Is Business Practice Morally Significant? James Dempsey Introduction This paper takes as its starting point the recent development of approaches to tackling ethical questions in business that are based on the social contract model1. These approaches have sought to establish a methodology to identify action-guiding norms that apply to people engaged in business activity, in particular they have been aimed at those operating in a corporate environment. The defining theory in this area remains Integrative Social Contracts Theory2 (Donaldson & Dunfee, 1999; Dunfee, 2006), although as both an approach to understanding corporate morality, and an approach in the social contracts tradition, it has been subjected to significant criticism. The criticisms have been wide-ranging, and as Dunfee himself admits there is considerable scope for development of the theory (Dunfee, 2006). In his 2006 review of the state of ISCT Dunfee identifies nineteen areas for additional work. In this paper I will focus on one in particular – the theoretical justification of the macrosocial contract – although implications for many others will flow from any conclusions reached here. One such implication is worth emphasising, and I will touch on it directly: this is the challenge posed to the concept of bounded moral rationality, criticism of which, Dunfee notes, has been largely absent from the extensive commentary on ISCT. I will start by outlining the main aspects of ISCT, as proposed by Donaldson and Dunfee, and I will then consider the criticisms of this theory made by Ben Wempe (Wempe, 2007)3. Wempe makes these criticisms by way of a comparative analysis with successful applications of social contract theory to questions of political authority (e.g. Hobbes and Rousseau) and to questions of social justice (e.g. Rawls). From this analysis, Wempe identifies four design criteria that any successful CBE must satisfy, and argues that, as it stands, ISCT does not satisfy any of them. Working within Wempe’s framework, I will argue that it is in fact possible to interpret ISCT as satisfying the first of his design criteria, although this is not how the theory has typically been interpeted by critics nor, perhaps, by its authors. This first design criterion is that of ‘self-discipline’ with regards to the theoretical or practical aim of the application of contract theory. The idea is that no application should try and accomplish more than is reasonable given the nature and the limitations of the contract model. Having identified an aim within ISCT that is disciplined in this way, I will go on to argue that a satisfactory rendering of the contract model to achieve this aim promises to satisfy Wempe’s other design criteria as well. Unfortunately, however, ISCT as it currently stands does not succeed in doing this. Part of the problem, the part on which I will focus, rests with an initial contracting situation that is neither independently justified, nor plausible as a means for reaching 1 To follow the convention in current literature on the subject, I shall call such theories ‘contractarian theories of business ethics’, hereafter CBEs. This title is potentially misleading, however, since the intention is to capture all theories that utilise a social contract framework, and not a subset that make certain assumptions about contractors’ motivations, as is the case when ‘contractarian’ is used as a contrast to ‘contractualist’ (for an outline of this distinction see, for example, the Stanford Encyclopaedia entry on ‘Contractualism’ (Ashford & Mulgan, 2008)) 2 Hereafter ISCT 3 For a development of this criticism, see also (Wempe, 2004), (Wempe, 2005) 1 the desired conclusions. It is here that the concept of bounded moral rationality is supposed to play its role, and can be found wanting. I conclude by suggesting that, in order to get to the bottom of the challenges faced by ISCT, more attention should be given to the theory that is undoubtedly its major inspiration: Rawls’ theory of a ‘political’ conception of justice in his Political Liberalism (Rawls, 1993). The ISCT Project To start with, then, I will consider the main points of ISCT. The basic background against which ISCT is set is one of disagreement4. Dunfee and Donaldson start their book with two examples based on the oil company Royal / Dutch Shell. The first concerns Shell’s behaviour in Nigeria, where their efforts to secure a gas development project were attacked by critics as helping to bring about the trial of nine environmental activists, including the author Ken Saro-Wiwa; moreover, they were also attacked for making no effort to dissuade the Nigerian government from implementing the death sentences which were subsequently handed down. The second example concerns Shell’s plans to dispose of the Brent Spar oil rig in the North Sea, and their televised confrontations with Greenpeace protestors who tried to halt the operation. Dunfee and Donldson argue that ‘Shell’s travails were ethical in nature, and harmful to its standing in both the business world and the eyes of the public’ (Donaldson & Dunfee, 1999, p. 2). Shell, it thus appears, had contravened rules established in the common ethical beliefs of the business world, but why is this important? According to Dunfee and Donaldson, to understand both the nature of these beliefs and their substance requires ‘a different approach to business ethics, an approach that exposes the hidden but all-important understandings or “contracts” that bind industries, companies and economic systems into moral communities. It is in these economic communities, and in the implicit understandings that provide their ethical glue, that the stuff of business ethics is found’ (Donaldson & Dunfee, 1999, p. 3). The disagreement that these examples illustrate is twofold: on the one hand, it illustrates a disagreement over time, where the Brent Spar episode ‘forced Shell... to recognise that Europeans had shifted their ethical attitudes towards the environment’ (Donaldson & Dunfee, 1999, p. 5). On the other hand it illustrates disagreement between contemporary communities since Shell was also forced ‘to recognise that some countries, Nigeria for example, had distinctly non-European ethical expectations for companies’ (ibid.). It is here that Dunfee and Donaldson give us an idea of how they plan to deal with such disagreements; they say: ‘Our approach confirms that the social contracts that arise from specific cultural and geographic contexts have legitimacy – but only within limits [...] The social contract approach that we will adopt holds that any social contract existing outside these boundaries must be deemed an illegitimate one. In this sense, all particular or “microsocial” contracts, whether they exist at the national, industry, or corporate level, must conform to a hypothetical “macrosocial” contract that lays down objective moral boundaries for any social contracting.’ (Donaldson & Dunfee, 1999, p. 6) This approach in itself, however, gestures towards another significant locus of disagreement in issues of business ethics. Whereas the examples above illustrate substantive differences between 4 It is interesting to think about these conditions of disagreement in the context of Wempe’s fourth criterion that I will outline later, that of ‘domain-specificity’. 2 community norms both over time and between contemporaneous communities, this new disagreement is methodological5. In fact, it is this methodological disagreement that Dunfee and Donaldson identify as being at the root of the problems that have hindered progress in the field of business ethics. They characterise it as follows: ‘One group of researchers approaches business ethics through empirical or behavioural ideas, i.e., through concepts that describe and explain factual states of affairs, such as managerial motivation, organisational accountability structures, and relationships between ethical behaviour and financial performance. In other words, this camp focuses on the “is” of economic affairs. The other camp focuses on normative concepts, i.e., ideas that, while not necessarily grounded in existing business practices and structures, are what ethicists call “prescriptive.”’ (Donaldson & Dunfee, 1999, p. 9) What Dunfee and Donaldson are ultimately interested in is a normative theory of business ethics, but while they refer to the two approaches that they have characterised as the ‘empirical’ and ‘normative’ approaches respectively, they do not side exclusively with the normative side of the disagreement. In fact, they do not look to solve this disagreement by demonstrating the superiority of one of the approaches over the other, but rather to reconcile the two; this is due to the fact that, considered purely from a normative point of view, approaches from both the empirical and normative traditions have their strengths and weaknesses, the weakness of one being the strength of the other. The weakness of the empirical approach they deal with quickly, referencing Moore by saying that ‘*t+o suppose that one can deduce an “ought” from an “is,” or, what amounts to the same thing, that one can deduce a normative ethical conclusion from empirical research, is to commit a logical mistake some dub the “naturalistic fallacy”’ (Donaldson & Dunfee, 1999, p. 9). Normative approaches do not make this mistake, since they draw upon specifically normative evidence and arguments. However, and significantly, Dunfee and Donaldson argue that they face their own particular problem. By ‘normative approaches’ they specify that they have in mind ‘the pivotal traditions of ethical theory – in other words, [...] the broad normative theories of consequentialism, virtue ethics, Kantian deontology, and pragmatism’ (Donaldson & Dunfee, 1999, p. 12) and they argue that ‘the difficulty of such approaches lies largely in their imprecision’ (Donaldson & Dunfee, 1999, p. 13). In essence, the basis of this argument runs back to the substantive disagreements that they discussed earlier. Their assertion is that, although any substantive ethical judgment must be normatively justified in order to be legitimate, the kinds of disagreements that we find regarding substantive ethical judgments in business are ones that are not capable of being resolved by traditional ethical theories. They are not capable of saying, of conflicting judgments, that one and only one is legitimate: they either appear to legitimise both judgments, or appear unable to reach a firm conclusion on either. While this is a general problem with normative ethical theory, Dunfee and Donaldson argue that it is particularly acute within the business environment, for the reason that ‘the world of business *...] is inescapably “artifactual,” or, in other words, inescapably dependent upon convention and agreement for its shape and character *...+ This “artifactual” character of business means that the rules and structure of business can vary dramatically from culture to culture, from industry to industry, and from company to company’ (Donaldson & Dunfee, 1999, p. 14)6. In other words, they 5 Moreover, as a methodological disagreement, it exists not amongst communities that form part of society, but rather amongst students of business, both academic and in the practicing community 6 This feature is another we might add to the list of those characteristic of the business environment 3 seem to be suggesting that the range of substantive judgments over which traditional normative theory will not be able to resolve conflict is greater in business situations, simply because the cultural environments in which each judgment is embedded are both complex and relevant to the legitimacy of those judgments. They provide two examples of such conflicting judgments: ‘[s]ome cultures emphasise property-rights dimensions of intellectual property, while others emphasise cooperative behaviour and societal sharing of innovations. Some tightly constrain the use of firmderived (inside) information in securities markets, while others show considerable indifference to the phenomenon’ (Donaldson & Dunfee, 1999, p. 16). The idea is that, in order to judge any action relating to intellectual property or insider information ethical or unethical, reference must be made to local customs. Without such reference, traditional normative theories are blind. It is the normative validity of arguments in the normative tradition, and the focus necessary to make substantive judgments in diverse business situations, drawn from the empirical tradition, that Dunfee and Donaldson seek to integrate. Thus, they aim to manage disagreement at the level of substantive ethical judgment by reconciling disagreement at the level of methodology. Exactly how they propose this is done I will consider next. However, first I can make the point that I believe is central to finding a way forward with the ISCT project: most commentators have taken the practical, and theoretical, aim of ISCT to be the use of the macro contract to manage disagreement at the level of substantive ethical judgment by providing the tools to adjudicate between competing judgments. For example, Wempe says: ‘*t+he principal ambition of ISCT is to seek to adjudicate possible conflicts between microsocial contracts originating from different economic communities by means of identifying universal, more fundamental principals called hypernorms’ (Wempe, 2007). It is not false that ISCT aims to do this. However, before it can justify such an aim, it must first establish a more fundamental principle, and this is the normative legitimacy of the reconciliation of the broad normative perspective (represented by the macro contract) with the community-specific agreements (embodied in the micro contracts) that are empirically identified. In other words, it must establish the normative legitimacy of the micro contracts themselves, and it is this task that is the primary objective of the macro contract7. That the macro contract then establishes principles in order to adjudicate between conflicting micro contracts is only its secondary role; without any reason to give such micro contracts normative weight in the first place, adjudicating between them is pointless. This claim is supported by Dunfee when he outlines how ethical obligations are justified under ISCT. He and Donaldson, he says, ‘envision that the initial contractors will recognise the ability of communities to generate binding ethical norms for their members in what is described as moral free space’ (Dunfee, 2006). This will be the starting point in my argument for a rehabilitation of the ISCT framework; first it will be necessary to give an overview of how the contract model is supposed to justify the normative legitimacy of community agreements, and Wempe’s criticism of this method. The ISCT Method 7 While it may be thought that local community agreements have normative weight independent of any macro contract, it is the strength of the claim that ISCT makes regarding their significance in determining normative conclusions that requires additional justification. I will explain later what this claim is and why it is so strong. 4 Dunfee and Donaldson start the exposition of their method by considering the contractors who will be party to the macro agreement. They outline the features that these contractors will have: they are rational and knowledgeable and they are not as ignorant as Rawlsian contractors, with the only facts hidden from them being their membership of economic communities, and their level of personal wealth; Dunfee and Donaldson imagine all qualifying representatives of humanity as being party to the contract. Importantly, each contractor brings with them moral principles that they hold prior to the contracting process. Dunfee and Donaldson characterise these as ‘settled understandings of deep moral values’ and identify them with the ‘hypernorms’ that will be central to their exposition (Donaldson & Dunfee, 1999, p. 27). It may seem strange to think of an array of contractors with settled moral positions getting together in order to agree on an approach to morality. Dunfee and Donaldson explain this by saying: ‘Because the contractors are unaware of other economic preferences and memberships, they lack detailed knowledge of their economic morality. Yet even though they lack such detailed knowledge, they know the basic values to which they subscribe. Some may profess philosophical utilitarianism. Some may profess philosophical Kantianism. Others may adhere to ethical principles articulated in their preferred religion [...] And some may subscribe to the specific principles that have been handed down to them historically through their family, their village, or their culture’ (Donaldson & Dunfee, 1999, p. 27) Moreover, Dunfee and Donaldson specifically acknowledge that the contractors will conclude that ‘it would be impossible to obtain an intellectual consensus concerning adoption of a single morality as the framework for global economic ethics...’ (ibid.). This, then, is almost a complete picture of the contracting situation from which a system of economic ethics is supposed to be derived. However, they do add two further assumptions: the first is that ‘many’ of the contractors ‘are driven by an innate moral sense which leads them to recognise elements of a foundational morality’ (ibid.); the second is that, given we are interested in economic ethics, there will be certain things of particular concern to the contractors, in particular they will recognise the importance of a framework of morality in order to avoid something akin to a Hobbesian state of nature in the realm of economic interactions. Following these two assumptions, Dunfee and Donaldson assert that their rational contractors would accept three core assumptions as they go about the contracting process, the implication being that these follow from the characterisation of the contractors that they have stipulated. These assumptions are as follows (Donaldson & Dunfee, 1999, p. 28): 1. All humans are constrained by bounded moral rationality 2. The nature of ethical behaviour in economics systems and communities helps determine the quality and efficiency of economic interactions. Higher-quality and more efficient economic interactions are preferable to lower-quality and less efficient economic interactions 3. Ceteris paribus, economic activity that is consistent with the cultural, philosophical, or religious attitudes of economic actors is preferable to economic activity that is not This first assumption is particularly important, and consists itself of at least four elements: firstly, that all humans encounter difficulties in processing and interpreting ethical data; secondly, they possess limited resources for gathering information to make moral decisions; thirdly, that they have a limited ability to construct moral theories that account for commonsense moral convictions and preferences; and finally that ‘one *cannot+ know in advance what the correct rules of business ethics 5 are for a specific system without having detailed information about the system and its participants’ (Donaldson & Dunfee, 1999, p. 32). It is in the establishment of the initial contractual situation that most fault can be found with the ISCT method. Not only must it persuade us that contractors who find themselves in that situation will agree to the particular terms set out by the theorist, but it itself must be justifiable by some external method. On the first point, I will argue that the contractors, as characterised, will not accept the assumption of bounded moral rationality, and so the argument will not get off the ground; the second point I will come back to when I consider Wempe’s objections. He points out that in successful applications of contract theories the initial contractual situation has been justified as modelling some desirable state of affairs, and it is that state of affairs which gives the contractors’ deliberations normative weight: in the case of theories of political authority it has modelled equality before the law, while in theories of social justice it has modelled a situation where all have equal basic liberties (Wempe, 2007). It is unclear what situation the ISCT contractual set-up is intended to model. Before coming back to this, I will outline the actual contracting process that Dunfee and Donaldson describe, and the terms of the contract that they assert will be established. They reemphasise the point they made earlier, that, given the contracting situation they have established, it will not be possible to establish agreement on a ‘thick’ morality that will determine the rules of ethical behaviour in all situations. In addition, they remind us that contractors will know that moral rationality is bounded, and emphasise that two of their core motivations will be ‘(1) to enhance efficiency by reducing uncertainty, and (2) to live in an economic environment compatible with their underlying cultural, ideological and religious interpretations’ (Donaldson & Dunfee, 1999, p. 37) 8. This said, they derive the following four terms of the macrosocial contract: 1. Local economic communities have moral free space in which they may generate ethical norms for their members through microsocial contracts 2. Norm-generating microsocial constracts must be grounded in consent, buttressed by the rights of individual members to exercise voice and exit 3. In order to become obligatory (legitimate), a microsocial contract norm must be compatible with hypernorms 4. In cases of conflicts among norms satisfying macrosocial contract terms 1-3, priority must be established through the application of rules consistent with the spirit and letter of the macrosocial contract Having set this out, it is worth returning to my earlier assertion that the primary aim of the macrosocial contract in ISCT is not to adjudicate between competing microsocial contracts, but rather to establish their normative legitimacy in the first place. This claim is reinforced by noticing that the first three terms of the contract deal precisely with this aim, while only the fourth concerns competing norms. While the notion of a microsocial contract as it is being used here is somewhat loose, it is not hard to specify more concrete examples of interactions that would fall under the heading: written contracts, for example, or explicit promises. More abstract notions of obligation8 The contractors’ inability to agree on a ‘thick’ morality is clearly at odds with their desire to reduce uncertainty, although not implausible given how they are characterised. When considering the plausibility of this characterisation, however, it is interesting to note how the basic picture of contractor motivation is somewhat unclear, compared with those found in the work of, for example, Hobbes and Rawls. 6 generating relations of the kind often supposed to generate ‘political’ obligations might well also fall under this heading. What all these relations have in common, particularly in the first two cases, is that it is uncontroversial that they generate moral obligations. If demonstrating this were the only aim of ISCT, then it would be a rather trivial theory. However, the aim of ISCT is significantly more substantial than this and the first term of the macrosocial contract is particularly important since it serves to make clear the strength of the claim that is being made: it is not just that microsocial contracts are prima facie normatively significant, but that they are so all told. That is, if a microsocial contract is legitimate, then it is not just one consideration amongst many that we must take into account in our moral reasoning, but rather it is the last word in moral matters for members of that community. In fact, the only time a legitimate microsocial contract might not be authoritative in this way is when it clashes with another legitimate microsocial contract. At the centre of this characterisation of the normative supremacy of the legitimate microsocial contract is the notion of ‘moral free space’, which appears in the first term of the contract, and ‘implies that communities will have significant leeway in the manner in which they choose to generate their own moral rules’ (Donaldson & Dunfee, 1999, p. 38). This leeway is not absolute, however, and is dependent on the support of the clear majority of the community and the ability of individual members who do not support particular rules to voice their dissent or exit the community (embodied in the second term of the contract). A rule that has the support of the majority of a community is called an ‘authentic’ norm, but an authentic norm is not yet ‘legitimate’; in order to be legitimate it must also be compatible with ‘hypernorms’, universal principles which demarcate the bounds of moral free space. It is in these concepts of hypernorms and moral free space that we see the reconciliation between the empirical and normative methodological approaches to business ethics that were discussed earlier. Moral free space gives explicit license to local communities to determine normatively significant moral rules for themselves, and so empirical study of actual ethical behaviour is shown to have normative weight. On the other hand, the existence of hypernorms acknowledges the need for community agreements to be held to certain standards in order to be able to claim normative legitimacy. By bounding the realm of moral free space, hypernorms provide this legitimacy in the tradition of broad and universal ethical theory. This established, it remains to identify which hypernorms exist. Dunfee and Donaldson divide them into three categories, which they call ‘procedural’, ‘structural’ and ‘substantive’9: procedural hypernorms are those that flow from the second term of the macrosocial contract, those required to ensure consent and the rights of voice and exit; structural hypernorms are those ‘that are necessary for political and social organisation’ (Donaldson & Dunfee, 1999, p. 51). The example of structural hypernorms provided by Dunfee and Donaldson is one that ‘obliges members of society to honour institutions that promote justice and economic welfare’ (ibid.) and thus supports the right to property. The final category of hypernorms, the ‘substantive’ one, is more problematic and has been the subject of much debate and criticism of the ISCT method. These hypernorms ‘specify fundamental conceptions of the right and the good’, and unlike the first two kinds are neither specified nor implicit in the terms of the macrosocial contract. All that the macrosocial contract has to say about them is that they do, in fact, exist and Dunfee and Donaldson consider that this is enough for ‘decision makers’ to be going on with, 9 It is worth noting that a presumption of any contract theory approach must be that some hypernorm exists to the effect that contracts are morally binding on the contractors (when undertaken under appropriate conditions), although Dunfee and Donaldson do not explicitly identify such a hypernorm in any of their three categories. 7 allowing them to commence their search for such norms. Criticism of this approach to substantive hypernorms has taken two opposing lines; most has focused upon Dunfee and Donaldson’s refusal to produce a list of substantive hypernorms that may be applied to practical decision making situations. Dunfee and Donaldson justify this refusal by arguing that moral concepts and linguistic terms are culturally specific, even if they do point to universal hypernorms, so any single list using certain concepts and terms would be misleading (Donaldson & Dunfee, 1999, p. 55). Wempe, although largely critical of ISCT, agrees with them on the substance, if not the justification, of this point, arguing that any application of the contract model must be ‘self-disciplined’, or in other words it must only attempt tasks for which it is fit for purpose, and that it is unrealistic to expect it to generate concrete substantive hypernorms (Wempe, 2007). Wempe’s criticism of the account of these norms, on the other hand, focuses on the method that Dunfee and Donaldson do propose for their identification, which appears to boil down to little more than an appeal to common sense. While it is unrealistic to expect the contract model to provide us with a list of substantive norms, a purported contract-based approach that claims that these norms are entirely independent of the supposed contract seems somewhat superfluous. Wempe’s suggestion is that a middle ground can be struck, with the contract model establishing ‘mid-level bridging principles’ (ibid.), although it is not entirely clear what these may look like. Wempe’s Criticism of ISCT I have already mentioned a number of the criticisms that Wempe levels at the ISCT model in the previous two sections, but it is worth pulling these together and summarising the overall structure of his argument, since this structure will be useful for framing the ways in which I will argue that ISCT may be taken forward coherently. Wempe’s criticism is based upon a comparative analysis of two uses to which the contract model has been put successfully in the past, the establishment of conditions for a legitimate use of political authority, and the formulation of principles of social justice. This analysis leads him to identify four main points of comparison for social contract theories, each of which can be broken down in some more detail. The ‘external logic’ of a theory is composed of two parts: first is a determination of who is to be a ‘party’ to the contract, although this appears to be more a nominal description of such parties as ‘citizens’ or ‘representatives of free and equal citizens’, than a detailed characterisation of what it is to be such a person. That additional detail comes later. The second part plays a greater role in Wempe’s analysis, and is the ‘theoretical aim’ of the theory. This is important since, as he argues later, only certain types of theoretical aim are suited to the social contract approach. The second point of comparison between theories is their ‘internal logic’. This again has two parts: the first is the problem to be addressed, which Wempe terms the ‘problem solution frame’, the idea being that in solving this problem, the theoretical aim of the theory will be achieved. For example, by solving the problem of ‘reconciling order with individual freedom’ Rousseau hoped to achieve the aim of legitimising political authority. The second aspect of the internal logic of a theory is the ‘function of the initial contract situation’; as Wempe says, however, this concerns more than just a statement of desired function: it also concerns how the contractual situation will be modelled to achieve this function. Part of this modelling will be the detailed characterisation of the parties to the contract. In reality, the contractual situation must be modelled with two functions in mind, the first is to persuade us that the contractors, as depicted, will arrive at the appropriate conclusions, the second in to convince us 8 that this contracting situation is independently justified. If it is not, then it is not clear why we should care about the conclusions that the contractors reach. For example, in the case of Rawls’ theory we care about the conclusions that his contractors reach since they are all free and equal and possess no knowledge that might lead them to judge unfairly. The third point of comparison Wempe calls ‘domain characteristics’. These we may think of as equating, in Rawls’ theory, to his ‘circumstances of justice’ that characterise the background conditions against which all questions of social justice are asked. As well as general background conditions, Wempe explicitly includes the nature of the ‘target group’ under the heading of domain characteristics, whether this is ‘natural’ in the case of theories of political authority, or ‘fixed’ in the case of Rawls’ characterisation of a closed society. The final point of comparison, Wempe terms the ‘theoretical assumptions’ which deal with the assumptions made regarding the possibilities of access to and exit from the contracting group, and the nature or existence of an authority governing that group. Having set out these points of comparison, Wempe uses them to derive four key design criteria for any social contract theory, including theories of business ethics, and uses these criteria as points of criticism of ISCT. The first of these criteria is quite a general one that relates to the external logic of the theory, specifically its theoretical aim, that he calls ‘self-disciplinedness’, the idea of which is that no application should try and accomplish more than is reasonable given the nature and the limitations of the contract model. In particular, he argues that previous successful applications of this model have been, and the social contract for business should be, ‘restricted to establishing general principles rather than concrete solutions to practical problems’ (Wempe, 2007)10. Thus he suggests that ‘the authors and critics of ISCT may alike be shown to pursue an unrealistic idea of what the contract model can accomplish – indeed an unrealistic idea of applied theories more in general’ (ibid.). As I mentioned earlier, when discussing substantive hypernorms, he particularly has in mind the appeal by critics for Dunfee and Donaldson to endorse a concrete list of such norms; it is less clear why the theory as presented by Dunfee and Donaldson is unrealistic, although with relation to hypernorms it is valid criticism that their determination is divorced entirely from the contractual process: that is, while Dunfee and Donaldson avoid drawing conclusions regarding substantive hypernorms that are too specific, this is at the expense of drawing any conclusions at all. As far as what a valid aim of a social contract model might be, Wempe references ‘classical’ social contract theories that used the contract ‘to specify the conditions of legitimate political authority’ (Wempe, 2007), where this aim is to be distinguished from an attempt to specify any concrete legislation. With regards to the aims of a social contract theory of business, he suggests ‘normativity (and contents?) of corporate morality’, although it is not entirely clear what we should understand by this as an aim. I will come back to this point later. The second critierion that Wempe highlights relates to the internal logic of the theory, specifically the problem solution frame, and he calls this ‘argumentativity’. The essence of this criterion is that the contract model should be used in an argumentative as opposed to purely a stipulative way, so ensuring that it provides ‘genuine added value’ rather than just a useful metaphor for expressing a certain point of view; as Wempe says, ‘the contract must somehow render intelligible why the terms 10 Clearly, general principles should guide solutions to practical problems; nonetheless, this does not mean that the contractors themselves must deliberate on, and pronounce a solution to, each of these problems individually. 9 of the contract deserve to be subscribed by the contractors, and hence why they deserve to be adopted by the audience, which the contract theorist addresses’ (Wempe, 2007). This criterion is fundamental to the success of any social contract theoretical approach, so much so that it seems to be less an independent criterion in itself and more a requirement for the successful coming together of all the other criteria around a well defined problem. I agree with Wempe that the argumentaion of ISCT is less than logically compelling, for reasons that will become clear. However, as I will argue, this is not for the lack of a clear aim or well defined problem. The third criterion Wempe calls ‘task-directedness’, which is also derived from the internal logic of the model, particularly the function of the initial contractual situation, and ‘is based on the observation that, in the more successful examples of the use of the social contract model, theorists always appear to work on the basis of a fairly precise task the contract is supposed to fulfil’ (Wempe, 2007). This criterion appears to have two key parts: first the identification of a suitable task, and secondly the successful and focused direction of the argument to address that task. In his discussion of task-directedness Wempe focuses on the first part, arguing that ISCT presents an obvious candidate for the task at hand: the resolution of conflicting microsocial norms. This, however, is not a suitable task since ‘the problem of “conflicting norms” cannot be solved in general’ (ibid.); in other words, if this general aim is to be addressed satisfactorily by contractors, then it must be specified in terms of more clearly defined problems for which contractors could reasonably be expected to find solutions. He goes on to suggest what a more suitable task might be, proposing the determination of which parties must be considered legitimate discussion partners in the establishment of microsocial norms, and the determination of reasonable shares in the product of business. These suggestions are interesting, but it appears that they would fit in better with his earlier discussions, those relating to the theoretical aim of the theory and the problem that must be solved to achieve this aim. What would be most useful to consider under this heading is the second part of the criterion that relates to the focusing of the proposed theory on the task that this external logic dictates, but this is not something that Wempe spends time discussing. It would seem reasonable to expect that any effort to achieve such focus would concentrate on the modelling of the contractual situation itself, especially the features and situations of the contractors themselves. This is a particularly important task to highlight with respect to ISCT since it is on this front that it falls down most clearly; the initial contractual situation neither relating explicitly to a central aim, nor being itself justified with regards to some desirable state of affairs that it is intended to model. It is this task that I will focus on most specifically later. The fourth and final criterion that Wempe discusses he calls ‘domain specificity’. This is derived from his comparison of the domain characteristics that are modelled by successful applications of social contract theory, and ‘concerns the fact that the contract model needs to be properly adapted to the domain to which it is applied’ (Wempe, 2007). The domains in which the classical theories that aimed at establishing legitimate political authority were set were, he argues, relatively minimalist since their sole role was to establish the undesirability of the state of nature. Modern theories of social justice, however, have employed more detailed characterisations of the domains in which they are set, since the domains themselves have had to play a more significant role in the argumentation of the theory. Both ‘domain specificity’ and ‘task directedness’ deal with the characterisation of the initial contracting situation, the distinction being that the former addresses more specifically the characteristics of the domain in which the contract is reached, while the latter focuses on the features and situations of the parties to the contract. As far as ISCT’s characterisation 10 of the domain of business ethics is concerned, Wempe argues that it relies too much on that employed by Rawls and does not account sufficiently for the nature of the business enterprise with which we are concerned. What we need is to account for a ‘backdrop of collective action aimed at the creation of added value’ where ‘*t+hese activities presuppose the establishment of an effective political authority to see to it that contractual obligations are honoured and to sanction promises made’ (Wempe, 2007). In addition we must consider, in the same manner as Rawls, what morally irrelevant features we want to exclude from deliberation in the ‘state of individual production’ (ibid.). Rehabilitating ISCT Drawing on Wempe’s framework, and elaborating the points that I made earlier, I will now argue that ISCT goes further to satisfying his criteria for a successful application of social contract theory than he allows. This argument will focus on the claim that ISCT can be interpreted as providing a clear and self-disciplined aim, albeit one that is not explicitly identified by its authors. I will then argue that, starting from this aim, ways in which the other criteria may be satisfied become more clear. At the beginning of this paper I discussed the various forms of disagreement which constitute the background for Dunfee and Donaldson’s theory; these could be summarised into two basic types: substantive disagreements on particular ethical judgments, the root of which can be found in conflicting community norms, and methodological disagreements between those that approach questions of business ethics in the ‘normative’ and ‘empirical’ traditions. It has usually been assumed by critics that, if a central aim of ISCT were to be identified, then it would be to resolve disagreement of the first kind, so determining which of the competing substantive judgments should be endorsed. As I argued earlier, however, such a task already presupposes that we have reason to think that any community-derived norms should be given normative weight. It is important here to remember that this presupposition may be understood in two ways: a weak way and a strong way. The weak way of understanding it is to say that (legitimate) community-derived norms have prima facie normative validity, whereas the strong way is to say that they and they alone determine our appropriate substantive ethical judgements. Provided that the process for arriving at these norms conforms to certain constraints, the weak assertion is uncontroversial; for example, an analogous assertion would be that, if I promise to meet you at midday in a certain place then I have a prima facie obligation to meet you at that place at midday. However, if ISCT were interpreted as being concerned only with prima facie obligations it would not be a very interesting theory, in part because it would not tell us much we do not know already, and in part because it would only present a very partial account of economic morality: it would accept that there is more to economic morality than legitimate community norms, but not tell us anything about what else we should take into account. It is clear from the way that Dunfee and Donaldson discuss the microsocial norms, however, and in particular their characterisation of ‘moral free space’ in which these norms are situated, that they consider such norms to be valid in the strong sense. This makes the claims of ISCT much more interesting, but certainly not uncontroversial: it is, therefore, this claim that microsocial contracts establish ethical norms that determine absolutely ethical requirements in the economic context that lies as the centre of ISCT, and it is its justification that must be ISCT’s central aim. 11 It is this aim that then justifies Dunfee and Donaldson’s attempt to reconcile the disagreement between normative and empirical approaches to business ethics. Any resulting theory must appeal to empirical evidence of the actual microsocial contracts in place in order to determine the norms that they generate; however, it must also establish that these are genuine norms in the tradition of normative theory. This reconciliation, then, is the problem that the contract method that they employ is designed to solve; by solving this problem through a discussion of the hypernorms that circumscribe it, and the elucidation of what counts as an ‘authentic’ community norm they aim to legitimise the notion of ‘moral free space’. This aim, much more than the secondary one of adjudicating between competing community norms, conforms to the criterion of ‘selfdisciplinedness’ that Wempe sets out. It is a ‘general principle’ as opposed to a ‘concrete solution to practical problems’ and as such conforms much more closely to the kind of conclusion that a group of contractors might agree upon. This can be seen by comparing it to the aims that Wempe identifies as being pursued by his two comparative theories; if we say that the aim of ISCT is to establish the legitimacy of moral free space, this is much more in line with the aim of classical social contract theories to establish the legitimacy of political authority, and with that of theories of social justice which is to establish the legitimacy of a basic structure. It is certainly the case that this is not the only aim of ISCT, and the more often discussed goal of arbitrating between competing community norms also plays a part in the theory. However, this is very much a secondary aim, and moreover, it is not altogether clear that it is an unreasonable one. Granted, if it is interpreted as requiring the identification of specific community norms and judging the relative merits of each against the others, then the criticism is warranted; but insofar as it is interpreted as establishing general or middle level principles that will be used in such arbitration, then it does not need to stray into the realm of ‘concrete solutions’. My primary conclusion, then, can be summarised as follows: that the theoretical aim of ISCT is self-disciplined in the sense that Wempe requires, and this aim is to establish the legitimacy of moral free space in economic ethics, the space in which legitimate community moral norms are the absolute arbiters of ethical judgements. I believe that once we understand the theoretical aim of ISCT in this way it will become much easier to satisfy the other design criteria that Wempe identifies for a satisfactory social contract theory of business ethics. I am not going to attempt to propose such a theory, since that would be impossible in the space available. However, I will draw on some of the comments already made to suggest what it might look like, and where we may look for further inspiration. Wempe’s second criterion is ‘argumentativity’ which, as I have said, does not in itself appear to be a criterion independent of the other three. Rather, it is more a coming together of the whole theory to address a well defined problem, the solution of which will achieve the theory’s aim. In this respect, a suitable problem has already been identified: if the aim is to legitimise the notion of moral free space, the problem is to reconcile the method of universal moral theories that establish normative authority with the method of empirical investigation which identifies community-determined norms. It is in addressing this problem that ISCT appears to fall down, and the ways in which it does can be seen by considering the final two criteria, those of task-directedness and domain specificity. The rest of my comments in this paper will be focused on the first of these. Task-directedness, as I argued earlier, is best understood as focusing on the contractors, their characteristics and initial situation prior to contract. This specification must do two things. First, it must lead us to the conclusion that such contractors would agree to a contract that endorses moral free space as a realm of action in which empirically determined microsocial contracts have authority, subject to the constraints of 12 hypernorms. Secondly, it must convince us that specifying contractors in such a way that they reach this conclusion is in some way independently justified, thus giving us a reason to accept their conclusions and likewise endorse the notion of moral free space. If we can endorse the Rawlsian contracting situation as appropriate because it models a situation in which all have equal basic liberties, what is it that the contracting situation in the business context models that makes us willing to endorse its conclusions? ISCT, as it stands, does not appear to be able to provide adequate justification in these two respects. There is more than a suspicion that the specification of the contracting situation is conducted entirely with the first aim in mind, with little thought as to the second; in other words the contractors and their features have been selected with the aim of making it plausible that they will agree to the existence of moral free space, but not with consideration as to why we should be interested in such an agreement. Moreover, it is also doubtful that such contractors would agree to a contract that endorsed moral free space. It is here that doubt can be cast on the notion of ‘bounded moral rationality’, the contents of which I outlined earlier. This notion is supposed to be legitimised since it will be accepted as a starting assumption by all contractors. Each contractor is assumed to arrive already in possession of moral principles, drawn from across the spectrum of possible moral positions. Many of these positions will be incompatible with the notion of moral free space: why should the act utilitarian, who already has a definite normative position regarding any substantive ethical judgment, endorse an agreement which allows communities to determine their own norms, many of which will be in opposition his? The answer to this, presumably, is that he has accepted the assumption of bounded moral rationality. However, despite Dunfee and Donaldson providing reasons why we may want to adopt this assumption, it does not seem unreasonable for the act utilitarian simply to decline from adopting it for the very reason that he adheres to act utilitarianism. If the assumption of bounded moral rationality does not hold, then the contractors will not agree to accept moral free space and the most that we may hope from the contracting situation established in ISCT is that all parties will agree that microsocial contracts are prima facie normatively significant. Each contractor will have their own explanation for why this is the case, and the contract model itself is providing nothing beyond a statement of rather trivial agreement. In addition to this point, two final problems with the argumentativity of the initial contractual situation remain to be mentioned: the first is that the establishment of substantive hypernorms is left outside the contractual mechanism. However, if the aim is to legitimise moral free space by reconciling the normative and empirical view points, then to leave the determination of a substantial part of the normative apparatus entirely outside the contractual frame would appear to doom the approach to at best a partial solution, at worst an incoherent one. The second regards motivation. Whereas theories of political authority tend to assume self-interested contractors, and theories of social justice a more Kantian motivation of providing public justification of actions to those whose moral status demands it, a clear characterisation of the motivations of contractors is lacking in ISCT. Conclusions and Future Research Having reviewed the ISCT project of Dunfee and Donaldson, and the criticism made of it by Wempe by way of a comparative analysis with other applications of social contract theory, I have used the framework that Wempe establishes to argue that ISCT, as it stands, can be seen to satisfy at least 13 one of the criteria for a successful social contract theory of business. This criterion, in one sense, is the most important since it requires the establishment of a clear aim that is ‘self-disciplined’ in the appropriate way. For ISCT this is to establish the legitimacy of moral free space in economic ethics. Moreover, ISCT highlights a particular problem, the solution of which promises to achieve this aim: how to reconcile the method of universal moral theories that establish normative authority with the method of empirical investigation which identifies community-determined norms. The identification of this aim, and method of achieving it, goes a long way to re-establishing the ISCT framework as one of the leading contenders in the race to establish a generally coherent theory of business ethics. However, much work remains to be done before such a theory can emerge and, using Wempe’s framework, I have tried to highlight exactly where that work must be done, in particular in the modelling of the contractors that will be party to the macro contract. This specification must conform to two criteria: it must contribute to the argument that makes it compelling that we should reconcile normative and empirical methods in a way that legitimises moral free space; and it must be independently justifiable, both as a plausible characterisation of human nature, and as modelling particularly its features that are relevant to the task of determining a theory of economic ethics. In closing I would like to suggest one place that future research may look in order to help resolve these issues with ISCT, and this is Rawls’ account of a ‘political’ conception of justice in his Political Liberalism (Rawls, 1993). Dunfee and Donaldson, it would appear, draw heavily on this account in their construction of ISCT; at least their theory bears many similarities to that of Rawls. Two of these similarities especially warrant further attention. Firstly, the parties in both theories come armed with their own, disparate, ‘comprehensive doctrines’ drawn from philosophical, religious and cultural sources. Secondly, both theories involve the construction of a ‘thin’ universal moral framework that circumscribes, but does not maximally specify, what counts as moral action in the domain in question: for Rawls these are the fundamental ideas that he finds in the public political culture of a democratic society, for Dunfee and Donaldson these are their ‘hypernorms’. There are distinct differences between the two approaches, however, further exploration of which may go some way to explaining the difficulties faced by ISCT. It is not clear that Rawls understands the scenario that he creates as a contractual situation at all; rather he is interested in identifying those elements of a concept of justice upon which all members of a liberal society will unanimously agree. This is important: identification of areas of unanimous agreement does not require us to understand each party’s motivation for their views, whereas describing a contractual situation does; related to this, unanimity does not require the parties to compromise, whereas agreement on questions where there is no unanimity will. The principles that Rawls derives from his exercise are indeed minimal: citizens should be free and equal and society should be fair; this is particularly the case since he accepts that there will be various acceptable interpretations of these principles. Moreover, Rawls specifies that in searching for these principles on which there will be unanimous agreement he has in mind agreement between reasonable citizens of liberal societies. This specification gives him leeway to assert that such people will accept as legitimate fully specified theories of justice that conform to these basic liberal political criteria, but that differ to their own interpretation. These are all points on which ISCT diverges from the approach taken by Rawls, and thus are potentially valuable areas for future research to address when trying to develop ISCT. I will finish by briefly attempting to show why. Dunfee and Donaldson seem to fall between wanting to use a contractual approach (the macrosocial contract) and appealing to unanimity (substantial hypernorms). Their contractors, however, not only have disparate comprehensive doctrines, but are 14 also not constrained to being either reasonable or liberal (or some appropriate analogy of these). This being the case, it is optimistic to think that they might show substantive unanimity, or be prepared to compromise on those issues dictated by the terms of the contract. The determination of the contractual question is further complicated by the lack of clarity regarding the contractors’ motivations. This issue of compromise is a good one on which to conclude. The prime case for compromise in ISCT is in the acceptance of bounded moral rationality and the legitimisation of moral free space, a move that I have argued is central to the whole ISCT argument. Rawls assumes this kind of compromise when he characterises citizens as reasonable, he does not attempt to derive it from a contract. Whether this is possible, or even desirable, is a question that future work on ISCT must answer satisfactorily if its conclusions are to be compelling. Bibliography Ashford, E., & Mulgan, T. (2008). Contractualism. (E. N. Zalta, Editor) Retrieved August 3, 2009, from The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2008 Edition): http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/contractualism/ Donaldson, T., & Dunfee, T. W. (1999). Ties That Bind. Boston: Harvard Business School Press. Dunfee, T. W. (2006). A Critical Perspective on Integrative Social Contracts Theory: Recurring Criticisms and Next Generation Research Topics. Journal of Business Ethics , 68, 303-328. Rawls, J. (1993). Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press. Wempe, B. (2007). Four Design Criteria for any Future Contractarian Theory of Business Ethics. Journal of Business Ethics , 81, 697-714. Wempe, B. (2005). In Defence of a Self-Disciplined Domain-Specific Social Contract Theory of Business Ethics. Business Ethics Quarterly , 15, 113-135. Wempe, B. (2004). On the Use of the Social Contract Model in Business Ethics. Business Ethics: A European Review , 13, 521-539. 15