Volume 1 - March 2011 VALUE BEYOND DETERMINATION René Le Senne’s Account of Obstacle as Mediation towards the Absolute FR. LORENZ MOISES J. FESTIN, PH.D. ANG PAGTATALABAN NG EROS AT AGAPE AYON KAY BENITO XVI FR. MAXELL LOWELL C. ARANILLA, PH.D. THE FAMILIENÄHNLICHKEITEN OF CONCEPTS Rethinking the Problem of Universals through Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations MARVIN M. CRUZ LOVE AS DUTY A Kierkegaardian Response to the Kantian Critique of the Divine Commandment JEROME C. JAIME “Thus Spoke Zarathustra” on Nihilism JOHN ZERNAN B. LUNA A PHILOSOPHICAL ANALYSIS OF THE NATURE OF DESIRE DANIEL A. DOMINGUEZ Semantics and the Transformational Generative Grammar An Interconnection BRYAN JOSEPH V. RODRIGUEZ STAFF MARVIN M. CRUZ JOHN ZERNAN B. LUNA FRANCIS ROI A. MADARANG BRYAN JOSEPH V. RODRIGUEZ Editors FR. LORENZ MOISES J. FESTIN, PH.D. Moderator Philippine Copyright © 2011 by San Carlos Seminary ISSN 2094-9448 THEORIA, translated as contemplative activity or study, is what Aristotle identifies as the highest operation of man’s intellectual faculty that constitutes the highest form of life. THEORIA is the official journal of the San Carlos Seminary Philosophy Department which aims to gather articles from students, graduates and professors. San Carlos Seminary reserves the rights to all the articles. Mass reproduction and photocopy is highly discouraged without explicit permission from the Editor. Page 3 VALUE BEYOND DETERMINATION René Le Senne’s Account of Obstacle as Mediation towards the Absolute FR. LORENZ MOISES J. FESTIN, PH.D. Atheism today may have the advantage of putting up a robust argument in view of the schematization of the current world order. The success of scientific research and the boost technology receives from it towards an unremitting progress have radically altered the way we live. Wittingly or unwittingly, we have redefined our way of life according to the ever changing state of experimental discipline. With science and technology providing the basic paradigm for human thought, the prevailing proclivity is to disregard anything that cannot be subjected to the rigors of scientific method, consequently eliminating religion and divinity from the list of problems worth addressing in any research or intelligent discussion. Religion and the problem of God have been reduced to cultural realities pertinent to sociology. Because they hardly meet the scientific standard, they are viewed as irrational residues of human thinking. And yet, on the other hand, we cannot also discount the fact that religion very much forms part of the framework of both individual and social life. Billions of people continue to commit what could be regarded as “unscientific” and “irrational” practice of belief and worship. Could this be because they have failed to appreciate the upshot of scientific explorations? Or is this due to the fact that much of humanity has yet to taste the benefits modern technology has generated? It’s true, atheism tends to flourish more in developed countries than in underdeveloped ones. This may suggest that religion and the belief it promotes are nothing but projections of a frustrated consciousness. March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 4 Value Beyond Determination People find themselves helpless and so they turn to something else beyond this world. But why would they have to turn to the beyond? Are they totally clueless as to what science has achieved even if they are hardly beneficiaries thereof? Majority of people today may barely have any access to the latest gadgets available in the market. But they are no strangers as to what these could do. The ubiquity of mass media and the efficiency of information technology not only have propelled people’s insatiable craving for the latest in technology but also have kept them updated about the latest in news and information. So why do people still turn to the beyond? Can they not see that the solution is already in the here and now? That’s precisely what puzzles us today. While the efficacy of science has lent credence to atheistic attitude, much of humanity has remained tied to its religious legacy. In this paper then, I wish to account for this paradox of belief and unbelief, of religion and irreligion, of theism and atheism in the face of what seems to be the irrepressible success of scientific explorations, driven and powered by a mathematical and mechanistic mental framework. For this purpose, I shall be putting forward the ideas of French philosopher René Le Senne, whose estimation of religion and belief seems to well account for such a paradox. 1. Le Senne’s Basic Argument René Le Senne belongs to the Cartesian tradition that emphasizes the centrality of experience. Here Descartes’ Cogito is to be understood not so much as the mere act of thought as the experience itself of the activity of thinking. By focusing on human experience, Le Senne is able to stress both the richness and irreducibility of experience. The richness of experience is inexhaustible in that it cannot be fully encompassed within the categories of human thought. Human thinking itself is an experience, or more accurately a mere part thereof. To contain it in human thought is to do injustice to its boundless wealth. It would be similar to fitting the infinite into the finite. March 2011 - Volume 1 Value Beyond Determination Page 5 Experience is irreducible. It cannot be condensed into a concept or thought. It goes beyond human thinking. And for that, one must acknowledge two possibilities in approaching human experience, both of which are important: one is characterized by fixedness in that experience is understood according to the terms and distinctions of human thinking; the other is marked by openness in that there is an acknowledgment that one’s take on the experience is not sufficient and encompassing. The interplay of these two possibilities is quite paradigmatic all throughout Le Senne’s treatment of human experience. Here one encounters the contrast and complementariness he establishes between pairs, particularly between determination and existence, between obstacle and value, between self and God. In the following, we shall take into consideration each of these pairs. It is hoped that with such an account, we can make sense of the paradox we mentioned a while ago. 2. Determination and Existence René Le Senne sees experience as embodying both determination and existence. By determination is understood the specificity and rigidity of the contents of experience. Here a certain necessity is encountered in that reality appears to be something inflexible and unbending, before which one can only respond in conformity and subjection. Determination appears to work to the advantage of scientific discipline. On account of the fixedness of entities, scientific research can discern patterns that characterize the order of things in reality. With this, science is given the opportunity to develop its technology, allowing it to exploit the possibilities determination offers it. Bacon’s declaration may well give expression to the essence of such a determination, namely, that in order to be able to command nature, one must obey it first. “For nature is only subdued by submission.”1 The pattern which science discovers in the determination of experience is usually expressed in the rigidity of quantitative formulas. March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 6 Value Beyond Determination This brings about the mathematization of the contents of experience, whereby everything has to be quantified in order for them to fit the mathematical schema employed to interpret experience. This process however can be restrictive. For this would marginalize elements of experience which are unquantifiable, such that the result it generates would not quite reflect the wealth that originally describes experience. Surely, scientific procedure involves the process of transcending the given not only by devising formulas that would give a simplified expression to the contents of experience but also by exploiting the advantages that determination occasions. However, the said enterprise remains in the realm of determination. While science makes the determination of things work for the advantage of human society, it also reinforces the mistaken impression that determination is all there is to experience. The schematization of experience is not an original invention of scientific discipline. For quite a significant period of time in the history of the western thought, something similar was taking place in philosophy, namely the rationalization of experience. From the time Parmenides asserted that being and thinkability are the same – to gar auto noein estin te kai einai2 – human experience has always been understood according to the categories of reason Descartes’ philosophy is essentially a critique of the restrictive effect of philosophical schematization. And if this critique could be said of a philosophy that resorts to rationalization, how much more applicable would this be to a more restrictive sort of schematization such as mathematization? This is exactly the point of René Le Senne. While science can aid us in making sense of our experience, it nonetheless leaves out a significant part of its original content, which seems to effectively limit the sphere of truth and human knowledge to what can be quantified and subjected to experiment. “Scientific experience is highly artificial in the conditions which it presupposes and in the goal it proposes. Experience reduced to scientific experience is harshly mutilated experience.”3 March 2011 - Volume 1 Value Beyond Determination Page 7 The restrictive effect of science however can be remedied by turning to the other aspect of experience, namely existence. Le Senne understands existence as that component of experience which pushes us past the determination of reality. Encountering the determinedness of things makes us direct our gaze to the beyond. It enables us to reach further than the limits set by our definition of reality. In other words, the existence component of experience breaches the closed character of our thoughts, leaving it open-ended and gaping as to allow for further modification and unrestricted enrichment. The transcendence that existence brings about, however, is not purely on the level of progress. As pointed out, science makes use of the fixedness of things to improve the lot of people. This it does by coming up with a systematic scheme of reality. But this in itself is restrictive. It leaves the human spirit locked up within the stricture of a systematized pattern. Existence presses further than progress. It propels beyond what can be predicted and expected. It provokes a longing and anticipation directed towards what is still undefined and undetermined. Existence thus consists in the aperture of the human spirit to what rises above it. Le Senne recognizes such an unrestrained movement of the human spirit in the reality of religion. Unlike science which treats experience by schematizing it according to its quantitative system, religion approaches experience in such a way that it takes into account the inexhaustibility and pervasiveness of experience, leading it to turn ultimately to God.4 Surely science may swank about the containment it enjoys over its subject matter. But it has ignored experience for the most part. For even the schematization it creates is an instance of experience itself. This only goes to show that experience is inescapable. It is prior to everything. It serves as the constant precondition of every activity, including what science does. And that’s exactly one basic argument of Cartesianism. “Thus it is especially expedient,” Le Senne argues, “to turn away from the partialness of a scientific empiricism, which subordinates respect for experience to its demands for schematization March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 8 Value Beyond Determination and measurement. Such a partialness ends up by restricting experience to that which can be found in laboratories by means of some apparatus and which is expressed in a mathematical formalism.”5 3. Obstacle and Value The interplay between determination and existence leads to a more particular contrast between obstacle and value. The encounter of determination in experience brings one face to face with the determinedness of reality as an obstacle. Obstacle constitutes a challenge to the spontaneity of the human spirit. It brings into question the actuality of freedom. It oppresses human consciousness, in such a way that one experiences it as an external imposition, constraining one to submit to its necessity. And yet such an encounter with obstacle can be directed towards the prospect of infinity. That is because the very limitation which obstacle presents and represents evokes the ideal of limitlessness. Here one is led to turn towards the reality of value which embodies the very ideal that obstacle lacks and appears to negate. “Value,” Le Senne argues, “is atmospheric. Either gently or violently, it introduces the infinite into the depths of souls. Value is sufficient and goes beyond all the negativity in determination.”6 The contrast between obstacle and value nonetheless must not be taken as consisting in mutual cancellation. For obstacle and value constitute a partnership that flourishes in an interplay. To cancel one readily leads to the nullification of the other. To uphold obstacle to the neglect of value is to lock oneself up within the confines of inevitability and fixedness, while to simply emphasize value without due regard for obstacle amounts to vagueness and imprecision. Values need to be expressed. However, the very attempt at articulation already requires determination, thus constraining value to fit into a defined detention. But this is simply unavoidable. For it is in the nature of human language to express thoughts in distinct manner. Without definition and distinction, human thought would be left in the darkness of ambiguity and elusiveness. March 2011 - Volume 1 Value Beyond Determination Page 9 Obstacle can thus be a vehicle towards the discovery and appreciation of value. For it not only evokes value by being opposite to it. It likewise lends its definiteness to make the articulation of value possible. Such an approach to obstacle enables one to look at it not only as something defined but also as a carrier of value. Le Senne offers concrete examples in this regard. He writes, “The evidence of the obstacle is inseparable from the evidence of value. The first act of the infant chewing with its lips on its mother’s breast and the last act of the drowning man struggling to keep himself afloat manifest an effort not only toward an end but, by means of this end, toward the appropriation of value which is existence itself. The skeptic, who denies value, defends the value of skepticism.”7 In this case, every obstacle would constitute an invitation towards the detection of value. And here even science would be led to discover that beyond the necessity of its schematization there exists a reality that evades every sort of systematization. Indeed, the mere fact that object and method of science are instances of obstacle already suggests that they can point to the ideal which they fall short of. And insofar as they constitute determination, they can likewise give expression to the value they evoke. Le Senne thus avers, “Obstacle was a hindrance which now becomes the objective mediation whereby the self raises itself from inferiority to triumph, from an attitude in which negation prevailed to a free flight in which obstacle no longer intervenes except as a propulsive factor.”8 4. Self and God The interplay of contrasts that we have so far tackled concerns the opposition in the realm of objects. This nonetheless has been occasioned by the intervention of human subjectivity. For it is precisely the dynamicity of the human spirit that distinguishes existence from determination, while the interaction between obstacle and value can be ascribed to involvement of human insightfulness in the latter. Such a distinction of Le Senne, however, presses on in such a way that even within the Cogito an interplay of contrast is established. Here March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 10 Value Beyond Determination Le Senne relates and contrasts the self with God, by speaking of the double Cogito, which consists in the distinction between the self’s weakness and divine infinity. “Subjectively, the content of experience is divided into the I of determination, or the self, and the I of value, or God. ”9 Human being experiences his self as finite. Despite the evasive nature of his experience, human being cannot deny that his self is limited. Still on account of the inexhaustibility of experience, the self recognizes a counterpart which represents the ideal it lacks. Just as the determinedness of obstacle evokes the open-endedness of value, so this time around the self, given its finiteness, is led to acknowledge a self that rises above all forms of definition. Le Senne states, “Manifestly, the self who alleges transcendence supposes thereby his own limitation, and undoubtedly his lowliness. Thus experience must first present to us so that we can recognize the situation and purposes leading the self to allege transcendence.”10 Le Senne’s framework makes the self understandable only in relation to God, in the same manner that the reality of God would not make sense without reference to the self. He writes, “What essentially constitutes the double cogito is that the two existential terms that it opposes and unites, namely, God, whom the self concretely experiences alternately in his will as obstacle and in his grace as value, and the self, which restricts the concrete experience of value by reason of the determinations of its own nature, can only be considered and can only exist by virtue of their connection.”11 Here the risk of ontologism is avoided. What comes to be emphasized is the subjectivity of God instead of his objective existence. Ontologism would want us to concern ourselves with the objectiveness of God’s reality.12 But that would turn God into a static all-embracing perfection, which would either confront human being as an infinite determination – which would already be a contradiction in terms – or drown him into its magnitude and extent, resulting thus in pantheism. Either way, God would be reckoned as a mere force, before which the self would not only remain helpless but also seem not to make sense. March 2011 - Volume 1 Value Beyond Determination Page 11 Le Senne sees God as the principle of value. By discerning value in the obstacles encountered, the self not only transcends determination but also draws closer to the source of transcendence. The detection of value evokes God or the reality of its source. Here the self is led to encounter God as a finite being. But by acknowledging him as the principle of value, one is readily reminded of his infinity. Le Senne thus characterizes God as infinite in himself but finite in his connection with us. What takes place in the God-self rapport is an encounter between the determination characteristic of human situation and value which traces its origin in God. According to Le Senne, both determination and value are important in the said encounter in that determination grounds communication whereas value gives foundation to communion. 5. Conclusion The unrelenting success of scientific research certainly does constitute a unique experience for people today. But as in any other experience, one can either get stuck within the determination which articulates such an experience or one can be led towards the infinity and absolute which value and existence insinuate. Undoubtedly, some have chosen to remain within the framework of science’s quantitative schematization, mesmerized perhaps by the order and efficiency it exhibits. Nonetheless, many have opted to go beyond the scientific account not so much because they doubt its efficacy – they are well aware of the benefits of science! – as because they are convinced that there’s more to our experience than what scientific method allows us to detect. March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 12 Value Beyond Determination Endnotes 1 Francis Bacon, Novum organum, I,3. 4 See Le Senne, p.226. 2 3 5 6 7 8 9 H. Diels, Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker (Berlin 1954), frag. 3, 231, 22. René Le Senne, Obstacle and Value (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1972), pp.25-26. Le Senne, p. 24. Le Senne, pp. 3-4. Le Senne, pp.216-217. Le Senne, p. 222. Le Senne, p.3. 10 Le Senne, p.14. 11 Le Senne, p.192. 12 See Michael Schmaus, Dogma: God and Creation (New York: Sheed and Ward, 1969), p 15. March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 13 ANG PAGTATALABAN NG EROS AT AGAPE AYON KAY BENITO XVI FR. MAXELL LOWELL C. ARANILLA, PH.D. 1. Panimula Sa homiliya ni Robert K. Tschannen-Moran ng United Congregation Church na nailathala sa internet noong unang araw ng Disyembre 1996, isinalaysay niya ang isang kwentong maaaring magbukas sa ating puso’t isipan sa iba’t ibang kahulugan ng pag-ibig. Ganito ang kanyang naging kwento: May isang lalaking nakaupo sa kabilang dulo ng dangan. Kausap niya ang kanyang tatay. Medyo hindi pa nakapag-aahit ang lalaki. Mukha itong balisa. Makikitang tila may mahalaga siyang sasabihin, subalit hindi niya malaman kung paano ito sasabihin. Nangangapa siya ng salita. Balisang-balisa siya at nagiging emosyonal na siya hanggang mangiyakngiyak niyang sinabi ang ‘di-malilimutang linyang iyon: “I love you, man!” (Mahal kita, ‘tay!). Dahil nakakahalata ang kanyang tatay sa totoo niyang dahilan, sumagot ito: “You’re not going to get my Bud Light” (Hindi mo makukuha ang Bud Light ko). Sa puntong ito, ang sawimpalad na binata ay bumaba ng daungan para simulan na naman ang kanyang nauna nang ginawa. Sa pagkakataong ito, sa kanyang kapatid na lalaki (1996:5).. Isang komersyal raw ito sa Estados Unidos. Sa patalastas na ito sa telebisyon, naipapakita ang problema sa pag-unawa sa pag-ibig. March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 14 ANG PAGTATALABAN NG EROS AT AGAPE Ayon kay Tschannen-Moran, sa wikang Ingles, ang salitang “love” ay maraming maaaring paggamitan. At kung minsan, nalilito na rin ang tao sa kung ano nga ba talaga ang kahulugan ng salitang ito at saan ba talaga ito dapat gamitin. Sa pagdaloy ng kasaysayan, ang mga pilosoper at manunulat ay mayroong iba’t ibang tawag sa salitang pag-ibig. Sa katunayan, ang pagibig ay nagkaroon ng iba’t ibang uri o mukha. May mga nagsasabing may apat na uri raw ng pag-ibig. Una, may pag-ibig daw na dumadaloy mula sa Diyos patungo sa tao; ikalawa, may pag-ibig naman daw na dumadaloy mula sa tao patungo sa Diyos; ikatlo, may pag-ibig din daw ng Diyos tungo sa kanyang Sarili; at ang huli’t ikaapat, may pag-ibig daw ng tao sa kapwa-tao (2006:179-181). Sa pilosopiya at sa relihiyon, nagkaroon din ng iba’t ibang tawag ang salitang pag-ibig. Ang apat na mukha raw ng pag-ibig ay ang “Eros,” ang “Philia,” ang “Storge,” at ang “Agape.” (1996:6). Ang una ay ang “Eros.” Ito ang “pag-ibig sa kasiyahan at sarap” (mas palalalimin pa natin ang paglalahad tungkol dito sa mga susunod pa nating pagtalakay). Ang ikalawa ay ang “Agape.” Ito ang “pag-ibig ng Diyos” (tulad ng “Eros,” magkakaroon din ito ng mas malalim na pagtalakay sa susunod na mga paglalahad). Ang ikatlo ay ang “Storge.”Ito ang “pag-ibig ng mga magulang.” Ang “Storge” o pag-ibig sa pagitan ng mga magulang at mga anak ang pangunahing karanasan sa pag-ibig ng sinumang tao. Sa sinapupunan pa lamang ay dama na natin ang pag-ibig ng ating mga magulang; dama na natin ang kanilang pagmamahal sa pagkanlong nila sa atin, sa paghehele ng ating mga nanay, sa pagpapatulog sa atin ng ating mga tatay. Hindi makikita sa Bagong Tipan o sa anumang sinaunang Kristiyanong sulatin ang salitang “storge.” Kung ang salitang “storge” ay isang likas na pagkiling lamang ng magulang sa kanyang anak, masasabi ngang wala itong masyadong kaugnayan sa buhay Kristiyano. Subalit kung ang salitang “storge” ay sumasalamin sa iba’t ibang nibel ng pagmamahal ng mga magulang sa kanilang mga anak, masasabing sinasalamin din ng salitang ito ang pag-ibig ng Diyos sa tao. Ipinakikita nito ang pagkandili ng inahing agila sa kanyang mga inakay na siyang paglalarawang ginamit naman sa Lumang Tipan (1996:6) March 2011 - Volume 1 ANG PAGTATALABAN NG EROS AT AGAPE Page 15 Ang huling mukha ng pag-ibig ay ang “Philia.”Ito ang “pag-ibig ng mga magkakaibigan.” Masasalamin ang salitang “philia” sa Bagong Tipan. Sa isa sa mga pagpapakita ni Jesus sa kanyang mga alagad, matapos ang Muling Pagkabuhay, tinanong ni Jesus si Simon Pedro, “Iniibig mo ba ako?” Ginamit ni Jesus ang salitang agape. “Iniibig mo ba ako tulad ng pag-ibig ko sa iyo?” Sumagot si Simon Pedro na gamit ang salitang philia. Kung titingnan mabuti ang sinabi ni Simon Pedro, ganito ang sinabi niya, “Kaibigan mo ako.” At tumugon si Jesus sa pamamagitan ng isang utos: “Pakainin mo ang aking mga tupa.” Muli, hiniling ni Jesus ang tungkol sa agape, tungkol sa kung gaano siya kamahal ni Pedro, at muli ang tugo ni Pedro ay philia. “Kaibigan mo ako.”“Alagaan mo ang aking mga tupa.”Sa huli, sa ikatlong pagkakataon, subalit sa pagkakataong ito ginamit na niya ang salitang philia, nagtanong si Jesus: “Pedro, kaibigan ba kita?”Ganoon na lamang ang pagkabalisa ni Pedro at sa ikatlong pagkakataon, “Jesus, alam mong kaibigan kita.” Kaya naman, “pakanin mo ang aking mga tupa.” Makikita sa tagpong ito sa Bagong Tipan, na maging sa pakikipagkaibigan kay Jesus kinakailangan ang aktibong pagkalinga sa iba. At ito rin ang katumbas na kahulugan sa karaniwang pagkakaibigan. Ang “Eros,” ang “Philia,” ang “Storge,” at ang “Agape” ang iba’t ibang mukha ng pag-ibig na ipinaliwanag at pinagnilayan ng mga pilosoper sa pagdaloy ng panahon. Subalitsa pagkakataong ito, pagninilayan natin ang dalawa sa mukha ng pag-ibig: ang “Eros” at ang “Agape” sa liwanag ng ensiklikal ni Papa Beniti XVI na Deus Caritas Est. 2. Eros Kapag ang salitang “eros” na ang napag-uusapan, iba’t iba na ang pumapasok sa isip ng tao. Nandiyan ang mga pelikulang erotika; nandiyan ang pagnanasa; nandiyan ang Walang patumanggang seks. At kung anu-ano pa. Ayon sa Banal na Papa, sa ensiklikal na “Deus Caritas Est,” dalawang ulit lamang ginamit ang “eros” sa Griyegong Lumang Tipan samantalang hindi ito ginamit sa Bagong Tipan (Deus Caritas Est, 13). Bago pa ang March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 16 ANG PAGTATALABAN NG EROS AT AGAPE ‘Sang-Kristiyanismo, itinuturing ng mga Griyego ang “eros” bilang pampalango. Inilarawan ito ng Papa sa ganitong paraan: Katulad ng ibang mga kultura, ang pangunahing turing ng mga Griyego sa eros ay isang bagay na nakalalasing; pinangingibabawan ng “banal na kabaliwan” ang pagunawa ng tao, na siya namang naglalayo sa tao mula sa kanyang panandaliang pag-iral na siya namang nagdadala sa kanya na maranasan ang rurok ng kagalakan dahil na rin sa pangingibabaw sa kanya ng kapangyarihang banal. Kaya naman, pangalawa lamang ang lahat ng mga kapangyarihan sa langit at sa lupa: Wika nga ni Virgil sa Bucolics, “Omnia vincit amor” – nagtatagumpay ang pag-ibig sa lahat – at idinagdag pa niya: “et nos cedamus amori” – halinang sumuko na rin tayo sa pag-ibig. Sa mga relihiyon naman, ang gawing ito ay makikita sa mga kulto ng pagkamabunga, bahagi nito ang “sagradong” prostitusyong nagaganap sa maraming mga templo. Kaya naman, ipinagdirwang ang eros bilang banal na kapangyarihan, bilang pakikiisa sa Banal (Deus Caritas Est, 4). Kaya naman masasabing ang “eros” para sa mga Griyego ay lango at walang disiplinang pag-ibig at hindi ito pag-akyat sa “ganap na kaligayahan” patungo sa Banal, kundi pagbulusok pababa, at pag-aalis sa dangal ng tao (Deus Caritas Est, 4). Sa isang banda nga, ang “eros” ay pagtatampisaw sa marumi, sa mga bagay na tila walang kinalaman sa pag-ibig. Ito ay pagkiling sa tawag ng laman at wala nang iba pa. Subalit pata sa mga makabagong manunulat at pilosoper naman, may naiibang pag-unawa rin sa salitang “eros.” Halimbawa na lamang ang ang pag-unawa ng kilalang manunulat na si Marc Gafni. Isa siyang panauhing iskolar ng Oxford University at ng Hartman Institute. Siya rin ang sumulat ng mabentang aklat naSoul Prints at tagapagtatag ng Bayit Chadash, isang pandaigdigang espiritwal na pagkilos na nakabase sa Israel. Sa aklat niyang “The Mystery of Love,” ipinakilala niya ang iba’t ibang mukha ng “Eros.” March 2011 - Volume 1 ANG PAGTATALABAN NG EROS AT AGAPE Page 17 Sabi ni Gafni, ang unang mukha raw ng “eros” ay ang “Kalooban.” Para kay Gafni, ang erotikong pamumuhay ay ang mabuhay mula sa kalooban ng tao. Ito ay ang paglalakbay sa gitna ng kawalan na nagdurugtong sa obheto at ng subheto. Ito ay ang pagiging kaisa ng iyong reyalidad, ang makapasok sa kaloob-looban ng karanasan. Kaya nga, ang erotikong pamumuhay ay ang mabuhay sa kaloob-looban at ang maging banyaga ay ang mabuhay sa labas ng iyong kalooban – ang mabuhay na walang masasabing kanlungan (2004:14-15). Ang ikalawang mukha naman daw ng “eros” ay ang “ganap na presensiya.” Hindi raw hiwalay ang katangiang ito sa unang mukha ng eros. Likas na dumadaloy ito mula sa unang mukha – mula sa kalooban. Subalit iba rin naman ito. Ang binibigyang-diin lamang ay ang katotohanang ang pag-iral mula sa kalooban ay nangangailangan ng ganap na presensiya. Ngunit maaari nating maranasan ang ganap na presensiya kahit na hindi pa tayo nakikiisa sa kalooban. Tungkol sa pagpapakita at pagdating ang ganap na presensiya. (2004:22-23). Sa madaling salita, wika nga ni Gafni, “Ang erotikang pamumuhay ay ang maging ganap ang presensiya sa kasaganaan ng isa’t isa, sa kasalimuutan ng pagkatao ng isa’t isa, at sa likas na karingalan. Ito ay ang hintayin ang ganap na pagdating ng isa” (2004: 24). “Pagnanasa”o pagnanais naman ang ikatlong mukha ng “eros.” Muli sa paliwanag ni Gafni, “Kapag ako ay nasa aking loob, kapag ako ay ganap na naroroon, nararating ko ang ikatlong mukha ng erotikang karanasan – ang pag-asam. Ang pag-asa at pagnanasa ay dalawa sa napakahalagang pagpapadama ng pag-ibig at ng eros. Basta ako ay nasa labas ng aking sarili, maaari kong balewalain ang pinakamalalim kong pagnanasa at pigilin ang aking mga inaasam. Subalit ang pagnanasa ay mahalagang bahagi ng anumang erotiko” (2004: 32). Ipinaliwanag din ni Gafni na kailangang mula sa kalooban ang eros, kasama na ang kaibuturan ng iyong pagnanasa. Ang pagkanasa-loob ay paanyaya sa tao na balikan ang kanyang mga pagnanasa, ngunit hindi ang lagpasan ang mga ito. Nararating ang totoong pagnanasa sa pamamagitan ng malalim na pagninilay na kung saan naaabot mo ang saksi sa kalooblooban. Ito ang lugar na kung saan umiiral ang pagiging hiwalay sa damdamin, na kungb saan iniisa-isa mo nang may pagmamahal ang lahat ng iyong mga pagnanasa…. Ang pagnanasa at pagnanais March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 18 ANG PAGTATALABAN NG EROS AT AGAPE ay mabubuti, hindi dahil lahat ng ating inaasam ay matutupad o magaganap, kundi dahil ang pag-asam ang nagpapaganap sa atin. Ang pag-asam mismo ang pumupuno sa kahungkagan. Kapag nais nating lumago, kapag tayo’y buhay at nagtataglay ng pagnanasa, nararating din natin ang kaganapan” (2004: 33-34). Ang huli’t ikaapat na mukha ng “eros” ayon kay Gafni ay ang “pagkakaugnay-ugnay ng mga pag-iral.” Ipinaaalala sa atin ng ating pagnanasa, pagnanais at mga luha na ang lahat ng umiiral ay magkakarugtong. Walang taong nabubuhay ng nag-iisa lamang. Ang salitang relihiyon nga raw ay nag-uugat sa Lating salita na ligare na may pagkakahawig sa salitang Ingles na “ligament” – at ito ay masasabing tungkol sa pagkaka-ugnay-ugnay. Kaya naman ang adhikain daw ng relihiyon ay ang mapag-ugnay-ugnay ang mga tao. Ang orihinal na intensyon ng relihiyon ay ang madala tayo papasook sa ating kalooban na kung saan mararanasan natin ang pundamental na pagkaka-ugnay ng lahat ng tao at ng lahat ng umiiral (2004: 37). “Binibigyan tayo ng eros ng pagkakataon na iwanan ang damdamin ng pag-iisa at paghiwalay at ang maranasan ang ating sarili bilang bahagi ng sang kwilt. Ang lumayo sa eros ay ang magkasala. Hindi lamang natin maiwawala ang pinadakilang bukal ng kasiyahan, kundi maiwawala pa natin ang mga bagay na pundasyon ng pagkaka-ugnay-ugnay na kung wala ang mga ito sa katapusan ang mundo ay babagsak” (2004: 37). Sa dalawang magkatunggaling pananawa sa eros, maitatanong natin kung ano nga ba ang kahulugan ng eros para sa tao. Dapat nga ba itong talikuran at wala nga ba itong kaugnayan sa salitang “agape”? 3. Agape Subalit bago natin sagutin ang mga katanungan sa itaas, balikan muna natin ang salitang “agape.” Ano nga ba ang “agape”? May mga nagsasabing ang “agape” ay ibang iba sa “eros.” Nagmula ito sa tradisyong Kristiyano. Sinasabing ito ang pag-ibig ng Diyos sa kanyang mga nilikha at ng mga nilikha sa kanilang Lumikha. Gayundin naman, sinasabi ring ang “agape” ay pag-ibig ng tao sa kanyang kapwatao dala ng kanyang pag-ibig sa Diyos. Kusa at walang ibang dahilan March 2011 - Volume 1 ANG PAGTATALABAN NG EROS AT AGAPE Page 19 ang pag-ibig na “agape.” Hindi ito nakabatay sa merito ng tao kundi sa kalikasan ng Diyos bilang pag-ibig (Mind, 86:532-54). Ito nga raw ang kahulugan ng Pasko. Nagkatawang-tao ang Diyos upang ganap na makipamuhay sa tao. Kaya naman sa Bagong Tipan agape ang salitang Griyego na madalas ginagamit kapag pag-ibig ang napag-uusapan. Ito raw ang pag-ibig na naglalarawan sa ating ugnayan sa iba; kapag mas madalas daw tayong magbigay, agape ang ating pag-ibig; kapag madalas na lumalapit sa atin at naghahanap sa atin ang Diyos, ito ay dahil sa kanyang agape (1996:4) Kung paghahambingin ang eros at ang agape,angeros na pag-ibig ay makamundo, samantalang ang agape ay pag-ibig na nag-uugat at hinubog ng pananampalataya. Kung ang eros ay pag-ibig na “pataas,” ang agape ay pag-ibig na “paibaba.” Kung ang eros ay makasariling pag-ibig (amor concupiscentiae), ang agape naman ay mapagbigay na pag-ibig (amor benevolentiae). Tila nga malalim ang pagkakaiba ng eros at ng agape kaya naman maraming pilosoper at mga manunulat ang naniniwalang mahirap pagsamahin at pagdugtungin ang eros at ang agape.Sa sulatin ng Swedish na teologong Luterano na si Anders Nygren (ang Eros and Agape), ipinaliwanag niya na may dalawang uri ng pag-ibig: ang pag-ibig na mapaghanap na tinawag niyang eros at ang pag-ibig na mapagbigay na tinawag niyang agape. Sinabi niya na tanging ang agape lamang ang masasabing tunay na Kristiyanong pag-ibig. Para kay Nygren, tayo ay nahaharap sa malinaw na pagpipilian sa pagitan ng dalawang uri ng pag-ibig; walang posibleng kompromiso at walang sintesis sa pagitan ng eros at ng agape (Dulles. 2006:20). At tulad ni Nygren, ganito rin ang paninindigan ni Denis de Rougement na isang Swisong Protestante. Para sa kanya, ang eros ay may kaugnayan sa mga mahihiwagang relihiyong (mystery religions), kay Plato at sa mga Neo-platonists. Isang itim na pag-ibig ang eros samantalang ang agape ay kumakatawan sa pag-ibig ng Diyos sa mundo na sinisimbolo ng pagiisang dibdib ni Cristo at ng Simbahan. Subalit may pagkakaiba rin ng pag-unawa si De Rougement at Nygren tungkol saeros at sa agape. Para kay De Rougement, ang eros ay isang irasyonal o walang katwirang pag-ibig at pagnanasa na laging hindi nakukuntento sa anumang nasa lupa at panandalian lamang; itinutulak nito ang kanyang maingingibig March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 20 ANG PAGTATALABAN NG EROS AT AGAPE sa ganap na pagsuko ng sarili at pagkuha sa lahat-lahat nito. Ang agape naman para sa kanya ay pagpapatotoo sa mundong ito at pagtanggap sa kahinaan at mga limitasyon ng tao. Samantala, para kay Nygren, ang eros ay isang intelektwal at makasariling anyo ng pag-ibig; at ang agape naman ay ganap na pagbibigay na walang hinihintay na kapalit – isang pag-ibig na mula sa itaas. Kaya nga sa unang tingin, tila kailangang mamili ang isang Kristiyano. Wika nga ni Papa Benito XVI: Sa mga tunggaliang pilosopikal at teyolohikal, madalas na pinalalalim ang pagkakaiba ng mga ito hanggang sa puntong nilalagyan na ito ng malinaw na salungatan sa pagitan nila: ang pababa at mapagparayang/ mapagbigay na pag-ibig – ang agape – ay tipikal na Kristiyano, samantalang ang pataas at makasarili o mapag-imbot na pag-ibig – ang eros – ay tipikal na diKristiyano, at natatangi sa kulturang Griyego (Deus Caritas Est, 7). Ngunit kung tuluyan ngang paghihiwalayin ang eros at ang agape, “kung darating sa sukdulan ang salungatang ito, magiging hiwalay ang diwa ng Kristiyanismo mula sa mga mahahalagang ugnayan na siyang batayan ng pag-iral ng tao at magkakaroon sila ng kanya-kanyang mundo, maaaring kahanga-hanga ito, ngunit ganap namang hiwalay sa masalimuot na kabuuan ng buhay ng tao (Deus Caritas Est, 7). 4. Ang Pag-uugnay Sa unang ensiklikal ni Papa Benito XVI, binanggit niya ang pahayag ni Friedrich Nietzsche: Ayon kay Friedrich Nietzsche, nilason ng Kristiyanismo ang eros, na datapwat sa bahagi nito’y hindi naman ganap na sumusuko, ay unti-unti rin namang naging isang masamang gawi. Dito, sinasabi lamang ng Alemang pilosoper ang tingin ng nakararami: hindi ba, dahil sa dami ng mga utos at bawal, ginawa nang mapait ng Simbahan ang pinakamahalagang bagay sa buhay? Hindi ba’t tila bigla na lamang siyang pumito March 2011 - Volume 1 ANG PAGTATALABAN NG EROS AT AGAPE Page 21 habang tayo’y nasa gitna ng kagalakan na siya namang kaloob ng Lumikha bilang patikim sa Banal? (Deus Caritas Est, 3). Itinanong ni Papa Benito XVI sa kanyang ensiklikal kung totoo nga ba ang sinabing ito ni Nietzsche. Inamin niyang hindi naman ganap na mali ang pilosoper na si Nietzsche. Subalit ipinaliwanag niyang hindi naman talaga hiwalay at salungat ang eros sa agape. Inihihilig tayo ng erosna tanggapin ang mga biyaya ng Diyos; at itinutulak nman tayo ng agape na ipasa sa iba ang ating natanggap. Ang eros ay ang paakyat na sandali sa buhay espiritwal ng isang tao na kung saan hinahanap natin ang Diyos, na siyang pinagmumulan ng bawat ganap na biyaya. Bahagi ng isa’t isa ang eros at ang agape; dalawang bahagi sila ng iisang proseso. Kung wala tayong tinanggap, wala tayong ibibigay; at kung hindi tayo handang magbigay, hindi tayo magiging handang tumanggap (Cardinal Dulles. 2006:21). Sa pahayag ni Papa Benito XVI, kanyang ipinaliwanag ang pagkakaugnay ng eros at ng agape: Subalit hindi maaaring ganap na paghiwalayin ang eros at ang agape – ang pataas na pag-ibig at ang pababang pag-ibig. Kung ang dalawang ito, sa kanilang pagkakaiba, ay makatagpo ng tamang pagkakaisa sa iisang reyalidad ng pag-ibig, mas matutupad naman ang totoong kalikasan ng pag-ibig. Datapwat sa simula’y mapag-imbot at pataas ang eros, ang pagkahalina sa dakilang pangako ng kaligayahan, sa pagkaakit sa isa, unti-unti nitong nakalilimutan ang sarili, habang papalago ang pagnanais niya sa ikasisiya ng isa, habang mas iniisip niya ang minamahal, ibinibigay niya ang kanyang sarili at nais niyang “nandoon siya” para sa isa. Sa gayon, pumapasok ang elemento ng agape sa pag-ibig na ito, dahil kung hindi, nagigingsalat at naiwawala ng eros ang kanya mismong kalikasan. Sa kabilang banda naman, hindi mabubuhay ang tao sa mapagparaya/mapagbigay at pababang pag-ibig lamang. Hindi maaaring bigay lamang siya March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 22 ANG PAGTATALABAN NG EROS AT AGAPE nang bigay; kailangan din niyang tumanggap. Dapat maging handa ang sinumang nais magbigay ng pagibig na tumanggap din ng pag-ibig bilang kaloob. Tama nga, tulad nang sinabi ng Panginoon, ang isang tao ay maaaaring maging daluyan na kung saan bubulwak ang mga ilog ng tubig na buhay (tng. Jn 7:37-38). Subalit upang maging ganoong daluyan, kailangan ng sinuman na laging uminum mula sa orihinal na bukal, na walang iba kundi si Jesu-Kristo mismo, na mula sa kanyang sinibat na puso’y bumukal ang pag-ibig ng Diyos (tng. Jn 19:34) (Deus Caritas Est, 7). Malinaw nga na ang eros at ang agape ay nagtatalaban at hindi totoong magkasalungat. Sa konteksto ng mga paliwanag ni Papa Benito XVI, makikita ang eros at ang agape ay totoong dalawang mukha ng pagibig na hindi magkakaroon ng kaganapan kung wala ang isa’t isa. Sa ensiklikal, malinaw itong ipinahayag: Dalawang bagay ang malinaw na lumalabas mula sa mabilis na pagbabalik-tanaw sa konsepto ng eros sa nakaraan hanggang sa kasalukuyan. Una, mayroong ugnayan sa pagitan ng pag-ibig at ng Banal: pangako ng pag-ibig ang kawalang-hanggan ang kawalangkatapusan – isang reyalidad na higit at ganap na iba sa pang-araw-araw nating pag-iral. Subalit nakita rin natin na ang daan upang marating ang hantungang ito ay hindi sa pamamagitan nang pagpapaubaya sa likas na simbuyo. Kinakailangan nang pagpapadalisay at paglago; at nagdaraan ang mga ito sa daan ng paglimot sa sarili. Malayo sa pagtalikod o “paglason” sa eros, hinihilom at ibinabalik ng mga ito ang totoong karingalan ng eros (Deus Caritas Est, 5). Pagpapadalisay tungo sa tunay at wagas na kahulugan ng eros ang kinakailangan upang magtagpo ang eros at ang agape. Ngunit paano nga ba ito magaganap? Siguro, kailangan munang kilalanin ng tao ang kanyang sarili. Ang tao, March 2011 - Volume 1 ANG PAGTATALABAN NG EROS AT AGAPE Page 23 higit sa anupaman, ay binubuo ng katawan at ng kaluluwa. Totoong tao ang taokapag matalik na nagtatalaban at nagkakaisa ang kanyang katawan at ang kanyang kaluluwa. At ang hamon saeros ay totoong mapagtatagumpayan kung ang pagkakaisang ito ay magagawa. Kung nanaisin lamang ng tao na maging purong espiritu at tanggihan ang kanyang laman, sabay na maiwawala ng espiritu at ng katawan ang kanilang karingalan. At kung tatanggihan naman ng tao ang espiritu at bigyang-pansin lamang ang katawan bilang natatanging reyalidad, mawawala rin ang dangal ng tao. Tanging sa pagtatagpo lamang ng eros at ng agape totoong nararating ng tao ang kanyang karingalan (Deus Caritas Est, 5). Kung babalikan natin si Papa Juan Pablo II, makikita rin natin ang kanyang pagpapahalaga sa katawan bilang kabahagi ng pagpapadama ng pagmamahal sa kapwa. Sa Familiaris Consortio o Apostolikong Panawagan sa Pamilya (1981, 11), sinabi ni Papa Juan II na ang bokasyon ng tao na ibigay ang sarili sa kapwa ay makikita sa pagbibigay ng mag-asawa sa isa’t isa ng kanilang mga sarili at katawan. Sa halimbawang ito ng mag-asawa, makikita natin ang kahulugan ng pagtatalaban ng katawan at ng espiritu ng tao upang ganap na mapagbigay sa iba; at ang pagbibigay na ito ay hindi nangangahulugang sekswal lamang. Wika nga ni Papa Juan Pablo II tungkol sa mga may bokasyon sa pagpapari o buhay relihiyoso, “sa kabila ng pagtalikod nila sa pisikal na pagpaparami, ang mga celibatong tao ay nagiging mabunga sa espiritwal na antas, nagiging ama at ina sila ng marami, nagiging kabahagi sa pagkakaroon ng katuparan ng isang pamilyang ayon sa plano ng Diyos” (1981:16). At dahil ang tao ay nagkatawangdiwa (espiritu), tinatawag ang tao na magmahal sa kanyang kabuuan. Kasama sa pag-ibig ng tao ang kanyang katawan, at nagiging kabahagi ang katawan ng espiritwal na pag-ibig [Familiaris Consortio o Apostolikong Panawagan sa Pamilya (1981:11). Tinutuligsa ang Simbahan dahil sa pagpaparumi raw nito sa eros. Subalit, kung tunay na hahalukayin ang kahulugan ng eros at hindi na ito itutumbas bilang katawan lamang na maaaring “gamitin,” matatagpuan din na ang eros ay tunay na isang mukha ng pag-ibig. Dapat lamang kilalanin ang eros,hindi bilang sekswal na bahagi lamang ng tao, kundi bilang bahagi ng kabuuan ng tao, kabuuan ng kanyang March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 24 ANG PAGTATALABAN NG EROS AT AGAPE malayang pag-iral, kabuuan ng kanyang malayang pagbabahagi ng BUONG SARILI. At ang eros na ito ay nagdadala sa atin tungo sa “lubos na kagalakan” sa Banal; dinadala tayo nito palabas sa ating mga sarili, at inaanyayahan tayo nito sa daan ng pag-akyat, pagtanggi, pagpapadalisay, at paghihilom (Deus Caritas Est, 5). Ngunit ano nga ba ang daan na ito na paakyat at ng pagpapadalisay? Ayon na rin kay Papa Benito XVI: Kumpara sa isang di-tiyak, “naghahanap” na pag-ibig, ipinahahayag ng salitang ito ang isang karanasan ng pag-ibig na totoong nakakikilala sa iniibig; nilalagapasan nito ang pagkamakasarili na namamayani noong una. Ngayon, ang pag-ibig ay naging malasakit at pag-aalala sa iniibig. Hindi na ito mapaghanap, na kung sa nalulunod sa pagkalango sa kaligayang ang isang tao; sa halip, hinahanap nito kung ano ang makabubuti sa minamahal: nililimot na nito ang sarili at handa at bukas-loob itong magsakrpisyo. Bahagi ng paglago ng pag-ibig tungo sa mas mataas na antas at mas dalisay na anyo ang paghahanap ngayon nito ng katiyakan, at nangyayari ito sa dalawang paraan: sa paraang eksklusibo o nagtatangi (ang taong ito lamang) at sa paraang “pangmagpakailanman.” Niyayakap ng pag-ibig ang kabuuan ng pag-iral sa bawat dimensyon nito, kasama na ang dimesnyon ng panahon o oras. Wala nang iba pang paraan, sapagkat nakatanaw ang pangako nito sa isang tiyak na hangarin: nakatutok ang paningin ng pag-ibig sa kawalanghanggan. Totoo ngang ang pag-ibig ay “lubos na kagalakan,” hindi sa kahulugang saglit na pagkalasing, kundi bilang isang paglalakbay, isang nagpapatuloy na exodo palabas sa kakitiran ng pagkamakasarili tungo sa kalayaan na dala ng pag-bibigay ng sarili, na nagbubulid naman sa totoong pagkakilala sa sarili at, tunay nga, sa pagkilala sa Diyos: “Ang sinumang magsikap na magligtas ng sarili ay mawawalan nito, at ang mawawalan naman ng sarili ang magsisilang March 2011 - Volume 1 ANG PAGTATALABAN NG EROS AT AGAPE Page 25 nito sa buhay” (Lc 17:33), tulad na rin nang inuulit-ulit ni Jesus sa mga Ebanghelyo (tng. Mt 10:39; 16:25; Mc 8:35; Lc 9:24; Jn 12:25) (Deus Caritas Est, 6). Hindi nga mapaghihiwalay ang eros at ang agape.Sa halip, ipinaliwanag ni Papa Benito XVI na ang mga magagandang katangian ng eros at agape ay maaaring pagsamahin sa iisang pagpapakita ng pag-ibig ng tao at ng Diyos. At upang magawa ang sintesis na ito, o ang pag-uugnay na ito ng eros at ng agape, kailangang padalisayin nng tao ang eros. Wika nga ni Papa Benito XVI: Una sa lahat, ang “pag-ibig” ay iisang reyalidad, na may iba’t ibang mukha; sa iba’t ibang panahon, maaaring mamayani ang isang mukha kaysa sa iba. Ngunit kung lubos na puputulin ang ugnayan ng isa’t isa, ang bunga nito ay isang karikatura o salat na anyo ng pag-ibig. Sa paglalagom, nakita rin natin na ang biblikal na pananampalataya ay hindi lumikha ng ibang mundo, o ng isang mundong laban sa pangunahing karanasan ng tao na walang iba kundi ang pag-ibig; sa halip, tinatanggap nito ang kabuuan ng tao; nakikisangkot ito sa paghahanap ng tao sa pag-ibig upang padalisayin ito at upang ipahayag ang mga bagong mukha nito. Higit sa anupaman, ipinakikita ang pagiging bago ng biblikal na pananampalatayang ito sa dalawang elemento na dapat bigyang-pansin: ang larawan ng Diyos at ang larawan ng tao. At ang larawang ito ay sabay na makikita kay Jesu-Cristo na totoong Diyos at totoong tao. Sa kanyang pagkakatawang-tao, binigyan niya ng dangal ang katawan ng tao, ang paghahanap ng tao sa anumang makapagpapaligaya sa kanya; ngunit sa kanyang kamatayan sa krus at muling pagkabuhay, binigyang-dangal din ni Jesus ang pagiging kalarawan ng Diyos ang tao – ang taong tulad ng kanyang Lumikha ay maaaring magbigay dahil nakatanggap siya ng lubos na pagmamahal sa isang Diyos na walang hinihintat na kapalit. March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 26 ANG PAGTATALABAN NG EROS AT AGAPE 5. Pangwakas Sa kasaysayan ng mundo, laging pinagtutunggali ang “eros” at ang “agape.” Kung paghahambingin ang eros at ang agape,angeros na pagibig ay makamundo, samantalang ang agape ay pag-ibig na nag-uugat at hinubog ng pananampalataya. Kung ang eros ay pag-ibig na “pataas,” ang agape ay pag-ibig na “paibaba.” Kung ang eros ay makasariling pag-ibig (amor concupiscentiae), ang agape naman ay mapagbigay na pag-ibig (amor benevolentiae). Madalas na sinasabing hindi sapat ang “eros” at kung minsan sinasabi pang masama ang “eros.” Subalit sa maanyong pagtalakay na ito at sa unang ensiklikal ng Banal na Papa, ang Deus Caritas Est, ipinakikita ang ugnayan ng dalawang konseptong ito ng pag-ibig. Ipinaliwanag ni Papa Benito XVI na hindi naman talaga hiwalay at salungat ang eros sa agape. Inihihilig tayo ng erosna tanggapin ang mga biyaya ng Diyos; at itinutulak naman tayo ng agape na ipasa sa iba ang ating natanggap. Ang eros ay ang paakyat na sandali sa buhay espiritwal ng isang tao na kung saan hinahanap natin ang Diyos, na siyang pinagmumulan ng bawat ganap na biyaya. Bahagi ng isa’t isa ang eros at ang agape; dalawang bahagi sila ng iisang proseso. Kung wala tayong tinanggap, wala tayong ibibigay; at kung hindi tayo handang magbigay, hindi tayo magiging handang tumanggap. Ipinaliwanag rin ng Papa na kung ang “eros” at ang “agape,” “sa kanilang pagkakaiba, ay magkatugma sa iisang reyalidad ng pag-ibig, matutupad ang totoong kalikasan ng pag-ibig. Mapag-imbot at pataas ngang pag-ibig ang eros, subalit sa pagkahalina nito sa dakilang pangako ng kaligayahan, sa pagkaakit sa isa, unti-unti nitong nakalilimutan ang sarili, at lumalago naman ang pagnanais niya sa ikasisiya ng isa; mas iniisip na niya ang minamahal; ibinibigay niya ang kanyang sarili at nais niyang “nandoon siya” para sa isa. Doon, pumapasok ang elemento ng agape sa pag-ibig na ito, dahil kung hindi, nagiging-salat at naiwawala ng eros ang kanya mismong kalikasan. Sa kabilang banda naman, hindi mabubuhay ang tao sa mapagparaya/mapagbigay at pababang pag-ibig lamang. Hindi maaaring siya lang ang nag-aabot. Hindi maaaring bigay lamang siya nang bigay; kailangan din niyang tumanggap.Dapat maging handa ang sinumang nais magbigay ng pag-ibig na tumanggap din ng pag-ibig bilang kaloob. March 2011 - Volume 1 ANG PAGTATALABAN NG EROS AT AGAPE Page 27 Sa puntong ito, malinaw nga na ang eros at ang agape ay nagtatalaban at hindi totoong magkasalungat. Sa konteksto ng mga paliwanag ni Papa Benito XVI, makikita ang eros at ang agape ay totoong dalawang mukha ng pag-ibig na hindi magkakaroon ng kaganapan kung wala ang isa’t isa. Kaya naman, sa ensiklikal na Deus Caritas Est, nakita natin na dahil tayo’y nakatanggap ng pag-ibig, natural lamang na ipasa rin natin ito sa iba sapagkat ito ang kalikasan ng pag-ibig. Ito ay tinatanggap at ibinibigay.Ang tao nga ay umiibig at iniibig rin.Sabay itong nagaganap. Walang dahilan upang maging punto ito ng pagpili sapagkat hindi walang kaganapan ang totoong Kristiyanong pag-ibig kung wala sa buong proseso ang pagtatalaban ng “eros” at ng “agape.” Mga Sanggunian Aquinas, Thomas. 2006. Christian Love. http://www.georgetown. edu/faculty/ap85 /1445/spring06/ChristianLove.html. Benedict XVI, Santo Papa. 2005. Deus Caritas Est (Encyclical Letter on Christian Love). Libreria Editrice Vaticana. Dulles, Avery. 2006. Love, the Pope and CS Lewis. http://forum.stirpes. net/religion-theology/23657-agape-eros.html Gafni, Marc. 2004. The Mystery of Love. New York, NY: Atria Books. John Paul II, Santo Papa. 1981. Famliaris Consortio (Apostolic Exhortation on the Role of the Christian Family in the Modern World). Pauline Lewis, C.S. 2006.The Four Loves.http://www.boundless.org/2006/ departments/pages/ a0000588.html. Tschannen-Moran , Robert. 1996. sermons/961201-1224.htm March 2011 - Volume 1 http://www.pastorbob.net/ Page 28 THE FAMILIENÄHNLICHKEITEN OF CONCEPTS Rethinking the Problem of Universals through Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations MARVIN M. CRUZ Twenty-first century philosophy exhibits the emergence of positivism and linguistic analysis. Metaphysical questions about the nature of existence and essence are disregarded and dismissed as misconceived construction of meaningless terms that find no place in verifiable truths. Likewise, the search for what is absolute or ultimate in the metaphysical sense is considered old-fashioned and irrelevant. Nevertheless, the questions of antiquity remain to be unresolved. The aversion from the speculative systems of the past does not solve these problems at all. Here the problem of the nature and function of universals is an example. The history of this problem presents serious problems to the understanding of concepts, their origin and their function in logical thought especially in questions of absolutism and pluralism. This paper offers to present Wittgenstein’s insights on meaning and practice as discussed in the Philosophical Investigations1 to aid a re-examination of the problem of universals. A final section presents a test-case in which certain problems are discussed using the method outlined below. 1. The Philosophical Investigations The Investigations opens a variety of ways at looking at the workings of language. Its main purpose, as its title admits, is ‘to investigate,’ i.e. to examine, language from its multiple dimensions in order to command a clearer view of it. In the Investigations, Wittgenstein remains firm to his insistence on the nature of philosophical discourse. The investigation to be carried out in the Investigations is philosophical in the sense that it aims at clarifying the practice of language and March 2011 - Volume 1 THE FAMILIENÄHNLICHKEITEN OF CONCEPTS Page 29 the nature of meaning. It is concerned with two principal topics: philosophy of language and philosophical psychology.2 The former concerns meaning, sense, reference, etc., while the latter concerns the activity itself. The Investigations addresses these concerns through examples where particular opinions about language could be brought to proper light. Below are certain themes that concern the aims of this paper. a. Naming and Ostension Wittgenstein’s analysis of language begins with a passage he quotes from Augustine’s Confessions3 in which he identifies “a particular picture of the essence of human language” (PI §1). “When they (my elders) named some object, and accordingly moved towards something, I saw this and I grasped that the thing was called by the sound they uttered when they meant to point it out. Their intention was shewn by their bodily movements, as it were the natural language of all peoples: the expression of the face, the play of the eyes, the movement of other parts of the body, and the tone of voice which expresses our state of mind in seeking, having, rejecting, or avoiding something. thus, as I heard words repeatedly used in their proper places in various sentences, I gradually learnt to understand what objects they signified; and after I had trained my mouth to form these signs, I used them to express my own desires.” (Augustine, Confessions, I. 8.)4 Wittgenstein takes Augustine’s opinion as a familiar mindset as to how language is said to work: “individual words in language name objects” (PI §1). A word and its meaning stand in a corresponding relation of object and its reference. Wittgenstein, however, quickly reveals the limitations of this idea: it fails to speak of any difference between kinds of words (PI §1). Augustine presents here only a valid picture of words that function primarily as nouns, but it does not depict such other functions that may pertain to words. Wittgenstein continues to illustrate this in two important examples: March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 30 THE FAMILIENÄHNLICHKEITEN OF CONCEPTS Now think of the following use of language: I send someone shopping. I give him a slip marked “five red apples”. He takes the slip to the shopkeeper, who opens the drawer marked “apples”; then he looks up the word “red” in a table and finds a colour sample opposite to it; then he says the series of cardinal numbers—I assume that he knows them by heart—up to the word “five” and for each number he takes an apple of the same colour as the sample out of the drawer.—— It is in this and similar ways that one operates with words.——“But how does he know where and how he is to look up the word ‘red’ and what he is to do with the word ‘five’?”——Well, I assume that he acts as I have described. Explanations come to an end somewhere.—But what is the meaning of the word “five”?—No such thing was in question here, only how the word “five” is used (PI §2). Let us imagine a language for which the description given by Augustine is right. The language is meant to serve for communication between a builder A and an assistant B. A is building with building-stones: there are blocks, pillars, slabs and beams. B has to pass the stones, and that in the order in which A needs them. For this purpose they use a language consisting of the words “block”, “pillar”, “slab”, “beam”. A calls them out;—B brings the stone which he has learnt to bring at such-and-such a call.——Conceive this as a complete primitive language (PI §2). The examples describe specific limitations in the Augustinian picture of meaning and present a rough sketch of language in daily interaction. The first example describes language in a very concrete activity—shopping. The story is basically “about behavior and the use of signs”5 and there is no mention at all of any verbal communication. Wittgenstein nonetheless makes an examination of how the words ‘apples’, ‘red’ and ‘five’ are taken to mean in this illustration. It seems that the Augustinian picture may fit perfectly the way the word ‘apple’ is to be understood, but as to the words ‘red’ and ‘five’, such description March 2011 - Volume 1 THE FAMILIENÄHNLICHKEITEN OF CONCEPTS Page 31 would be pointless. Wittgenstein, therefore, directs the attention rather to the manner of operation itself—“Well, I assume that he acts as I have described.” Hence, what matters here is not so much the correlation between a word and its object as the way in which acting, i.e. the behavior or reaction, is drawn out by the signs. Augustine’s picture describes a system of communication, but not everything that is language is this system (PI §3). The second illustration likewise carries out the same purpose. Wittgenstein sets this example as a ‘complete’ [vollständige], i.e. independent, primitive language. Here, words are entirely drawn as orders to be carried out by the assistant. The communication between builder A and assistant B takes place according to the instruction of former to the latter. The words ‘block’, ‘pillar’, ‘slab’ and ‘beam’ designate not objects or ideas but particular action to be done. The mastery that assistant B exhibits in this primitive language is shown not by his grasp of the things but by his proficient training into acting according to the instruction. There need not, therefore, be any mental idea ‘mediating’ the instruction and the execution (PI §6), for “[h]ere the teaching of language is not explanation [Erklären], but training [Abrichten]” (PI §5). The Augustinian picture, therefore, does not adequately present a fundamental picture of language. It already presupposes a particular training into the activity of naming and ostension that are at the whole already specific skills in language. This picture thus provides only a part of the entire picture of language. It describes the association of words to specific meanings in such a way that the “child is credited with an innate insight into the technique of assigning names to things.”6 Wittgenstein’s critique of ostensive explanations (§§26-38) reveals that the technique of naming forms part of what could be designated as the practice of language, for the meaning of a word can never be definitely resolved by ostensive explanations. Consider the definition of the number ‘two’ as an example (PI §28). An ostensive definition here can be variously interpreted in every case (PI §28). Perhaps you say: two can only be ostensively defined in this way: “This number is called ‘two’”. For the word “number” here shews what place in language, March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 32 THE FAMILIENÄHNLICHKEITEN OF CONCEPTS in grammar, we assign to the word. But this means that the word “number” must be explained before the ostensive definition can be understood.—The word “number” in the definition does indeed shew this place; does shew the post at which we station the word (PI §29). Likewise, words that function as color would invite similar problems. Wittgenstein thus maintains that meaning is to be understood in the practice itself that defines how the word functions appropriately. b. Language-Game and Rule-Following The discussion on naming and the paradox of ostension precipitates Wittgenstein’s analysis of language-game [Sprachspiel]. He describes it as “the whole, consisting of language and the action into which it is woven” (PI §7). Words function and find their original home [Heimat] in the language-game (PI §116) which presents how they receive meaning from the actual practice where they are used. Language is fundamentally an activity. Words are employed in the context of a social activity that includes “not just the uttering of words and the movement of limbs, but also […] what we might ordinarily consider their surroundings.”7 Wittgenstein’s description of language as ‘games’ shows the deep interconnection between meaning and the activity engaged into. The German word Spiel “covers [even] freeform activities that in English would be called ‘play’ rather than ‘games’.”8 Like games, each specific practice of language can be an autonomous activity, i.e. it does not need to have any external goal.9 The game assigns the meaning of a word according to the roles it takes in that language-game. Nevertheless, as practices founded in social life, language-games relate to another (in Wittgenstein’s analogy) like “an ancient city: a maze of little streets and squares, of old and new houses, and of houses with additions from various periods” (PI §18). Wittgenstein takes the game of chess to explain how a language-game functions.10 To show someone the ‘king’ in chess and to say “This is the king” amounts to nothing but to show him the shape of the king (PI §31). The meaning of this piece in the game can only be understood March 2011 - Volume 1 THE FAMILIENÄHNLICHKEITEN OF CONCEPTS Page 33 according to the rules that prescribe the use of such piece. In fact, the words “This is the king” can only be understood by one who already “knows what a piece in a game is” (PI §31). Playing the game, therefore, requires a familiarity with the landscape within which such an activity takes place. It requires a certain amount of mastery: A move in chess doesn’t consist simply in moving a piece in such-and-such a way on the board—nor yet in one’s thoughts and feelings as one makes the move: but in the circumstances that we call “playing a game of chess”, “solving a chess problem”, and so on (PI §33). Language, therefore, involves similarly a skilled proficiency in the activity. To understand a color, a name or a number pertains to a familiarity with such activity of identifying colors, naming or counting. The critique of naming opens to the questions as to how the meaning of a word is understood. How does the meaning of a word correspond to its application in this sentence? “But can’t the meaning of a word that I understand fit the sense of a sentence that I understand? Or the meaning of one word fit the meaning of another?” (PI §138). Wittgenstein’s response to these questions forms his long discussion of meaning, rules, and understanding in which he critiques the mentalist theory of meaning as a psychic event.11 Understanding the meaning of a word, as has been mentioned earlier, is revealed in the mastery of particular applications of that word in language. It consists in a familiarity with the rules and standards that set limit to indicate how the meaning of such word is to be properly understood. Wittgenstein, however, denies that grasping such a rule or standard is a mental event in the mind: But now it looks as if when someone says “Bring me a slab” he could mean this expression as one long word corresponding to the single word “Slab!”—— Then can one mean it sometimes as one word and sometimes as four? And how does one usually mean it?——I think we shall be inclined to say: we mean the sentence as four words when we use it in contrast with other sentences such as “Hand me a slab”, “Bring March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 34 THE FAMILIENÄHNLICHKEITEN OF CONCEPTS him a slab”, “Bring two slabs”, etc.; that is, in contrast with sentences containing the separate words of our command in other combinations.——But what does using one sentence in contrast with others consist in? Do the others, perhaps, hover before one’s mind? (PI §20). The appropriate interpretation of the meaning of a word or a sentence in language is significant in understanding how interaction happens in language-game. Each language-game contains within itself its own set of parameters, i.e. rules that act as a ‘sign-post’ [Wegweiser] (PI §85), within which interpretation and application attain conceivable definiteness. Rules, however, remain to be sign-posts; they do not rule out the multiplicity of interpretations. “Every action according to the rule is an interpretation,” for This was our paradox: no course of action could be determined by a rule, because every course of action can be made out to accord with a rule. The answer was: if everything can be made out to accord with the rule, then it can also be made out to conflict with it. And so there would be neither accord nor conflict here (PI §201). ‘Obeying a rule’ [der Regel folgen] therefore is a practice [eine Praxis] (PI §202), since any interpretation presupposes standards already set forward. Hence, “it is not possible to obey a rule ‘privately’ [privatim] (PI §202). Wittgenstein’s analysis of rule-following cites the vital importance of the social (i.e. public) dimension of interpretation, meaning and application against the temptation towards a qualified skepticism to meaning and interpretation that submits everything to mere conventions or personal taste. c. Family Resemblances Language, therefore, consists of several language-games that form a network that arise from the practical engagements within a community. Wittgenstein’s analysis of language-games, however, opens the inquiry into the ‘essence’ of language: March 2011 - Volume 1 THE FAMILIENÄHNLICHKEITEN OF CONCEPTS Page 35 For someone might object against me: “You take the easy way out! You talk about all sorts of languagegames, but have nowhere said what the essence of a language-game [Wesentlische des Sprachspiels], and hence of language, is: what is common to all these activities, and what makes them into language or parts of language. So you let yourself off the very part of the investigation that once gave you yourself most headache, the part about the general form of propositions and of language” (PI §65). As a response to his critic, he simply furthers his analogy of ‘games’ by enumerating several kinds of games (board-games, card-games, ballgames, Olympic games) and invites the inquirer to “look and see” [schauen] whether there is anything common at all. For if you look at them you will not see something that is common to all, but similarities, relationships, and a whole series of them at that. To repeat: don’t think, but look [denk nicht, sondern schau]! […] [W]e see a complicated network of similarities overlapping and criss-crossing: sometimes overall similarities, sometimes similarities of detail (PI §66). Wittgenstein summarizes this ‘network of similarities’ into ‘family resemblances’ [Familienähnlichkeiten]. In much the same way that family members exhibit various resemblances that are in no way common to all, but present overlapping and criss-crossing traits, ‘games’ also form a family (PI §67). The concept of ‘family resemblances’ presents a critique against the traditional conception of definition. This is not, however, to be understood as a ready submission to ambiguity; this rather is a recognition of the embeddedness of meaning and application into the multiple aspects of human practice. Wittgenstein identifies the temptation to locate very rigid restrictions to meaning as a mental cramp that fixates the mind to one conception of meaning. Nonetheless, the experience of ambiguity reveals that language completely eludes such fixation. March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 36 THE FAMILIENÄHNLICHKEITEN OF CONCEPTS But is it senseless to say: “Stand roughly there”? Suppose that I were standing with someone in a city square and said that. As I say it I do not draw any kind of boundary, but perhaps point with my hand—as if I were indicating a particular spot. And this is just how one might explain to someone what a game is. One gives examples and intends them to be taken in a particular way.—I do not, however, mean by this that he is supposed to see in those examples that common thing which I—for some reason—was unable to express; but that he is now to employ those examples in a particular way. Here giving examples is not an indirect means of explaining—in default of a better. For any general definition can be misunderstood too. The point is that this is how we play the game (PI §71). Wittgenstein, therefore, goes against the usual requirement for ‘crystalline purity’ (cf. PI §107) and exactness in definitions. He insists that ‘exactness’ as a criterion arises in language only within the conception of usefulness. Thus, such criterion is unnecessary and can hence be discarded on account of the sufficiency of already attending explanations (PI §88). Consequently, the intersecting network of family resemblances also denies the sublimity of logic as an “ideal ‘must’ to be found in reality” (PI §101). It is nothing else for Wittgenstein but an unshakable [unverrückbar] ideal that fixates the vision like “a pair of glasses on our nose through which we see whatever we look at” (PI §103). What constitutes the actual interaction in the language-game, however, is the activity itself—the actual engagement in practice—and not the formality of logical operations. The analysis of rule-following reveals the public character of any understanding and application of expressions in language. A shared language reveals the common form of life [Lebensform] shared by a community. “To imagine a language means to imagine a form of life” (PI §19). A form of life is characterized by several languagegames that overlap to one another. Language is not a result of purely arbitrary human agreement in opinions, but of a form of life lived March 2011 - Volume 1 THE FAMILIENÄHNLICHKEITEN OF CONCEPTS Page 37 by a community that shows the characteristic social life unique to it that embodies its culture, customs, standards, experiences, etc.12 Understanding the practices, hence the language, of another means, therefore, to share a form of life. 2. The Problem of Universals and the Philosophical Investigations Wittgenstein’s invitation to see language as a game pushes the understanding of the nature of universals beyond the conflicting paradigms of essentialism and the nominalism. In contrast to such traditional views, Wittgenstein rejects the priority of such theories and demonstrates the reality that human language as an activity does work even without such theories (PI §1). The question as to how language does so pertains simply to its actual performance in social life. This, however, does not commit Wittgenstein to any form of skepticism. He plainly insists that explanation (theory) qua explanation is an activity that already presupposes a whole range of practices within which it becomes fully intelligible as a justification. The insistence that theories ought to take such priority to the activity itself brings about the assumptions that result to the stubborn need for rigorous frameworks. This fixation then gives rise to philosophical confusion (cf. PI §101, 103). Essentialism and nominalism impose complex sets of requirements to the nature of universals. Objectivism (essentialism) and conventionalism (nominalism) exist as pictures through which reality is assumed to operate. There then arises the logical tendency to put forward reductionist conclusions, since the standards in place were really from the beginning of the inquiry already fixed constructions that influence how observed reality is perceived.13 Hence, essentialism situates universals within a strict metaphysical framework thereby diminishing the role of social life; nominalism, on the other hand, upholds the arbitrary capacity of the thinking agent and hence rules out the objectivity most cherished by essentialism. Wittgenstein, however, maintains that such conceptions neglect that universals emerge from human activities such as naming that involve rules providing their foundation.14 Here, Wittgenstein clarifies the function of such activity by pushing aside particular mindsets that result only to difficulties; his investigation proposes that understanding such March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 38 THE FAMILIENÄHNLICHKEITEN OF CONCEPTS activity as naming falls within the context of several other activities involving activities (such as ‘using a word’ and ‘pointing to a thing’) which hang together in a relation grounded on human practice in general. The problem of universals, therefore, can be seen as the result of the failure to understand the belongingness and interdependence of activities to the entire plurality of human practical engagements. The real solution to the problem then consists in the clarification of the role of universals in language (PI §202). And we may not advance any kind of theory. There must not be anything hypothetical in our considerations. We must do away with all explanation, and description alone must take its place. And this description gets its light, that is to say its purpose, from the philosophical problems. These are, of course, not empirical problems; they are solved, rather, by looking into the workings of our language, and that in such a way as to make us recognize those workings: in despite of an urge to misunderstand them. The problems are solved, not by giving new information, but by arranging what we have always known. Philosophy is a battle against the bewitchment of our intelligence by means of language (PI §109). a. Universals and Familienähnlichkeiten The perception of similarities, whether discrete or remarkable ones, and the use of concepts in language are undeniably everyday human experiences. Concepts aid thinking and speech. In the opinion of the essentialist, such connection between a mental concept and the plurality of things designated by it can only be explained through a metaphysical principle—an ‘essence.’ Things of one particular species do not only appear to be similar, but they are essentially the same. The mind recognizes this unity in essence through its capacity for abstraction, but the unity itself exists as an actualized principle in its several instances. Wittgenstein, however, puts aside this requirement for an external metaphysical framework that characterizes essentialism and embarks rather into a description of how concepts are actually used in everyday discourse.15 The problem of meaning, March 2011 - Volume 1 THE FAMILIENÄHNLICHKEITEN OF CONCEPTS Page 39 hence, requires not an explanation through a complex metaphysical system, but simply an understanding of the dynamics of language.16 This distinction is vital so as not to quickly label Wittgenstein as a positivist. His interests were broader as compared to positivism. Wittgenstein maintains that meaning is a function that emerges from human interaction. It forms a family which embodies the form of life shared by a community bound together by experience, culture, needs and customs. The idea of family-resemblances among words and their application is an affirmation of this webbed network of interdependence. Language-games are primarily activities and hence create an interlocking network that weaves together language to other human activities (cf. PI §23). Viewing language in terms of overlapping language-games discards the need for much exactness and complexity17 typical of metaphysical systems and gives way to the gradual shadings of family resemblances.18 The doctrine of analogy somehow stands close to this conception of meaning; it maintains that predicates apply to their subject in partly the same but partly different manner. The conception of meaning into family resemblances likewise affirms this interrelatedness, although it does not impose any metaphysical requirement; what is taken as foundation for such similarities is the belongingness of meaning to a family of activities. b. Universals and Language-games The absence of metaphysical constructions in Wittgenstein’s account of universals and his conception of family-resemblances of meaning, however, do not imply that he denies objectivity. Total relativism is entirely alien to Wittgenstein’s emphasis on the significance of a community in the interpretation and application of words in languagegame. As an activity, language is a trained proficiency (PI §5) involving such rules that set standards for what is appropriate, i.e. intelligible, in a given context. Meaning originates from the arrangements in the language-game which is its home (PI §116) as seen from his criticism of the idea of a private language. The interpretation and application of words cannot find justification except within a set of socially preestablished practices. Wittgenstein’s insights bear evidence against the tenability of absolute March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 40 THE FAMILIENÄHNLICHKEITEN OF CONCEPTS relativism in language. The arbitrariness of nominalism is incongruent to the intelligible activities within the language-game. The standards that pertain to a language-game are parameters that allow words in language to become meaningful by being organized into their roles in language. The nominalist thus may be right in the stress he puts on “the role of human interests and human purposes in determining our choices of principles of classification”19 but he misses the point by ruling out objectivity as illusory being plainly imposed by the mind. “The nominalist is so impressed by infinite diversity of possible classifications that he is blinded to their objectivity.”20 Meaning is not an object separable from the framework of the practice that defines its role in language. “To imagine a language,” maintains Wittgenstein, “is to imagine a form of life” (PI §19). The tenability of nominalism, therefore, could be much improved by a recognition of the public nature of the meaning and the application of words in language. As there can be no private language (PI §261), meaning cannot simply be confined to a private choice made by an individual receiving universality through a consensus among others. The very conception of consensus (agreement and disagreement) could not but take place in a venue where a practice already operates. c. Beyond Objectivism and Conventionalism Wittgenstein’s analysis of language moves beyond the particular issues of objectivism and conventionalism into the nature of language and practice. His analysis proposes a recognition of the dynamicity of language and meaning among human interactions. The problem of universals stands as a pseudo-problem requiring not a new set of theories but a clarification of how universals as such function in language. Wittgenstein’s therapeutic methodology thus relieves the mind of its paralysis to one inordinate view and enables it to perceive wider horizons.21 The analysis carried out, however, does not just end with the dissolution of the problem. Such endeavor would seem futile if it would only result in plain verbal dispute over the matter. A command of a clearer view by the dissolution of the problem ought to bring about a different way of looking at other issues related to it. The next section shall go over a select survey of some possible implications of the reinterpretation March 2011 - Volume 1 THE FAMILIENÄHNLICHKEITEN OF CONCEPTS Page 41 of the problem of universals proposed in this study. The problem of universals touches several other problems as its long history suggests and thus its resolution would benefit the understanding of such other related disciplines. What have been included here are only possibilities, not compelling implications, which may aid in understanding the foreseeable influence of this reinterpretation to other fields. d. Exploring the Implications of the Investigations’ Critique (1) Moral Language In 1936, the logical positivist Alfred Jules Ayer published the influential book Language, Truth and Logic where he expounds an emotivist theory of ethics. In accordance with logical positivism’s theory of knowledge, he suggests that ethical propositions amount to nothing but mere reports of personal sentiments towards an action. Nonetheless, this was not an entirely new ethical theory, for centuries before him, the philosopher David Hume (1711-1776) already denied any implicative relation between descriptive and evaluative assertions.22 Ayer denied the function of ethical proposition as ethical on the grounds that empirical analysis does not provide any warranted claim beyond the individual’s pronouncement of a personal belief or sentiment. Such positivist analysis committed to the ‘principle of verification’ inevitably delimits the claim to universality of ethical propositions thus reducing their value to conventional paradigms among common personal sentiments. Alasdair McIntyre, one of the critics of emotivist ethics, showed that such opinion is loosely founded on misconceived presuppositions that do not give notice to the historical character of moral concepts. He writes, Some philosophers have even written as if moral concepts were a timeless, limited, unchanging, determinate species of concept, necessarily having the same features throughout their history. […] In a less sophisticated way, historians of morals are all too apt to allow that moral practices and the content of moral judgments may vary from society to society and from person to person, but at the same time these historians have subtly assimilated different moral concepts—and March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 42 THE FAMILIENÄHNLICHKEITEN OF CONCEPTS so they end up suggesting that although what is held to be right or good is not always the same, roughly the same concepts of right and good are universals.23 He points out that the alleged failure of ethical paradigms to account for changing contexts such as historical epochs is not a flaw in moral concepts themselves but a flaw in understanding their relative application to different contexts in history. Moral concepts constitute the evaluative vocabulary of a particular social context characterized by the practical engagements in the social life of that community. Philosophical ethics, therefore, has the role of clarifying how such moral concepts function within the social life that provides roles for the concepts to play. In addition, philosophical discourse takes part in changing moral concepts by lubricating its appropriation to social life.24 Consider for example the concept ‘good’—the most widely designated word in ethics. The concept ‘good’ is central to any moral vocabulary such that the appropriation of it in social life fixes the working set of moral concepts. ‘Good,’ however, as the existence of many ethical schools show, is not very clearly designated. Several accounts attempt to propose a definition of it through formal analysis, while others make practical delimitations. These, however, have proven unsatisfactory; the concept ‘good’ escapes exact definition.25 Hence, some opinions take forms of moral skepticism and relativism. Moore, however, in his Principia Ethica (1903) claims that ‘good’ is a simple, unanalyzable property.26 He suggests a form of intuitionism against the opinions that fall into what he calls the ‘naturalistic fallacy’ that designates ‘good’ as a natural thing—pleasure, satisfaction, food, etc.27 Such opinions confuse the predicate copula ‘is’ to identity (e.g. in ‘two plus three is five’) and hence they assume that ‘good’ as predicable ought to be interchangeable (consider the contrast between ‘pleasure is good’ and ‘the good is pleasure’). Such error results due to a poor analysis that Moore seeks to replace in his work. The analysis of the concept ‘good’ through its many roles in the practice of language, however, reveals something more than what the intuitionists claim. Intuition does not itself rule out the possibility March 2011 - Volume 1 THE FAMILIENÄHNLICHKEITEN OF CONCEPTS Page 43 of arbitrariness that may result to ambiguity. Hence, it would be an insufficient ground. An analysis of its grammar, i.e. its use in language, may provide a better understanding. Consider this example: when one asserts that ‘an apple is good’, one indicates that what he seeks is something sought in general by people who want what he wants.28 The predicate ‘good’ is not merely an indicative of personal preference, for it involves a “criteria characteristically accepted as a standard”29 by those who apply the word in similar context. The concept ‘good’ is not a mere result of many personal accounts that converge to form a single concept by convention; rather the word plays a role in the network of social life and is intelligible not according to a neatly constructed definition but by its role in such context where it receives justification. To predicate ‘good’ to something is to invoke a set of criteria nested in the social landscape of a community. Moore’s analysis ended with the conception of ‘good’ as a simple precisely because he did not fully acknowledge the interconnectedness and interdependence that characterize language and social life. Moore was actually invoking a pure concept of ‘good’ as if it could be understood in vacuum, i.e. outside social life. Emotivists, on the other hand, likewise make an erroneous denial of the functional integration of concepts to social life. Their insistence that moral utterances are reducible to personal sentiments results from a misconception that language could only function in a limited way, i.e. describe empirical facts or assert tautologies. Contrary to such opinion, language involves a family of functions that stand parallel to the network of human activities stemming from a shared form of life. Moral utterances, therefore, play a different role, which differentiates them from other assertions. Emotivism does not attend sufficiently to the distinction between the meaning of a statement which remains constant between different uses, and the variety of uses to which one and the same statement can be put.30 Emotivists, therefore, tend to conflate meaning and use, and even confuse the primary use of moral utterances in human language to assertions of empirical facts.31 March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 44 THE FAMILIENÄHNLICHKEITEN OF CONCEPTS (2) The Inexorability of Mathematics The primary problem that undoubtedly gave rise to Wittgenstein’s interests in philosophy was that of the foundations of mathematics and logic. A huge section of his Nachlass contains several of his insights in mathematics, which centered on the conflict between regarding the content of mathematics as transcendental (i.e. that a mathematical reality has truth and meaning regardless of human rules or use) and espousing a psychologistic interpretation of mathematical truths.32 This dispute apparently parallels the opposition between that of the realist and the idealist, and Wittgenstein’s insights concerning the real and ideal have significant contributions to understanding the nature of mathematical and logical statements. Wittgenstein’s early writings in the Tractatus reveal his hesitation in giving up totally his early transcendental picture of logic and mathematics. There he assigns logical truths with absolute value: “Logic must look after itself. […] In a certain sense, we cannot make mistakes in logic.”33 It contains its own justification, and hence its meaning (as tautologies)34 is completely independent of human rules or use. Wittgenstein, however, dropped this initial opinion when he began to look at language in terms of games, which include not only the rules of its operation but also the wider background that covers even human practice. Mathematics thus in this conception belongs properly not to an independent transcendent absolute, but to a system of social engagements in a community; but then, asks Wittgenstein: “What does the peculiar inexorability of mathematics consist in?”35 It is first important to recognize that mathematical statements are widely different from empirical ones. The former according to Wittgenstein are ‘nonrevisable’; they play a special role in language. “Mathematics as such is always measure, not the thing measured.”36 Unlike empirical statements, mathematical ones do not describe empirical facts and hence no such facts or sensory impression can make them true or false.37 When one adds two to five and gets eight, he does not cast any doubt as to whether the mathematical statement ‘two plus five makes seven’ is correct or not; rather, what he does is to redo his counting in the assumption that he must have had somewhere made a mistake. Mathematical statements, therefore, are March 2011 - Volume 1 THE FAMILIENÄHNLICHKEITEN OF CONCEPTS Page 45 considered as such according to the role they play in human practice; their inexorability exhibits a specific arrangement in human practice, not in anything transcendent, that assigns to mathematics a different role in language. “There is no guarantee that our mathematics will not change (indeed it has), and certain statements that were considered nonsense will then become necessary (such as “2 – 4 = -2” before and after the introduction of negative numbers).”38 Mathematical propositions are thus ‘grammatical’ in function, i.e. they pertain to new ways that introduce useful innovations to the vocabulary and articulation of a practice.39 Thus, the introduction of negative numbers to the number system allowed new ways of doing arithmetic, while the emergence of imaginary numbers paved the way to different meanings for ‘multiplication,’ ‘square root’ and even ‘number’ itself.40 Some interpreters of Wittgenstein, however, in this area of his work immediately labels Wittgenstein’s conception of mathematics as conventionalist,41 in which “the logical necessity of any statement is always the direct expression of a linguistic convention.”42 Such reading, however, does not run consistently with Wittgenstein’s conception of mathematics. Such conventionalism ascribes the correctness of mathematical statements as a result of the plain agreement among mathematicians who grant them objectivity. “Wittgenstein’s target here is not our common notions of mathematical objectivity, but the misleading picture of the source of this objectivity.”43 Mathematics simply provides the common framework where without which even agreement or disagreement would make no sense at all. Agreement does not make a mathematical statement true, but simply provides the venue in which truth and falsity along with its role in language would be intelligible.44 “So you are saying that human agreement decides what is true and what is false?”—It is what human beings say that is true and false; and they agree in the language they use. That is not agreement in opinion but in form of life (PI §241). Mathematical statements that arise from this common framework take their place in language according to their use, i.e. in their ability to facilitate activities such as doing arithmetic, counting, solving a March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 46 THE FAMILIENÄHNLICHKEITEN OF CONCEPTS mathematical problem or evaluating an equation. Wittgenstein’s insights thus provide points to clarify such apparent conflict between the conception of mathematics as inexorable and the changes that may take place due to new mathematical conventions. Endnotes 1 2 3 4 The Philosophical Investigations, henceforth Investigations, was edited and translated into English by G.E.M. Anscombe and published in 1953 (New York: The Macmillan Company). All references cite the third edition of the work and designates the title as ‘PI’. All citations from Part I follow Wittgenstein’s numbering of the remarks. McGinn, Wittgenstein and the Philosophical Investigations (London: Routledge, 1997), p.9. The choice of Augustine for the beginning the Investigations serves different opinions. Anthony Kenny points out that Wittgenstein’s presentation of Augustine is misleading, Legacy of Wittgenstein (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1984), pp.10-11. Ray Monk, however, claims: “Connected with the degree of personal involvement required to make sense of it, there is another reason why it seems appropriate to begin the book with a quotation from St. Augustine’s Confessions. And that is that, for Wittgenstein, all philosophy, in so far as it is pursued honestly and decently, begins with a confession.” Ludwig Wittgenstein: The Duty of Genius (London: Penguin Books, 1990), p.366. For discussions of Wittgenstein’s choice of Augustine, see Stanley Cavell’s “Notes and Afterthoughts on the Opening of Wittgenstein’s Investigations” in Sluga and Stern’s The Cambridge Companion to Wittgenstein (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), pp.261-295; Fergus Kerr’s Theology After Wittgenstein (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1986), pp.38-42; and David Stern’s Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations: An Introduction (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), pp.72-75. PI §1, this is Wittgenstein’s translation of the quoted Latin text. 5Stern, Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations, p.86. 6McGinn, Wittgenstein and the Philosophical Investigations, p.41. 7Stern, Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations, p.89. 8 Ibid., p.89. March 2011 - Volume 1 THE FAMILIENÄHNLICHKEITEN OF CONCEPTS Page 9 47 Kenny, Wittgenstein, p.163. 10 Wittgenstein remarks, “The question ‘What is a word really?’ us analogous to ‘What is a piece in chess?’”, PI §108. 11 Wittgenstein’s discussion of rule-following together with his discussion on private language has been interpreted in several ways. The most provocative arrangement of the argument is that of Saul Kripke’s Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language: An Elementary Exposition (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1982) where he interprets Wittgenstein’s arguments into a skeptical framework of rule-following. The exposition here, however, follows McGinn’s Wittgenstein and the Philosophical Investigations, pp.82-106. 12 The discussion of forms of life is provided clear elaboration in Wittgenstein’s last writings. See On Certainty, edited by G.E.M. Anscombe and G.H. von Wright, translated by Denis Paul and G.E.M. Anscombe (New York: Harper & Row, Publishers, 1969). 13 In Wittgenstein’s analogy, they are like “a pair of glasses on our nose.” PI §103. 14 See for example PI §49: “Naming is a preparation for description.” 15 Whether Wittgenstein denied the validity of metaphysics or found its conclusions untenable is not at all very clear. A reading of the Tractatus reveals that what he clearly denies is that of speaking beyond the limits of language. Hence, some interpreters take Wittgenstein to be arguing solely against the act of metaphysical discourse, but not the existence of the entities proposed by metaphysics. Some even read some of Wittgenstein’s writings as paving the way to the construction of a metaphysical language that would be sufficiently valid. See for example M.J. Charlesworth’s Philosophy and Linguistic Analysis (Pittsburgh: Duquesne University, 1959), pp.219-220; and Hugh Petrie’s “Science and Metaphysics: A Wittgensteinian Interpretation” and E.D. Klemke’s “The Ontology of Wittgenstein’s Tractatus” both in Essays on Wittgenstein edited by E.D. Klemke (Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1971), pp.138169 and pp.104-119 respectively. Other recent interpreters, however, have challenged such readings where Wittgenstein seems to be advancing a kind of ‘theory.’ They take a literal reading of Wittgenstein’s insistence that philosophy is solely an activity, not a body of doctrines and hence dismiss the possibility of metaphysical discourse, cf. Tractatus LogicoPhilosophicus, henceforth TLP, trans. by D.F. Pears and B.F. McGuinness (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, Ltd, 1961), §4.112, PI §§126-128. For a reading on these interpretations, see David Stern’s Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations pp.40-55 where he identifies the two camps as the Pyrrhonian and non-Pyrrhonian readings of Wittgenstein. 16 PI §116: “What we do is to bring words back from their metaphysical to their everyday use.” March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 48 THE FAMILIENÄHNLICHKEITEN OF CONCEPTS 17 Cf. PI §107: “The more narrowly we examine actual language, the sharper becomes the conflict between it and our requirement.” 18 “A Philosophy of Mathematics Between Two Camps” by Steve Gerrard, p.176 in The Cambridge Companion to Wittgenstein edited by Hans Sluga and David Stern, pp.171-197. Gerrard regards this as a shift from Wittgenstein’s calculus-based language to a wider conception of language through games. 19 “Universals and Family Resemblances” by Renford Bambrough, p.121 in Loux, Universals and Particulars: Readings in Ontology (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1970), pp.106-124. 20 Ibid., p.123. 21 Such comparison of philosophical elucidations to therapies can be found in PI §133. 22 On Hume’s dichotomy between ‘is’ and ‘ought,’ see James Baillie’s Hume on Morality (New York: Routledge, 2000), pp.136-138. 23 Alasdair McIntyre, A Short History of Ethics: A History of Moral Philosophy from the Homeric Age to the Twentieth Century (New York: The Macmillan Company, 1966), p.1. 24 Ibid., p.2. 25 Even Aristotle’s designation of good as that which is desired is ambiguous. Cf. The Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle translated with an introduction by Sir David Ross (London: Oxford University Press, 1954), p.1. 26 Charlesworth, Philosophy and Linguistic Analysis, p.28. 27 Ibid., pp.29-30. 28 Ibid., p.58. 29 Ibid. 30 Ibid., p.259. 31 Ibid. 32 Gerrard, “A Philosophy of Mathematics Between Two Camps”, pp.172173. 33 TLP §5.473. 34 TLP §6.126. 35 Remarks on the Foundation of Mathematics I, §4 in Gerrard, “A Philosophy of Mathematics Between Two Camps”, p.177. 36 Ibid., p.178. 37 Ibid., p.179. 38 Ibid. March 2011 - Volume 1 THE FAMILIENÄHNLICHKEITEN OF CONCEPTS Page 39 Monk, The Duty of Genius, p.468. 40 Ibid., pp.546-547. 49 41 Gerrard, “A Philosophy of Mathematics Between Two Camps”, p.183. Gerrard identifies as one example Michael Dummet’s article “Wittgenstein’s Philosophy of Mathematics” in The Philosophical Review 68 (1959), pp.324-348, reprinted in Wittgenstein: The Philosophical Investigations edited by George Pitcher (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1968). 42 Ibid., p.425. 43 Ibid., p.191. 44 Ibid., p.190. March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 50 LOVE AS DUTY A Kierkegaardian Response to the Kantian Critique of the Divine Commandment JEROME C. JAIME Most people would consider love as a good. Some thinkers would even go as far as claiming it to be the good—a necessary good.1 Hence, to their opinion, love would be an end worthy of pursuit such that a moral precept obliging it would be universally valid. In this manner, one may even speak of self-perfection resulting from love: a perfection opening man even more fully to others.2 Love, therefore, becomes a necessary condition in a relationship between persons. As a good, it gives meaning to one’s existence: “it frees the lover from slavery to the relatively meaningless.”3 Love seeks what is good for oneself and for the other, as it reveals the goodness in the lover and the beloved leading to their perfection. One wants those whom one loves to be perfect and to enjoy all possible goods.4 It is a good that is sought for the well-being of every man. The search for completeness through a love-relationship seems to be imbedded in human nature. “It is not only necessary but also noble; for we praise those who love their friends and it is thought to be a fine thing to have many friends.”5 No one would want to live in isolation, even if he has all the other goods of the world.6 Man has a natural longing to complete himself by personally relating with other men, for without “love, there can be no true interpersonal relations”7 among people. Isolation can only be conquered through a union of individuals through unselfish love. Nonetheless, the lover, though he does not expect the other to love him in return, also has a need to be loved. If the lover would deny his need for affection, expressing love would soon become a burden and it would only result to a different form of isolation. “A truly personal and human sphere is created where two or more persons meet as persons in mutual love.”8 Even if the beloved is an enemy, love would transform him such that he also becomes capable of reciprocating the goodness expressed by the lover. March 2011 - Volume 1 LOVE AS DUTY Page 51 This therefore grounds somewhat reasonably the affirmation made by religious traditions of the divine command that raises the act of love and benevolence as necessary moral responsibility that all should fulfill. This is a generally acceptable idea among many religious and non-religious perspectives. The ‘divine command theory’ claims that love is a necessary good because it is commanded by a sovereign divine authority. This kind of obedience, nonetheless, is not a blind submission to authority. Love remains to be seen as an activity9 whereby a person consciously, deliberately and intentionally expresses benevolence towards another individual. Such love is made perfect through God’s intelligently-willed order as a divine lawgiver by which man in his rational obedience is directed to his end. 1. Kantian Critique of the Divine Commandment Philosophers like Kant are not easily persuaded by such arguments; they deny that love has to be or could be commanded. Kant denies the idea that moral norms could be deemed as universally binding simply by virtue of natural inclination or of divine authority. He asserts that the ultimate source of the principles of the moral law should be grounded “in reason considered in itself, without reference to specifically human conditions, to human nature or to any factor in human life or society.”10 He therefore concludes that “nothing in the world—indeed nothing even beyond the world—can possibly be conceived which could be called good without qualification except a good will.”11 In the Critique of Practical Reason and Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals, Kant directly puts forward a critique of the divine commandment. He contends that there are only two ways to take the commandment: either as pathological love (passionate) or practical love (duty). He writes, It is in this way, undoubtedly, that we should understand those passages of Scripture which command us to love our neighbor and even our enemy, for love as an inclination cannot be commanded. But beneficence from duty, when no inclination impels it and even when it is opposed by a natural and unconquerable aversion, is practical love, not pathological love: it resides in the March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 52 LOVE AS DUTY will and not in the propensities of feeling, in principles of action and not in tender sympathy; and it alone can be commanded.12 Here, Kant clearly identifies the divine commandment as practical love and rejects the idea that any kind of action motivated by or done out of such sentiment and feeling can be commanded. Hence, one could but express love for another as practical love, i.e. in actions which arise not from inclinations, but which arise from duty. For Kant, acting out of sentiment is something beyond the control of one’s will. The same affection towards men is possible no doubt, but cannot be commanded, for it is not in the power of any man to love anyone at command; therefore it is only practical love that is meant in that pith of all laws.13 Kant understands the divine commandment as practical love on the basis that moral life cannot require that one strive to develop sentiments or feelings of love for others in which they mean more than acting from and for the sake of duty. 14 “For Kant the demands of moral life require that we act from maxims that are consistent with the moral law.”15 Likewise, he argues that if one would accept the commandment as a rule, it would mean that individuals should have a kind of disposition wherein “to love God means […] to like to do His commandments; to love one’s neighbor means to like to practice all duties towards him.”16 Consequently, it cannot compel anyone to have such a disposition, for it would be plainly absurd. For a command to like to do a thing is in itself contradictory, because if we already know of ourselves what we are bound to do, and if further we are conscious of liking to do it, a command would be quite needless; and if we do it not willingly, but only out of respect for the law, a command that makes this respect the motive of our maxim would directly counteract the disposition commanded.17 March 2011 - Volume 1 LOVE AS DUTY Page 53 For Kant, this kind of disposition is an ‘Ideal of Holiness.’18 In this state, there is nothing in the individual that would tempt him to deviate from the moral law. Though this is impossible to be attained because, “being a creature, […] he can never be quite free from desires and inclinations, […] they can never of themselves coincide with the moral law.”19 2. Kierkegaard on the Triangular Nature of Love The Kantian idea of love is only one of the many possible interpretations to the concept of love. Although, there may be common ideas in every thinkers’ elucidation of the term, “there [remains] considerable confusion as to what love is and how it works.”20 An appropriate understanding of love that fits the idea of the divine commandment is therefore needed to accomplish the task of giving a plausible response to the critique elaborated in the last section. There are two key concepts in the divine commandment: the individual and the concept of love as duty. These two are very much interrelated such that one cannot conceive of love as a duty without first being able to understand who is the individual. Kierkegaard’s treatment of these two concepts and his system of thought provide a more dynamic interpretation of the divine commandment and its ethical foundation. a. The Other as Neighbor The concept of the individual plays a very crucial and significant role in Kierkegaard’s philosophy. In his philosophy, Kierkegaard reinstates man to his original position so to speak.21 His thought detaches the individual from the mob and places him in the face of his own absurd existence wherein he becomes the main actor. He is not merely a spectator but an active individual who realizes his very essence as “a personal center of responsibility, selfhood and equality.”22 For Kierkegaard, the “highest self-actualization of the individual is the relating of oneself to God, not as the universal, absolute Thought, but as the absolute Thou.”23 March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 54 LOVE AS DUTY Kierkegaard adds another complicated point to this already radical understanding of the individual. In describing the ‘self’ he adds: “Such a derived, constituted relation is the human self, a relation which relates itself to its own self, and in relating itself to its own self relates itself to another.”24 Here the Other occupies a significant place in the process of self-realization. The self is confronted by the fact that, though one exists as an individual, one is not alone in the world. The attainment of selfhood is a joint affair among individuals who are all equal. This equality among individuals is exemplified in the concept of the neighbor. The neighbor is a hidden quality of the other such that it can only be seen through a kind of divine assistance. Each individual is a neighbor to oneself. “Although on the surface level they may have differences, both are unique human beings who must learn to recognize and appreciate their common characteristics, as well as their differences”25 The concept of neighbor is indeed an intrinsic value of the other. All people possess this intrinsic value. “There is not a single person in the whole world who is as surely and easily recognized as the neighbor.”26 Therefore, one easily recognizes a neighbor, since the neighbor is any person.27 To recognize the neighbor is to respect the other as he is. It safeguards the other from the Sartrean mistake which says that the self is shattered when the “stare of the other turns me into an object”28 and can only be recovered if one transform the other into an object.29 Kierkegaard offers the concept of neighbor as a solution. “The neighbor is self-denial’s middle term that steps in between self-love’s I and I, but also between erotic love’s and friendship’s I and the other I.”30 The neighbor, however, is not identical with the term Other. When Kierkegaard uses the term ‘neighbor,’ it refers to every human person who is apart from the I but nonetheless bears resemblance thereto in virtue of being an individual. However, the same concept may not apply to God when he discusses the divine commandment. He would consider God not as a neighbor (i.e. the proper object of love) but the ‘middle term’ of Christian love. The I (self), the other (neighbor) and God constitute the dialectical movement of love that reaches its synthesis in Christian love. Love therefore has a triangular nature March 2011 - Volume 1 LOVE AS DUTY Page 55 whereby God is the middle term. It is only in this sense that one can properly love the other without falling into the dangers of selflove. Kierkegaard thus sees the nature of Christian love in terms of a triangular dynamic: Worldly wisdom is of the opinion that love is a relationship between persons; Christianity teaches that love is a relationship between: a person – God – a person, that is, that God is the middle term. [...] To love God is to love oneself truly; to help another person to love God is to love another person; to be helped by another person to love God is to be loved.31 For Kierkegaard, two people who love each other see their equality, either because of the image of God in them, or because of the foundation of love within them.32 “When someone goes with God, he does indeed go without danger; but he is also compelled to see and to see in a unique way.”33 Therefore, one fulfills the requirement of the commandment, “Thou shall love thy neighbor,” and the neighbor precisely is everyone. To love therefore means to love without preference. The reason is very simple: “the neighbor has the object that is without difference. The neighbor is the utterly unrecognizable dissimilarity between persons or is the eternal equality before God.”34 The divine commandment says that one has a duty to love the neighbor, not the friend or the beloved. It does not forbid one to love the friend but admonishes one: “love your friend honestly and devotedly, but let love for the neighbor be what you learn from each other in your friendship’s confidential relationship with God.”35 “The ‘neighbor’ is what thinkers call ‘the other,’ that by which the selfishness in self-love is to be tested.”36 Loving the other as the neighbor also means respecting the other as a Thou. When one is able to discern this common watermark among individuals through a kind of divine assistance, one is, to some extent, motivated to love the other in whom it is perceived.37 “Only if it is mediated by the commanded love of God can the commanded love of neighbor reach out to every other human being, excluding no one on preferential grounds.”38 March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 56 LOVE AS DUTY b. Love as Duty: Between Christian Love and Preferential Love Kierkegaard answers the central question, why is there a need, or simply why should love be commanded, and thus, a duty by distinguishing three kinds of love. He tries to distinguish the distinctively Christian form of love (agape, caritas) from both erotic love (eros, amor) and friendship.39 “The aim of both erotic love and friendship is to love this single human being above all others and in distinction from all others.”40 The kind of love that the divine commandment speaks of is a love that stands in sharp contrast with these two kinds of love. While the divine commandment compels the individual to love (agape) all without exclusion, erotic love and friendship are both preferential and exclusive. Kierkegaard writes, The issue between the poet and Christianity can be defined very precisely as follows: Erotic love and friendship are preferential love [Forkjerlighed] and the passion of preferential love; Christian love [Kjerlighed] is self-denial’s love, for which this shall vouches. To deprive these passions of their strength is the confusion. But preferential love’s most passionate boundlessness in excluding means to love only one single person; self-denial’s boundlessness in giving itself means not to exclude a single one.41 For Kierkegaard, only by becoming duty can love become secure from the dangers of self-love that is akin to passionate preferential love. “Just as self-love selfishly embraces this one and only self that makes it self-love, so also erotic love’s passionate preference selfishly encircles this one and only beloved, and friendship’s passionate preference encircles this one and only friend.”42 Three things destroy erotic love and friendship: “changes in our inclinations and feelings, changes in the objects we love, and the unhappiness, pain, and suffering that can lead to despair.”43 However, love can be secured from these if it is a duty, and so compliance is motivated by a sense of duty imposed by the commandment to love the neighbor, independent of one’s inclinations and feelings. “Only when it is a duty to love, only then is love eternally secured against every change, eternally free in blessed independence, eternally and happily secure against despair.”44 March 2011 - Volume 1 LOVE AS DUTY Page 57 It is possible to put up an argument against the divine commandment by saying that love ought to be spontaneous if it is to be sincere. Spontaneity is one aspect of passionate preferential love. Nevertheless, Kierkegaard argues that even spontaneous love seeks security. “Therefore the two swear an oath, swear fidelity or friendship to each other.”45 However, this oath offers nothing but a false security because the two persons who swear to love each other forever, “swears by something that is lower than [love] itself.”46 “The two swear by their love to each other forever, instead of swearing love to each other by eternity.”47 Therefore, both of them swear by something that could change over time. If what one feels changes, then there would be nothing else that would bind their love. The only way to find true security if one is to make an oath is to swear by the higher or “if one is to swear by eternity, then one swears by the duty that one ‘shall love.’”48 Spontaneous love is still subject to change because “it is not consciously grounded upon the eternal”49 but depends entirely on one’s emotion and feeling. It could change into its opposite, “into hate”50 or “it can become the sickness of jealousy.”51 This is what Kierkegaard means by securing love against change, he is thinking of changes in the desires or feelings that are in part constitutive of preferential love, desires and passions that sometimes spontaneously alter even when there is no change in the object of love or in the lover’s beliefs about the object. 52 Kierkegaard also speaks of love being free in blessed independence. “Only when it is a duty to love, only then is love eternally made free in blessed independence.”53 Christian love is a kind of love that is independent from any mutable characteristics of the object. On the other hand, erotic love has for its object the beloved, while friendship cannot exist without the friend. “The dependence of erotic love and friendship on mutable characteristics of the beloved and the friend make them vulnerable to alterations in their objects.”54 If in any case the beloved loses his external attractiveness, erotic love fades and dies. Friendship is also destroyed if at one point the friend starts to become unfaithful, and the virtues for which he was cherished turn into vices. The divine commandment of love has no other object than the neighbor who is every human being, who possesses nothing of the perfections of the beloved or the friend. Love does not require the March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 58 LOVE AS DUTY perfection of its object. “Erotic love [Elskov] is defined by the object; friendship is defined by the object; only love for the neighbor is defined by love [Kjerlighed].”55 “Only when it is a duty to love, then is love eternally and happily secured against despair.”56 One experiences despair when one loses a friend or beloved. Despair pertains to the unhappiness brought about by preferential love. Christian love by becoming duty and by undergoing the change of eternity secures the individual from any danger of preferential love. Rather than be in despair, “the one who loves is with blessed joy conscious of this and God in his confidant.”57 Kierkegaard, therefore, offers an alternative to Rational love which is merely grounded on reason’s practical function. As such, what it only implies is that Rational love (in the same way as preferential love) falls short of an appropriate interpretation that can appropriately describe the real value of the act of love. 3. Love and the Three Stages on Life’s Way Kierkegaard is very much credited by general histories of philosophies for his ideas concerning the three spheres of existence or what he calls three stages on life’s way.58 The three modes follow a hierarchical pattern from the most basic to the highest level of existence: the aesthetical, the ethical, and the religious. The levels of love explained above follow a similar scheme; hence, the aesthetical is to preferential love, ethical is to rational love and religious is to Christian love. a. The Aesthetical Sphere: Preferential Love The aesthetic sphere as the first stage of existence is “characterized by self-dispersal on the level of sense.”59 Man in the aesthetical stage (the aesthete)60 regards his existence as an expression of freedom. The aesthete lives in such a way that he is almost entirely governed by his emotions, impulses, and passion. The aesthete thus presents a preferential love. It is a love driven by passion and pleasure and security from pain. Thus, one loves a friend or a beloved because of the perfection that one perceives in the other. At times, it is simply motivated by self-love.61 Preferential love, nonetheless, later loses the March 2011 - Volume 1 LOVE AS DUTY Page 59 passion that motivates it; “the sophisticated aesthete realizes that the pursuit of pleasure itself becomes boring, […] but he tries to solve this problem from within the aesthetic sphere.”62 Thus, to avoid boredom he never makes any serious commitments to any person. Moreover, since aestheticism is a form of alienation from selfhood, the aesthete cannot love the other in the right way. It cannot satisfy the demands of the commandment to love oneself in the right way63 because the aesthete does not know himself. “At this volatile moment of near derangement, one can make “THE LEAP.” By the sheer force of his passion, the individual rips himself out of his old form of existence (aestheticism), and by losing his self, gains his self.”64 b. The Ethical Sphere: Rational Love (Kantian Ethics) The individual thus enters the second stage of existence: the ethical sphere. In this stage, the individual “accepts determinate moral standards and obligations, the voice of universal reason, and thus gives form and consistency to his life.”65 His new life is thus constituted by a new self who makes choices not out of sheer passion but out of a definite ethical code. It does not matter what kind of ethical code one adopts as long as it fulfills these two imperatives which Kierkegaard requires: a commitment to self-perfection and a commitment to other human beings.66 Rational love, therefore, is very much appropriate for the ethical individual. It is a love of a rational being who “utters the commands of morality to himself.”67 The ethical self is Kant’s autonomous will who acts in practical love. He does not love to become happy but simply for the sake of moral uprightness. To do an act of kindness for the other is morally good; hence, the will affirms it to be a worthy course of action. Rational love, nonetheless, still fails to be an ideal actualization; this is very evident in the limitations of the ethical sphere. Although […] the ethical involves a balance of the aesthetic, the moral and the religious […] there is nevertheless certain harshness in Kierkegaard’s ethical realm. The individual is engaged in a constant self-scrutiny and self-judgment from which there is March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 60 LOVE AS DUTY no reprieve. It is almost more than one can bear. And indeed, Kierkegaard talks about an “ethical despair” that eventually brings the individual to his or her knees.68 The ethical man’s love is often cold and leads to despair. Moreover, rational love does not see the eternal’s mark—the neighbor—in the person. What he rather sees is loveworthiness. “Someone we call a loveworthy man is a man who above all does not take too much to heart eternity’s or God’s requirement for an essential and essentially strenuous life.”69 The ethical man loves the other because reason and morality tells him that it is worthwhile to do so. The ethical individual, therefore, becomes aware of his own self-insufficiency, his sin, guilt and incapacity to conform with the demands of the commandment. In the point of ethical despair and meaninglessness, the individual makes a “leap of faith” to the religious sphere. c. The Religious Sphere: Christian Love (Kierkegaard) The highest form of self-actualization is attained in the religious sphere. And as the individual makes a leap to this sphere his love also achieves the perfection of Christian love. He, therefore, becomes what Kierkegaard calls the “Knight of Faith.” Kierkegaard’s best model for a person who has reached the religious sphere of existence is the biblical character Abraham. Christian love is a love that makes no distinctions. Therefore in some sense, the religious individual who loves according to the commandment leaves the friend and the lover. He does not see them; what he rather perceives is the neighbor. The individual loses himself by an act of self-denial. “True love is self-denial’s love.”70 This selfdenial’s love is the Christian idea of self denial not the human idea of self denial.71 Kierkegaard says, The merely human idea of self denial is this: give up your self-loving desires, cravings and plans – then you will be esteemed and honored and loved as righteous and wise. […] The Christian idea of self-denial is: give March 2011 - Volume 1 LOVE AS DUTY Page 61 up your self-loving desires and cravings, give up your self-seeking plans and purposes so that you truly work unselfishly for the good – and then, for that very reason, put up with being abominated almost as a criminal, insulted and ridiculed.72 The Christian ideal of love is foolishness to reason and an offense to the world.73 This kind of love alone “can open man to the infinite in a way that no mere reasoning can.”74 Thus, Christian love is the highest form of love and the real fulfillment of the divine commandment. The individual fulfills his commitment to humanity and to his God and reaches self-actualization. “We owe all our love to God, but that he commands us to express this in loving our Neighbor; one loves God by loving one’s Neighbor.”75 One is confronted with the fact that one cannot love without divine assistance.76 One rests one’s confidence not upon the power of one’s autonomous will but on God’s hands. “And the man who appropriates and affirms his relationship to God in faith becomes what he really is, the individual before God.”77 Endnotes 1 2 3 4 “Joseph Fletcher would even make it the good. If Fletcher is correct, love is a necessary good, obligatory for those who admit this fact.” Thomas M. Garrett, Problems and Perspectives in Ethics (New York: Sheed and Ward, 1968), 174. Garrett, Problems and Perspectives in Ethics, 173. Ibid., 162. Ibid., 165. 5Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics in Steven M. Cahn and Peter Markie, Ethics: History, Theory, and Contemporary Issues (New York: Oxford University Press, 2002), 167. 6 Ibid. 7Garrett, Problems and Perspectives in Ethics, 169. March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 8 9 62 LOVE AS DUTY Ibid., 164. Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics in Cahn and Markie, Ethics: History, Theory, and Contemporary Issues, 171. 10 Frederick Copleston, S.J., A History of Philosophy Vol. VI Modern Philosophy: From The French Enlightenment to Kant (New York: Doubleday Dell Publishing Group, Inc., 1994), 313. 11 Kant, Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals and What is Enlightenment?, trans. by Lewis White Beck (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill Educational Publishing, 1959), 9. 12 Ibid., 15-16. 13 Kant, Critique of Practical Reason, 104. 14 Alan R. Drengson, “Compassion and Transcendence of Duty and Inclination,” Philosophy Today 25, 1 (Spring 1981), 35. 15 Ibid., 35. 16 Kant, Critique of Practical Reason, 104. 17 Ibid. 18 Ibid. 19 Ibid., 105. 20 Garrett, Problems and Perspectives in Ethics, 160. 21 James Collins, The Mind of Kierkegaard (Chicago: Henry Regnery Company 1953), 175. 22 Ibid., 176. 23 Copleston, A History of Philosophy Vol. VII, 341. 24 Kierkegaard, The Sickness unto Death in Palmer, Kierkegaard for Beginners, 67. Italization is the author’s. 25 Ben Alex, Soren Kierkegaard: An Authentic Life (Copenhagen: Scandinavia Publishing, 1997), 30. 26 Kierkegaard, Works of Love, 52. 27 Ibid. 28 Garrett, Problems and Perspectives in Ethics, 158. 29 Palmer, Looking at Philosophy, 353. 30 Kierkegaard, Works of Love, 54 31 Ibid., 106-107. 32 Alex, Soren Kierkegaard: An Authentic Life, 30. 33 Kierkegaard Works of Love, 77. March 2011 - Volume 1 LOVE AS DUTY Page 63 34 Ibid., 68. 35 Ibid. 36 Ibid., 21. 37 Quinn, “Kierkegaard’s Christian Ethics,” 365. 38 Ibid., 359. 39 Here friendship and erotic love are treated as both preferential love. However, it does not mean that Kierkegaard claims that erotic love is always wrong or that all forms of friendship are selfish, he only points out in the Works of Love that the there are dangers with such kinds of relationships. The problem arises when a man “does not see to it that his wife [or his friend are] to him the neighbor.” Kierkegaard, Works of Love, 141. Pia Sotoft also says, “Many have misread Works of Love by suggesting that Kierkegaard’s view of love between man and woman is negative. If they were right, Kierkegaard would have a problem. But that is not the case. Kierkegaard doesn’t make any judgments here, he just tries to analyze relationships among people, while pointing out the dangers of self-love.” Alex, Soren Kierkegaard: An Authentic Life, 29. 40 Quinn, “Kierkegaard’s Christian Ethics,” 354. 41 Kierkegaard, Works of Love, 52. 42 Ibid., 53. 43 Quinn, “Kierkegaard’s Christian Ethics,” 357. 44 Kierkegaard, Works of Love, 29. 45 Ibid. 46 Ibid., 30. 47 Ibid., 31. 48 Ibid. 49 Ibid. 50 Ibid., 34. Italization is the author’s. “Hate is a love that has become its opposite, a love that has perished [gaae til Grunde]. Down in the ground [I Grunden] the love is continually aflame, but it is the flame of hate; not until the love has burned out is the flame of hate also put out.” 51 Ibid. 52 Quinn, “Kierkegaard’s Christian Ethics,” 355. 53 Kierkegaard, Works of Love, 37. 54 Quinn, “Kierkegaard’s Christian Ethics,” 355. 55 Kierkegaard, Works of Love, 66. March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 64 LOVE AS DUTY 56 Ibid., 40. 57 Ibid, 279. 58 Collins, The Mind of Kierkegaard, 43. 59 Copleston, A History of Philosophy Vol. VII, 342. 60 Palmer, Kierkegaard for Beginners, 80. 61 Kierkegaard, Works of Love, 54. 62 Palmer, Kierkegaard for Beginners, 84. 63 Kierkegaard, Works of Love, 17. 64 Palmer, Kierkegaard for Beginners, 100. 65Copleston, A History of Philosophy Vol. VII, 343. 66Palmer, Kierkegaard for Beginners, 102. 67MacIntyre, A Short History of Ethics, 194. 68 Palmer, Kierkegaard for Beginners, 108. 69 Kierkegaard, Works of Love, 370. 70 Ibid., 369. 71 Ibid., 194. 72 Ibid. 73 Quinn, “Kierkegaard’s Christian Ethics,” 362. 74 Garrett, Problems and Perspective in Ethics, 169. 75 Kirmmse, Kierkegaard in Golden Age Denmark in Quinn, “Kierkegaard’s Christian Ethics,” 363. 76 Kierkegaard, Works of Love, 24. Italization is the author’s. 77Copleston, A History of Philosophy Vol. VII, 343. March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 65 “Thus Spoke Zarathustra” on Nihilism JOHN ZERNAN B. LUNA It is very embarrassing to think that a great thinker like Friedrich Nietzsche is often recalled on account of his seemingly radical atheism, as per his declaration ‘God is dead.’ Sadly, mainstream criticisms have, more often than not, boxed him under this label, preventing further exploration of the richness of this philosophy. Be it as it may, our current philosophical studies are now rising from such shame and attempting to revive the murdered ideas. The bookshelf of our knowledge requires a much awaited space for new thinkers; the kind that will boost our awareness of what our world today needs, what society today needs. Philosophy after philosophy, resolve after resolve, our quest to understand Being, that fountain of existence, and to understand the meaning of life and of the universe, has led us to countless ideas none of which seems to satisfy our thirst, our human thirst for reason. Let this paper be further satiation, albeit a temporary one, an offering of enlightenment to anyone who wants a taste of something new, something light and worth appreciating. Nietzsche is a positive thinker, this the writer guarantees, and the guide for such thought is none other than the very book with which he was, though not completely, condemned for: ‘Thus Spoke Zarathustra.’ It is with hope of considering Nietzsche under a new light that this paper is written. Man cannot afford to disregard even the most dangerously provocative ideas, if he is to find meaning during his short life-span. It may be that Nietzsche is just one among the many drabbles in the classroom, though it pains to excuse such a possibility. But no drabble would be so irrelevant if it directs attention to a deeper sense of things. Although wide in the contexts with which Nietzsche tackles, this paper will focus solely on an exposition of aforementioned particular book. Nevertheless, what is need is a singular line of thought through which a discipline of interpretation will be guided. The primary foundation of this paper is Bernard Reginster’s book, ‘The Affirmation of Life.’ It is March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 66 “Thus Spoke Zarathustra” on Nihilism impossible to exhaust an explanation on how this book is relevant in considering Nietzschean mindset. Although much of the same context in the book has been tackled before Reginster, it offers the most up-todate discussions. True to its name, the book tackles on how Nietzsche affirms life in his attempt to overcome nihilism. The basis for such an account is what the philosopher’s central project is: something that can be found in (almost) all his writings. This project concerns nihilism: its effects on contemporary European ideals and its future implications on mankind. Although Nietzsche’s ‘The Will to Power’ offers the most extensive discussions about nihilism, it is also with considerable weight that the book of Zarathustra tackles the same concern. Note, however, that most of the references that will be made are on the first two parts of the book- the writer believes it provides sufficient passages for the purpose of this paper. 1. Return to the Earth Among the many things with which Nietzsche is often accused of is his blatant and apparent attack on religion, particularly the one which stands on the Judeo-Christian Tradition. ‘Thus Spoke Zarathustra’ is no exception from this, and it is not only on account of the passage ‘God is dead.’ More than that, the book deals on what it refers to as the Afterwordly1. Another passage in the prologue says “To sin against the earth is the most dreadful thing, and to esteem the entrails of the unknowable higher than the meaning of the earth,”2 which also tramples any religious claim of any sort like a name for God, a world in the after life, ethereal truths and the like. Needless to say, there is an aspect of religion that seems to provoke aggression on the part of Nietzsche. The book in concern here does not show grace in expressing this, but the specific aspect with which Zarathustra seems to dwell is on, as stated, the afterwordly. A chapter in the first of four parts of the book is entitled as such. True to their title, people of ‘after worldly’ disposition concern themselves to anything beyond the world that is known, that is, a material world. In the narrowest of understanding, they are priests3 who designate existence on the basis of an ambiguous reality, something that cannot be conferred by any faculty or instrument. The March 2011 - Volume 1 “Thus Spoke Zarathustra” on Nihilism Page 67 attack with which the said chapter in the book proceeds touches on both the doctrine and the teacher. It may seem from the outset that Nietzsche is simply perverting what is held of much value on the part of the religious lot, which is tantamount to devaluating it. Once a particular reality of a person is devaluated, it will no longer have any authority on the part of the person, and the moral judgment that depends once depends on such conventional reality will be, in a way, set free on its own. The truth of the matter is that these priests lie is a dangerous ground, Nietzsche would say. They stand on the idea that there is something beyond this world that speaks of the purpose of man, and they seem to claim the way, the only way to it. What is dangerous is the fact that with little or no way of proving nor of denying the existence of such reality means a firm hold on what a priest says require much defensive stance. In other words, someone who knows he is protecting something vulnerable, and is firmly resolved to such protection, is always willing to resort to measures even as drastic as murder. Add the fact that there is fear on account of said person that should he fail to protect this doctrine of the other world, he will lose his soul. Doubt, it would mean, is a grave sin on the part of a believer. This complicated process entails the birth of a religious fanatic, which is not rare in modern society. There is another aspect to this. What is of utmost urgent concern is the condition through which the Overman is to be realized. In order to do this, people must, in a way, ‘Make straight his way.’ The problem of the after world does not only point to the dangerous fanatic. There is, in a graver matter, the need to reconsider the value of the world today. Consider the scenario of the ascension as found in the Synoptic Gospels of the Judeo-Christian Scriptures. It is said there that as Jesus was no longer seen in the sky and as the apostles were still at awe at the powerful revelation, an angel had to come down and instruct them to go on with their lives. In a way, that is what Nietzsche tries to snap out of the religious lot. There is simply too much work to be done right here, right now, that a time to refer to another world is not affordable. A person who claims he knows there is heaven but does not know earth is not a real human person, Nietzsche would say. March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 68 “Thus Spoke Zarathustra” on Nihilism People should not look at the sky- at least not for the whole of their lives. The demands of the ground is commitment to it, to toil and work, to wage war, to discover and develop- in truth, Nietzsche knows that we still need to make this world a better place- we have no time to talk about heaven. The nihilistic context4 of the doctrine of the after world is what is referred to as ‘despair’. Despair is a form of nihilism wherein the state of such disposition realizes that the world in which he lives does not allow the actualization of his values. Take for example a person who wants to be a doctor, but the society in which he lives does not allow, or does not recognize the need for doctors to be trained. Such person will most likely fall into nihilistic despair. Zarathustra accuses the priests of directing the will of the people into a world other the one that would instantiate the Overman. More importantly, the priests actually made the world in which man lives in inhospitable to his values. The same chapter of the after worldly discusses the root of this doctrine to the unrealizability of what its creators hold with much value.5 “It was suffering and incapacity that created all after-worlds.”6 Suffering connotes another devaluation, that is, the devaluation of the human self. Whatever suffering it was that led to the creation of such doctrine hardly matters, because obviously enough, every suffering has that unacceptable state of displeasure to the status quo, it is not mainly physical suffering.7 Nevertheless, it was the priests, those after worldly people, who first fell to nihilistic despair which eventually triggered our alienation from the necessary condition of the earth for the realization of the Overman. The earth is the arena for the overman to rise. Under Spartan code the king is the survivor of a brutal ordeal of skill and wit, after which his words become supreme, and Sparta will be led into glory. Should human feet keep on trying to escape this valley of tears he calls the material world, it will never actualize its worth, the Overman will not find its place on the face of humanity. Man must return to the earth. 2. Man and the Necessity of God’s Death As far as Nietzsche is concerned there is much about man that needs to be reconsidered; thus the whole point about the many books he March 2011 - Volume 1 “Thus Spoke Zarathustra” on Nihilism Page 69 has written. The same disposition has led the countless philosophical projects in recorded history the motion that it has taken. Simply put, it would appear that the whole point of philosophizing is to realize the existential identity of man. If existence precedes essence, and man is this existence, what kind of existence? “Man is something that shall be overcome. What have you done to overcome him?”8, thus goes a celebrated passage in the book. Self-overcoming is not exclusive to Nietzschean philosophy. There have been many schools of thought which demanding this sort of ‘transcending of one’s self.’ However, there is an aspect of Nietzsche’s version of transcendence which is different from the rest. The usual emphasis of transcendence would be going beyond limits- not succumbing to lower appetites, doing more than what is necessary, going beyond the boarders of bodily capacities, and the like practices. Thus Spoke Zarathustra teaches transcendence while considering all these as essential features9but there is another requirement. This would be referred to as ‘transvaluation.’ Nietzsche is not a nihilist; he is not counted among those who consider the non-existence of values, nor of the inability of the world to make such values possible. It is therefore surprising that he is often times considered as a devaluator, hence a precursor of nihilism. However, this would be very difficult to accept if we consider the famous passage ‘God is dead.’ God, for apparent reasons, represents the value of religion. And religion, if it is to be taken as a creation of man, represents a value which he has imposed upon himself- a spiritual value. This value has grown to a point where it has shaped civilizations. Meaning to say, more often than not, religion is the very discipline which evolutionary man has used to humanize his existence on the face of the earth. Insofar, however, as values are concerned, religion pretty much has limited the very valuation of man. In the context of ‘The Genealogy of Morals’ Nietzsche provides how the valuation of the priests has affected and continues to contribute on what we know today as our valuations; kindness, mercy, gentleness, justice, etc. These are nothing more than inverted values of the noble race. “The noble virtues of courage, self-confidence and intelligence [now] became the vices of cruelty, arrogance and pride”10, that is, to name a few. Religion has played a significant role in inverting the values of the nobles which were once the values standing on the ground of power. March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 70 “Thus Spoke Zarathustra” on Nihilism The Overman, as what Zarathustra echoes across the whole of parts three and four of the book, does not stand on values other than that which he creates11. This necessarily means that he has to go beyond the values that conventional authority has imposed on him, specifically one that is held by religion. No religion holds any moral authority other than which it declares to have come from an incontestable being, which it has named ‘God’. The impact, then, of having declared the death of God is understood in the context with which religion has concentrated its moral authority. What Zarathustra actually meant is that the dawn of the Overman entails the destruction of conventional values created by religion.12 God had to die, Nietzsche would say, because we have to let go of all that limits the actualization of our ultimate self. God is the embodiment of religion, and unless man finally lets it go, he will never be able to realize the possibility of the Overman. It has been noted that a form of nihilism is despair; that the world in which a person lives in does not allow the instantiation of the values which he holds. There is another form, and this completes the idea of Nietzschean nihilism, according to Bernard Reginster. The two relevant aspects of nihilism is that first there has to be a value held, and second there has to be a condition through which such values are realized. Despair allows no such condition, which means a person lives in a world that does not set the condition for his values. Now in the case wherein there is a condition, or that the world allows for the realization of such values, but the values themselves loses their ‘value’, that is to say their being worth pursuing, such nihilism is called ‘disorientation.’ Following the example used earlier, it could be that a person pursuing medicine finds available training, and the society in which he lives gives worth to such practice, which means what he values is esteemed. But in a state of disorientation, the person would see medicine as no longer worth pursuing, for one reason or another. What is relevant here is that there was once something valued, something affecting the moral judgment of a person, something being pursued, but for some reason the person finds at some point such value as no longer worth pursuing. The case may be that being a doctor loses its appeal, or any like factor. Regardless, once a person March 2011 - Volume 1 “Thus Spoke Zarathustra” on Nihilism Page 71 loses sight of the worth of a value, hence losing such value altogether, he is in a state of disorientation. 3. Deicide and the Overman: Purpose Driven The danger of nihilism lies in the disposition to which it takes man. Such disposition is completely devoid of any purpose, of any reason to live. Imagine a world where everybody is in such state. Simply put, ‘why’ will not have any answer for anyone. That is why it is important for a person to keep his feet on the ground, and to realize the need to transcend the values he has imposed on himself. Otherwise, nihilism will be the only consequence left for him. If the world in which we live gains a new value, it will be a place worth living. And so long as a person lives in such a world there is a greater possibility of realizing the overman. Man should not be ashamed of himself because he can grow beyond himself, and he should know this better than what the cruel dictates of religion would impose. What’s the big deal about God’s death, then? It’s not really about God, it’s about what he seems to represent. Often times he will be used to justify things which are tantamount to making excuses for personal incapability. At other times he will be pointed to when a certain kind of suffering makes it way. Regardless, he stands for something that has made man lazy on the face of existence. Whether or not Nietzsche really was a radical atheist is beyond accurate consideration. But true to his project, the writer believes that Nietzsche would’ve tapped on anything so long as it instantiates a reason for man to keep on holding on to a certain value, hence continue on living. The Overman gives man a reason, something to make him always attempt to outgrow himself, to transcend... even to the point of going beyond the God which the society around him has created. March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 72 “Thus Spoke Zarathustra” on Nihilism Endnotes 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 The first essay of ‘The Genealogy of Morals’ deals with the same subject, but under a different term. What concerns Nietzsche more in this essay is the impact of the priests, that is, the divinization of suffering, and the transformation of ‘bad’ to ‘evil’. Such transformation required the priests to teach the doctrine of a ‘spiritual reality,’ sort to speak. Friedrich Nietzsche, Thus Spoke Zarathustra, (Penguin Books Inc. USA, 1996), p 13. Chapter 4 of the Second Part (Walter Kaufman ed.,) deals extensively on Zarathustra’s perspective of the priests. (p. 90). Nihilism is traditionally understood as synonymous to nothingness. This is rather broad and uncritical. According to Bernard Reginster, a form of nihilism requires a set of values, and a condition with which such values are actualized. The form will depend on the absence or disregard of any one of these elements. “Among them, too, there are heroes; many of them have suffered too much therefore they want to make others suffer.” –On Priests, p 91. Thus Spoke Zarathustra, p 31. On account of those who seem to claim pleasure in self-inflicted suffering (masochists, sadists, etc.), the idea of Nietzsche applies only in so far that it is not actually the state of suffering which gives them pleasure but the state of pain, or the absence of a certain pleasure. Suffering in its strictest sense means an encounter of a total devaluation of something significant to another person. Thus Spoke Zarathustra, p 12. If a plausible division of the book shall be made, the writer believes that the first part of the book together with a greater portion of the second part deals with exposing what self-overcoming necessitates, while the rest of the book deals with actual actualizations of over-coming. 10 Julian Young, Nietzsche’s Philosophy of Religion, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006) p 149. 11 “And however must be a creator in good and evil, verily, he must first March 2011 - Volume 1 “Thus Spoke Zarathustra” on Nihilism Page 73 be an annihilator and break values. Thus the highest evil belongs to the highest goodness; but this is creative.” –On Self-Overcoming, p116. 12 “Everything that the good call evil must come together so that one truth may be born. O my brothers, are you evil enough for this truth? The audacious daring, the long mistrust, the cruel No, the disgusting, the cutting into the living- how rarely does all this come together. But from such seed is truth begotten. Alongside the bad conscience, all science has grown so far. Break, break, you lovers of knowledge, the old tablets.” – On Old and New Tablets, p200. Sources Thus Spoke Zarathustra: a book for none and all, Walter Kaufman trans., (Penguin Books USA Inc., 1996). The Birth of Tragedy and The Genealogy of Morals, Francis Golffing trans., (New York: Anchor Books Doubleday, 1956). Reginster, Bernard, The Affirmation of Life, (Cambridge, M.A.: Harvard University Press, 2006). ________, “Nietzsche on Ressentiment and Valuation,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 57, 2, (June, 1997) 281-305. Zeitlin, Irving, Nietzsche; a Re-Examination, (Cambridge: Oxford Polity Press, 1994). Young, Julian, Nietzsche’s Philosophy of Religion, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006). March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 74 A PHILOSOPHICAL ANALYSIS OF THE NATURE OF DESIRE DANIEL A. DOMINGUEZ 1. Introduction Philosophers throughout history have been interested in the nature of human desires and its relevance to society and morality. Desire is an innate human reality. It affects our actions, our judgments, and our way of living. In order for the readers to have a better understanding of human desires, I will present its general meaning in terms of its nature and dynamics, as well as the two contemporary models and the interpretations of some philosophers, followed by some moral question based on Aristotle and Mortimer Adler’s perspectives. 2. Nature of Desire Desire is an impulse towards an object or experience that promises or guarantees enjoyment or satisfaction in its attainment. It is a part of the human passions which constitute human reality. Every desire has its object, which the subject usually lacks. Desire cannot be self-enclosed.1 In other words, desire is desire for something; it reaches beyond itself.2 In a negative sense, it is an unfulfillment; in a positive stance, it is an anticipation of something that can satiate a lack or unfulfillment. The negative, thus, solicits the positive. When the negative impulse aggravates, the anticipation becomes obsessive. The intensity of the emptiness inside becomes congruent with the obsession outside. The more a person is hungry, the more he becomes obsessed with food, which is the object of this hunger. Moreover, desire is related to motivation. When a person desires something, he will normally be motivated to pursue what he desires. March 2011 - Volume 1 PHILOSOPHICAL ANALYSIS OF THE NATURE OF DESIRE Page 75 3. Dynamics of Desire There are two kinds of desires: (1) innate or natural desires and (2) conditioned or artificial desires.3 Natural desires are desires that one naturally manifests within human conditions, such as food, sex, drink, knowledge, friendship, and beauty. Artificial desires are desires that are dictated to us by our environment or by society. Good examples of artificial desires are gadgets, wealth, and commercial luxuries. Natural desires are derived from within, from our human nature while artificial desires, on the contrary, arise from external influences. The existence of the object of desire depends upon the kind of desire one has. Natural desires have their real objects. The desire for food entails for an existence of food. Artificial desires, on the other hand, may or may not entail the actual existence of their object. Some people may desire to buy limousines, and limousines do exist. Others may desire for a so-called “flying train” which appears in many films today but they do not exist in reality. Unlike artificial desires, our natural desires are grounded in our human existence. The lack expressed by natural desires is geared toward fulfillment in life. Desire, in this context, becomes desire for life. The desire for life is a manifestation of the instinct to struggle for survival which is inherent to all human beings. This explains why natural desires are first in order compared to artificial desires, although today there are distortions such as greed, selfishness, and an emphasis on artificial worldly desires over natural desires in our socio-economic structures. In the fulfillment of desire, there are two movements: satisfaction and departure. When one is hungry, he yearns for food. After being fulfilled in eating, his desire for food ends. Thus, one finds in these processes a homeostatic model4: the desire disappears when the desire is satisfied. This homeostatic model, however, is different from desiring pleasure. Pleasure is often equated with happiness. There is, however, a decline in happiness when the pursuit of pleasure is repeatedly attained. Say for instance, a person desires for ice cream. Once he attains the object of his desire, he obtains pleasure from it, and therefore he becomes happy. But when his desire for ice cream exceeds what can please him, he may not become happy. March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 76 PHILOSOPHICAL ANALYSIS OF THE NATURE OF DESIRE A paradoxical characteristic of desire is its infinitude. Man has an infinite number of desires. After he attains a desirable object, he has the tendency to be dissatisfied again, and he strives for the same object again. Yet, on the larger scheme, man’s simple desires are inclined to generate complex desires. For example, a man purchases for himself a desktop computer. He is satisfied at having one but eventually becomes dissatisfied with it at another time. When he is no longer satisfied with his desktop, he desires a better version or buys a laptop. After some time, he again becomes discontented. He then opts for a palm desktop. Whichever the case, there is a sense of infinitude in the desires that man possesses. 4. Two Contemporary Models of Desire Before linking the concept of desire to the history of philosophy, let us first examine two contrasting views on desire which are predominant in the twentieth century. These two views serve as the foundation of the historical account of the notion of desire in the realm of philosophy. Namely, these are desire as sex (Freudian) and desire as power (Hegelian).5 Sex or the libido is a particular energy or drive for the object of one’s desire. It is characterized as affective yet often out of control. It is ecstatic – it takes one outside oneself. The desire to surrender to the other implies a concomitant desire not to overpower the other. Conversely, power emerges out of concrete relationships in society. It is a result of the distinction between a master and a slave, as expounded by Hegel and Nietzsche. Power invokes desire to dominate and control others. Moreover, power allows us to achieve self-consciousness at the same time.6 The desire for sex can aggravate and become a desire for power. In sexual relation, when the desire instigates control over the other as it is not supposed to, it becomes excessive. Thus, this libidinal desire is translated into a form of power. Although the dichotomy between desire for power and desire for sex dominate the twentieth century discussion on the philosophy of desire, it serves as the threshold into the historical account of the notion of desire, which has been an apparent issue since the dawn of March 2011 - Volume 1 PHILOSOPHICAL ANALYSIS OF THE NATURE OF DESIRE Page 77 ancient Greek philosophy. The concept of desire as an antecedent for sex and power traces its roots from the dialogues of Plato, Socrates, and a number of Sophists. 5. Philosophers and Their Notion of Desire In this section, I will discuss the philosophical roots of the discussion on desire, focusing on the essential points. We begin from the time of the ancient Greeks. The sophist Polus equates desires with power. He affirms that the aim of rhetoric is to acquire power. Thus, he concludes that a successful orator can do anything he desires.7 The greater the desires one has, the more he becomes powerful in society. Socrates, in this regard, refutes Polus by saying that inasmuch as man can do whatever he desires, he may opt not do the things he desires. Callicles, another sophist, asserts that the supreme good is the power to satisfy all desires. Socrates disagrees with Callicles by saying that it is impossible for one to satisfy all his desires. Human desires are unlimited, and if they are unlimited, it is impossible to satisfy them all. Therefore, desires can be satisfied only when they are limited.8 Plato’s discussion of desire is highlighted in his concept of έρως (literally, “eros”), which can be found in the Symposium. Ερως is casually translated as “love,” but in its original context, it is rather the halfway between love and desire. The pre-Socratic philosophers apply this term for whatever impulses drive all beings in nature toward their goals as well as for the specifically human impulse to grasp and to possess.9 Aristophanes explains έρως with the use of a myth. According to him, men originally had four arms and four legs, like two human beings tied up together in a single body. These entities, who are clever and strong, became a threat to the Greek gods. In an attempt not to be overpowered by such beings, the gods separated men into two. Thus, men became half-beings, and as such, man continuously searches for the being who will complete him as he journeys through life. Eρως, in this context, is a desire for what one does not possess. The lover is a man who is unsatisfied, and therefore he strives to search for the one who shall eventually satisfy his existence. The priestess Diotima teaches that έρως is a desire that cannot be satisfied by any particular object in the world. The lover ascends from March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 78 PHILOSOPHICAL ANALYSIS OF THE NATURE OF DESIRE the love of particular beautiful entities (objects and persons) to the love of beauty itself, which is virtually the good that the soul desires. Our desires should lead toward the pursuit of the good. The difficulty in Plato is that he identifies the good to the world of Forms, which can never be found in ordinary encounters in life. The notion of desire gradually changed during the Renaissance. Desire became understood as the pursuit of knowledge – knowledge of one’s self, of bodies, of society, and of the universe. The knowledge of such contributes to the achievement of arts, sciences, and politics. Hence, personal desires must conform to higher desires of knowledge. Many times, the pursuit for knowledge demands a will for control and power in order to attain such end. Hobbes speaks of desire as any endeavor towards or away from an object that causes that endeavor. Since desires are causes for actions, they are considered as motions. Desire, in a narrow sense, is similar to appetite. Aversion is also an appetite. In a broad sense, aversion is a desire away from the object that causes the desire. Hobbes oftentimes confuses desire in the narrow sense (that is, appetite) with love and pleasure (voluptas), and aversion with hate or annoyance (molestia). Thus, his concept of desire contributes to his mechanistic view of man and society, which is summed up in the proposition that man is but a body in motion. By the 17th century, desire is identified with passion. For empiricists like David Hume, the knowledge of one’s passions will enable one to attain self-knowledge. Jean-Jacques Rousseau deals with feelings in his social doctrine of man. He speaks of feelings as intermediary between reason and experience.10 Feelings are reflections of one’s true self. Understanding one’s feelings allows one to understand oneself. Selfconsciousness, therefore, comprises reason, experience, and feeling. In this regard, desire fully expresses itself through feelings. 6. The Ethical Problem of Desires from the Viewpoint of Aristotle and Adler Plato’s notion of the good, which consists in the contemplation of the good, presents a dilemma that gives less emphasis on human desires. March 2011 - Volume 1 PHILOSOPHICAL ANALYSIS OF THE NATURE OF DESIRE Page 79 Aristotle proposes a solution to this. He incorporates the concept of desire with his notion of good. Doing good, for Aristotle, does not only entail the knowledge of the good, but also, the desire to do it. Desire is an important element in knowing and doing the good. It functions between knowledge and action.11 It is not a form of love, an emotion itself, or a drive or passion for a particular object or person; rather, desire pertains to a kind of power over oneself and one’s emotions. In this context, desire entails self-control and mastery over bodily pleasures. Mortimer J. Adler (1902-2001), a proponent of Aristotelian ethics, states that there are two kinds of desires: natural and acquired desires. Natural desires are desires intrinsic to human nature. Acquired desires are desires that are influenced by man’s social environment or circumstances. Natural desires can be classified as “needs” or real goods, while acquired desires are “wants” or apparent goods. For Adler, desires can be problematic especially when one wants more than what one needs. Real goods refer to goods that ought to be desired, whether one actually and consciously desires them, since they are perceived as good to us. Examples of real goods are basic biological needs in order to survive – food, drink, shelter, and clothing. On the other hand, “wants” or apparent goods are considered desires insofar as one can actually desire them, even if they cannot be good for us. The question posed here is how can man realize the ultimate end of his desires, given that there is such distinction between real and apparent goods. Going back to Aristotle, the answer is happiness, and happiness (understood as the totum bonum) should be the content of every man’s telos. Desires that are properly grounded in the pursuit of the good will enable one to attain one’s ultimate happiness. This is what Adler refers to as right desires.12 Then, what are wrong desires? Adler points out three roots for wrong desires. The first root is when a desire is only a partial good, yet is desired as if it were the only or total good. The second root is when desire is taken as an ultimate end, and not as a means to the totum bonum. The third root is when the object of desire is actually evil or harmful. Wrong desires may involve money and pleasure. Money is important in day to day life, but it becomes a wrong desire once it is March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 80 PHILOSOPHICAL ANALYSIS OF THE NATURE OF DESIRE treated as a desire in itself or a complete good thus leading to selfserving purposes. Pleasure is important as a means to acquire the good, but it can be desired wrongly in the same manner that it can be desired rightly. In general, the distinction between right and wrong desires are important in the study of moral acts because the good zeroes in right desires, while the bad is rooted in wrong desires. That is why Adler recognizes Aristotle’s need of virtue. Virtue is the moderation between the excess and the lack, and therefore virtue is needed for the proper orientation of human desires. Aside from the practice of virtues, one has to desire the ultimate purpose of all goods – the totum bonum or the ultimate good, and not just the partial or temporal goods which include wealth, power and desire. 7. Conclusion Desires are important in the realm of philosophy. They are related to our understanding of society and of morality. In this paper, I have laid down the nature and dynamics of desire, as well as its problem in the history of philosophy. Nevertheless, the problem lies on to the readers. Can one’s life be dictated by his desires? Or can one masters over his desires? The most important matter in this regard is that one should be able to properly channel his desires in his pursuit of genuine happiness or ultimate fulfillment. Desires are innate to man. They speak of the inner stirrings of man. It depends on man as to how he can integrate his desires with his being. Endnotes 1 2 William Desmond, Desire, Dialectic, and Otherness: An Essay on Origins (New Haven and London: Yale University Press, 1987), 18. Ibid. March 2011 - Volume 1 PHILOSOPHICAL ANALYSIS OF THE NATURE OF DESIRE Page 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 81 cf. Peter J. Kreeft, “C. S. Lewis’s Argument from Desire,” G. K. Chesterton and C. S. Lewis: The Riddle of Joy, ed. Michael H. MacDonald and Andrew A. Tadie (Grand Rapids, MI: William B. Eerdsman, 1989), 250. See footnote in Joseph J. Godfrey, A Philosophy of Human Hope (Dordrecht, Netherlands: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, 1987), 16. “Homeostatic” here includes both resolution to zero-level tension and resolution to optimum-level tension (not necessarily “zero”). Hugh J. Silverman, ed., Philosophy and Desire (New York: Routledge Publishing, 2000), 1. Ibid., 1. cf. Alasdair MacIntyre, A Short History of Ethics (New York: The Macmillan Company, 1966), 28. cf. MacIntyre, 30. Ibid., 52. 10 Silverman, ed., Philosophy and Desire, 6. 11 Ibid., 4. 12 cf. Mortimer J. Adler, Desires: Right and Wrong – The Ethics of Enough (New York: Macmillan Publishing Company, 1991), 36. March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 82 Semantics and the Transformational Generative Grammar An Interconnection 1. Introduction BRYAN JOSEPH V. RODRIGUEZ Chomsky has been known in the field of linguistics for his development of the Universal Grammar and the Transformational Generative Grammar. His theory has even become a revolution in the field of linguistics named after him. He is said to be one of the linguists who tried to formalize the study of language, i.e., studying language without semantic reference. With this, a great number of misconceptions have arisen, one of which is the misconception about his so-called “distaste for semantics.”1 Before this discussion proceeds, it should first be clarified that this study acknowledges the fact that in forming a linguistic theory, it is possible that grammar can be independently studied from the sense of the sentence under study. This is evident in the second chapter of his Syntactic Structures. However, the study of reference and meaning, especially that of lexical entries, is necessary for studying grammar. Another fact that should be recognized is that in the Syntactic Structures, there is no statement about formal semantics, unlike in many of his books such as the Studies of Semantics in Generative Grammar, Aspects Theory of Syntax and The Minimalist Program, wherein he explicitly shows the surface structure and the deep structure. In the later development of the theory, this refers to the phonemic form and the logical form, wherein the phonemic form is the grammatical component of an utterance of a particular language and the logical form is the semantic component. The proofs of the interconnection of semantics to the Transformational Generative Grammar, from which the misconception arises, are to be discussed in the following sections. March 2011 - Volume 1 Semantics and THE Transformational Generative Grammar Page 83 2. Intelligibility of the Parts of Speech Traditionally, grammar, as in composition, can be studied, like in for example the English language, through the relation of words and their arrangement in a particular sequence within a sentence.2 However, although the morphemes of a sentence are limited, words of a particular language are indefinite. Linguistic theory will be fundamentally impossible if these indefinite set of words are individually related to each other, i.e., certain rule has to be set in order to determine the words precede and succeed it. Thus, if the words are not classified according to their functions, then, there would be indefinite set of rules, depending upon the number of words a particular language has. Consequently, the first task of linguistic theory is to classify the words according to their function. Thus, parts of speech are formed to easily identify the function of a word in a given sentence. Every word can thus be classified among the eight parts of speech: Noun, Pronoun, Verb, Adjective, Adverb, Conjunction, Preposition and Interjection.3 Few of these are used by the structuralist tradition of the Phrase-Structure and of Chomsky’s Transformational Generative Grammar. This classification by function has its source in the meaning of the word. Take for example the word “ball” in the sentence “The man hit the ball.” The phrase “the ball” is a noun phrase made up of an article (T->the) and a noun (N->ball). Not all words can substitute the noun in the NP->T + N. At a first glance, this process (substitution or rewrite) is very structural; however, a deeper analysis of the process could lead one to the notion that it has appeal to the study of meaning and reference. In order for a word to be a noun (thus be substitutable to N) it should be able to fulfill the description of a noun, i.e., name of people, place or thing.4 Thus, the reference and meaning of the word “ball” should first be known to the speaker before one can use the word as a noun. Hence, determining the meaning of the word “ball,” as a name for an object that is round or of roundish body or mass, thus, a name of an object, could suffice for substituting it to N. This is a clear proof of Chomsky’s claim of semantics’ connection with grammar, in the intelligibility of the parts of speech. However, this is an account of mere nominalization or naming; it is concerned merely with lexical items which, in themselves, have semantic characterization.5 March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 84 Semantics and THE Transformational Generative Grammar 3. Intelligibility of Transformations applied In the previous section, the concern is on the morphemic level which can be taken as one of the proofs of relevance of semantics to grammar. From hereon, the concern will be on the level of sentences and their formation. One of Chomsky’s concrete arguments for the inadequacy of phrasestructure is that of the notion of constituency. In his examples which can also be seen below, sentences (1a-b) can yield sentence (2) through conjunction. (1) (a) the scene—of the movie—was in Chicago (b) the scene—of the play—was in Chicago (2) the scene—of the movie and of the play—was in Chicago6 This is possible since sentences (1a), which can be referred to as S1, and (1b), which can be referred to as S2, are both grammatical sentences of English and differs only slightly from each other such that X appears in S1 as S1=A—X—B and Y appears in S2 as S2=A—Y—B, where X and Y are constituents of the same type in S1 and S2 respectively. The resultant sentence of the conjunction (2), which can be referred to as S3, is then a sentence derived from combining S1 and S2 thus yielding S3=A—X and Y—B.7 However, this transformation is not possible for sentences (3a-b), thus cannot yield sentence (4). Although it has, in fact, fulfilled the requirements for the conjunction of two sentences, such result for the transformation applied is not a grammatical sentence of English. (3) (a) the scene—of the movie—was in Chicago (b) the scene—that I wrote—was in Chicago (4) the scene—of the movie and that I wrote—was in Chicago 8 The elements that can be substituted to variables X and Y in S1=A— X—B, S2=A—Y—B and S3=A—X + and + Y—B in this example is not clear. The clarity of the variables used in the transformations effected to strings depends upon the constituency of the variables X and Y, March 2011 - Volume 1 Semantics and THE Transformational Generative Grammar Page 85 i.e., they need to be of the same type. Here, it seems that semantics is necessary to trace the course of determining X and Y. This, however, does not mean that semantics is confined to the convention-based. Rather, these sentences (3a-b) originate from what can be called the kernel. What has been demonstrated here is the fact that the semantic component of a structure is necessary in performing the transformation to a grammatical sentence in English. (5) (a) The movie has a scene. (b) The scene was in Chicago. (6) (a) I wrote a scene. (b) The scene was in Chicago. The sentences above (5a) and (6a) are not the same. These are sentences where X and Y are derived according to how each sentence is to be understood. Thus, the variables X and Y of the sentences (5ab), respectively, are not of the same constituents. Another argument for the relation of semantics to grammar, particularly to the Transformational Generative Grammar is the Tobsep. There are two structural analyses which operate the same transformation or structural change, i.e., X1–X2–X3–X4 -> X1–X2–X4–X3. This consists of either V1-> V+Prt or V2-> V+Comp. Given the sentences “Everyone in the lab considers John incompetent.“ and “The police brought him in.”9, the structure of these sentences can be analyzed as: Sentence -> X—V—Y In the first sentence, wherein X->NP­1 and Y->NP2, “NP1 = everyone + in + the + lab and NP2 = John.”10 (7) “Sentence -> X—Va—Comp—Y”11 Sentence -> Everyone in the lab—considers—incompetent— John Thus, transformation begins in this part. This has the effect of interchanging the third and the fourth segments of the string to which it applies.12 Thus yielding: March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 86 Semantics and THE Transformational Generative Grammar (8) Sentence -> X—V­a—Y—Comp13 Sentence -> Everyone in the lab—considers—John— incompetent (Everyone in the lab considers John incompetent.) In the second sentence, NP is composed of Pronoun instead of the article + Noun. Thus, the formula might as well be substituted. (9) Sentence -> X—V1—Prt—Pronoun Sentence -> The police—brought—in—him Thus, transformation begins in this part. This has the effect same as the example identical to this structural analysis, i.e., interchanging the third and the fourth segments of the string to which it applies. Thus yielding: (10) Sentence -> X—V1—Pronoun—Prt14 Sentence -> The police—brought—him—in (The police brought him in.) What makes the two structural analyses distinct from one another are their verbs (V1 and V2) which bring a particle (Prt) and a complement (Comp) respectively. Hence the structural change made to any sentence that has the same structural analysis as the two above, is in itself, ambiguous. Hence, the only possible way to determine whether a sentence that takes a structural change as above is to identify a particle or a complement in reference to the word, particle or complement, and its function to the verb. This distinction is necessary for Tobsep to be intelligible. For if not, neither of the two structural analyses will be intelligible, and in result, any transformation that can occur to one of the two Tobsep can occur to the other. Such case would lead to confusion whether a sentence should provide a Tobsep (Prt) or Tobsep (Comp). Last of these proofs is put in sentences (11a-b). (11) (a) The book is interesting. (b) The child is sleeping. March 2011 - Volume 1 Semantics and THE Transformational Generative Grammar Page 87 Here, it might be seen that a possible nominalizing transformation of T­adj may occur to (11a). Thus, applying the Tadj, converts sentences (11a-b) into (12a-b). Observing the sentences above, (11a) appears to bear a similarity in structure with sentence (11b). And thus the same structural analyses can be effected: Tadj. (12) (a) The interesting book (b) The sleeping child The competent speaker-hearer of the English language will recognize that both “interest” and “sleep” can be taken as verbs. However, the words “interesting” and “sleeping” are different. “Interesting” is an adjective while “sleeping” remains to be a verb.15 Thus, In the given examples above, (11a) can be analyzed as S-> NP+V+Adj, while (11b) can be analyzed as NP+C+be—ing+V, where the transformation follows Af+v-> v+Af#. A support to this claim is to place the word ‘very’ as a test for each instance. This word only appears in modifying adjectives as for example in very tall, very old, etc. Here sentence (13b) is not a grammatical English sentence, unlike (13a). (13) (a) The book is very interesting. (b) The child is very sleeping. ‘Very’ appears in the occurrences of adjectives and adverbs as a modifier, but it, it cannot appear within any verbs. This peculiarity of the occurrences of the word “very,” and the like, does not only happen in the structure, but also in its function of modification.16 Modification cannot be identified within the structure alone; rather the function that the word takes identifies its proper meaning and reference. 4. Clarification In the Syntactic Structures, it is acknowledged that, there is no semantic reference, in creating a grammar, or the formation of grammar is not based on meaning of the sentence. It may thus appear that a basic foundation of this grammar is that it does not appeal March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 88 Semantics and THE Transformational Generative Grammar to the study of meaning or semantics. Even from the beginning, on paragraph 2.3, Chomsky had mentioned the independence of syntax on semantics. Indeed, the question like “how can one construct a grammar with no appeal to meaning?” is actually, logically unsound. Take for example the sentence, “Colorless green ideas sleep furiously.” This is a grammatical sentence as it can be seen. This statement itself is meaningless. However, this does not mean that semantics is irrelevant to grammar. There are possible semantic implications of studying syntax which could be seen in the remarks in §8.17 Even the formation of the Transformational Generative Grammar, which carries such a strict sense of independence of grammar from semantics, is concerned with the meaning of a sentence, by understanding it from the history of kernel sentences, and in turn, understanding the kernel sentences themselves. Hence, this grammar can be said, not just to generate all and only the grammatical sentences of English, but also to explain much of the problem of ambiguity of sentences in a particular language, more particularly, the English language, which is a concern of semantic studies.18 According to Chomsky, it is not just difficult to prove that semantic notions are of no use to grammar, but it is also impossible.19 It could then be claimed that there are striking correspondences between the structures and elements that are discovered to be formal, grammatical analysis and specific semantic functions. Thus, the correspondences between formal and semantic features exist and cannot be ignored. He even claimed that the §8 of the Syntactic Structures suggests briefly an investigation of semantic function of level structures which can be considered as a reasonable step towards the interconnections between syntax and semantics.20 It should also be understood that the author of the book does not disregard the fact that semantics is also necessary for linguistic analysis of sentences, which syntax could be said to be of less help. To understand a sentence, we must know more than the analysis of the sentence on each linguistic level. We must also know the reference and meaning of the morphemes or words of which it is composed.21 5. Notes a. Semantics is the study of meaning of particular elements of language in its various linguistic levels. It does not merely concern itself with March 2011 - Volume 1 Semantics and THE Transformational Generative Grammar Page 89 the necessary or contingent connection of the meaning to the word, phrase, fragment, sentence or paragraph of a given language. It also deals with how does meaning relate itself with the linguistic elements and levels. b. Grammar is according to Chomsky, “a device of some sort for producing all and only grammatical sentences.” According to him, there are two kinds of grammar according to function. The first is the universal grammar. This theory states that there is a “universal grammar which is a part of the genetic birthright of human beings.” This serves a “template for language that any specific language fits into.” This is evidenced through observation of the verbal behavior of children. Grammar, according to him “has certain rules which are too hidden, too complex to be figured out by children who have so little evidence to go on.”22 Hence, there is a basic structure that a child can use to generate indefinite number of grammatical sentences of any particular language. The second kind is particular grammar. Particular grammar is the grammar of a specific language. c. Phrase Structure Rules generate sentences through substitution. Σ: # Sentence # F : 1. Sentence ->NP + VP 2. VP -> Verb + NP 3. NP -> {NPsing NPpl } 4. NPsing -> T + N + ø 5. NPpl -> T + N + S 6. T -> The 7. N -> man, ball, etc. 8. Verb -> Aux + V 9. V -> hit, take, walk, etc. 10. Aux ->C(M) + (have + en) (be + ing) 11. M -> will, can, may, shall, must23 d. Transformational Generative Grammar works in the manner of substitution. This is more like the Phrase-Structure Grammar, However, in the Transformational Generative Grammar, the substitution occurs in not in the morphemic level, but in the syntactic level. March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 90 Semantics and THE Transformational Generative Grammar Passive – optional: Structural analysis: NP – Aux – V – NP Structural change: X1 – X2 – X3 – X4-> X­4 – X2 + be + en – X3 – by + X124 Wherein X1=NP X2=Aux X3=V X4=NP 6. Appendix In this appendix, a brief account of terminologies and notations used in the paper are presented. These terminologies and notations are given a section in this paper in order that these may be fully clarified as they are used herein. i. “-> This is a symbol which reads ‘rewrite as.’ X->Y; wherein X and Y are strings.”25 “Rewrite X as Y.”26 ii. + This is a symbol for the process which forms the “finite vocabulary of symbols” into strings called “concatenation.”27 iii. – This is also a symbol for the process which forms the “finite vocabulary of symbols” into strings called “concatenation.” It has no syntactic relevance. However, it is “used to emphasize certain subdivision of utterance which is the concern of the moment.”28 iv. – In the case of discussing transformations, this hyphen assumes a special use. “It is used to indicate the inversion of the first two segments.”29 v. ( ) Parentheses are used to indicate that the element or elements inside the parentheses are optional, meaning, it or those may or may not occur.30 vi. { } “Brackets are used to indicate choice among elements.” This means that either of elements inside the brackets should occur. X-> {Y + Z Y} ; wherein X, Y and Y+Z are strings. X->Y+Z X-> Y31 March 2011 - Volume 1 Semantics and THE Transformational Generative Grammar Page 91 vii. “NP” stands for “Noun Phrase.”32 viii. “VP” stands for “Verb Phrase.”33 ix. “T” stands for the modifier of a Noun, i.e. article or adjective.34 x. “N” stands for “Noun.”35 xi. “NP­­­sing” stands for “Noun Phrase in singular form.”36 xii. “NPpl” stands for “Noun Phrase in plural form.”37 xiii. Σ stands for “finite set of initial strings.”38 xiv. F stands for “finite set of ‘instruction formulas. ’”39 xv. “[Σ, F]” stands for “grammar [Σ, F] beginning with the initial string of Σ and with each string in the sequence being derived from the preceding string by application of one of the instruction formulas of F.”40 xvi. “Aux” stands for “Auxiliary verb.”41 xvii. “V” stands for “main verb.”42 xviii. “C” stands for the conditional element of the verb considering the state of the number and time.43 xix. “M” stands for the additional optional morpheme depending upon the state of ‘C’.44 xx. “en” is an affix of both have and be as optional additional auxiliary morpheme.45 xxi. “S” as a string stands for “sentence.”46 xxii. “S” as a morpheme is an “affix of a regular verb if the NP is in the singular form.”47 xxiii. Ø The Zero Morpheme is a blank element which is an affix of a verb if the NP is in plural form.48 xxiv. “past” is an affix of a verb if the time of the verb is in the past.49 March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 92 Semantics and THE Transformational Generative Grammar xxv. “Af” stands for “Affix.”50 xxvi. “#” is interpreted as “word boundary.”51 xxvii. “A” stands for the “morpheme of contrastive stress.”52 xxviii. “wh” is a morpheme which is added to the “NP” when the Question Transformation Tq that occurred is not answerable by yes or no. For animate nouns: Wh+he-> /huw/ Wh+him-> /huwm/ For inanimate nouns: Wh+it->/wat/53 xxix. “Adj” stands for “adjective.”54 xxx. “PP” stands for “prepositional phrase.”55 xxxi. “Prt” stands for “particle.”56 xxxii. “Comp” stands for “complement.”57 Endnotes 1 Władysław Chłopicki, “Graeme Ritchie: The Linguistic Analysis of Jokes,” Elsevier, 37, (2005), 962. 3 Ibid, p. 20. 2 4 As can be portrayed in the function of a diagram, a sentence is a pattern of relation of words in a certain sequence. Forlini, Bauer, Biener, Capo, Kenyon, Shaw, and Verner, Grammar and Composition, Prentice-Hall, Inc., Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey, 1990, p. 98. “Diagramming is a way of seeing all of the many different parts of a sentence relate to each other. Like a blueprint, a diagram can make a fuzzy mental picture of a sentence clear and logical.” Ibid, p. 20. March 2011 - Volume 1 Semantics and THE Transformational Generative Grammar Page 5 6 7 8 9 93 Chomsky, Noam, Studies on Semantics in Generative Grammar, Mouton Publishers, Inc., Hague, Paris, 1972, p.196. “The semantic characterization of lexical items and the structure in which they appear can be given in terms of phrase-markers and transformations, for the uninteresting reason that virtually anything intelligible can be presented in these terms.” Chomsky, Noam, Syntactic Structures, Mouton Publishers, Hague, Paris, 1957, p. 35. In the (26) of the book, Sn=…X/Y…. however, for the sake of a clearer demonstration, the ellipses are replaced with variable A and B in this study. Cf. Ibid, p. 36. Cf. Ibid, p. 36. The examples above (i.e., Everyone in the lab considers John incompetent; and The police brought him in) are examples (88) and (82iii) respectively by Chomsky in the Syntactic Structures wherein, he compared this sentence with sentences (82i), (82ii) and (83). Ibid, p. 76. 10 Ibid, p.76. “…we must analyze (88) into the structure NP1—Verb—NP2, where NP1= everyone + in + the + lab and NP2= John.” 11 (86) in the Syntactic Structures is (7) in this study. Ibid, p. 77. “We now extend Tsep permitting it to apply to strings of the form (92) as well as to strings of the form (86), as before. (92) X—Va—Comp—NP.” 12 Cf. Ibid, p. 77. “Thus, the treatment of the verb + complement and verb + particle constructions are quite similar.” 13 Cf. Ibid, p. 76. “Further investigation of the verb phrase shows that there is a general verb + complement (V + Comp) construction that behaves very much like the verb + particle construction just discussed. Consider the sentences (88) everyone in the lab considers John incompetent (89) John is considered incompetent by everyone in the lab. 14 Prescript Transformational Structure § 13 15 Cf. Chomsky, Noam: Syntactic Structures, Mouton Publishers, Hague, Paris, 1957, p. 72-73. “In the phrase structure grammar we have a rule March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 94 Semantics and THE Transformational Generative Grammar (72) Adj->old, tall...” (73) the child is sleeping. Which lists all of the elements that can occur in the kernel sentences of the form (71). Words like “sleeping,” however, will not be given in this list, even though we have such sentences as 16 Ibid, p.74. […]it will never introduce “sleeping” into the context “very—.” Since “very” never modifies verbs. 17 Ibid, p. 93. “The remarks in §8 about possible semantic implications of syntactic study should not be misinterpreted as indicating support for the notion that grammar is based on meaning.” 18 Ibid, p. 92. “This [understanding ambiguous sentences on the transformational level] gives an independent justification and motivation for description of language in terms of transformational structure, and for the establishments of the transformational representation as a linguistic level with the same fundamental character as other levels. Furthermore, it adds to the force to the suggestion that the process of “understanding a sentence” can be explained in part in terms of the notion of linguistic level.” 19 Ibid, p.100. “It is, of course, impossible to prove that semantic notions are of no use in grammar, just as it is impossible to prove the irrelevance of any other given set of notions.” 20 Ibid, p.102. 21 Ibid, p. 103-104. 22 David Cogswell, Chomsky for Beginners, 23 Noam Chomsky, Syntactic Structures, Mouton Publishers, Hague, 1957, p. 110. 24 Noam Chomsky, Syntactic Structures, Mouton Publishers, Hague, 1957, p. 111 25 Justin Leiber, Noam Chmosky: A Philosophic Overview, St. Martin’s press incorporated, New York, 1975, p. 54-55. “E.g. (I) S->a+(S) - The arrow means ‘rewrite S as a+(S).’” Noam Chomsky, Aspects of the Theory of Syntax, The M.I.T. press, Campbridge, Massachusettes, p. 66. “The natural mechanism for generating Phrase-markers such as (3) is a system of rewriting rules. A rewriting rule is a rule of the form March 2011 - Volume 1 Semantics and THE Transformational Generative Grammar Page (4) A-> Z/X—Y *(3) Ibid, p. 65.” 95 Where X and Y are (possibly null) strings of symbols, A single category symbol, and Z is a nonnull string of symbols. 26 Cf. Noam Chomsky, Syntactic Structures, Mouton Publishers, Hague, 1957, p. 26. “Suppose we interpret each rule X->Y[...] as the instruction “rewrite X as Y.” 27 Cf. Ibid, p. 109. “It [linguistic level] has finite vocabulary of symbols […] which can be placed in a linear sequence to form strings of symbols by an operation called concatenation and symbolized by +.” 28 Cf. Ibid. 29 Ibid, p. 109-110. 30 Cf. Ibid , p. 110. 31 The strings X and Y and the element Z are used to substitute the exact example of Chomsky, i.e., a, b and c, in order that there would be consistency in the examples of the prescript. However, there would be no syntactic significance herein. Cf. Ibid, p. 110. “We use […] brackets (or listings) to indicate choice among elements. Thus both the rules (121i) and (121ii) (121) (i) a->b(c) (ii) a-> {b+c b} are abbreviations for the pair alternatives: a->b+c, a->b.” 32 Cf. Ibid, p.26. 33 Cf. Ibid. 34 Cf. Ibid. 35 Cf. Ibid. 36 Cf. Ibid, p.28. 37 John Lyons, Chomsky, Wm. Collins & Co. Ltd, Fontana, 1970, p. 57. 38 Noam Chomsky, Syntactic Structures, Mouton Publishers, Hague, 1957, p. 29. March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 96 Semantics and THE Transformational Generative Grammar 39 Ibid, p. 29. 40 Ibid. 41 Ibid, p. 38. 42 John Lyons, Chomsky, Wm. Collins & Co. Ltd, Fontana, 1970, p. 57. 43 Cf. Noam Chomsky, Syntactic Structures, Mouton Publishers, Hague, 1957, p. 39. “(29) (i) C->{S in the context NPsing} Æ in context NP pl past}” 44 Cf. Ibid, p.39. “(iv) M-> will, can, may, shall, must, etc.” 45 Ibid. “(iii) Aux-> C(M) (have+en) (be+ing) (be+en)”. 46 There is not any definite source for this. However, this proposition is implied in the Syntactic Structures. This has been used in this study in order for an easier representation. 47 See footnote 39. 48 See footnote 39. 49 See footnote 39. 50 Noam Chomsky, Syntactic Structures, Mouton Publishers, Hague, 1957, p. 39. “(ii) Let Af stand for any of the affixes past, S, Ø, en, ing. 51 Ibid, p.39. “[…] where # is interpreted as word boundary.” 52 Ibid, p. 65. “Suppose we set up a morpheme A of contrastive stress to which the following morphophonemic rule applies.” 53 Ibid, p. 69. footnote 2. 54 Cf. Ibid, p. 72. (71) “T—N – is – Adj (i.e., article – noun – is – adjective)” 55 Cf. Ibid, p. 74. “[…] prepositional phrase (PP)” 56 Cf. Ibid, p. 75. “Consider first such verb + particle (V+Prt) construction as ‘bring in,’ ‘call up,’ ‘drive away’.” 57 Cf. Ibid, p. 76. “[…]general verb +complement (V+Comp).” March 2011 - Volume 1 Semantics and THE Transformational Generative Grammar Page 97 Sources Chłopicki, Władysław, “Graeme Ritchie: The Linguistic Analysis of Jokes,” Elsevier, 37, Chomsky, Noam, Aspects of the Theory of Syntax, The MIT Press, Massachusetts, 1965. ________, Cartesian Linguistics: A Chapter in the History of Rationalist Thought, Harper and Row Publishers, New York , 1966. ________, “Logical Syntax And Semantics,” Language, 31,1, (January-March 1955), 36-45. ________, Studies on Semantics in Generative Grammar, Mouton & Co. N.V., Publishers, Paris, 1972. ________, Syntactic Structures, Mouton Publishers, Hague, 1957. ________, “Systems of Syntactic Analysis,” The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 16, 3, (September 1953), 242. ________, The Minimalist Program, The MIT Press, Massachusetts, 1995. Leiber, Justin, Noam Chomsky: A Philosophic Overview, St. Martin’s Press, Inc., New York, 1975. Lyons, John, Chomsky, Wm. Collins & Co. Ltd, Fontana, 1970. March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 99 A BRIEF HISTORY The annual celebration of the Philosophy Week began in 2004 as a simple mix of activities and jingles. It aimed to arouse interest in the study of philosophy of students in San Carlos Seminary through participation in the various activities. The Philosophy Week has grown and developed ever since. It has improved not only in the number of activites but also in the participative response to the objectives from students. During the celebration of the Fourth Philosophy Week in 2008, the reflections and essays of the participants as well as a synopsis of that year’s academic symposium were brought into a single volume under the name THEORIA. This was followed by another volume in 2009. By 2010, it was decided that the official Academic Journal for the Philosophy Department shall be made under the same name. March 2011 - Volume 1 Page 101 Contributors Fr. Lorenz Moises J. Festin, Ph.D. is the dean of the Philosophy Department of San Carlos Seminary where he currently teaches Cosmology, Anthropology, Thesis Writing and Philosophical Synthesis. He also teaches at San Carlos Graduate School of Theology and De La Salle University in Manila. Fr. Maxell Lowell C. Aranilla, Ph.D. is professor at the Philosophy Department of San Carlos Seminary where he teaches Epistemology, Philosophy of God and Philosophy of Education. He also teaches at De La Salle University in Manila. Marvin M. Cruz earned his degree in Philosophy at San Carlos Seminary in 2009. His article in this journal is a summary of his thesis for which he received the Zwaenepoel Award for Best Thesis in 2009. Jerome C. Jaime earned his degree in Philosophy at San Carlos Seminary in 2010. His article in this journal is a summary of his thesis for which he received the Zwaenepoel Award for Best Thesis in 2010. John Zernan B. Luna earned his degree in Philosophy at San Carlos Seminary in 2011. His article in this journal is a summary of his thesis for which he received the Zwaenepoel Award for Best Thesis in 2011. Daniel A. Dominguez earned his degree in Philosophy at San Carlos Seminary in 2011. His articles appear in the SCSInformation, the official newsletter of San Carlos Seminary. Bryan Joseph V. Rodriguez earned his degree in Philosophy at San Carlos Seminary in 2011. He served as Chairman of the Intellectual Formation Committee in 2010 and organized the Sixth Philosophy Week that year. March 2011 - Volume 1