law by all rational beings." But when he begins to deduce from this precept any of the actual duties of morality, he fails, almost grotesquely, to show that there would be any contradiction, any logical (not to say physical) impossibility, in the adoption by all rational beings of the most outrageously immoral rules of conduct. All he shows is that the consequences of their universal adoption would be such as no one would choose to incur. On the present occasion, I shall, without further discussion of the other theories, attempt to contribute something towards the understanding and appreciation of the Utilitarian or Happiness theory, and towards such proof as it is susceptible of. It is evident that this cannot be proof in the ordinary and popular meaning of the term. Questions of ultimate ends are not amenable to direct proof. Whatever can be proved to be good, must be so by being shown to be a means to something admitted to be good without proof. The medical art is proved to be good by its conducing to health; but how is it possible to prove that health is good? The art of music is good, for the reason, among others, that it produces pleasure; but what proof is it possible to give that pleasure is good? If, then, it is asserted that there is a comprehensive formula, including all things which are in themselves good, and that whatever else is good, is not so as an end, but as a mean, the formula may be accepted or rejected, but is not a subject of what is commonly understood by proof. We are not, however, to infer that its acceptance or rejection must depend on blind impulse, or arbitrary choice. There is a larger meaning of the word proof, in which this question is as amenable to it as any other of the disputed questions of philosophy. The subject is within the cognisance of the rational faculty; and neither does that faculty deal with it solely in the way of intuition. Considerations may be presented capable of determining the intellect either to give or withhold its assent to the doctrine; and this is equivalent to proof. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 52 UTIL V DEONT Util good – Solves cultural relativism Utilitarianism does not abide by “moral intuitions” because morality varies across societies, time, and individuals- Utilitarianism is a normative ideal that does not base its philosophy on ethical intuition Ian Montgomerie, 2000. (Software Engineer, A Utilitarian FAQ, July 1, 2000, http://www.ianmontgomerie.com/manifesto/utilitarianfaq.html#WHYACCEPT) The most obvious argument against "our moral intuitions" (and that is the exact phrase used by countless philosophers), is that they are not "ours". Popular conceptions of morality vary dramatically across societies, across time, and between individuals. There are some underlying common features, but what is or is not morally intuitive varies dramatically according to who you ask. When someone talks about "moral intuition", they are probably speaking for their own moral intuition, but regardless of what they think they are probably not speaking for the majority of humanity across the ages. One thing about a normative ideal is that it is consistent - its nature does not depend on who you are, where you live, or what you were raised to believe. Most arguments from moral intuition implicitly assert that the arguer's moral intuitions are either universal, or are somehow superior to the differing intuitions of others, but they have no basis to support either of those claims. Trying to build an objective, normative ethical philosophy on a foundation of subjective intuition is not productive. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 53 UTIL V DEONT Util good – solves equality Utilitarianism is concerned with maximizing the overall welfare of people and equitable distribution of wealth Ian Montgomerie, 2000. (Software Engineer, A Utilitarian FAQ, July 1, 2000, http://www.ianmontgomerie.com/manifesto/utilitarianfaq.html#WHYACCEPT) Utilitarianism in practice has fairly significant egalitarian implications, because a very uneven distribution of resources is unlikely to be utility-maximizing. For more information on this, see the question "Does Utilitarianism favor the redistribution of wealth?" in this FAQ. Utilitarianism is concerned with maximizing the overall welfare of people, and a reasonably equitable distribution of wealth appears to be a good way of doing this in practice. It is certainly true, however, that Utilitarianism will promote inequality when doing so is utility maximizing. To promote equality at the expense of utility is to say that equality is in itself inherently good, and that in some circumstances it is permissible to increase equality even when that is not what the people themselves value. The Utilitarian response to this criticism is that, while people often feel a concern for equality in itself, this is because that has become a part of the prescriptive morality of modern cultures. Equality is usually beneficial in practice, and so beliefs that equality is a good thing have thrived. The prevalence of modern belief in equality should be understood not as evidence that equality is good in itself, but as evidence that belief in equality has produced good results in practice. Utilitarianism establishes why equality is a good thing (it often promotes welfare), and then promotes it exactly as far as its benefits justify. It should be noted that the people who criticize Utilitarianism for not promoting equality usually place much more importance on equality than the average person. Many of the modern Egalitarian philosophers who criticize Utilitarianism for being insufficiently egalitarian believe that welfare should be sacrificed to equality in fairly dramatic ways. A school of thought started by John Rawls, for example, believes that inequality is only permissible when it increases the welfare of the least well off member of society. Such a philosophy argues that it is better to have a society where everyone is poor, than to have a society where a few are very poor but most are very well off. Most people do not agree with such ideas. Philosophies which would tend to produce policies more egalitarian than Utilitarian policies tend to call for strategies that would produce very high equality at a significant cost in wealth. One of the hallmarks of Utilitarianism is that it sanctions any effective method for welfare maximization. This means that Utilitarianism is compatible with using a highly productive market economy to generate wealth, and then redistributing it in an efficient and effective manner. Highly egalitarian philosophies other than Utilitarianism often specify rather extreme methods of how equality is to be achieved, such as the compensatory resource distribution of Rawls or the formation of cooperatives under Marxism. These are often not very compatible with market mechanisms, and thus would have substantial problems of inefficiency. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 54 UTIL V DEONT Util good – Scientifically backed Ethics are irrelevant, our theory is backed by scientific data Ian Montgomerie, 2000. (Software Engineer, A Utilitarian FAQ, July 1, 2000, http://www.ianmontgomerie.com/manifesto/utilitarianfaq.html#WHYACCEPT) The most devastating criticism of intuition comes from science, not from philosophy. Philosophy tends to view moral intuitions as some sort of fundamental evidence that constitutes morality, indicating what is right and good for humans to do. In reality, however, such intuitions are the product of biological and cultural evolution. Whenever a certain mental trait granted a survival advantage to those possessing it, that trait became more common. Whenever a certain belief granted a competitive advantage to those believing it, that belief spread. This has long been obvious in general, but recently the specifics are becoming equally obvious. Time and again, scientists in fields from evolutionary biology and evolutionary psychology to psychology and economics keep discovering that human behavioral tendencies and cultural norms correspond to the predictions of evolutionary selection. Our moral intuitions are prescriptive - but not in any moral sense. They prescribe behaviors which promote fitness, in the sense of "survival of the fittest". They do so precisely because they are the result of a process of evolutionary selection (biologically, and culturally) which gave the advantage to intuitions which promoted fitness. The unsettling truth is that the legacy of moral intuition that history has left us cannot conform to any moral ideal which is not equivalent to that which, in practice, best promotes its own survival. Humans have the capabilities of general purpose reasoning which enable us to break from the tyranny of our evolutionary legacy, but only if we choose to use it effectively. In the modern world, reason has shown the power to thrive as never before, serving to promote ideas based on their truth rather than their ability to ensure their own survival. Utilitarianism applies this power to morality, allowing us to discover what is right, rather than what idea of right is most selected for. To make that discovery, we must be entirely willing to reject our intuitions. Indeed, we have good reason to - evolution selects for norms, tendencies, and other determinants of intuition so long as they work well in most situations. Human intuitions are expected to break down in uncommon situations, and to sometimes contradict each other, because this is part and parcel of "bounded rationality" - using the cheapest, most effective decision strategies in the real world. Unlike a proper normative standard, low level human reasoning is not rationally consistent because that is a waste of resources for everyday reasoning. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 55 UTIL V DEONT Util good – Universially applicative Utilitarianism provides an ethical theory that applies to every situation in a well defined manner Ian Montgomerie, 2000. (Software Engineer, A Utilitarian FAQ, July 1, 2000, http://www.ianmontgomerie.com/manifesto/utilitarianfaq.html#WHYACCEPT) A third reason to support Utilitarianism is because of its strong support. The Utilitarian approach to morality can actually be derived from a small set of axioms, such as Bayesian reasoning and Pareto Optimality. These are technical ideas that not everybody accepts, but Utilitarians can point to a small set of reasonable founding assumptions and say "if you accept these, then our philosophy provably follows from them". Because of the power of the concepts it is founded on, Utilitarianism provides an ethical theory that applies to every situation in a well defined manner. Utilitarianism is not easy to apply in practice, but when one gets down to it other philosophies are not either. In fact, most non-Utilitarian philosophies can't even be consistently applied in theory. Philosophies based on the idea of natural rights, for example, have never managed to come up with a complete specification of what to do when different rights conflict with each other. They give some guidance about what to do in relatively ordinary situations, but not how to resolve every possible conflict. Utilitarian theory can provide an answer in any situation, so that we only have to worry about the practical problems that come from applying the ethical theory. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 56 UTIL V DEONT Consequentialism good – Weigh benefits/consequences The duties proclaimed by the affirmative are accommodated by the consequentialist framework; it is simply recognized that these duties exist due to their benefits to society, and must thus be weighed against other concerns consequentially. Jeffrey Lipshaw in 05 (adjunct prof. @ Indiana University School of Law, 36 Cumberland Law Review 321, “DUTY AND CONSEQUENCE: A NON-CONFLATING THEORY OF PROMISE AND CONTRACT”, ln) The source of our normative judgments about things like opportunism requires careful consideration. Modern philosophical consequentialism (of which utilitarianism and welfare economics [*333] are subsets) is properly traced back to Hume, who clearly considered opportunism to be at the core of human nature and would not be the least surprised that moral notions had grown up around it. Indeed, according to Hume, the obligation of promising, apart from any legal consideration, is one "of those three laws [the others being the stability of possession, and its transference by consent], that the peace and security of human society entirely depend; nor is there any possibility of establishing a good correspondence among men, where they are neglected." 40 Hume's view of the obligation of promise, much less contract, is wholly non-deontological. The obligation of promise is not natural (i.e., to will an obligation to another contravenes one's natural self-interest). But over time, it becomes apparent that the mere stability of possession and its transference by consent is not enough to ensure harmony. Hence, "promises have no natural obligation, and are mere artificial contrivances for the convenience and advantage of society." 41 Hume demonstrates this by the example of a promise extracted by force or duress: A man, dangerously wounded, who promises a competent sum to a surgeon to cure him, wou'd certainly be bound to performance; tho' the case be not so much different from that of one, who promises a sum to a robber, as to produce so great a difference in our sentiments of morality, if these sentiments were not built entirely on public interest and convenience. 42 The acknowledged mutual benefit of the honoring of promises--a sort of ritual incantation of a particular set of words, signs, or symbols--produces a "sentiment of morals that concurs with interest, and becomes a new obligation upon mankind." 43 Note, moreover, that this is apart from any legal consequence: "After these signs are instituted, whoever uses them is immediately bound by his interest to execute his engagements, and must never expect to be trusted any more, if he refuse to perform what he promised." 44 Hence, opportunism is an issue that arises in connection with the moral issue of promise before it ever becomes conflated with the legal act of contract. It is therefore hardly a new insight that non-contractual (as well as contractual) obligations can be explained empirically and [*334] consequentially and without resort to deontology. Eric Posner's thesis of social norms, that reputation is a commodity to maximize one's rational self-interest, is Hume's thesis merely restated in the modern lingo of law and economics. What Posner's work presupposes (which Hume, to his credit, does not) is the source of his normative judgment about utility. 45 Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 57 UTIL V DEONT Consequentialism good – Evaluating Catastrophic Consequences When catastrophic consequences are being weighed with rights, the only moral option is to adopt a consequentialist framework. Tim Stelzig in 98 (prof. of philosophy @ West Virginia University, University of Pennsylvania Law Review, Vol. 146, No. 3, “Deontology, Governmental Action, and the Distributive Exemption: How the Trolley Problem Shapes the Relationship Between Rights and Policy”, March, p. 902-903) Yet, as Blackstone also realizes, the "local or occasional necessities of the state" sometimes demand that rights be "modified, narrowed, or enlarged."Bluntly put, sometimes the public good wins out. Rights clearly must give way in catastrophic cases, where harms of colossal proportion will be suffered unless some right is violated. For example, if stopping a terrorist from launching a salvo of nuclear missiles against China required killing several innocent hostages, it would be undeniably" morally permissible-though nevertheless unfortunateto sacrifice the hostages for the greater good. Even a healthy respect for the hostages' rights cannot suffer consequences of such magnitude. Catastrophic cases" do not fundamentally challenge the notion that rights protect us from being sacrificed for the public good. Such cases merely reveal that rights have thresholds." Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 58 UTIL V DEONT Consequentialism good – Solves morality Consequentialist decision making is the moral imperative; any other form of evaluation constitutes a moral evasion, all morals that do not coincide with the theory are corrupt, and the theory respects the value of the individual. Kai Nielsen in 72 (prof. emeritus of philosophy @ University of Calgary, Ethics, Volume 82, “Against Moral Conservatism”, p. 229-230) Alan Donagan, arguing rather as Anscombe argues, maintains that "to use any innocent man ill for the sake of some public good is directly to degrade him to being a mere means" and to do this is of course to violate a principle essential to morality, that is, that human beings should never merely be treated as means but should be treated as ends in themselves (as persons worthy of respect).ll But, as my above remarks show, it need not be the case, and in the above situation it is not the case, that in killing such an innocent man we are treating him merely as a means. The action is universalizable, all alternative actions which would save his life are duly considered, the blasting out is .done only as a last and desperate resort with the minimum of harshness and indifference to his suffering and the like. It indeed sounds ironical to talk this way, given what is done to him. But if such a terrible situation were to arise, there would always be more or less humane ways of going about one's grim task. And in acting in the more humane ways toward the fat man, as we do what we must do and would have done to ourselves were the roles reversed, we show a respect for his person.12 In so treating the fat man-not just to further the public good but to prevent the certain death of a whole group of people (that is to prevent an even greater evil than his being killed in this way)-the claims of justice are not overidden either, for each individual involved, if he is reasoning correctly, should realize that if he were so stuck rather than the fat man, he should in such situations be blasted out. Thus, there is no question of being unfair. Surely we must choose between evils here, but is there anything more reasonable, more morally appropriate, than choosing the lesser evil when doing or allowing some evil cannot be avoided? That is, where there is no avoiding both and where our actions can determine whether a greater or lesser evil obtains, should we not plainly always opt for the lesser evil? And is it not obviously a greater evil that all those other innocent people should suffer and die than that the fat man should suffer and die? Blowing up the fat man is indeed monstrous. But letting him remain stuck while the whole group drowns is still more monstrous. The consequentialist is on strong moral ground here, and, if his reflective moral convictions do not square either with certain unrehearsed or with certain reflective particular moral convictions of human beings, so much the worse for such commonsense moral convictions. One could even usefully and relevantly adapt here-though for a quite different purpoge-an argument of Donagan's. Consequentialism of the kind I have been arguing for provides so persuasive "a theoretical basis for common morality that when it contradicts some moral intuition, it is natural to suspect that intuition, not theory, is corrupt." Given the comprehensiveness, plausibility, and overall rationality of consequentialism, it is not unreasonable to override even a deeply felt moral conviction if it does not square with such a theory, though, if it made no sense or overrode the bulk of or even a great many of our considered moral convictions, that would be another matter indeed. Anticonsequentialists often point to the inhumanity of people who will sanction such killing of the innocent, but cannot the compliment be returned by speaking of the even greater inhumanity, conjoined with evasiveness, of those who will allow even more death and far greater misery and then excuse themselves on the ground that they did not intend the death and misery but merely forbore to prevent it? In such a context, such reasoning and such forbearing to prevent seems to me to constitute a moral evasion. I say it is evasive because rather than steeling himself to do what in normal circumstances would be a horrible and vile act but in this circumstance is a harsh moral necessity, he allows, when he has the power to prevent it, a situation which is still many times worse. He tries to keep his 'moral purity' and avoid 'dirty hands' at the price of utter moral failure and what Kierkegaard called 'doublemindedness.' It is understandable that people should act in this morally evasive way but this does not make it right. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 59 UTIL V DEONT Consequentialism good – Solves morality Only consequentialist thought can explain moral reasoning, which is necessary for any application of moral principles. Walter Sinnot-Armstrong in 92 (prof. of philosophy @ Yale University, Philosophical Perspectives, 6, Ethics, “An Argument for Consequentialism”, p.398) The most common way to choose among moral theories is to test how well they cohere with our intuitions or considered judgments about what is morally, right and wrong, about the nature or ideal of a person, and about the purpose(s) of morality.' Another kind of intuition is often overlooked. We also have intuitions about principles of practical and moral reasoning, such as those captured by deontic logic. In order to be principles of reasoning other than substance, these principles must be consistent with all substantive moral theories. But consistency is not enough. We want the deeper kind of coherence that comes only with explanation. A moral theory that simply reports the principles behind common moral reasoning but cannot explain why these principles are so common or so plausible is inferior in this respect to another moral theory which not only includes the principles but also explains why they are true. Why is the explanatory theory better? Because we want a moral theory to help us understand moral reasoning, and such understanding is gained only when our principles are explained. Without such understanding, our intuitions do not seem justified, and we cannot know whether or how to extend our principles to new situations. These are reasons to prefer a moral theory that explains our principles of moral reasoning. This preference for explanation provides a new method for choosing among competing moral theories. I will illustrate and apply this method in this paper. First, I will argue that a certain principle holds for reasons for action in general and for moral reasons in particular. Next, I will argue that this principle of moral reasoning cannot be explained by deontological moral theories or by traditional forms of consequentialism. Finally, I will outline a new kind of consequentialism that provides a natural explanation of this principle of moral reasoning. Its explanatory power is a reason to prefer this new version of consequentialism. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 60 UTIL V DEONT Consequentialism good – Solves genocide in policy making Consequentialist policy-making leads to deterrence of genocide. Eric Blumenson in 06 (prof. of law @ Suffolk University Law School, 44 Columbia Journal of Transnational Law 801, “The Challenge of a Global Standard of Justice: Peace, Pluralism, and Punishment at the International Criminal Court”, ln) The consequentialist argument is that an appropriately structured punishment will best produce a net social benefit, in excess of the opportunity costs, inmate's suffering, and other losses it will impose. This is an empirical claim about the utility of punishment that may hold true generally but be false at a particular time or place. If the total consequences of a particular prosecution would ultimately be dire rather than beneficial, the consequentialist argument for prosecution would seem to fail. 73 Yet consequentialists are among the strongest advocates for a policy of "prosecution regardless." They must believe either that predicted dire consequences are so often exaggerated that maximum utility can be obtained by uniformly dismissing such predictions; 74 or [*825] more likely, that the immediate consequences, although dire, will be ultimately outweighed by long-term benefits. However, there is a major difficulty, arguably not insurmountable, with identifying and calculating the costs and benefits. In most domestic systems, the expected benefit will usually involve a reduction in crime, due to the deterrent, normreinforcing, incapacitative, or rehabilitative impact of incarcerating offenders. For the ICC, this is also an expectation. Many people argue that if genocide and crimes against humanity are reliably prosecuted and punished, a deterrent effect should follow - if not for some megalomaniacal leaders, at least for the subordinates who would otherwise carry out their orders. Only consequentialism can justify the actions necessary to reach some moral end. Walter Sinnot-Armstrong in 92 (prof. of philosophy @ Yale University, Philosophical Perspectives, 6, Ethics, “An Argument for Consequentialism”, p. 415-416) All of this leads to necessary enabler consequentialism or NEC. NEC claims that all moral reasons for acts are provided by facts that the acts are necessary enablers for preventing harm or promoting good. All moral reasons on this theory are consequential reasons, but there are two kinds. Some moral reasons are prevention reasons, because they are facts that an act is a necessary enabler for preventing harm or loss. For example, if giving Alice food is necessary and enables me to prevent her from starving, then that fact is a moral reason to give her food. In this case, I would not cause her death even 416 / Walter Sinnott-Armstrong if I let her starve, but other moral prevention reasons are reasons to avoid causing harm. For example, if turning my car to the left is necessary and enables me to avoid killing Bobby, that is a moral reason to turn my car to the left. The other kind of moral reason is a promotion reason. This kind of reason occurs when doing something is necessary and enables me to promote (or maximize) some good. For example, I have a moral reason to throw a surprise party for Susan if this is necessary and enables me to make her happy. Because of substitutability, these moral reasons for actions also yield moral reasons against contrary actions. There are then also moral reasons not to do what will cause harm or ensure a failure to prevent harm or to promote good. What makes these facts moral reasons is that they can make an otherwise immoral act moral. If I have a moral reason to feed my child, then it might be immoral to give my only food to Alice, who is a stranger. But this would not be immoral if giving Alice food is necessary and enables me to prevent 'Alice from starving, as long as my child will not starve also. Similarly, it is normally immoral to lie to Susan, but a lie can be moral if it is necessary and enables me to keep my party for Susan a surprise, and if this is also necessary and enables me to make her happy. Thus, NEC fits nicely into the above theory of moral reasons. NEC can provide a natural explanation of moral substitutability for both kinds of moral reasons. I have a prevention moral reason to give someone food when doing so is necessary and enables me to prevent that person from starving. Suppose that buying food is a necessary enabler for giving the person food, and getting in my car is a necessary enabler for buying food. Moral substitutability warrants the conclusion that I have a moral reason to get in my car. And this act of getting in my car does have the property of being a necessary enabler for preventing starvation. Thus, the necessary enabler has the same property that provided the moral reason to give the food in the first place. This explains why substitutability holds for moral prevention reasons. The other kind of moral reason covers necessary enablers for promoting good. In my example above, if a surprise party is a necessary enabler for making Susan happy, and letting people know about the party is a necessary enabler for having the party, then letting people know is a necessary enabler for making Susan happy. The very fact that provides a moral reason to have the party also provides a moral reason to let people know about it. Thus, NEC can explain why moral substitutability holds for every kind of moral reason that it includes. Similar explanations work for moral reasons not to do certain acts, and this explanatory power is a reason to favor NEC.17 Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 61 UTIL V DEONT Nuclear War Outweighs Nuclear War will always outweigh- the risk of extinction means it is prohibited absolutely George Kateb, 1992. (The Inner Ocean: Individualism and Democratic Culture, Cornell University Press, 1992.pgs. 111-112) Schell's work attempts to force on us an acknowledgment that sounds far-fetched and even ludicrous, an acknowledgment that the possibility of extinction is carried by any use of nuclear weapons, no matter how limited or how seemingly rational or seemingly morally justified. He himself acknowledges that there is a difference between possibility and certainty. But in a matter that is more than a matter, more than one practical matter in a vast series of practical matters, in the "matter" of extinction, we are obliged to treat a possibility--a genuine possibility-as a certainty. Humanity is not to take any step that contains even the slightest risk of extinction. The doctrine of no-use is based on the possibility of extinction. Schell's perspective transforms the subject. He takes us away from the arid stretches of strategy and asks us to feel continuously, if we can, and feel keenly if only for an instant now and then, how utterly distinct the nuclear world is. Nuclear discourse must vividly register that distinctiveness. It is of no moral account that extinction may be only a slight possibility. No one can say how great the possibility is, but no one has yet credibly denied that by some sequence or other a particular use of nuclear weapons may lead to human and natural extinction. If it is not impossible it must be treated as certain: the loss signified by extinction nullifies all calculations of probability as it nullifies all calculations of costs and benefits. Abstractly put, the connections between any use of nuclear weapons and human and natural extinction are several. Most obviously, a sizable exchange of strategic nuclear weapons can, by a chain of events in nature, lead to the earth's uninhabitability, to "nuclear winter," or to Schell "republic of insects and grass." But the consideration of extinction cannot rest with the possibility of a sizable exchange of strategic weapons. It cannot rest with the imperative that a sizable exchange must not take place. A so-called tactical or "theater" use, or a so-called limited use, is also prohibited absolutely, because of the possibility of immediate escalation into a sizable exchange or because, even if there were not an immediate escalation, the possibility of extinction would reside in the precedent for future use set by any use whatever in a world in which more than one power possesses nuclear weapons. Add other consequences: the contagious effect on nonnuclear powers who may feel compelled by a mixture of fear and vanity to try to acquire their own weapons, thus increasing the possibility of use by increasing the number of nuclear powers; and the unleashed emotions of indignation, retribution, and revenge which, if not acted on immediately in the form of escalation, can be counted on to seek expression later. Other than full strategic uses are not confined, no matter how small the explosive power: each would be a cancerous transformation of the world. All nuclear roads lead to the possibility of extinction. It is true by definition, but let us make it explicit: the doctrine of no-use excludes any first or retaliatory or later use, whether sizable or not. No-use is the imperative derived from the possibility of extinction. By containing the possibility of extinction, any use is tantamount to a declaration of war against humanity. It is not merely a war crime or a single crime against humanity. Such a war is waged by the user of nuclear weapons against every human individual as individual (present and future), not as citizen of this or that country. It is not only a war against the country that is the target. To respond with nuclear' weapons, where possible, only increases the chances of extinction and can never, therefore, be allowed. The use of nuclear weapons establishes the right of any person or group, acting officially or not, violently or not, to try to punish those responsible for the use. The aim of the punishment is to deter later uses and thus to try to reduce the possibility of extinction, if, by chance, the particular use in question did not directly lead to extinction. The form of the punishment cannot be specified. Of course the chaos ensuing from a sizable exchange could make punishment irrelevant. The important point, however, is to see that those who use nuclear weapons are qualitatively worse than criminals, and at the least forfeit their offices. John Locke, a principal individualist political theorist, says that in a state of nature every individual retains the right to punish transgressors or assist in the effort to punish them, whether or not one is a direct victim. Transgressors convert an otherwise tolerable condition into a state of nature which is a state of war in which all are threatened. Analogously, the use of nuclear weapons, by containing in an immediate or delayed manner the possibility of extinction, is in Locke's phrase "a trespass against the whole species" and places the users in a state of war with all people. And people, the accumulation of individuals, must be understood as of course always indefeasibly retaining the right of selfpreservation, and hence as morally allowed, perhaps enjoined, to take the appropriate preserving steps. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 62 UTIL V DEONT Nuclear war outweighs Nuclear war must be thought of in consequential terms because of its large magnitude, and immoral acts need to be justified to prevent it. William H. Shaw in 1984 (socialist professor and former Chair of the Philosophy Department at San Jose State University., Ethics, Vol. 94, No. 2. (Jan., 1984), pp. 248-260., http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=00141704%28198401%2994%3A2%3C248%3ANDAD%3E2.0.CO%3B2-7 ) Of all the moral issues that face us today, however, nuclear policy is the one that, because of the complex factual issues and number of persons likely to be affected, most cries out to be handled in consequentialist terms. Although it is clearly good even on utilitarian grounds that we have a repugnance to making threats of immoral behavior, even where P6 would condone it, the limits of a narrowly deontological perspective are soon obvious. For one thing, such discussions do not easily integrate finely grained factual issues or questions of probability, such as the chances of a nuclear accident, into their overall moral assessments. Much hangs on the real, historical and political (as opposed to merely game-theoretically supposed), consequences of the contemporary practice of deterrencenuclear proliferationand on assessing accurately the feasibility of alternatives to the current arms race. A moral theory with significant consequentialist strands would seem to be necessary to give these sorts of considerations their due. Deontological approaches to nuclear questions have no doubt appeared attractive to many as a result of the poor quality of what passes for utilitarian reasoning in this area. Utilitarianism has unfortunately come to be identified with the so-called strategic reasoning associated with military planners and benighted bureaucrats, the narrowness and jaundiced assumptions of which make it a very mad logic indeed.'' Utilitarians will have to reexamine their factual premises and move their analyses out of the narrow confines of game theory if they are to assist in the ethical reappraisal of nuclear policy, to which our troubled times have given rise and to which this essay has attempted to contribute. Even if it is imperative to act based on morality, extreme consequences, such as nuclear catstrophe, still override deontological concerns. Eric Blumenson in 06 (prof. of law @ Suffolk University Law School, 44 Columbia Journal of Transnational Law 801, “The Challenge of a Global Standard of Justice: Peace, Pluralism, and Punishment at the International Criminal Court”, ln) Both of the above theories quickly lead to extreme applications that very few would accept. A white lie about someone's whereabouts is surely required when telling the truth would facilitate his murder, contra Kant's deontological absolutism. And the minimize-injustice view, which licenses the authorities to unjustly kill one so that two putative murder victims survive, forsakes human rights in the name of rights. Here is a third possibility which does not force us to such unacceptable conclusions. This view does recognize the inviolable status of individuals, but it also incorporates the common intuition that this status has a limit. That limit is the catastrophic exception. Put in different words, a person's right to justice, and the ICC's duty to deliver it, are of great weight, but they are not absolute and can be overridden in extreme circumstances. This position is often labeled threshold deontology - the threshold is that level of aggregate harm (or, alternatively, aggregate injustice) at which deontological rights and duties are overridden. 147 Below that threshold, a person's human rights cannot be impinged, even if doing so would produce great benefits or avert serious harms to others. But violating someone's rights is justified when the aggregate harm that would result reaches the catastrophic threshold. 148 This view gets much of its force from the intuitive responses most people have to extreme scenarios such as the ticking bomb hypothetical, where torturing a terrorist's child is the only way to reveal the location of a nuclear bomb in time to defuse it. That intuition distills into the view that, in the words of Michael Moore, "a very high threshold of bad consequences ... must be threatened before something as awful as torturing an innocent person can be justified." 149 Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 63 UTIL V DEONT Nuclear war outweighs Preventing nuclear war is a deontological imperative because of the huge stakes and no accurate method of figuring out the future. Robert E. Goodin in 1985 (D.Phil. in Politics at Oxford,Ethics, Vol. 95, No. 3, Special Issue: Symposium on Ethics and Nuclear Deterrence. (Apr., 1985), pp. 641-658. “Nuclear Disarmament as a Moral Certainty”, http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0014-1704%28198504%2995%3A3%3C641%3ANDAAMC%3E2.0.CO%3B2-L ) That the logic of nuclear deterrence is incorrigibly probabilistic is widely acknowledged. Strategists and social scientists describe as its "fundamental premise" the proposition that "nuclear weapons make probable the rejection [by one's opponents] of armed aggression as a potential policy alternative" (emphasis added). Moral philosophers also fully acknowledge the nature of the gamble. In the words of Bernard Williams, "The morality of deterrence is, I think, legitimately one in which you think principally about those steps which make it less lightly that the weapons get used" (emphasis added). My argument is that all such notions of probability and likelihood are simply inappropriate in these circumstances. Maybe such concepts are not even meaningful at all when applied to situations involving reflective human agents rather than mere random processes. But in any case it is clear that, where probabilities of nuclear war are concerned, we just do not know enough about the shape of the underlying distribution to justify employing any of the standard techniques for estimating probabilities. That we can have no reliable probability estimates is in itself quite enough to render probabilistic reasoning about such affairs wildly inappropriate. Certainly we have no solid objective statistics, based on frequency counts or such like. The balance of terror has kept the peace for the past thirtyfive years, to be sure. But thirty-five years is just too short a run on which to base our probability judgments, given the unacceptability of even very small probabilities of such a very great horror. Besides, nuclear war is just not the sort of thing whose probabilities we dare to estimate by trial-and-error procedures-the first error may well mark the learner's own end.' Nor do we have any well-validated scientific theories (about, e.g., the genesis and escalation of international conflicts) from which we might hope to derive reliable estimates of the probability of a breakdown in deterrence which would lead to a large-scale nuclear war. We suffer not from a lack of such theories but rather from a surfeit of them; and none can prove itself decisively superior to all the others.' Nor, finally, do we have any particularly good reason to place any great faith in subjective probability estimates. Of course, we can always bully people into stating their "best guess" as to the chances of anything occurring; we can even bully them into rendering those probability estimates consistent. But when such estimates are as groundless as those concerning the chances of nuclear deterrence collapsing into nuclear war are, we should not set any great store by them. Ellsberg says, "It's no use bullying me into taking action . . . by flattering my 'best judgment.' I know how little that's based Alas, most people do not. Psychological evidence suggests not only that "individuals are poor probability assessors" but also, "and perhaps more important, that they underestimate their poorness by assessing probabilities too tightly."1° Knowing this-and knowing all the severe distortions to which judgments under uncertainty are prone1'-it would be sheer folly for us to predicate any profoundly important policy choices on such fallible subjective probability estimates. The upshot is that it is altogether inappropriate to engage in probabilistic reasoning about the chances of a breakdown in the balance of terror that leads to a large-scale nuclear war. Objective statistics are unavailable; theories are too numerous and too divergent; subjective estimates are known to be too unreliable." The problem is not just that we cannot estimate point probabilities with any great precision-that we cannot say whether the probability of nuclear war this century is 10 percent or 15 percent. Nor is it even just that we cannot make the sorts of order-of-magnitude judgments that would allow us to make ordinal judgments about relative probabilities. We are in a worse situation still. We cannot even say with confidence in what direction any particular strategic innovation pushes the probability of all-out nuclear war. Some theories maintain that that risk is increased by cruise missiles or spacebased defenses or nuclear proliferation. Others hold the opposite.13 Neither logic nor experience enables us to choose confidently between these theories, and only a fool would trust unaided hunches with so much at stake. The most that can be claimed for deterrence is that it will probably work to prevent war. So if probabilistic reasoning is inappropriate in these circumstances, deterrence is too. In short, my complaint against nuclear deterrence is that it amounts to playing the odds without knowing the odds. That constitutes recklessness par excellence. It would be the height of irresponsibility for anyone to wager the family home on rolls of such radically unpredictable dice. Where millions of lives are at stake, that judgment must surely apply even more harshly. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 64 UTIL V DEONT Consequentialism = Inevitable Deontology inevitably runs into a necessity for consequentialist principles regarding the right to life that are unanswerable by assertions of “moral duty”. Eric Blumenson in 06 (prof. of law @ Suffolk University Law School, 44 Columbia Journal of Transnational Law 801, “The Challenge of a Global Standard of Justice: Peace, Pluralism, and Punishment at the International Criminal Court”, ln) For deontologists, the issue becomes especially complicated when treating retributive justice as an absolute requirement would destroy other moral rights they regard as equally absolute. If ICC charges against LRA leaders would prolong the war as the Acholi leaders claim, the result would be not simply deaths, but killings perpetrated in violation of a non-negotiable right to life. Should the ICC not indict, thereby perpetrating an injustice in order to avoid a greater injustice? War crimes prosecutions are prone to such dilemmas. Sometimes prosecuting some individuals would result in many more escaping punishment. 129 Sometimes obtaining [*843] indictments may induce a criminal regime to cling to power, leaving that country's population consigned to suffer continued violations of their most fundamental human rights. Dworkin famously described such rights as "trumps," because they demarcate areas in which the individual is inviolable, and thus trump even a majority's competing preferences or interests. 130 These rights and moral duties are not supposed to be subject to trade-offs - but in the above cases, observing one non-negotiable right or duty will sacrifice another. Each cannot trump the other, so how should one assess this collision of absolutist moral demands? Embracing a moral imperative to bring criminals to justice does not answer this question, unless accompanied by reasons why this moral command should have priority over the others. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 65 UTIL V DEONT Deontology bad – Lacks humanity / morality The idea that moral duties must absolutely come before consequences lacks a basic sense of morality and humanity. Eric Blumenson in 06 (prof. of law @ Suffolk University Law School, 44 Columbia Journal of Transnational Law 801, “The Challenge of a Global Standard of Justice: Peace, Pluralism, and Punishment at the International Criminal Court”, ln) The central problem with these rigid rules is, of course, their absolutism: They take what seem to be important moral considerations entirely off the table. 138 If we take there to be a [*846] retributive duty to bring criminals to justice, they posit that the ICC has an absolute duty to assure prosecution, rendering irrelevant any undesired destructive impact it would have. It does not matter if that impact is catastrophic, or fully foreseeable, or wholly set in motion by the prosecution. Kant believed this, and is famous for a parallel deontological claim - that one is obligated not to lie, even when it means divulging the whereabouts of someone to an enemy bent on killing him. 139 Most people would no doubt regard this as the view of a fanatic, or of someone lacking basic humanity. The challenge is how to properly respond to such dangers yet still recognize the obligations of justice in a principled way. Consider two alternatives to the purist view, each of which treats obligations of justice as a priority, but one that can be overridden by other moral considerations. Deontology cannot justify the performance of actions required to achieve an ultimate moral duty without resorting to consequentialism. Walter Sinnot-Armstrong in 92 (prof. of philosophy @ Yale University, Philosophical Perspectives, 6, Ethics, “An Argument for Consequentialism”, p. 413) Of course, there are many other versions of deontology. I cannot discuss them all. Nonetheless, these examples suggest that it is the very nature of deontological reasons that makes deontological theories unable to explain moral substitutability. This comes out clearly if we start from the other side and ask which properties create the moral reasons that are derived by moral substitutability. What gives me a moral reason to start the mower is the consequences of starting the mower. Specifically, it has the consequence that I am able to mow the grass. This reason cannot derive from the same property as my moral reason to mow the lawn unless what gives me a moral reason to mow the lawn is its consequences. Thus, any non-consequentialist moral theory will have to posit two distinct kinds of moral reasons: one for starting the mower and another for mowing the grass. Once these kinds of reasons are separated, we need to understand the connection between them. But this connection cannot be explained by the substantive principles of the theory. That is why all deontological theories must lack the explanatory coherence which is a general test of adequacy for all theories. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 66 UTIL V DEONT Deontology Bad – Contridicts itself Deontology is flawed – it is impossible to construct a deontological framework without extensive contradiction and total regulation of action. Tim Stelzig in 98 (prof. of philosophy @ West Virginia University, University of Pennsylvania Law Review, Vol. 146, No. 3, “Deontology, Governmental Action, and the Distributive Exemption: How the Trolley Problem Shapes the Relationship Between Rights and Policy”, March, p. 922) The structure of deontic norms is equivalent to that of agentrelative injunctions of the form of 'You must not do x.''~'As an agentrelative restriction, the point is not that Xnot occur, but that you, indexed to each, not do x.Io0 Given this structure, if rights are to have any practical meaning, the variable's referent must be given substantive content.lOl Otherwise, one will not know which facts should be given accord and will not know how to act properly. Given this structure, deontology cannot be thought plausibly to exhaust morality. The reason is that the world is virtually saturated with normativity. If deontological maxims were exhaustive of morality, each identifiable situation to which morality applies would have to be governed by a separate deontological maxim. Normativity would be replete with trumping commands, governing even the most picayune situations. This notion is implausible for at least three reasons. Such a view raises an "epistemological problem," a "conflicts problem," and an "insufficiency problem." Deontological impacts cannot be measured to determine questions of policy, while deontology itself is filled with paradoxes. Jeffrey Lipshaw in 05 (adjunct prof. @ Indiana University School of Law, 36 Cumberland Law Review 321, “DUTY AND CONSEQUENCE: A NON-CONFLATING THEORY OF PROMISE AND CONTRACT”, ln) Academic law, particularly in its explanatory and normative role for commercial relationships, aspires to science and, as such, abhors deontology. Two primary reasons for this exist. First, consequences are measurable, at least in theory. There is no "methodological purchase" in deontology. 10 Second, deontology is fraught with paradox. For every duty, there is a seemingly polar opposite consideration. Consideration of duty entails bright lines and gray areas, law and equity, fixed rules and intuitive application. Recognition of the paradox of deontology is as old as our thinking about right and wrong. The theology of the prophet Micah was based on the inability of human reason to reconcile justice and mercy. But Micah's resolution was bereft of philosophy or science, and left the untying of the knot to God. 11 The paradoxes of deontology (much less the paradox posed by our apparent inability to reconcile deontology and consequentialism) are particularly frustrating to anyone who wants to set forth a unified theory. 12 Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 67 UTIL V DEONT Deontology bad – Justifies killings Deontology justifies killing in the name of moral intentions. PETER SINGER in 1978 (Professor of Bioethics at Princeton University, Doing Evil to Achieve Good: Moral Choice in Conflict Situations., ed. Richard McCormick and Paul Ramesy. Chicago: Loyola University Press, 1978. 267, “Do Consequences Count? Rethinking the Doctrine of Double Effect JSTOR) Traditional Roman Catholic thought makes an important distinction between what one directly intends and what one merely foresees as a consequence of one's actions. Suppose a doctor is faced with a pregnant woman who announces her intention of committing suicide unless she can obtain an abortion. From his past knowledge of the patient, the doctor believes she will carry out the threat. Traditional Roman Catholic morality nevertheless prohibits the abortion because it regards the act as the direct killing of an innocent human being, which is always wrong. Neither the goal of saving the woman's life, nor the fact that if the woman kills herself the fetus will also die, can justify the abortion, for the traditional view is that the end cannot justify the means. On the other hand, according to the traditional Roman Catholic view, a doctor confronted with a pregnant patient who has cancer of the uterus may remove the uterus. He knows, of course, that this will result in the death of the fetus, but here the death of the fetus is not directly intended, either for its own sake or as a means to an end. It is an unwanted side effect of removing the cancerous uterus. These two cases illustrate the distinction between the directly intended effect of our actions and the foreseen but unwanted side effects of what we do. This distinction is the basis of the doctrine of double effect, which holds that while there are some things we are never justified in doing directly, we may permit them to occur as a side effect of some other action that we do for a sufficient or proportionate reason. As the cases show, the doctrine claims that there is a crucial moral difference between actions the consequences of which are, apparently, identical. For if the doctor performs an abortion on the woman who will otherwise commit suicide, he will save her life, while if he does not, both she and the fetus will die; and exactly the same is true of the choice to remove the cancerous uterus. The idea that so slender a distinction as that between what we intend to do and what we foresee as the result of our actions could make so decisive a moral difference between acts whose consequences appear to be identical, has led many non- Catholics to regard the doctrine of double effect as a paradigm example of spurious moral casuistry, the kind of reasoning that has given the word "jesuitical" its condemnatory overtones. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 68 UTIL V DEONT A2: Util and freedom mutally exclusive Utilitarianism recognizes the value of individual freedom; it simply places a calculus of the harm dealt by freedom in some cases before that freedom. Roger Scruton in 06 (phd in philosophy, Wall Street Journal, “Thoroughly Modern Mill”, May 19, pg. A.10) Mill's rebellion against utilitarianism did not prevent him from writing a qualified defense of it, and his "Utilitarianism" is acknowledged today as one of the few readable accounts of a moral disorder that would have died out two centuries ago, had people not discovered that the utilitarian can excuse every crime. Lenin and Hitler were pious utilitarians, as were Stalin and Mao, as are most members of the Mafia. As Mill recognized, the "greatest happiness principle" must be qualified by some guarantee of individual rights, if it is not to excuse the tyrant. In response to his own wavering discipleship, therefore, he wrote "On Liberty," perhaps his most influential, though by no means his best, production. At the time, Benthamite ways of thinking were influencing jurisprudence, and arguments based on the "general good" and the "good of society" appealed to the conservative imagination of the Victorian middle classes. It seemed right to control the forms of public worship, to forbid the expression of heretical opinions, or to criminalize adultery, for the sake of a "public morality" which exists for the general good. If individual freedom suffers, then that, according to the utilitarians, is the price we must pay. According to Mill's argument, that way of thinking has everything upside down. The law does not exist to uphold majority morality against the individual, but to protect the individual against tyranny -- including the "tyranny of the majority." Of course, if the exercise of individual freedom threatens harm to others, it is legitimate to curtail it -- for in such circumstances one person's gain in freedom is another person's loss of it. But when there is no proof of harm to another, the law must protect the individual's right to act and speak as he chooses. Utilitarianism is not exclusionary; rather, exclusion reflects the society applying utilitarianism. F. Neil Brady in 85 (assistant prof. of management @ San Diego State University, Journal of Business Ethics, “A Defense of Utilitarian Policy Processes in Corporate and Public Management”, issue 23-30, p. 24) In short, there is a kind of myopia that occurs in both corporate and public processes, but it is a narrowness of vision which discourages the expression of extreme or unpopular preferences and solicits, instead, moderate, current, or common preferences. That is, expressions of preference at the periphery get washed out, not just selected preferences such as sympathies for whales. Furthermore, even if this were true, nothing that Tribe has said can convincingly connect this flaw to utilitarian procedures per se. Utilitarian theory in principle allows for the weighing of all preferences – ‘high’ or ‘low’, retrospective or prospective. And although policy processes do seem to undervalue peripheral interests, such a phenomenon may be due as much to human socialization, for example, as to a given decision-making procedure. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 69 UTIL V DEONT A2: Utilitarianism kills human rights. It is the because of consequences that human rights must be upheld-utilitarianism is not mutually exclusive with human rights Taranovsky in 2003 (Dmytro, Utilitarianism, <http://web.mit.edu/dmytro/www/Utilitarianism.htm>) Some people argue that utilitarianism is contrary to human rights. The support for human rights is based on our feelings and deep beliefs that human rights are good. These feelings do not arise in a vacuum. They are acquired because, as history repeatedly shows, violations of human rights have horrible consequences. Censorship, more likely than not, prevents indispensible changes in societies that practice it. The benefits of torture are insignificant compared to the suffering it inflicts and the damage to benevolence of the society. Because of fallibility of human nature and the special nature of fundamental rights, abridgements of human rights cause unacceptable danger to the society. For example, allowing the government to conduct a lottery for forcible organ donations would present unacceptable danger for abuse as the government can kill any person by faking the lottery results. It is such abuses in the past, senseless government sponsored murders for alleged public good that cause a subconscious aversion to such lottery. Thus, the utilitarian benefits of human rights coincide with the main reasons why the feelings on human rights have developed. Unlike reliance on feelings, utilitarianism places human rights on a strong logical foundation. The intuitions for human rights are fragile, and many societies lack them; even in the United States today, government sponsored homicide of certain helpless "undesirable" people, i.e. death penalty, is considered acceptable. Moreover, wrong intuitions can create fictitious rights, like the right of parents to beat their children, or, in the past, the right of slave owners to their lawfully acquired property, slaves. Therefore, utilitarianism protects and enhances human rights. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 70 UTIL V DEONT A2: Util doesn’t account for separateness A2: Util doesn’t account for separateness – util is egalitarian. Bentley in 2000 (Kristina A., has an MA in political theory from Rhodes University and completed a PhD in the Department of Government at the University of Manchester in 2001. From 1996–1998, Dr Bentley was a lecturer in political theory in the Department of Political Studies and International Relations at Rhodes University. Her areas of research interest are theories and concepts of rights, the rights of vulnerable persons, rights and multiculturalism, and the enforceability of social and economic rights; Suggesting a “Separate” Approach to Utility and Rights: Deontological Specification and Teleological Enforcement of Human Rights, Sapientia, September, < http://www.abdn.ac.uk/pir/postgrad/vol1_issue3/issue3_article1.pdf>) Thirdly, and most significantly for rights, there is the objection that utilitarians do not account for the “‘separateness’ of persons” (Goodin, 1995: 23). However, this is to discount the utilitarian conviction that every individual is “a distinct locus of value” counting equally with everyone else, and furthermore utilitarianism assumes that people are roughly similar in their capacity for pleasure and pain. Therefore, empirical assumptions of broad similarity among people and generally diminishing marginal utility across all resources lead utilitarians to embrace policies and practices and institutions that are broadly egalitarian in form. That ensures that there will be a strong utilitarian presumption against exploiting some people for the benefit of others (Goodin, 1995: 23). Goodin therefore advocates what he refers to as “government house utilitarianism” as being “a uniquely defensible public policy” (Goodin, 1995: 27) as it in this sphere that utilitarianism is particularly appropriate to decision making and solving the sorts of problems which public officials inevitably encounter. This relates to rights in the sense that public officials are charged with the often onerous tasks of carrying out and enforcing the duties associated with rights. While this position will be discussed in more detail in section 6.2 below, it is worth mentioning here that many of the hard choices which officials have to make arise out of questions of conflicts of rights at this level. It may well prove to be the case the that the optimal, if not the maximal, way of making such decisions for any given society involve the sort of utilitarian private vices and public virtues which Goodin identifies. Therefore, the idea of “satisficing” rather than maximising utilitarianism which is discussed in the following section is worth considering as it may be provide a way of indicating the level at which the teleological compromise should be struck in any given case involving a conflict of rights. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 71 UTIL V DEONT A2: util= suffering In some instances, Utilitarians are willing to let some suffer in order to promote the welfare of others; but this notion is not unlike any other philosophy-your suffering arguments are non-unique Ian Montgomerie, 2000. (Software Engineer, A Utilitarian FAQ, July 1, 2000, http://www.ianmontgomerie.com/manifesto/utilitarianfaq.html#WHYACCEPT) It is quite true that Utilitarianism would sanction any "horrible" act if a sufficiently large number of people wanted it to happen. For any given act which causes some finite decrease in welfare, there exists some number of people whose desire for that act would, all together, cause them to gain enough welfare to justify the act. This has been used in a great many thought experiments designed to criticize Utilitarianism for supporting some seemingly repugnant deed because enough people wanted it to happen. One common example is the Roman Coliseum and its gory battles to the death. The Roman public quite enjoyed the spectacle, and there exists some large but finite number of Romans whose welfare gains from watching the games would seem sufficient to justify them. One rebuttal to this is that in practice, it may be beneficial in the long run to prevent many "horrible" acts to work against the perception that they are necessary. Something such as the violent Roman games, for example, would likely have significant negative psychological side effects on the viewers, plus of course the suffering of those actually fighting in the arena. In the long term, a utility maximizing strategy could involve trying to get rid of the institution and focus the public on less destructive forms of entertainment - which would probably require denying people the pleasure of watching the games in the short term. Also, it is often necessary to engage in a great deal of hand waving to make a horrible action truly utility maximizing when all alternatives are considered. In the case of a public with a strong desire for blood sports, for example, they could be satisfied by volunteers. Sufficient payment can induce people to take great risks very willingly. Sending slaves to die in the games may make sense if you fundamentally don't care about the lives of slaves, but not if you regard the welfare of all people as important enough to pay for. In the real world, things like slavery can be effective from the perspective of a selfinterested person who is not the slave, but they are virtually never the welfare maximizing alternative. While some specific "horrible" acts might not be advocated by Utilitarians in practice, however, one can always come up with an example sufficiently contrived that there would be no Utilitarian objections to it. The real question in such extreme examples, apart from the obvious one of how reliable our real-world intuitions are in such unreal situations, is exactly how much that differs from non-Utilitarian philosophies. Utilitarianism is explicit about being willing to let some suffer in order to promote the welfare of others, but virtually every other philosophy is willing to support the same thing. The difference is that they are less obvious about it, being horrified at the deliberate sacrifice of another but supporting behavior which amounts to the same thing. See the next question in this FAQ, "Utilitarians would sanction things like sacrificing a healthy man to use his organs to save five sick men", for more details on this. In general, all ethical philosophies must trade off the welfare of some for the welfare of others (or ignore it entirely), because it is not possible to satisfy the welfare of everybody at once. Given that, it is virtually impossible to prevent situations where a horrible thing ends up happening to some people because preventing it would violate some other moral rule, or would require others to sacrifice too much of their well-being. Gonzaga Debate Institute 2007 CLEARY/GORDON LAB 72 UTIL V DEONT Survival outweighs in African Morality FOR AFRICANS THE SHORT-TERM AND LONG-TERM SURVIVAL TAKES PRECEDENCE OVER WHAT WE CALL ‘MORALITY.’ THIS IS AN AFRICAN SOURCE Malindi, 2005. (Grace M.E., Ph.D., Department of Agriculture Extension Services, 14-16th April, 2005, “A PAPER PRESENTED AT THE DURBAN CONFERENCE International Conference on HIV/AIDS and Food and Nutrition Security”, Ministry of Agriculture, Malawi, IFPRI.Org.) Bota et al., (2001) attest to the fact that institutional development in the rural areas such as markets, trading centers and community schools has introduced unintended consequences of providing havens for sexual promiscuity. It was also observed that, some women especially those in the female-headed category sell out sex to meet their basic needs. Thus, the need for immediate survival takes precedence over morality and longer -term survival and prevention strategies. It has also been shown that work requirements and demands by the marketing and banking systems make extension workers and farmers spend prolonged periods away from their spouses. This also increases their chance of engaging in extra-marital sex. For example, farmers have to travel long distances and wait for a number of days to witness their tobacco being sold, or access money after sales.