Magic: A Problem in Semantics DOROTHY HAMMOND Brooklyn College, C.U.N.Y. Anthropologists, from TyIor to the present, have so defined magic that, although it might shade into or overlap with religion, it is a separate phenomenon distinct from religion. Theorists have made differentfeatures the chief means of differentiation, but no matter how defined the distinction cannot be easily or consistently maintained. This paper suggests that the concept of magic as a distinct entity is the factitious result of ethnocentric classification, and that magic should be included within religion as one fype o f the practices of which religious ritual is composed. [magic; reltgion; theory, history ofl T HE PUBLICATION OF a considerable number of articles, compilations, and monographs during the last decade testifies to movement of the anthropological study of religion out of its long stay in the doldrums. Reawakened theoretical interest has been accompanied by renewal attacks on the perdurable problem of definition. Current definitions are not sufficiently incisive. To define religion in Tillich’s terms as “the ultimate concern” leads to the possible inclusion of anything from politics to sport and thus cannot single out a specific cultural institution. The even more prevalent definition by reference to a dichotomy between secular and sacred, the idea of the “set apart,” is a mere circularity, religion being the attribution of religious significance. Recent attempts at definition aim less at universal essences than, more modestly, at a clear designation of the topic. The need to provide a ready index for identification has led a number of anthropologists to resume Tylor’s position that religion entails a belief in spiritual beings (Goody 1961; Horton 1960; Spiro 1966). Consistency in the application of Tylor’s definition commits these writers to another of his concepts, that magic is to be considered as separate from religion. Spiro thus includes magic with politics and art as functional alternatives to religion (1966: 116). Horton describes magic as *’secular’’ (1960: 218). This logical consequence of the definition is disconcerting, for it contains what apAccepted for publication 20 November 1969. pears to be an inherent contradiction between the ideas of “secular” and “supernatural.” Moreover, the ethnographic data compel recognition that a sharp distinction between magic and religion can hardly be sustained. Spiro, in the course of making a point about religion in his narrow sense of the term, illustrates his argument with a magical belief (1966: 110). This may be the result of momentary carelessness, but Spiro’s slip does demonstrate the difficulty of maintaining consistency in the differentiation. Evans-Pritchard, who also advocates a clear distinction between magic and religion (1965:33), attributes the confusion concerning their relationship to semantic difficulties (1965:llO). By this he means the problems of translating the diverse terminologies from various cultures into anthropological categories. But the semantic problem is in reality twofold: it consists not only of the difficulties of translation, but also the more elementary issue of what anthropologists mean by their own concepts. As a general rule, twentiethcentury anthropologists do not dichotomize magic and religion. They tend rather to hyphenate them and refer explicitly or implicitly to some sort of continuum. However, the conception of magic and religion as overlapping or intergrading phenomena still conveys the idea that the terms denote at least partially distinct entities. Despite the overlap, they contrast sufficiently to indicate that the terms have the same hierarchical status in a classikation of belief systems. 1349 1350 American Anthropologist The consensus on some distinction between magic and religion is limited to the idea that there is a distinction. Beyond this, a review of the literature discloses irreconcilable disagreements among theorists, as well as inconsistencies within discussions and discrepancies between conceptual schemes and ethnographic data. The source of the difficulty may well lie in the distinction itself. If the idea that magic and religion have equal categorical status is rejected and magic subordinated within the more inclusive category, it follows that the distinction makes a part into an equivalent and separate whole. This mixing of levels of classification would account for the continuing confusion of which Evans-Pritchard so justly complains. Anthropologists have been struggling with the spurious, and therefore insoluble, problem of the extent and content of the contrast between religion and magic. The real problem is what is the place of magic in religion; how does the part fit into the whole? Like most ethnological terminology, religion and magic are words in common usage. Their employment to classify institutions of other cultures has necessitated radical redefinition to free the terms from their cultural matrix and to eliminate inherent value judgments. To what extent all ethnocentrism has been overcome is open to question. Ward H. Goodenough holds that anthropological usage still expresses ethnocentric rather than objective judgment (1963:480). The fact that current usage continues to reflect theories of nineteenth-century evolutionists supports his charge. The delineation of magic as a distinct anthropological category is more the work of Frazer than of any other single theorist. By redefining religion as belief in spiritual beings, Tylor had made it possible to include a wide variety of belief systems in the same category as Christianity. Magic, however, he discussed merely as a survival; thus relegated, the term retained its pejorative connotation (Tylor 1889: Vol. 1, Ch. 4). Frazer, however, related magic more closely to religion, although an underlying ethno- [72, 1970 centrism assigned magic to an earlier stage in the evolution of belief systems. Because he accepted Tylor’s definition of religion, personification served to differentiate between the earlier and later stages. Unlike religion, magical belief lacks personification, and its practices exploit supernatural mechanisms (Frazer 1900:48-60). These two characteristics-impersonal forces and manipulative techniques-remain as current critical diagnostic features. Durkheim and Malinowski each added another dimension to the definition of magic. Durkheim based his distinction on the organization of personnel: religion involves the community and establishes a church, but magic concerns individuals and forms only a clientele (1915:4345). Malinowski focused on the purposes of ritual. He attributed intangible, long-term goals to religious rituals in contrast to the employment of magic to supplement inadequacies in technology for the achievement of concrete, immediate ends ( 1948:67-70). Because most supernatural belief systems contain both personified and nonpersonified conceptions of supernatural power, the criterion of personification only rarely permits definite assignment. Frazer was entirely aware of this fact, which he accounted for as part of the evolutionary sequence. Such beliefs represented transitions from magic to religion or the conservative retention of older elements into the later stage. But without the explanation provided by an evolutionary doctrine, the intermediate is merely indeterminate, and much of the ethnographic data demonstrate the inadequacy of the criterion. The differentiation made by Durkheim received one of its most direct attacks from Warner on the basis of his fieldwork in Australia (1937:229-243). Among the Murngin, the same totemic rituals are used for individual therapy as for communal welfare; the community is directly or indirectly participant in transactions between the magician and client, and thus magic has a church no different from religion. Other de- HAMMOND] Magic: A Problem in Semantics 1351 scriptive materials bear out Warner’s point on the conception of supernatural power. that the line between public and private is Benedict described religion as entailing two extremely tenuous. polar attitudes, one of which might predomiMalinowski’s contrast between the practi- nate in a given instance, but both might be cal goals of magical ritual and the broad so- expressed simultaneously. These attitudes cial values fostered by religious ritual seems Benedict termed “animism,” Tylor’s conto hinge more on terminology than on sub- cept, and “animatism,” adapted from Marstance. The difference seems to be a stylistic ett. Marett had coined “animatism” to desigchoice of concrete or abstract phrasing. nate a primitive diffuse supernaturalism Trobriand garden magic for a plentiful har- from which animism and mana had both vest contributes not only to subsistence but evolved (1914: 14). In Benedict’s usage, adalso to those values to Trobriand ethos ex- mism reflects “mads experience with perpressed in the production of excessive sons” and animatism reflects their “experiamounts of food and its lavish display. The ence with things” (1938:647). Practice folanalysis of what social values mean in spe- lows concept: where the supernatural is percific terms often reveals that the “good life” sonified, ritual strives for rapport; where the of a people entails, or is symbolized by, supernatural is impersonal, ritual strives for good crops or increase in cattle herds or control. Mana and its analogues-wakan, some equally material good. And it is more manitu, and orenda-conceptualize the imthe symbolic significance of these items than personal supernatural. Magic falls neatly the technological uncertainty that tends to into place as the body of formalized procesurround them with ritual (W. H. Good- dures by which such power is controlled and utilized. enough 1963:478; Nadel 1957:193). Goode, like Benedict, dismisses dichotWhen applied to ethnographic data, none of these theories completely differentiates omy in favor of a continuum. Unlike Benemagic from religion even in regard to the se- dict, he does not bypass the different criteria lected critical trait. Nor do they correlate suggested by various theorists but boldly atwith one another; the increase ceremonies tempts to overcome the contradictions of the Arunta are classed as religion by within and among the separate schemes by Durkheim but magic by Frazer, and Tro- combining them all into a single structure. briand garden rituals, which Malinowski His suggested bipolar continuum opposes terms magic, would be religion according to ideal types of magic and religion in which Durkheim. If more features are taken into magic contrasts with religion in the concrete specificity of its goals, its manipulative attiaccount, the line blurs all the more. Marett is probably the best-known early tude, instrumental character, belief in impertheorist to advance the concept of a magi- sonal power, professional-client relationcoreligious continuum (1914:28). He con- ships, individualism, voluntarism, and uncurred in Frazer’s concept of magic as an scheduled performance ( 1951:52-55). earlier stage of religion, but his own judgGoode’s model rests on the expectation ment that belief in mana was as much reli- that on analysis the descriptive data will gion as animism led him to reject personifi- form significant clusters toward the two cation as a main criterion and to reject a poles. If the traits do not exhibit substantial clear-cut distinction between magic and reli- correlation, the ideal types are merely hypogion. thetical constructs. There seems to have Benedict, far more than Marett, cogently been little testing of the actual extent of corformulated the idea that magic and religion relation on which the relevance of Goode’s form a continuum. She disregarded evolu- model depends. Notable exceptions, howtionary sequence and put aside most of the ever, come readily to mind. Australian indiscrepant subsidiary criteria to concentrate crease ceremonies are manipulative but 1352 American Anthropologist communal and obligatory. Trobriand garden ritual is instrumental with specific concrete goals, but it is also obligatory, communal, and calendrical. Among the Zuni, the gods may be manipulated rather than supplicated. Bunyoro magic horns used instrumentally in behalf of a client become “personalized” (Beattie 1967:229). Of the two continuum models, Benedict’s has had wider influence. Her comprehensive and economical theory, Norbeck (1961 :35) notes, provides the conceptual basis implicit in the analyses of many ethnologists. A sampling of the literature confirms Norbeck’s comment. There is some shying away from the term “supernatural”; “nonempirical” is substituted as though “empirical” were any less a category of the observer than “natural.” An occasional obeisance is made to other variables, but discussions largely tend to follow Benedict’s emphasis on conceptions of supernatural power and the modes of access to it. In much of the writing the terms most frequently associated with magic are “impersonal,” “mechanical,” “automatic,” “compulsive,” “coercive,” “efficient,” “learned techniques,” and “acquired skills.” Such associations indicate that usage gives more weight to the employment of power than to the nature of the power. This emphasis seems a natural corollary of the shifts in anthropological interest. Nineteenth-century theorists such as Tylor and Frazer were primarily concerned with the cognitive function of religion. For a considerable time thereafter, attention turned to sociological and affective functions. Discussions of these subjects could refer to the procedures of magic without much concern for the conception of its power. More recently, however, reflecting general intellectual interest in problems of meaning, anthropologists are again turning to the study of how men create a meaningful order out of their experiences in a chancy and indifferent universe: “attempts to provide orientation for an organism which cannot live in a world it is unable to understand” (Geertz 1968:314). In Benedict’s analysis [72, 1970 of primitive religion magic clearly has cognitive value. Benedict, like Marett, relied on mana or mana-like concepts to explicate the world view implicit in magic. The critics of this interpretation have pointed out its major flaw. Malinowski surely goes too far in his dismissal of mana concepts as part of religion at all (1948: 58). Norbeck, however, justly contends that many ethnographic accounts of magic describe no such concept nor indicate that the practitioners of magic entertain any idea of this kind ( 1963 :5 10). Apparent logical necessity or desire for a neat theory are insufficient grounds for imputing its covert presence. Norbeck (1961 :49), therefore, suggests that religion includes three power concepts: personified power, impersonal power such as mana, and “a conception of supernatural efficiency or power inherent in certain mechanical cause and effect sequences.” In short, although some magical practices can be related to mana, a large residue appears as unexplained automatic efficacy. Magic exploits a seeming cause-and-effect sequence without any accounting for either the nature of the cause or the nexus between them. Some anthropologists take this quality of being inexplicable to be the very essence of what constitutes magic. It is a “mysterious art” (Bidney 1963 5 0 5 ) ; magic lacks theory (Howells 1948:49); magic has no cosmological content (Middleton 1967: ix); magic specifically refers to that which cannot be made orderly and comprehensible (Galtier 19635 0 6 ) . If magical systems are without rationale or meaning, it is their pervasiveness and persistence that are truly inexplicable. Magic is presumed to have only expressive functions and an attributed instrumental utility. But it is most unlikely that magic can have these values for human beings unless they somehow perceive its relevance to their conception of reality. Otherwise, magic is utterly anomalous-a symbol without a referent, a projection without a source. There are substantial data to show that such a position is hardly tenable. The fairly Magic: A Problem in Semantics HAMMOND] frequent attribution of all deaths and major misfortunes to witchcraft and sorcery, for example, patently demonstrates cognition in magic. Witchcraft and sorcery reflect social conflict and obviously express hostility and resentment of loss. Rituals are used as instruments of prevention and vengeance, but they also express a cosmology. The cosmos is held to be benign or neutral; evil derives from the character of human beings. No matter how elliptically phrased, it is a seriQUS statement about the nature and locus of evil. Primitive societies rarely produce their own theologians. Usually the task of abstracting conceptual content from symbolic expression in myth and ritual devolves on ethnologists who have tended to concentrate on myth. Kluckhohn (1965: 147) suggests that the preference reflects the importance of statements of belief in Western religions. Perhaps it has seemed easier to move from one set of words-the myth-to another set of words-a statement of its meaning-than to translate rituals into statements. That which is communicated by a gesture is often hard to put into words. With difficulty or not, a reasonably close reading of the anthropological literature discloses that magic ritual does indeed communicate its meaning. The gesture is understood, but the commenters seem to resist recognizing their own insight. Those who deny cognition in magic seem not to be listening to what they themselves say. Howells, for example, in one passage finds no adequate explanation for the potency of magic (1948:49-50); elsewhere he writes that magic gives man the “conviction that he can take care of himself. . . Man can put his best foot forward with magic; he can act on his own behalf. . (1948:63). Statement after statement can be found that point to the central concept in magic. “In magic man depends on his own strength . .” (Frazer 1900:711). “Magic is the one and only specific power, a force unique of its kind, residing exclusively in man. .” (Malinowski 194856). “Magic is not thought to take place by itself. It is only . .” . . .. . 1353 when men make magic . . . that results are to be expected” (Beattie 1964:206). Magic “is never looked upon as one of the forces of nature which can be utilized by man, but is regarded as a cherished cultural possession which derives its powers from man’s abstinence and from his knowledge of tradition” (Evans-Pritchard 1967:4). The power that makes magic effective is a projection of man’s capacity to act effectively by means of his knowledge and skill. Analysis of myths for the meaning of magic also seems to have encountered some anthropological resistance. It is true, as Nadel remarks, that there are magical systems without associated myths (1957: 192); but this sometimes can also be said of other kinds of rituals. According to Evans-Pritchard, the relatively few Zande myths about magic do not account for its power (1967: 10-12). Although Trobriand mythology is much richer, Malinowski emphasized that it too lacks such explanation (1948: 117). There are, however, myths elsewhere that do have bearing on what magic signifies. In Winnebago mythology Hare achieves a sense of identity with his human kinsmen; with the acquisition of arrows, a bow, and the skill to use them he acquires the symbolic essence of human culture. And thus, as the exemplar of what is truly human, he proceeds to make curing rituals (Radin 1948). It is hard to see how a myth could more plainly state its meaning than the Nupe myth that tells of a man who once attempted to seek out god. His long arduous quest was fruitless, and he returned to report that god was both distant and indzerent. Men, therefore, must help themselves by learning how to make “medicine” (Nadel 1954: 17-18). The reluctance to find the rituals and myths of magic meaningful might hint that anthropologists too share the attitude Malinowski (194851 ) describes: “ ‘Magic’ seems to stir up in everyone some hidden mental forces, some lingering hopes in the miraculous, some dormant beliefs in man’s mysterious possibilities.” These human potentialities are not 80 American Anthropologist 1354 mysterious. Norbeck (1961 : 5 0 ) suggests that magic has its mundane analogue in technology. To a certain extent this is obviously true, and yet it seems to miss the main point. Horton (1968:66) argues that a technological prototype tends to give rise to explanatory models that are secular or scientific in character. Although this sequence need not be universally true, it supports the idea that magic and technology per se are not closely linked. Magic seems to concern techniques far less than the user’s skill, knowledge, or talents. Leach’s comment that mark. But “libido” in the strictly psychotency” (1967:98) is perhaps closer to the the mark. But “libido” in the strictly psychoanalytic sense-and judging by the tenor of his article that is how Leach means itscarcely refers directly to man’s capacity for effective action on the basis of culturally acquired skills. Lhi-Strauss plainly considers magic to be a projection of human action, but he does not make entirely clear the grounds for his interpretation. Moreover, his analysis seems to involve an unnecessarily complex sequence of processes of projection, introjection, and reprojection ( 1966: 220-22 1) On the whole, it seems both economical and reasonable to reinterpret Norbeck‘s triad of power concepts on the basic assumption that these are best understood as projective symbols. The power of spiritual beings reflects the authority of other people. (Whether this is the authority of the clan as Durkheim had it or that of the father in the Freudian view is here immaterial.) Magical power reflects the capabilities of the self, and mana, the dynamic forces of the physical universe. Man’s ability to acquire skills and use them to shape his world is thus projected as one of the universal superordinate powers. The traditional hostility between deistic belief and magical belief is understandable. An ideology that holds man to be wholly dependent on powerful gods must view a conception of man as one of the ruling forces in the cosmos as hubris of a most literal and damnable kind. . [72, 1970 Erwin R. Goodenough, discussing the persistence of magical practices in Judaism, writes that religious symbols “originally of direct and inherent power have gradually been made to refer in addition to more remote spiritual forces” (1953: 160). The use of the adjective “remote” is highly suggestive. In small-scale societies, effective action is performed by the self and by familiar others. In large-scale societies, the exercise of power by distant authorities or even unknown agents may provide the source for the projection of “remote spiritual forces.” But the immediacies are never wholly superseded, and even those religions that place most weight on a transcendent omnipotent deity retain practices expressing the projection of the immediate. Spiro, who defines religion narrowly as belief in superhuman beings, argues that the child‘s dependency on adults “develops images of powerful figures” and that these “deep-seated perceptive sets, acquired in the very early experience of the child, comprise the essential basis for the actor’s conviction that the beliefs which comprise the religious tradition of his society are true” (1964: 113). On the same basis it can be argued that the validity of magical belief is equally rooted in the child’s experience. The child quite early discovers his own power to summon and dismiss, to grasp and release, to build and destroy. Maturation and enculturation further his sense of mastery, and this experience will be repeated every day of his effectively functioning life. Magic is no mere compensatory fantasy to palliate the inadequacies of primitive technologies. The simpler hand technologies would more likely induce a greater sense of mastery than machine technolog, no matter how productive and efficient. Witness the satisfaction in building a fire, even with the help of a box of matches and the Sunday paper, compared to resetting the thermostat. Moreover, it is not the incompetents of a society who are granted magical power. The awareness of the power of the self is by no means necessarily limited to mastery over technological processes and material ... HAMMOND] Magic: A Problem in Semantics objects. Although it is the dependency of the child that “develops images of powerful figures,” this need not develop an accompanying feeling of utter helplessness. The beloved child in almost any society may well have a keen sense of his own ability to manipulate adults, In the give-and-take of intimate association those in subordinate positions are not without means to gain compliance with their desires from their superiors. And those in positions of authority are obviously able to control the actions of other people. One must also recognize that beliefs in impersonal power, such as mana, have an equally early and significant base in the child‘s experience with pressure, motion, heat, light, and all the other manifestations of a dynamic universe. There has been no attempt in this paper to analyze mana concepts. It has, however, been assumed that the existence of impersonal power is one of the fundamental postulates of many religions. The position that religious cosmology is comprised of three equally legitimate concepts of superordinate power makes the reality of magic as a separate entity altogether doubtful. The potency symbolized in magical practices is interwoven with the other powers. It can be used to exploit mana or constrain the gods. Conversely, such power may be the gift of a supernatural being. It seems appropriate then to limit the range of meaning of the term-to restrict “magic” to the designation of mechanical religious practices. This is, in effect, the way many anthropologists actually use the term, although they do so without any explicit rationale. Magic would serve as a denotation for one type of ritual behavior, and thus belong to the set of terms in that category, such as prayer or sacrifice. With these propitiatory rites it is contrastive, not with religion. Just as prayer and sacrifice express the belief that the universe is governed by personified beings whom one can reach by words and gifts, so magical practices express the belief in human powers as effective forces. The use of such practices in rituals addressed to the gods is not a discordant intru- 1355 sion of magic into religion. The composite ritual states-that the gods do not rule done; their will and power are accompanied by the will and power of men. Examination of the concept indicates that the distinction between magic and religion, whether phrased as dichotomy or polarity, is unwarranted. Magic is not an entity distinct from religion but a form of ritual behavior and thus an element of religion. That the distinction has led only to confusion supports the judgment that the abstraction is based on misinterpretation. It has not only falsified the relation between religion and magic, and led to obscurantism concerning magic, but it has also given rise to a truncated concept of religion as a whole. The cosmological concepts inherent in religions are more complex than belief in spiritual beings only. Because the index of “belief in superhuman beings” recognizes only one aspect of religion, it seems preferable to substitute the definition that religion entails belief in superordinate agencies. REFERENCES CITED B E A ~ EJOHN , 1964 Other cultures. New York: Free Press. 1967 Divination in Bunyoro, Uganda. I n Magic, witchcraft, and curing. John Middleton, ed. Garden City: Natural History Press. BENEDICT,RUTH 1Y38 Religion. I n General anthropology. Franz Boas, ed. Boston: Heath. BIDNEY,DAVID Comment on Murray and Rosalie Wax, the notion of magic. Current Anthropology 4 :495-518. DURKHEIM, EMILE 1915 The elementary forms of the religious life. Joseph Ward Swain, London: Allen and Unwin. [original ed. 1912.1 EVANS-PRITCHARD, E. E. 1965 Theories of primitive religion. London: Oxford University Press. 1967 The morphology and function of magic: a comparative study of Trobriand and Zande ritual and spells. I n Magic, witchcraft, and curing. John Middleton, ed. Garden City: The Natural History Press. JAMESG. FRAZER, 1900 The golden bough. 2nd ed. London: Macmillan Co. [References are to 1922 abridgment.I 1963 1356 American Anthropologist GALTIER,CHARLES 1963 Comment on Murray and Rosalie Wax, the notion of magic. Current Anthropology 4: 495-5 18. GEERTZ,CLIFFORD 1968 Ethos, world-view and the analysis of sacred symbols. In Every man his way. Alan Dundes, ed. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall. GOODE,WILLIAMJ. 1951 Religion among the primitives. Glencoe: The Free Press. GOODENOUGH, ERWINR. 1953 Jewish symbols in the Greco-Roman period. Vol. 2. Bollinger Series 37. New York: Pantheon Books. GOODENOUGH, WARDHUNT 1963 Cooperation in change. New York: Russell Sage Foundation. GOODY,JACK 1961 Religion and ritual: the definition problem. British Journal of Sociology 12: 142-1 64. HORTON,ROBIN 1960 A definition of religion and its uses. Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute 90:201-220. 1968 Ritual man in Africa. In Readings in anthropology. Morton Fried, ed. New York: Crowell. HOWELLS,WILLIAM 1948 The heathens. Garden City: Doubleday. KLUCKHOHN, CLYDE 1965 Myths and rituals: a general theory. Ztr Reader in comparative religion. William A. Lessa and Evon Z. Vogt, eds. New York: Harper and Row. LEACH,EDMUND R. 1967 Magical hair. In Myth and cosmos. John Middleton, ed. Garden City: The Natural History Press. L~vI-STRAUSS, CLAUDE 1966 The savage mind. Chicago: The Uni- [72, 19701 versity of Chicago Press. MALINOWSKI,BRONISLAW 1948 Magic, science, and religion. Glencoe: The Free Press. MARETT,R. R. 1914 The threshold of religion. London: Methuen. MIDDLETON, JOHN 1967 Introduction. In Magic, witchcraft, and curing. John Middleton, ed. Garden City: The Natural History Press. NADEL,S. F. 1954 Nupe religion. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. 1957 Malinowski on magic and religion. In Man and culture. Raymond Firth, ed. New York: Humanities Press. NORBECK,EDWARD 1961 Religion in primitive society. New York: Harper. 1963 Comment on Murray and Rosalie Wax, the notion of magic. Current Anthropology 4:495-5 18. RADIN,PAUL 1948 Winnebago hero cycles. Indiana Publications in Anthropology and Linguistics, Memoir 1. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. SPIRO,MELFORD 1964 Religion and the irrational. In Symposium on new approaches to the study of religion. Proceedings of the American Ethnological Society. Seattle: University of Washington Press. 1966 Religion: problems of definition and explanation. In Anthropological approaches to the study of religion. A.S.A. Monographs 3:85-126. London: Tavistock. TYLOR,EDWARD B. 1889 Primitive culture. 2nd ed. New York: Holt. [First ed. 1871.1 WARNER,W. LLOYD 1937 A black civilization. New York: Harper.