Journal of Business Ethics (2006) DOI 10.1007/s10551-006-9074-9 Ó Springer 2006 Anomie and Ethics at Work Eva E. Tsahuridu ABSTRACT. The paper reports on research undertaken in three organisations seeking to explore anomie at work. This research explores whether a distinction in the levels of anomie between peopleÕs perception of the work and non-work contexts exists in three organisations, that is whether people are more likely to feel more hopeless and helpless in their work or non-work life. It also looks at whether people in different organisations have significantly different levels of anomie. A significant difference in the non-work anomie between organisations, but no significant difference in work anomie between organisations, was found. In the three organisations researched, the anomie score in the non-work context is lower than in the work context, indicating that respondents perceive the work context as more anomic. The work anomie for the total sample was found to be significantly higher that the non-work anomie. The implications for ethical behaviour at work and business ethics are discussed. behaviour. Anomie is related to helplessness and hopelessness. It is the lack of purpose, identity or values in a person or in a society that leads to a breakdown of the norms that rule the conduct of people and assure the social order (Kuczmarski and Kuczmarski, 1995, cited in Roshto, 1995). AnomieÕs essence is normlessness (Cohen, 1993) and it results in loss of meaning and a sense of injustice (Thorlindsson and Bernburg, 2004). Despite the numerous factors identified for the moral regression at work (Fassin, 2005), one element that remains relatively unexplored is anomie; and its possible effect on moral regression at work, stress, wellbeing and performance, not yet addressed. The normlessness that is anomie, may be responsible for the moral regression that has been found by people in organisations (French and Allbright, 1998; Schminke and Ambrose, 1997; Weber; 1990). Anomie may result in moral regression because the values that regulate the ends and means of humans who are anomic are weakened, and as a consequence the common meaning that is created in society and leads to morality and ethics, disappears (Bernburg, 2002) or as Merton (1957) more strongly claims, capitalistic competitiveness makes people lose their ethical goals. For Durkheim, anomie is a state of amorality (Horton, 1964). This paper reports on a research project conducted in three disparate organisations in Australia, and explores anomie in the business and non-business contexts and anomie and organisational ethical climates (Victor and Cullen, 1988) and personal ethical ideologies (Forsyth, 1980). The typology for differentiating between organisations used was OuchiÕs (1980) bureaucracies, markets and clans. OuchiÕs organisational types were used because they have been found to affect the development of the ethical climate (Wimbush et al., 1997). The organisations were selected based on secondary research and interviews with their top management, which revealed that organisation Alpha possessed the KEY WORDS: Anomie, morality, business ethics, work anomie Introduction The inconsistency between the moral behaviour of people in their work organisations and their moral behaviour outside work is recognised in practice and research. People at work are generally found to be less ethical than they are outside work. Consequently, efforts have been made to identify the factors that make ‘goodÕ people do ‘badÕ things (Bersoff, 1999), to distinguish their judgements and actions between their life at work and life outside work. Exploring anomie at work may improve understanding of the influence of the work environment on behaviour at work, especially ethical Dr Eva E. Tsahuridu is a Senior Lecturer at the University of Greenwich Business School in London, UK, Her main research interests include moral autonomy, anomie, and ethical leadership. Eva E. Tsahuridu characteristics of a bureaucracy, organisation Beta those of clan and organisation Gamma those of a market. This research explores whether a distinction in the levels of anomie between the work and nonwork contexts exists, and whether people in different types of organisations have significantly different levels of anomie i.e. whether the organisational climate affects anomie at work. This research also looked at the ethical ideologies of the respondents to see if a relationship exists between ethical climate and ethical ideology i.e. if people with certain ethical ideologies are attracted to organisations with different climates. Moral behaviour at work The distinction between moral behaviour at work and other contexts may be the outcome of the different requirements in the workplace, such as specialisation, division of labour and the emphasis on goal achievement. This difference in requirements is characteristically explained by David Ewing (1978, p. 168), who states that ‘‘only in America do we make a big production of guaranteeing such civil liberties as free speech, privacy, conscience and due process to all people, except from the hours of 9 to 5, Monday through Friday.’’ The same sentiments are expressed by Werhane (1999) in discussing the individual in the organisation. She explains that not all employees in the private sector enjoy rights to due process, freedom of speech, privacy, rights to employment information and job security, whilst the public sector does not guarantee the right to form unions. It is noted, however, that the U.S. constitution applies to interactions between persons or institutions and the state, and not to the private sector (Radin and Werhane, 2003). The ‘‘apples and barrels’’ debate (Treviño and Youngblood, 1990) developed to understand and prescribe ethical behaviour at work. The debate focuses on the causes of bad behaviour and offers the bad organisation and the bad individual as the two possibilities for its cause. It is increasingly realised that the context (the barrel) plays the major role in shaping behaviour at work (Treviño and Brown, 2004). This realisation is in line with the general acceptance of the influence of context in all human behaviour (Zimbardo, 2004). In the sphere of work, however, what is different is the perception that business has its own ethics and the ethical values of life do not apply there. Freeman (1994) called this false idea that ethics and business are separate and mutually exclusive, the separation thesis, and appeals for its rejection in order to make the clarification of the moral content of business activity possible. In addition to the organisational requirements and influence of the context, persons at work are also responsible for differences in behaviour. Jackall (1988) explains that at work individuals abdicate their personal responsibility and autonomy to the imperatives of the work place, while Fassin (2005) develops a number of micro and macro level elements that explain unethical behaviour at work, such as stakeholder expectations, the short term focus of business, the Anglo-Saxon model of governance, the psychology of the people in business and their rationalisations as well as pressure for success, and role models and dominance of financial over ethical considerations. In parallel to the attempts to identify why people behave differently in organisations and the influence of the workplace, there is an ongoing debate about the moral status of the organisation. This debate also has implications on how and why people behave in organisations and who is responsible for such behaviour. Different shades of moral personhood (absent, secondary, limited, full) are attributed to organisations (see Ewin, 1991; French, 1979, 1996; Garrett, 1989; Ladd, 1970/1984; Metzger and Dalton, 1996; Nagel, 1979; Weaver, 1998; Wilmot, 2001). The view that sees organisations lacking moral personhood perceives them as ‘‘incapable of exercising moral freedom, i.e. acting on the basis of moral considerations’’ (Nesteruk, 1991, p. 80). This view sees organisations as amoral structures whose bases for action are economic and market considerations (Nesteruk, 1991), a view that is grounded on the separation thesis discussed earlier (Freeman, 1994). The moral personhood issue of organisations remains unresolved, and it appears unlikely that organisations will be recognised as having full moral personhood as this gives rise to unresolvable consequences for individual agency and responsibility. Beyond the question of personhood, however, organisations are environments in which human agents play roles, follow rules and exercise morality (Nesteruk, 1991), a view that is less controversial and generally more acceptable. The literature identifies that business Anomie and Ethics at Work organisations, regardless of their moral status that has great implications for moral agency and moral responsibility, are likely to make people feel less responsible for decisions and actions taken within them. Williams (1997), for example, argues that business organisations shape the individual in them, so much that they do not see the ethical dimension of business life. Jackall (1988) claims that organisational life makes managers unable to see most issues that confront them as moral, even when the problems they face are presented in moral terms. This is an outcome of the nature of the employment relationship which grants a certain degree of control to employers over the behaviour of their employees, resulting in the relinquishment of some of their autonomy (Radin and Werhane, 1996), a phenomenon that can be explained by the zone of indifference (Barnard, 1938), the range within which individuals are willing to obey authority without questioning it. Barnard called this phenomenon irresponsible because people in organisations do not affect their morality in their behaviour. Beach (1990) explains that organisational influence is exercised by dividing tasks among members, establishing standard practices, transmitting objectives, providing communication channels and training and indoctrinating its members with knowledge, skill and loyalties. These influences ‘‘allow them to make the decisions the organisation wants made in the way the organisation wants them made’’ (Beach, 1990, p. 11). As such, the organisation provides both the ends and the means of their activities. The organisation also affects the locus of choice on decision-making (Vaughan, 1998). Vaughan explains that the organisation as a social context shapes what a person perceives as rational. The specialisation and division of labour that occurs in organisations may make people within organisations unable to see the immorality of certain actions. Each action is a part of a chain of actions and, even though each individual act may be legitimate and moral, all the actions linked together may constitute an immoral activity. Business organisations are subjected to increased pressure for more responsible behaviour and are now seeking to improve the ethicality of their decisions and actions, including their behaviour towards employees. Anomie, leads to moral regression and amorality, so understating anomie can help businesses to understand one of the elements that affects peopleÕs ethical behaviour at work. Anomie Anomie and anomia is a measure of relatedness to society. Anomie is primarily a phenomenon developed in sociology, however, moral anomie is used in philosophy to explain moral lawlessness, a state where there is no freedom, but only a lack of orientation (Benn, 1988). Anomie, developed by Durkheim (1947) and, later, Merton (1957, 1968), is a state in which there is ‘no legitimate end to oneÕs desires, no goal, no conclusionÕ (Lindholm, 1997, p. 754). Durkheim examined different characteristics of societies and discussed that a society where differentiation and individualism are prevalent is more likely to lead to anomie (Aron, 1967). Such societies are more likely to lead to anomie because the more society encourages individuals to fulfil their own personalities and gratify their desires, the greater the risk of social disintegration. Durkheim perceived that the complex division of labour would eliminate the historic forms of normative regulation, and render them inappropriate (Toddington, 1993). He believed that society provided ethics to individuals, so the elimination of its normative regulation would lead to anomie. Anomie, DurkheimÕs research revealed leads to suicide, while Merton found that anomie leads to increases in deviant behaviour (Mansfield, 2004). For Durkheim the concept of anomie refers to deregulation and normlessness, whilst for Merton it is the result of relative deprivation (Box, 1981). Bernburg (2002) also distinguishes between DurkheimÕs and MertonÕs anomie, and explains that for Durkheim anomie results because economic activity is deregulated and society does not provide a normative framework to limit peopleÕs desires. This lack of framework is consistent with PolanyiÕs (1957) development of the lack of embeddedness of the economic activity of the market, which for Durkheim was at a state of chronic anomie (Rose, 1966). Anomie theorists such as Merton, which are from the American context, explains Bernburg (2002), do not emphasise anomie as the lack of ‘socially valued goalsÕ (p. 729) as Durkheim does, but rather as lack of regulation in goal achievement with no reference to the appropriateness of the goals themselves. Polanyi (1957) explains that modern society unlike societies that existed in the past lack the Eva E. Tsahuridu embeddedness of the market system. As a consequence, Polanyi argues (in Bernburg, 2002) the market becomes self-regulated instead of being regulated by other social institutions. Social relationships in such a context are embedded in the economic system instead of the economic system being embedded in social relationships. Polanyi (1957, p. 3) explains that a self-regulated market ‘could not exist for any length of time without annihilating the human and natural substance of societyÕ. The lack of embeddedness of the market leads it to become unregulated from society and loose its moral, political and social regulation (Munck, 2004), thus making it a context where anomie is more likely to exist. Merton (1968) distinguished between social and individual anomie. Individual anomie, or anomia (Rose, 1966), refers to a state of mind expressed by individuals who live under anomic conditions (Stole, 1956, cited in Deflem, 1989). DurkheimÕs and MertonÕs anomie refers to a state of society, while anomia refers to an individualÕs state of mind (Deflem, 1989). As a psychological state, anomia refers to a state of amoral existence where there are no values to which one can refer and adopt for use in deciding and living and, as a result, people feel detached from society. Anomous individuals are those who fail to conceive themselves as choosers, makers and testers of norms (Hampden-Turner, 1970). Hampden-Turner defines anomie as meaninglessness and normlessness, because the ability to choose between norms, combine norms and invest norms into the human environment enable people to discover human meaning. ‘‘The anomic person does not see and does not want to know. It is all too big and too complicated and besides what can he do?’’ (HampdenTurner, 1970, p. 74), which leads to a common experience by anomic people of becoming ‘‘a thing’’ (p. 75). The anomic person, he comments, is often ‘deluded, helpless, obedient, hostile, conforming and cruelÕ (p. 97). Similarly, Fromm (1955) sees people in the market society as ‘dehumanisedÕ, considering themselves successfully employed elements instead of agents who possess human powers. The detachment from society and the subsequent formlessness is blamed on a number of factors, including the industrial revolution (Emler and Hogan, 1992; Shepard et al., 1995), the rise of emotivism (Lindholm, 1997; MacIntyre, 1993), the replacement of virtues with values (Himmelfarb, 1995), scientific rationalism, neo-classical economics (Fromm, 1942; McKenna and Tsahuridu, 2001) and capitalist economies (Lindholm, 1997). Emler and Hogan (1992) discuss the loss of community that resulted from the industrial revolution in the 18th century and the accompanying loss of moral authority and supervision. The outcome of this change in society and business is the assumption, accepted by psychology and Durkheim, that ‘‘people will be inclined to transgress when their actions are anonymous’’ (Emler and Hogan, 1992, p. 203). This provides an explanation for the regression in morality by people in organisations. The recent interest of ethics in business and the attempts to remoralise it (Tsahuridu, 2002) can benefit from a clearer understanding of organisational anomie and anomia at work. Anomia is related to the ethical climate the organisation provides (Cohen, 1993), to ethical decisions and to ethical behaviour. Anomia, by definition, appears to exclude moral consideration and be more closely associated with amorality. Anomia precludes meaningful and free human action because it does not allow for the autonomy of self-government by the values of a conscious person (Toddington, 1993). Anomie may explain why the assumption of ethical decisionmaking models (Butterfield et al., 2000; Treviño, 1986) in organisations, that people recognise and think about an ethical dilemma when they are confronted with one, is questionable (Gioia, 1992), since anomie results in normlessness, therefore lack of norms to trigger moral awareness. There is very little evidence of research on anomie in organisations. Zahra (1989) used anomie as one of the elements that make up attitudes and affect the perceptions of organisational politics. More recently, Caruana et al. (2000, 2001) used anomie to research studentsÕ and marketing professionalsÕ behaviour and found some evidence for a relationship between anomie and fraudulent behaviour. Passas (2001) worked on anomie and white-collar crime. Finally, Mansfield (2004) proposed that anomie contributes to role ambiguity, stress and uncertain relationships in the work context. Generally, anomie and anomia are developed in sociology and, despite the disagreement as to their exact definition and cause; there is a consensus that Anomie and Ethics at Work they are undesirable. Anomie impedes morality, personal well-being, dehumanises people and makes them hopeless and helpless things. Anomie is also found to affect peopleÕs behaviour and it has been linked with fraudulent and dishonest behaviour. So anomie seems to have negative consequences not only for the anomic individuals but also for ethics at work and in society. In business organisations, the anomic manager is described as parallel to a sociopathic manager (Miceli, 1996), where pursuit for profit excludes all moral considerations from decision-making. Certain formal and informal aspects of the goal-pursuing nature of corporations, such as end-focused leadership conducted without concern for the means, limited participation and autonomy by members, the strict compartmentalisation of peopleÕs activities at work, reward systems and socialisation, are likely to increase the presence of anomie at work (Cohen, 1993). This research is a first attempt to find out if in fact anomie increases in the work context and if organisations with different ethical climates have different levels of anomie at work. Ethical climate and ethical ideologies The ethical climate of organisations examines employeesÕ perceptions of the organisational influence on ethical judgements and also reflects behavioural expectations the organisation places on them. An organisationÕs ethical climate helps to determine ‘‘(a) which issues members of an organisation consider to be ethically pertinent, and (b) what criteria members of an organisation use to understand, weigh, and resolve these issues’’ (Cullen et al., 1989, p. 51). An organisationÕs ethical climate sets the behavioural expectations of ethics at work. It does not necessarily define what is right and wrong but focuses on what the individuals in an organisation think the organisation considers ethical (Dickson et al., 2001). A basic assumption of Victor and CullenÕs (1987) ethical climate research is that ethical criteria are prevalent and significant in organisational decision-making. That is, organisational decisionmaking does not only involve statements of fact but also it frequently involves questions about ‘‘what ought to be’’ (p. 52). This understanding of ethical climate is important because it clarifies that an organisationÕs ethical climate has normative content and it communicates to an organisationÕs members what they ought to do, as well as what is acceptable and expected. The capacity of an organisation to influence moral behaviour is a consequence of its possession of the ethical climate. An ethical climate does not necessarily prescribe ethical behaviour. Organisations that have instrumental ethical climates will not promote ethical judgements or behaviour and are more likely to produce unethical and criminal behaviour (Cohen, 1993). Different types of ethical climate are associated with different types of ethical behaviour (Cullen et al., 1989). Victor and Cullen (1988) proposed nine ethical climates based on the philosophical distinctions of egoism, benevolence and principle at the individual, local and cosmopolitan levels of analysis. Each proposed ethical climate is distinct and represents a form of reasoning that might be used in organisational decision-making. Empirically, Victor and Cullen confirmed the existence of five climates: Caring, Rules, Law and Code, Independence and Instrumental. In this research, the ethical climate of the three organisations is measured to explore if different climates lead to different levels of anomie. Ethical ideologies were examined using the Ethics Position Questionnaire (EPQ) (Forsyth, 1980, 1992). The EPQ contains 20 statements and assesses respondents in terms of relativism and idealism. Individuals who score high on the 10-item relativism scale, eschew universal moral principles and believe that morality depends upon the nature of the situation and the individuals involved. Idealists, individuals who score high on the 10-item idealism scale, believe that morality requires acting consistently with moral principles, norms or laws. The EPQ is a useful tool for the assessment of ethical ideologies in business ethics research (Davis et al., 2001). The ethical ideologies were examined to see if people with different personal ethics were attracted and selected by the different organisations. Methodology and measurement instruments This research explores whether a difference in the levels of anomie between the work and non-work contexts exists, and whether people in organisations with different ethical climates have significantly different levels of anomie. This research also looked Eva E. Tsahuridu at the ethical ideologies of the respondents to see if people with different ethical ideologies are attracted to organisations with different climates. The research was undertaken in three Australian organisations that differ in form and approximate OuchiÕs (1980) distinction of bureaucracy, clan and market. OuchiÕs organisational types are used because they affect the development of the ethical climate and also differ in ethical climate dimensions. The organisations were guaranteed anonymity and are referred as Alpha, Beta and Gamma. Organisation Alpha is a public organisation and is considered a bureaucracy. The ethical climate of a bureaucracy is predominantly Law & Code and Rules in terms of Victor and CullenÕs (1987, 1988) ethical climate types. Organisation Beta, a private service provision organisation, is considered a clan and the most democratic of the three organisations examined with Caring and Independence as its expected climate dimensions. Organisation Gamma is a tertiary educational institution and is considered a market organisation, which is expected to have a predominantly Instrumental climate. The sample consisted of managers (N = 93) from the three organisations, with all individuals from the same hierarchical level (middle management). Sections or departments of the organisations with similar characteristics were used to recruit the subjects, thus limiting intra-organisational variance. The individuals were required to have at least 1 yearÕs experience in the organisation and be in a middle management position, with project or personnel supervisory experience similar to the criteria used by Elm and Nichols-Lippitt (1993). A total of 32 valid questionnaires were collected from organisation Alpha (a response rate of 64%), 31 from organisation Beta (a response rate of 77.5%) and 30 from organisation Gamma (a response rate of 69.8%). The respondents were presented with Victor and CullenÕs (1988) Ethical Climate Questionnaire (ECQ), which also contained the Work Anomie Scale. They were also asked to resolve six work and six personal dilemmas (their analysis is outside the scope of this paper). They then were presented with ForsythÕs (1980) EPQ that contained the Personal Anomie Scale, followed by demographic questions. All instruments in this research involved ethical overtones and choices, but the EPQ instrument is the most intimate and thus presented last to minimise social desirability responses. The ECQ, EPQ and Work and Non-work Anomie Scales required responses on a 7 point Likert scale (from: 1 = Completely Disagree, to: 7 = Completely Agree). The anomie scale (Table I) developed by Bachman, Kahn, Davidson, and Velasquez (1967 cited in Zahra, 1989), and used by Zahra (1989), referred to general estrangement and it was used in this research with the EPQ. The scale was also converted for the purposes of this research (Table II), to reflect organisational estrangement, by translating the questions to reflect organisational life hopelessness. These statements were tested for clarity and face validity. It must be stressed that the non-work and work anomie scales were presented with the EPQ and the ECQ, respectively. As mentioned earlier the objective was to explore if people were more likely to report different levels of anomie between the different organisations and between the work and non-work contexts. TABLE I Anomie scale – non-work 1. 2. 3. 4. 5. 6. 7. 8. I feel no one really cares much about what happens to me. The life of the average person is getting worse, not better. These days I do not know whom I can depend on. These days I get the feeling that I am just not a part of things. I get the feeling that life is not very useful. No one cares what happens, when you get right down to it. People do not really care what happens to the next person. It is hardly fair to bring a child into the world the way things look now. Source: Bachman et al. (1967, cited in Zahra, 1989, p. 27). Anomie and Ethics at Work TABLE II Anomie scale – work 1. 2. 3. 4. 5. 6. 7. 8. These days I get the feeling that in business, individuals are just not a part of things. The life of the average person in business is getting worse, not better. These days in business, I do not really know whom one can depend on. I feel no one in business really cares much about what happens to individuals. I get the feeling that life at work is not very useful. I find it hard to be hopeful for the future of the world the way things look now. In this organisation no one cares what happens, when you get right down to it People in business do not really care what happens to the next person. The reliability of the ECQ was confirmed by Elm and Nichols-Lippitt (1993) and Victor and Cullen (1987). The reliability of the EPQ has been confirmed by Forsyth (1980) and Van Kenhove et al. (2001). The reliability of the non-work anomie scale developed by Bachman et al. (1967, cited in Zahra, 1989) was confirmed (a = 0.76). The reliability of the non-work anomie scale was a = 0.86 and that of the work anomie scale was a = 0.85. Analysis and discussion In the ethical climate dimensions, differences were found in Caring, Law & Code and Rules between the organisations (see Table III). The overall inter-organisational difference in the Caring, Law & Code and Rules dimensions is significant (at the 0.01 level). As expected, organisation Beta had the highest score in Caring, organisation Alpha the highest in the Law & Code and Rules dimensions. Organisation Beta was also expected to have the highest Independence score, but that was not confirmed in this study. Organisation Gamma scored higher in Independence, a fact that can be explained by the nature of work and greater autonomy in tertiary educational institutions, while organisation Beta is greatly affected by government and funding department regulations in addition to professional body codes. Organisation Alpha scored higher in the Instrumental dimension but the difference was not significant. The Scheffe test performed on the inter-group differences (Table III), confirmed their statistical significance (p < 0.05) in the Caring climate between organisations Beta and Gamma. It also confirmed the difference in the Law & Code climate between all three organisations and in the Rules climate between organisations Alpha and Gamma. In the ethical ideologies measured by the EPQ, organisation Beta had the lowest mean score in relativism and the highest in idealism. Organisation Alpha had the lowest score in idealism while organisation Gamma scored the highest in relativism. To test the significance of these differences, an ANOVA was performed but there were no significant differences in the idealism and relativism scores between the three organisations (See Appendix A). TABLE III Differences in ethical climate by organisation* (ANOVA) Caring Law and Code Rules Instrumental Independence Total Alpha Beta Gamma 3.79 4.87 4.34 3.93 3.79 3.80 5.58 4.76 4.08 3.63 4.19 4.86 4.30 3.81 3.70 3.35 4.12 3.93 3.89 4.06 *Mean score on a 7 point scale with 1 = completely disagree, 7 = completely agree. ANOVA (Scheffe) b>c a>b>c a>c NS NS Eva E. Tsahuridu This finding indicates that people who are attracted to and retained in the different types of organisations are not significantly different in terms of their ideologies. In analysing anomie there is no significant difference in work anomie (see Table IV) between the three organisations, although organisation Beta, which was the most caring, has the lowest mean. There is, however, a significant difference in nonwork anomie. Organisation Beta has again the lower level of non-work anomie, while organisation Alpha, which was the most bureaucratic organisation, showed the highest level of non-work anomie. An interesting finding presented in Table IV is that, in all three organisations, the anomie score in the non-work construct is lower than in the work construct. In order to test whether that difference is significant a Paired Differences Test was performed (see Table V), which revealed that overall non-work anomie is significantly lower than work anomie, in the total sample. This finding indicates that people in this research were more likely to feel helpless and hopeless when they were thinking about work and business than when they were thinking about life in general. These findings give some support to the claim that the business realm is in a state of anomie (Rose, 1966) and that it may be impossible to make business organisations anomie free (Cohen, 1993). Overall, there was no significant difference in the anomie scores between organisations in the work anomie scale, even though organisation Beta, which had a caring climate, has the lowest mean, therefore further research in different organisations and larger samples is required. There was a significant difference, however, in the non-work anomie scale. This TABLE IV Differences in work and non-work anomie by organisation (ANOVA) Organisation n Work anomie M (SD) Non-work anomie M (SD) Alpha Beta Gamma F 32 31 30 4.27 (1.15) 3.67 (1.27) 4.18 (1.05) 2.4 3.18 (1.20) 2.32 (0.92) 2.81 (1.08) 5.1* *p < .01. TABLE V Work and non-work anomie Work anomie Non work anomie Paired differences T N M (SD) 93 93 4.04 (1.18) 2.77 (1.12) 1.27 (0.97) 12.55* *p < .01. finding needs to be explored further to understand what makes people perceive work and non-work anomie differently, and understand why the organisational context renders people more hopeless and helpless. Conclusion Efforts to address moral regression at work may not be effective until we understand the effect of the work context on its people. Anomie appears to be an important element we need to understand if we are to improve our knowledge of the factors that affect peopleÕs decisions and behaviour in the work context, since as it has been established, anomie may result in moral regression or amorality. The work context seems to be perceived as generally more normless by people at work, despite differences in ethical climates. Anomie lies at the centre of this normlessness and the emphasis on costs, profits, returns to shareholders, and market share, may provide the reasons that lead to anomie. Anomie leads to more deviant and criminal behaviour. Our attempts to improve the ethics in business may fail if we do not understand anomie and its causes and symptoms. An important element that needs to be explained is whether the relinquishment of our autonomy at work leads us to feel more anomic in that context. It is important to understand which market characteristics lead to increased levels of anomie and the possibilities of redesigning the philosophy and purpose of organisations to reduce the negative effects work seems to have on people, as well as work itself. It thus seems appropriate to question not only the means of business organisations but also the ends, the appropriateness of the goals and the effects these goals may have on levels of anomie. Anomie and Ethics at Work The research findings indicate that people at work are more likely to feel hopeless and helpless, and also more likely to behave deviantly, as anomie at work context is higher that in the non-work context in the three organisations. They also showed that the people in organisation Alpha, which was the most rule and law based organisation, had the highest work anomie, and a significantly higher level of non-work anomie. This may indicate that people in more anomic work places are greatly affected in their non-work life i.e. they take work at home; or there are other elements in a rule and law context that impact on how life in general is perceived. The impact of autonomy at work on anomie may shed some light on this phenomenon. Anomie disables moral thinking which, argues Paine (1996), is needed by managers, not only because it is the right thing to do but also because it strengthens organisations and contributes to their performance, thus moral thinking has ethical and instrumental implications. In terms of the individual at work, it is important to refer to the pursuit of the human ideal of happiness and the effect-increased levels of anomie have on the pursuit of that ideal. The implications of these findings are that the work sphere, in general, may contain a fundamental ingredient that increases the feeling of hopelessness and helplessness. Efforts to identify this element will help organisations increase their contribution to a sustainable future, where sustainability is defined as ‘‘flourishing in time immemorial’’ to make life good and meaningful (Ehrenfeld 2000, cited in Wheeler, Colbert, and Freeman, 2003, p. 17). Identifying this element in organisations may also help people to be morally autonomous and not helpless and hopeless ‘thingsÕ. It also explains why good people do bad things, given that people feel less like moral agents at work and feel the work norms weak in affecting decisions and behaviour. Attempts made to improve work-life balance, decrease stress at work and improve employee well-being may be better informed by an understanding of anomie. The incidents of unethical behaviour will also be better explained. Attempts to improve ethics at work, and reliance of those attempts on codes and regulations may continue to be ineffective if people continue to perceive the work context as highly anomic. The small number of the sample both in terms of organisations and respondents from each organisa- tion, limited to an Australian city, affect the generalisability of the findings. Further research in other geographic locations and types of organisations would contribute to the validation of the current findings. In addition, the current research was limited to managers or supervisors. Research in different organisational levels may reveal different levels of anomie. It is expected that people in the lower levels of organisations who typically have less autonomy, will exhibit higher levels of anomie in comparison to those of managers. Further research in corporations that fulfill to a greater extent the profile of market organisations will also be valuable, as these organisations better fulfill the characteristics that lead to anomie. APPENDIX A Differences in ethical ideologies by organisation (ANOVA) Organisation n Individual idealism M (SD) Individual relativism M (SD) Alpha Beta Gamma F 32 31 30 4.49 (1.05) 4.95 (0.76) 4.64 (0.90) 2.1 4.25 (0.94) 3.80 (0.87) 4.26 (1.12) 2.2 References Aron, R.: 1967, Main Currents in Sociological Thought, R. Howard and H. Weaver (Trans.), Vol. 1 (New York, Doubleday). Barnard, C. I.: 1938, The Functions of the Executive (Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA) Beach, L. R.: 1990, Image Theory: Decision Making in Personal and Organizational Contexts (John Wiley & Sons, Chichester) Benn, S. I.: 1988, A Theory of Freedom (Cambridge University Press, New York) Bersoff, D. M.: 1999, ÔWhy Good People Sometimes do Bad Things: Motivated Reasoning and Unethical BehaviorÕ, Personality & Social Psychology Bulletin 25(1), 28–39. Box, S.: 1981, Deviance, Reality and Society 2nd edn (Holt, Rinehart and Winston, London). Bernburg, J. G.: 2002, ÔAnomie, Social Change and CrimeÕ, British Journal of Criminology 42, 729–742. Eva E. Tsahuridu Butterfield, K. D., L. K. Trevino and G. R. Weaver: 2000, ÔMoral Awareness in Business Organizations: Influences of Issue-related and Social Context FactorsÕ, Human Relations 53(7), 981–1018. Caruana, A., B. Ramaseshan and M. T. Ewing: 2000, ÔThe Effect of Anomie on Academic Dishonesty Among University StudentsÕ, The International Journal of Educational Management 14(1), 23–30. Caruana, A., B. Ramaseshan and M. T. Ewing: 2001, ÔAnomia and Deviant Behavior in Marketing: Some Prelimimary EvidenceÕ, Journal of Managerial Psychology 16(5), 322–338. Cohen, D. V.: 1993, ÔCreating and Maintaining Ethical Work Climate: Anomie in the Workplace and Implications for Managing ChangeÕ, Business Ethics Quarterly 3(4), 343–358. Cullen, J. B., B. Victor and C. Stephens: 1989, ÔAn Ethical Weather Report: Assessing the OrganizationÕs Ethical ClimateÕ, Organizational Dynamics 18(2), 50–62. Davis, M. A., M. G. Andersen and M. B. Curtis: 2001, ÔMeasuring Ethical Ideology in Business Ethics: A Critical Analysis of the Ethics Position QuestionnaireÕ, Journal of Business Ethics 32, 35–53. Deflem, M.: 1989, ÔFrom Anomie to Anomia and Anomic Depression: A Sociological Critique on the Use of Anomie in Psychiatric ResearchÕ, Social Science and Medicine 29(5), 627–634. Dickson, M. W., B. D. Smith, M. W. Grojean and M. Ehrhart: 2001, ÔAn Organizational Climate Regarding Ethics: The Outcome of Leader Values and the Practices that Reflect ThemÕ, The Leadership Quarterly 12, 197–217. Durkheim, E.: 1947, The Division of Labor in Society, G. Simpson (Trans.) (Free Press, New York). Elm, D. R. and M. Nichols-Lippitt: 1993, ÔAn Investigation of the Moral Reasoning of ManagersÕ, Journal of Business Ethics 12, 817–833. Emler, N. and R. Hogan: 1992, ÔIndividualizing Conscience: New Thoughts on Old IssuesÕ, in W. M. Kurtines, M. Azmitia and J. L. Gewirtz (eds.), The Role of Values in Psychology and Human Development (John Wiley & Sons, New York), pp. 200–238. Ewing, D.: 1978, ‘Employee Freedom within the OrganizationÕ, Paper presented at the Power and Responsibility in the American Business System: Proceedings of the Second National Conference on Business Ethics, Bentley College, April 7 & 8. Ewin, R. E.: 1991, ÔThe Moral Status of the CorporationÕ, Journal of Business Ethics 10, 749–756. Fassin, Y.: 2005, ÔThe Reasons Behind Non-ethical Behaviour in Business and EntrepreneurshipÕ, Journal of Business Ethics 60, 265–279. Forsyth, D. R.: 1980, ÔA Taxonomy of Ethical IdeologiesÕ, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 39(1), 175–184. Forsyth, D. R.: 1992, ÔJudging the Morality of Business Practices: The Influence of Personal Moral PhilosophiesÕ, Journal of Business Ethics 11, 461–470. Freeman, R. E.: 1994, ÔThe Politics of Stakeholder Theory: Some Future DirectionsÕ, Business Ethics Quarterly 4(4), 409–421. French, P.: 1979, ÔThe Corporation as a Moral PersonÕ, in T. Donaldson and P. H. Werhane (eds.), Ethical Issues in Business: A Philosophical Approach 3rd edition, (Prentice Hall, New Jersey), pp. 100–109. French, P. A.: 1996, ÔIntegrity, Intentions and CorporationsÕ, American Business Law Journal 34(2), 141–155. French, W. and D. Allbright: 1998, ÔResolving a Moral Conflict Through DiscourseÕ, Journal of Business Ethics 17, 177–194. Fromm, E.: 1942, The Fear of Freedom (Routledge & Kegan Paul, London) Fromm, E.: 1955, The Sane Society (Fawcett Premier Books, New York) Garrett, J. E.: 1989, ÔUnredistributable Corporate Moral ResponsibilityÕ, Journal of Business Ethics 8, 535–545. Gioia, D. A.: 1992, ÔPinto Fires and Personal Ethics: A Script Analysis of Missed OpportunitiesÕ, Journal of Business Ethics 11, 379–389. Hampden-Turner, C.: 1970, Radical Man: The Process of Psycho-social Development (Schenkman Publishing, Cambridge) Himmelfarb, G.: 1995, The De-moralization of Society: From Victorian Virtues to Modern Values (Alfred A Knopf, New York). Horton, J.: 1964, ÔThe Dehumanization of Anomie and Alienation: A Problem in the Ideology of SociologyÕ, British Journal of Sociology 15(4), 283. Jackall, R.: 1988, Moral Mazes (Oxford University Press, New York) Ladd, J.: 1970/1988, ÔMorality and the Ideal of Rationality in Formal OrganizationsÕ, in T. Donaldson and P. H. Werhane (eds.), Ethical Issues in Business: A Philosophical Approach 3rd edition, (Prentice-Hall, New Jersey), pp. 110–122. Lindholm, C.: 1997, ÔLogical and Moral Dilemmas of PostmodernismÕ, Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute 3(4), 747–760. MacIntyre, A.: 1993, After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory 2nd edn (Duckworth, London) McKenna, R. J. and E. E. Tsahuridu: 2001, ÔMust Managers Leave Ethics at Home? Economics and Moral Anomy in Business OrganisationsÕ, Reason in Practice 1(3), 67–76. Anomie and Ethics at Work Mansfield, P.: 2004, ÔAnomie and Disaster in Corporate Culture: The Impact of Mergers and Acquisitions on the Ethical Climate of Marketing OrganisationsÕ, Marketing Management Journal 14(2), 88–99. Merton, R. K.: 1957, ÔSocial Structure and AnomieÕ, American Sociological Review 3, 672–682. Merton, R. K.: 1968, Social Theory and Social Structure 3(The Free Press, New York) Metzger, M. B. and D. R. Dalton: 1996, ÔSeeing the Elephant: An Organizational Perspective on Corporate Moral AgencyÕ, American Business Law Journal 33, 489– 576. Miceli, N. S.: 1996, ÔDeviant Managerial Behavior: Costs, Outcomes and PreventionÕ, Journal of Business Ethics 15, 703–709. Munck, R.: 2004, ÔGlobalization, Labor and the ‘Polanyi ProblemÕÕ, Labor History 45(3), 251–269. Nagel, T.: 1979, Mortal Questions (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge) Nesteruk, J.: 1991, ÔLegal Persons and Moral Worlds: Ethical Choices within the Corporate EnvironmentÕ, American Business Law Journal 29, 75–97. Ouchi, W. G.: 1980, ÔMarkets, Bureaucracies, and ClansÕ, Administrative Science Quarterly 25, 129–141. Paine, S. L.: 1996, ÔMoral Thinking in Management: An Essential CapabilityÕ, Business Ethics Quarterly 6(4), 477–492. Passas, N.: 2001, ÔFalse Accounts: Why Do Company Statements Often Offer a True and Fair View of Virtual RealityÕ, European Journal On Criminal Policy and Research 9(2), 117–135. Polanyi, K.: 1957, The Great Transformation: The Political and Economic Origins of Our Time (Beacon, Boston) Radin, T. J. and P. H. Werhane: 1996, ÔThe Public/ Private Distinction and the Political Status of EmploymentÕ, American Business Law Journal 34(2), 245–260. Radin, T. J. and P. H. Werhane: 2003, ÔEmployment-atwill, Employee Rights, and Future Directions for EmploymentÕ, Business Ethics Quarterly 13(2), 113–130. Rose, G.: 1966, ÔAnomie and Deviation: A Conceptual Framework for Empirical StudiesÕ, British Journal of Sociology 17(1), 29–45. Roshto, P. G.: 1995, ‘A Review of ‘‘Values Based Leadership Rebuilding Employee Commitment, Performance, & Productivity’’Õ, Retrieved 8/8/1997, from www.cber.nlu.edu/DBR/ROSHTO.htm. Schminke, M. and M. L. Ambrose: 1997, ÔAsymmetric Perceptions of Ethical Frameworks of Men and Women in Business and Nonbusiness SettingsÕ, Journal of Business Ethics 16, 719–729. Shepard, J. M., J. Shepard, J. C. Wimbush and C. U. Stephens: 1995, ÔThe Place of Ethics in Business: Shifting Paradigms?Õ, Business Ethics Quarterly 5(3), 577–601. Thorlindsson, T. and J. G. Bernburg: 2004, ÔDurkheims Theory of Social Order and Deviance: A Multi-level TestÕ, European Sociological Review 20(4), 271–285. Toddington, S.: 1993, Rationality, Social Action and Moral Judgement (Edinburgh University Press, Edinburgh) Treviño, L. K.: 1986, ÔEthical Decision Making in Organizations: A Person-situation Interactionist ModelÕ, Academy of Management Review 11(3), 601–617. Treviño, L. K. and S. A. Youngblood: 1990, ÔBad Apples in Bad Barrels: A Causal Analysis of Ethical Decisionmaking BehaviorÕ, Journal of Applied Psychology 75(4), 378–385. Treviño, L. K. and M. Brown: 2004, ÔManaging to be Ethical: Debunking Five Business Ethics MythsÕ, Academy of Management Executive 18(2), 69–81. Tsahuridu, E. E.: 2002, ‘The Remoralisation of BusinessÕ, Paper presented at the International Conference of Reason in Practice and the Forum for European Philosophy: Developing Philosophy of Management, St AnneÕs College, Oxford, 26–29 June. Van Kenhove, P., I. Vermeir and S. Verniers: 2001, ÔAn Empirical Investigation of the Relationships between Ethical Beliefs, Ethical Ideology, Political Preference and Need for ClosureÕ, Journal of Business Ethics 32, 347–361. Vaughan, D.: 1998, ÔRational Choice, Situated Action, and the Social Control of OrganizationsÕ, Law & Society Review 32(1), 23–61. Victor, B. and J. B. Cullen: 1987, ÔA Theory and Measure of Ethical Climate in OrganizationsÕ, in W. C. Frederick (eds.), Research in Corporate Social Performance and Policy 9 (JAI Press, Greenwich), pp. 51–71. Victor, B. and J. B. Cullen: 1988, ÔThe Organizational Bases of Ethical Work ClimatesÕ, Administrative Science Quarterly 33, 101–125. Weaver, W. G.: 1998, ÔCorporations as Intentional SystemsÕ, Journal of Business Ethics 17, 87–97. Weber, J.: 1990, ÔManagersÕ Moral Reasoning: Assessing their Responses to Three Moral DilemmasÕ, Human Relations 43(7), 687–703. Werhane, P. H.: 1999, ÔJustice and TrustÕ, Journal of Business Ethics 21, 237–249. Wheeler, D., B. Colbert and R. E. Freeman: 2003, ÔFocusing on Value: Reconciling Corporate Social Responsibility, Sustainability and a Stakeholder Approach in a Network WorldÕ, Journal of General Management 28(3), 1–28. Williams, O. F.: 1997, ÔThe Challenge: Envisioning the Good LifeÕ, in O. F. Williams (eds.), The Moral Imagination (The University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame, Indiana), pp. 1–15. Eva E. Tsahuridu Wilmot, S.: 2001, ÔCorporate Moral Responsibility: What Can We Infer from Our Understanding of Organisations?Õ, Journal of Business Ethics 30, 161– 169. Wimbush, J. C., J. M. Shepard and S. E. Markham: 1997, ÔAn Empirical Examination of the Multi-dimensionality of Ethical Climate in OrganizationsÕ, Journal of Business Ethics 16, 67–77. Zahra, S. A.: 1989, ÔExecutive Values and the Ethics of Company Politics: Some Preliminary FindingsÕ, Journal of Business Ethics 8(1), 15–29. Zimbardo, P. G.: 2004, ÔA Situationist Perspective on the Psychology of Evil: Understanding How Good People are Transformed into PerpetratorsÕ, in A. G. Miller (eds.), The Social Psychology of Good and Evil (Guilford Press, New York), pp. 21–50. Business School University of Greenwich, Park Row, London, SE10 9LS, U.K. E-mail: te21@gre.ac.uk