IN THE MATTER OF THE HUNTING BILL AND THE EUROPEAN CONVENTION ON HUMAN RIGHTS OPINION I. Introduction 1. We are asked by the International Fund for Animal Welfare to advise whether the Hunting Bill, as amended by the House of Commons and put before the House of Lords in June 2003 as HL Bill 95 (‘the Bill’), is compatible with the European Convention on Human Rights (‘the Convention’). We are asked particularly to focus on Article 8, Article 11, Article 14, and Article 1 of Protocol 1, as well as on the issues raised in the seventeenth report of the Joint Committee on Human Rights. 2. 2. In summary, it is our opinion that the Bill – if passed into law – would be compatible with the Convention. We consider that Articles 8 and 11 are not applicable to this case and that any interference with rights falling within their scope is in any event justified. We consider that Article 1 of Protocol 1 and Article 14 are likely to be applicable but, again, that any interferences with the rights protected by those Articles are justified. We take the view that Bill raises no significant issues under any other Articles of the Convention. The Bill 3. Clause 1 of the Bill provides that A person commits an offence if he hunts a wild mammal with a dog, unless his hunting is exempt. 1 Clause 4 provides that it is a defence for a person to show that he reasonably believed that the hunting in question was exempt. 4. The exemptions are contained in Schedule 1 and include: Paragraph 1 – Stalking a wild mammal or flushing it out of cover if certain conditions are met. One such condition is that reasonable steps are taken to ensure that the wild mammal is shot dead and that the dogs used are controlled so that they do not obstruct this objective (which seems to us broadly to mean that dogs may be used to find and expose a wild mammal but reasonable steps must be taken to ensure that they do not kill it or attack it). Paragraphs 3 and 4 – Hunting rats and rabbits Paragraphs 7 and 8 – Recapturing and rescuing wild mammals (again, provided that reasonable steps are taken to ensure that the dogs do not obstruct the objectives of recapture or the relief of suffering) 5. It is also an offence, under clause 3, for a person to permit land or dogs belonging to him to be used in the course of the commission of an offence under clause 1. 6. Hare coursing (namely a competition in which dogs are, by the use of live hares, assessed as to skill in hunting hares) and certain activities related to it are made offences by clause 5. Where this opinion refers to hunting, it should be taken as including hare coursing unless the context requires otherwise. Background 7. Bills proposing a ban or the formal regulation of hunting have been put before Parliament on many occasions. Prior to 2000, each had been introduced as a Private Member’s Bill. The Government first introduced a Hunting Bill into the House of Commons on 7 December 2000, amidst 2 considerable publicity. The Bill considered in this Opinion is the most recent version, introduced to the House of Commons on 3 December 2002, as amended and sent to the House of Lords. 8. In December 1999, the Government appointed a committee, chaired by Lord Burns, to hold an inquiry into hunting with dogs and the effect of a ban. The Burns Report was completed on 9 June 2000. Its conclusions included the following (paragraph references are to the Summary and Conclusions section): Population management Most farmers, landowners and gamekeepers consider that fox populations need to be managed. Most foxes are probably killed by methods involving guns. In lowland areas, other means of control could replace all hunting with dogs; in upland areas, it would be difficult to avoid the use of dogs for flushing out to guns or for digging out – paragraphs 34 and 35. Hunting with dogs kills only about 15% of culled red deer – paragraph 38. There is no real need to cull hares; hare coursing is essentially recreational – paragraph 40. Hunting with dogs does not have any significant effect on the mink population – paragraph 43. Animal welfare None of the legal methods of killing foxes is without difficulty from a welfare perspective. However, hunting with dogs above ground can lead to death from ‘massive injuries to the chest and vital organs, although insensibility and death will normally follow within seconds’. The Committee was ‘satisfied… that this experience seriously compromises the welfare of the fox’. The Committee’s ‘tentative conclusion’ was that lamping has fewer adverse welfare implications, though it was less confident that 3 the use of shotguns was necessarily preferable to hunting with dogs – paragraphs 56-61. Most scientists agree that deer are likely to suffer in the final stages of hunting. Stalking is in principle the better method of culling deer from an animal welfare perspective – paragraphs 51 and 52. Being pursued, caught, and killed by dogs seriously compromises the welfare of hares – paragraph 64. There seems reason to suppose that the same applies to mink – paragraph 67. Employment 6,000-8,000 jobs depend to some degree on hunting, 700 of which result from direct employment by hunts and 1,500-3,000 of which result from direct employment on hunting-related activities. It is not possible to say how many jobs would be lost if hunting were banned – paragraphs 18 and 19. Other aspects of hunting Hunting is a recreational activity. It also plays a part in social and cultural life the loss of which would be keenly felt, though this varies greatly from community to community – paragraphs 22 and 26. 9. In 2002, the Scottish Parliament passed the Protection of Wild Mammals (Scotland) Act 2002, which is similar to the Bill. It has been challenged twice in the Outer House of the Court of Session, in Trevor Adams and others v Scottish Ministers [2003] SC 171 and Whaley and Friend v the Lord Advocate (judgment of 20 June 2003). To a considerable degree, these cases raise issues which coincide with those raised by our instructions. In both cases, the court held that the prohibition on hunting wild mammals with dogs did not violate the Convention. 10. In those cases, the petitioners averred the following facts, among others: 4 Hunting is a long-established activity in which people from many different walks of life participate. It contributes to the social cohesiveness of rural communities and is an intensely social activity. It is partly a recreational activity and partly an effective means of controlling fox populations – Adams, paragraphs 36, 37, 40, 41. Hunting communities are ethnic communities. Banning hunting can take away hunters’ lifestyles and remove their ‘primary characteristic’. There is no automatic right to join a hunt: people must apply and be admitted – Whaley, paragraph 22. 10. With regard to the compatibility of the 2002 Act with the Convention, in Adams, the court held that: Fox hunting with dogs does not fall within the scope of ‘private life’ within the meaning of Article 8 (paragraphs 102-103) and large estates of land are not part of the ‘home’ within the meaning of Article 8 (paragraph 102) However, the livelihood of a self-employed huntsman is a ‘possession’ which is ‘controlled’ by a ban within the meaning of Article 1 of Protocol 1 (paragraph 129) and the Act treated people differently by distinguishing between types of hunter, which was a ground within the meaning of Article 14 (paragraph 136) Taking into account the discretionary area of judgment accorded to the Scottish Parliament, any interference with Convention rights was nevertheless justified (e.g. paragraph 136). 11. In Whaley, the court held that: Fox hunting has a public rather than private quality for the purposes of Article 8 (paragraphs 64-65) 5 Huntsmen do not belong to a minority generally recognised as in need of special protection; the pursuit of fox hunting as a profession or as a recreation cannot be said to be integral to the individual personality of every member of a hunt so as to engage Article 8 (paragraph 69) The prohibition on fox hunting does not impinge on thought, religion, or belief within the meaning of Article 9 (paragraph 72) Article 10 confers no entitlement to carry on fox hunting (paragraph 77) Article 11 is not engaged because the prohibition prevents a particular activity rather than the assembling of a hunt (paragraph 80) Even if Articles 8-11 were engaged Parliament was within its discretionary area of judgment in concluding that the prohibition was necessary for the protection of morals (paragraph 87) Engaging in mounted fox hunting does not confer a personal characteristic or ‘status’ for the purposes of Article 14 (paragraph 96) 12. The seventeenth report of the Joint Committee on Human Rights has raised a further issue. The Committee considered that the Bill was not incompatible with Article 8 was potentially incompatible with Article 1 of Protocol 1 because ‘the Bill… so far as it would have made unlawful the performance of contracts already entered into, would have been likely to deprive the parties to the contracts of the benefit of them… As a general principle, compensation for such a deprivation is required under P1/1 [Article 1 of Protocol 1] unless there is the strongest justification for not providing it’ (paragraph 1.16). 13. We agree with the Court of Session in Whaley that arguments under Articles 9 and 10 are of virtually no merit, and so we propose to consider Articles 8 and 11, Article 1 of Protocol 1, and Article 14. In doing so, it is important to bear in mind that arguments under those Articles might be made by individuals in a number of capacities, including (a) as recreational 6 hunters, (b) as landowners, (c) as owners of dogs and hunting equipment, and (d) as professional, employed hunters. II. Article 8 14. Article 8 provides that 1. Everyone has the right to respect for his private and family life, his home and his correspondence. 2. There shall be no interference by a public authority with the exercise of this right except such as is in accordance with the law and is necessary in a democratic society in the interests of national security, public safety or the economic well-being of the country, for the prevention of disorder or crime, for the protection of health or morals, or for the protection of the rights and freedoms of others. Potential arguments against the Bill 15. In our view, the potential arguments under Article 8 are that the Bill, without justification, would (i) interfere with the right to respect for private life by preventing hunters from hunting; and/or (ii) interfere with the right to respect for the home by preventing landowners from using their land or allowing their land to be used for hunting. 16. It is our view that a ban on hunting with dogs interferes neither with respect for private life nor with respect for the home and that, if there were any such interference, it is justified. Interference 7 Private life 17. Hunting is, in our view, an inherently public activity. The hunters themselves describe it as highly social and a community interest. Even when it takes place on private land, it generally involves large groups of people and is in open view to anyone who happens to be passing. It is difficult to see how it could be described as ‘private’. 18. We maintain this view despite the fact that ‘private life’ has been interpreted generously by the European Court as covering, for example, certain activities which take place in public. In PG & JH v United Kingdom [2002] Crim LR 308, the European Court summarised the position at paragraph 56: ‘Private life is a broad term not susceptible to exhaustive definition. The Court has already held that elements such as gender identification, name and sexual orientation and sexual life are important elements of the personal sphere protected by Article 8… Article 8 also protects a right to identity and personal development, and the right to establish and develop relationships with other human beings and the outside world… It may include activities of a professional or business nature… There is therefore a zone of interaction with others, even in a public context, which may fall within the scope of “private life”.’ 19. There are limits, however: in our view, there must be some clear private or personal element to an activity to bring it within the definition. In PG, for example, the applicant’s voices were recorded when being charged for an offence and when in their police cell and later analysed. This did interfere with their private life even though their conversations took place in not wholly private circumstances, but this was because information personal to them was thereby covertly obtained and stored. Moreover, the applicants could properly expect that their conversations would be private and would not be recorded and analysed. The same did not apply, for example, to demonstrators whose photographs were taken in Friedl v Austria (1995) 21 EHRR 83: accordingly, this did not interfere with their private life. In our 8 view, the Bill does not impinge on huntsmen in any comparable fashion, nor can they have any reasonable expectation to privacy when hunting. 20. Moreover, in our opinion, mere engagement with others cannot of itself involve private life. Thus, in Botta v Italy (1998) 26 EHRR 241 the European Court held that the right to obtain access to a beach concerned ‘interpersonal relations of such broad and indiscriminate scope’ that it could not concern the applicant’s private life. To rely on the highly communal aspects of hunting to bring it within the sphere of private life seems to us to turn Article 8 on its head. 21. Nor can it sensibly be suggested that Article 8 in any sense engenders a general right of liberty of action which does not have a specifically private character, despite the comment in paragraph 61 of Pretty v United Kingdom (2002) 35 EHRR 1 that ‘the notion of personal autonomy is an important principle underlying the interpretation of [Article 8] guarantees’. This cannot, in our view, be taken to mean that Article 8 confers a right to conduct oneself as one pleases, as emphasised by the intensely personal context of Pretty. The ability, by bringing about one’s own death, to put an end to personal suffering and to prevent a humiliating death caused by debilitating illness stands in stark contrast to the activity of hunting. 22. Finally, we do not think that huntsmen can rely on being a minority group to bring their activity into the sphere of private life. It is true that in Chapman v United Kingdom (2001) EHRR 18, as well as other cases, it has been recognised that interfering in the lifestyle of minority groups might engage Article 8. In Chapman, a Gypsy’s private life was held to be in issue when she was refused planning permission to station her caravan at a particular site. But this was because this was so integral to her traditional, minority lifestyle that it impinged directly on her personal identity and ‘her ability to lead her private life… within that tradition’ (paragraph 73; emphasis added). We do not think that hunters are a minority group in the same sense: they themselves proclaim the wide and varying backgrounds of those who participate in hunts. This is so whether 9 or not there is some application system for joining a hunt: that does not make them an ethnic minority or other minority group by way of analogy with Chapman. This is consistent with the Scottish court’s decision in Whaley. Moreover, we do not consider that the activity of hunting can be said to be sufficiently part of the identity of a person who engages in it to form part of his private life. Home 23. In our view, it is unlikely that a landowner can claim that the land he uses for hunting is his home. The European Court seems to interpret ‘home’ as a settled place where a person lives or at least has sufficient domiciliary connections – see Niemietz v Germany (1993) 16 EHRR 97, at paragraphs 30 and 31 (where the European Court went so far as to say that a professional office could fall within the scope of ‘home’ in certain circumstances). It does not seem to encompass all the land a person happens to own, though, whatever his connections with it. In Loizidou v Turkey (1996) 23 EHRR 513, for example, the Court held that ‘it would strain the meaning of the notion “home” in Article 8 to extend it to comprise property on which it is planned to build a house for residential purposes. Nor can that term be interpreted to cover an area… where one has grown up and where the family has its roots but where one no longer lives.’ 24. We know of no case where the European Court has considered whether land which adjoins a place of residence forms part of the ‘home’. In our view, while a small, ‘lived-in’ garden might well do so, it is unlikely that land which is vast and wild enough to sustain hunting with dogs forms part of the ‘home’. This is supported by the view taken by the Scottish courts. Justification 25. Even if it could be said that the Bill does interfere with the right to respect for private life or the home, it is highly likely, in our view, that a court would consider such an interference to be justified under paragraph 2 of Article 8. 10 26. In our view, any interference caused by the Bill would meet the first requirement of being ‘in accordance with the law’. This means that it must be accessible and formulated sufficiently precisely to allow individuals to regulate their conduct (Sunday Times v United Kingdom (1979) 2 EHRR 245, paragraph 49). In our view, the Bill is clear and precise and meets these criteria. 27. To be justified, an interference must also be necessary in a democratic society in pursuit of a legitimate aim listed in the Article. In this regard, it must correspond to a pressing social need, be proportionate to that need, and be supported by relevant and sufficient reasons (Sunday Times, paragraph 62). 28. Since this involves balancing the public interest against the rights of individuals, the courts will allow Parliament a discretionary area of judgment. This is a domestic law doctrine which is not the same as but is similar to the Strasbourg doctrine of the ‘margin of appreciation’. This was first recognised in Handyside v United Kingdom (1979-80) 1 EHRR 737, in which the European Court said at paragraph 48: ‘By reason of their direct and continuous contact with the vital forces of their countries, State authorities are in principle in a better position than the international judge to give an opinion on the exact content of these requirements as well as on the “necessity” of a “restriction” or “penalty” intended to meet them… It is for the national authorities to make the initial assessment of the reality of the pressing social need implied by the notion of “necessity” in this context.’ 29. Domestic courts have recognised that this reasoning does not apply in quite the same way in the domestic context. However, similar principles do apply in certain circumstances. Thus, in R v DPP, ex parte Kebilene [2000] 2 AC 326, at page 380: ‘Difficult choices may have to be made by the executive or the legislature between the rights of the individual and the needs of society. In some circumstances it will be appropriate for the courts to 11 recognise that there is an area of judgment within which the judiciary will defer, on democratic grounds, to the considered opinion of the elected body or person whose act or decision is said to be incompatible with the Convention… It will be easier for such an area of judgment to be recognised when the Convention itself requires a balance to be struck, much less so where the right is stated in terms which are unqualified. It will be easier for it to be recognised where the issues involve questions of social or economic policy, much less so where the rights are of high constitutional importance or are of a kind where the courts are especially well placed to assess the need for protection.’ See also the comments of Lord Bingham, sitting in the Privy Council, at page 703 of Brown v Stott [2003] 1 AC 681. Numerous similar comments have been made since then at all levels of the domestic legal system: see e.g. R (ProLife Alliance) v BBC [2003] 2 All ER 977, especially paras. 7477 (Lord Hoffmann) and 131-144 (Lord Walker). 30. In our view, it is highly likely that a court would recognise that the Bill pursued a legitimate aim, namely ‘the protection of morals’. It seems to us indisputable that the treatment of animals and the means taken to prevent perceived cruelty to animals is a question of public morality. There is ample evidence to support the view that hunting with dogs harms the welfare of animals, not least the Burns Inquiry, summarised above. The European Court has shown itself willing to accept the assertions of the government as to the aim it is pursuing in the absence of clear evidence that it was not acting in good faith (see, for example, Tre Traktorer Aktiebolag v Sweden, (1991) 13 EHRR 309, paragraphs 56-58) and, as recognised in Handyside, questions of public morals fall squarely within the ‘discretionary area of judgment’. In this case in particular, hunting with dogs is a matter of acute public controversy where deference to the elected legislature is likely to be extensive. It may well be that, if the Bill is enacted, those who oppose it will be able to persuade a future Parliament, perhaps as a result of a change of government, to take a different view as to what public morals require: that simply illustrates that this issue falls within the essentially political arena, which in a democracy is to be resolved by Parliament and not by the courts. 12 31. We also consider that the Bill is consistent with the requirements of proportionality. Once it is accepted that the legitimate aim is to prevent cruelty to wild animals by hunting and killing them with dogs, then there is no real option but full prohibition. Statutory regulation would hardly be adequate as, by definition, it would allow the offending activity to persist. In our view, it lies well within the discretionary area of judgment for Parliament to conclude that banning fox hunting corresponds proportionately to a pressing social need and does so for relevant and sufficient reasons. III. Article 11 32. Article 11 provides: 1. Everyone has the right to freedom of peaceful assembly and to freedom of association with others, including the right to form and join trade unions for the protection of his interests. 2. No restrictions shall be placed on the exercise of these rights other than such as are prescribed by law and are necessary in a democratic society… for the protection of… morals… Potential arguments against the Bill 33. The argument would appear to be that the Bill violates Article 11 by preventing hunters from gathering to hunt. It is clear that they are not prevented from gathering for any other lawful reason. Application 34. In our view, Article 11 is unlikely to be held applicable in this case. 35. Firstly, a hunt is not, in our opinion, an ‘association’ within the meaning of Article 11. As the European Commission of Human Rights stated in Mark Anderson v United Kingdom (1998) 25 EHRR CD 172, ‘freedom of association… has been described as a right for individuals to associate “in 13 order to attain various ends”’ and not for merely “social” purposes. In our view, the killing of foxes is not an ‘end’ contemplated by the Article; it is of a wholly different nature from the objectives of the organisations which Article 11 is generally held to cover, such as political parties, professional bodies, and religious organisations. 36. Secondly, the right of peaceful assembly – and there is room to doubt whether a hunt could properly be called ‘peaceful’ in any event – does not provide a right ‘to assemble for purely social purposes’ (Anderson). 37. Thirdly, huntsmen are not prohibited from assembling or associating at all. They are merely prohibited from conducting themselves in a particular manner once they have done so: they may still ride together or take part in a mock hunt, for example. As the European Court said at paragraph 38 of National Union of Belgian Police v Belgium (1970) 1 EHRR 578, ‘the Article does not guarantee any particular treatment’ even of trade unions, which are listed as a ‘special aspect of freedom of association’. 38. However, it must be recognised that there is a possibility that Article 11 would be held to apply. At paragraph 102 of Chassagnou v France (1999) 29 EHRR 615, that the European Court held that Associations communales de chasses agrees (bodies consisting of huntsmen and landowners) were associations within the meaning of Article 11. However, these bodies were set up by law for a particular purpose: ‘to encourage, on their hunting grounds, an increase in game stock, the destruction of vermin and the prevention of poaching, to instruct their members in how to hunt without interfering with property rights or crops and in general to improve the technical organisation of hunting so that the sport can be practised in a more satisfactory manner’. In our view, these bodies and their purposes are different from British hunts, though they are more akin, perhaps, to the Countryside Alliance. The Countryside Alliance, of course, could still exist and operate if the Bill were passed (though it would be restrained from inciting the criminal offence). We still consider, therefore, that Article 11 would not be engaged by the passage of the Bill. 14 Justification 39. Even if the Bill did interfere with the right to freedom of peaceful assembly and association, we take the view that such interference would be held justified for essentially the same reasons given in relation to Article 8 at paragraphs 25-31 above. IV. Article 1 of Protocol 1 40. Article 1 of Protocol 1 provides: Every natural or legal person is entitled to the peaceful enjoyment of his possessions. No one shall be deprived of his possessions except in the public interest and subject to the conditions provided for by law and by the general principles of international law. The preceding provisions shall not, however, impair the right of a State to enforce such laws as it deems necessary to control to use of property in accordance with the general interest or to secure the payment of taxes or other contributions or penalties. Potential arguments against the Bill 41. The arguments appear to be that the Bill violates Article 1 of Protocol 1 because, without justification and without providing for compensation, it: (i) prevents landowners from using their land or allowing their land to be used for hunting; and/or (ii) prevents owners of dogs and hunting equipment to use those dogs or that equipment for hunting; and/or (iii) prevents professional hunters or those directly employed in hunting from attaining the benefit of their contracts of employment (namely wages) and/or exercising their profession. 15 Possessions 42. As the European Court held in James v United Kingdom (1986) 8 EHRR 123 at paragraph 37, this Article ‘in substance guarantees the right of property’. There can be no doubt that land, dogs, and hunting equipment are possessions within the meaning of the Article. However, the matter is more complex with regard to contractual rights and to the fruits of a business or profession. 43. It is clear that Article 1 of Protocol 1 applies only to existing and not to future possessions (Marckx v Belgium (1970) 2 EHRR 330, paragraph 50). However, in certain circumstances, a right to a future possession might itself be a possession for the purposes of the Article. In Andrews v United Kingdom (App. no. 37657/97, decision of 26 September 2000), the European Court held that ‘future income itself is only a “possession” once it has been earned, or an enforceable claim to it exists’ and in Gratzinger v Czech Republic, it said that ‘“possessions” within the meaning of Article 1 of Protocol 1 can be either “existing possessions”… or assets, including claims, in respect of which an applicant can argue that he has at least a legitimate expectation that they will be realised…’ This might include contractual rights (Association of General Practitioners v Denmark 62 DR 226). 44. In our view, therefore, the anticipated fruits of a contractual agreement will be ‘possessions’ within the meaning of Article 1 of Protocol 1 only if (i) there is an enforceable, legal right to them, and (ii) there is a legitimate expectation that they will be obtained. 45. As far as we can see, the only contracts the conclusion of which would be prevented by the Bill would be contracts of employment directly relating to prohibited hunting. There is no reason why other contracts, say for sale of equipment or land, should not be completed (there might, of course, be 16 issues with regard to interference with the enjoyment of the property forming the subject of the contract, but that is another matter). 46. It is our view that nobody has a legitimate expectation to permanent employment. Any legal right to future employment under a contract extends only so far as the applicable notice period (as recognised by the European Commission in Association of General Practitioners). Moreover, we do not see how, in the current climate, an employee whose job depends on hunting with dogs can have a legitimate expectation that he will remain in employment. The possibility that hunting with dogs might be made illegal has been public knowledge for several years. We respectfully doubt whether the Joint Committee on Human Rights was right to consider that a legitimate expectation might nonetheless survive because it is not certain that the Bill will be approved by Parliament. This appears to us to be inconsistent with the approach taken in National & Provincial Building Society v United Kingdom (1988) 25 EHRR 127, in which it was held that the applicants’ claims for restitution, partly based on a House of Lords judgment declaring a set of regulations unlawful, were not ‘possessions’. In part, this was because ‘it is reasonable to question whether the [applicants] could have had a “legitimate expectation”… that the Government would not have reacted as they did to the outcome of the litigation [namely by introducing a Bill into Parliament retrospectively to authorise the regulations]’ (paragraph 68). 47. Since the Bill is unlikely to come into force for quite some time yet, we consider it likely that any contractual right to employment which could amount to a ‘possession’ under Article 1 of Protocol 1 will no longer be in existence. 48. However, it is likely, in our opinion, that the economic interest of a professional hunter in continuing his profession as a business (if such a thing exists) would be a possession for the purposes of Article 1 of Protocol 1. In Tre Traktorer, paragraph 53, the European Court held that ‘the economic interests connected with the running of [a restaurant] were 17 “possessions” for the purposes of Article 1 of the Protocol’. (See also Karni v Sweden 55 DR 157 at 165.) Type of interference 49. The European Court held in James at paragraph 37 that Article 1 comprises ‘three distinct rules’: ‘the first rule, set out in the first sentence of the first paragraph, is of a general nature and enunciates the principle of the peaceful enjoyment of property; the second rule, contained in the second sentence of the first paragraph, covers deprivation of possessions and subjects it to certain conditions; the third rule, stated in the second paragraph, recognises that the Contracting States are entitled, amongst other things, to control the use of property in accordance with the general interest.’ 50. It is important to decide which of these three rules applies for the purposes of the proportionality exercise and, in particular, the requirement for compensation. The European Commission has held that ‘it follows from the case law of the Convention organs that as regards deprivation of possessions there is normally an inherent right to compensation… However, in the Commission’s view such a right to compensation is not inherent in the second paragraph [on control]… When assessing the proportionality of the regulation in question it will be of relevance whether compensation is available…’ (Baner v Sweden 60 DR 128). 51. In our view, the Bill controls the use of property rather than deprives people of their possessions. There is to be no transfer of ownership land, dogs, or equipment; the Bill merely prohibits their use for hunting with dogs. Moreover, the skills used by a professional hunter would be retained by him and available to be used elsewhere, not least for the purposes of lawful hunting. 52. We think it highly unlikely that it could be said that the degree of control was sufficient to amount to a de facto expropriation or that any economic 18 loss caused by this control could itself be held to be a deprivation of property. Firstly, economic gains from use of property are future possessions which cannot, in our opinion, legitimately be expected to materialise in this case. Secondly, while accepting the possibility of de facto expropriation if the enjoyment of property is so constrained that it is no longer of any real use, the European Court has made clear that there can be no deprivation while there remains some substance in the right to enjoy the property in question, even if some economic loss is sustained. For example, in Matos e Silva v Portugal (1997) 24 EHRR 573, at paragraph 85, the European Court held that the applicants were not deprived of their property by steps taken to expropriate their land for a nature reserve and to prevent them working the land. This was so even though the Court recognised that ‘the disputed measures have… greatly reduced [the applicants’ right to deal with and use their possessions] in practice… and affect the very substance of ownership in that three of them recognise in advance the lawfulness of expropriation’. Justification 53. An interference with property rights may be justified if it is in the ‘public interest’, in the case of a deprivation, or the ‘general interest’, in the case of control of use. The Court has held that this requires a balancing exercise to be carried out in much the same way as that required by the second paragraphs of Articles 8 and 11, i.e. that there has to be a legitimate aim and the interference has to satisfy the test of proportionality. However, the requirements are less stringent. The text is not identical: there is no requirement for the interference to be “necessary” in a democratic society. The European Court has noted in James at paragraph 46 that ‘the notion of “public interest” is necessarily extensive’ and that ‘the Court… will respect the legislature’s judgment as to what is “in the public interest” unless that judgment be manifestly without reasonable foundation”. 19 54. Since our view is that any interference to property rights is properly characterised as ‘control’, the issue of compensation is a relevant but far from decisive factor. We consider that the Bill is proportionate without it, especially having regard to the discretionary area of judgment to be afforded to Parliament in this sensitive area of social and economic policy. Accordingly, it is our view that any interference with the right to property under Article 1 of Protocol 1 is justified.1 V. Article 14 55. Article 14 provides: The enjoyment of the rights and freedoms set forth in this Convention shall be secured without discrimination on any ground such as sex, race, colour, language, religion, political or other opinion, national or social origin, association with a national, property, birth or other status. Potential arguments against the Bill 56. It could be argued that the Bill would be incompatible with Article 14 because it unjustifiably allows such hunting with dogs as falls within Schedule 1 but criminalises all other hunting with dogs. 57. The main distinctions would seem to be between (a) The prey: rabbits and rats may be hunted, while other wild mammals may not; (b) The purposes of the hunting: dogs may be used for flushing out, to locate animals for rescue, and so on; (c) The animals used for hunting: e.g. falconry is still permitted. We might add that, should a court hold that contractual rights to wages were ‘possessions’ contrary to our opinion, the Bill would deprive their owners of those possessions and would therefore trigger a right to compensation. This was the approach taken in Association of General Practitioners. 1 20 Requirements of Article 14 58. In Wandsworth LBC v Michalak [2003] WLR 617, the Court of Appeal listed four questions to be asked when considering Article 142. These same questions were asked by the European Court in Rasmussen v Denmark (1985) 7 EHRR 371. They are: (i) Do the facts fall within the ambit of one or more of the substantive Convention provisions? (ii) If so, was there different treatment as respects that right between the complainant on the one hand and other persons put forward for comparison on the other? (iii) Were the chosen comparators in an analogous situation to the complainant's situation? (iv) If so, did the difference in treatment have an objective and reasonable justification: in other words, did it pursue a legitimate aim and did the differential treatment bear a reasonable relationship of proportionality to the aim sought to be achieved? Ambit 59. As noted above, we consider that the only substantive Article engaged by the Bill is Article 1 of Protocol 1. Our view is therefore that only those persons who own the relevant property could rely on Article 14. However, it should be noted that ‘ambit’ is construed widely (see, for example, paragraphs 32-41 of the judgment of Laws LJ in The Queen (on the application of Carson) v Secretary of State for Work and Pensions [2003] 3 All ER 577) and there is a possibility that a court would consider that the Bill had an impact sufficiently related to the rights contained in Article 8 or Article 11 to fall within their ambit. 2 It has been stressed in a number of decisions since Michalak, as it was by Brooke LJ in that case itself, that the four questions should not be approached in a rigid way and may well merge into one another: see e.g. R (Purja) v Ministry of Defence [2004] 1 WLR 289, paragraphs 47, 66, and 70. 21 Different treatment 60. Clearly, there would be different treatment between a hunter whose manner of hunting fell within the exceptions and one whose manner of hunting did not. 61. However, in our view, this difference in treatment cannot be said to fall within one of the prohibited grounds. While the list in Article 14 is not exhaustive, it is clear from the wording of the Article itself and from case law such as James (paragraph 74) that a difference in treatment will only fall within Article 14 if it is based on a relevant ground. In Kjeldsen v Denmark (1970) 1 EHRR 711 (paragraph 56), that was interpreted to mean ‘a personal characteristic by which persons or groups of persons are distinguishable from each other’. 62. It should be noted that Brooke LJ observed in Michalak at paragraph that ‘the narrow approach evidenced in Kjeldsen's case… appears to have been superseded in… more recent decisions’ and that, in Rasmussen, the European Court took the view that ‘there is no call to determine on what ground this difference was based, the list of grounds appearing in Article 14 not being exhaustive’. However, we do not take this as meaning that there is no longer a need for a ‘status’ or ‘characteristic’; rather that such terms are accorded a relatively broad meaning. This can be seen from the recent case of Magee v United Kingdom (2001) 31 EHRR 22, in which, at paragraph 50, the European Court held that geographical location was not a ‘personal characteristic’ or ‘status’ and therefore different treatment on that basis did not violate Article 14. 63. In our view, the fact that a huntsman hunts a particular species or employs a particular means of hunting cannot be said to be a ‘status’ even in the broader sense of the word. Accordingly, there can be no discrimination contrary to Article 14. However, we consider for completeness the remaining issues under this Article below. 22 Analogous situation 64. At paragraph 61 of Carson, Laws LJ reformulated this question as follows: ‘are the circumstances of X and Y so similar as to call (in the mind of a rational and fair-minded person) for a positive justification for the less favourable treatment of Y in comparison with X?’ To a certain degree this question overlaps with the questions of different treatment and justification. However, taking it alone, it seems to us that, the positions of hunters falling within and without the exceptions are similar enough to be analogous. Justification 65. As the European Court said in National & Provincial, ‘Contracting States enjoy a margin of appreciation in assessing whether and to what extent differences in otherwise similar situations justify a different treatment in law’ (paragraph 88). To be justified a measure must pursue a legitimate aim and have a reasonable relationship of proportionality with that aim (James, paragraph 75). 66. Though it is important to recognise that it is the difference in treatment which must be justified in Article 14, the issues raised are similar to those already discussed above at paragraphs 25-31. We take the view that there is ample evidence to support Parliament’s view (if that is the view at which it finally arrives by enacting the Bill) that using dogs to chase and kill is sufficiently different from using dogs to locate and expose wild mammals: most of the animal welfare concerns raised by the Burns Inquiry related to the chase and the kill. Looking at it another way, we consider that allowing flushing out to remain lawful is also justified, since the Inquiry identified that real difficulties would arise in upland areas if hunters were not allowed to use dogs to flush animals out. 67. In our view, it is more difficult to sustain the difference in treatment created by forbidding hunting with dogs while allowing hunting with birds of prey 23 and forbidding the hunting with dogs of certain wild mammals while allowing the hunting with dogs of others. Nevertheless, we take the view that there are genuine distinctions between hunting with dogs and falconry such that the difference in treatment would fall within the discretionary area of judgment accorded to Parliament. We think the same applies to hunting rats and rabbits: it would seem likely, for example, that it would be much more difficult to shoot a rat or a rabbit than a fox or deer. And, while there might be less of a distinction between rabbits and hares, the Burns Inquiry concluded that hares need not be culled at all, thus, in our view, justifying the ban on hare coursing in particular. VI. Conclusion 68. We consider that neither Article 8 nor Article 11 is applicable in this context. However, even if they were, we are of the opinion that any interferences with the rights contained in those articles would be justified. While we consider that the Bill would interfere with certain property rights, we think that any interference would be ‘control of use’ rather than ‘deprivation’ of property and that expectations of future income under contracts are unlikely to amount to ‘possessions’ at all. Accordingly, compensation is not required by Article 1 of Protocol 1 and we consider that the interferences would be justified without it. Finally, we do not consider that there is a difference in treatment on a relevant ground for the purposes of Article 14 but, if there is, we again take the view that it would be justified. 69. Though some of our individual conclusions differ from those of the Court of Session and Adams and Whaley and our opinion has considered some issues not raised in those cases, we consider that those judgments provide strong support for our overall conclusion, albeit that they concerned different legislation in a different jurisdiction. 24 70. Accordingly, in our view, the Bill is likely to be regarded as compatible with the Convention if passed into law, even in the absence of a compensation scheme. Rabinder Singh QC Mathew Purchase Matrix Chambers, Griffin Building, Gray’s Inn, London WC1R 5LN. 27 February 2004 25