1. Jacob Golomb, Weaver Santaniello and Ronald Lehrer, editors. Nietzsche and Depth Psychology. Albany: State University of New York Press, 1999. (XV + 364 pages) ISBN: 0-7914-4139-3 2. Summary A collection of seventeen essays plus one introductory one, this book analyzes the theme of Nietzsche and depth psychology from the supposition that Nietzsche himself wished to be considered a psychologist and viewed psychology as a pathway into the most fundamental problems of the human condition. Nietzsche’s philosophy, both in style and content, is approached as holding within it a psychological methodology that aims towards enabling the reader towards two existential goals: firstly in the analysis of one’s values and systems of belief and secondly, in the fostering of creativity, authenticity and self-overcoming. His oeuvre is also viewed as being reflective of his personal therapeutic aims and, in this respect, is considered an anticipatory exercise in the practice of psychoanalytic self-reflection. As the contributors of this volume demonstrate, Nietzsche’s observations on the phenomena of human consciousness were of great interest to early depth psychologists because he offered to them both theoretical and practical insights. Not only were his ideas influential in the evolvement of their thought, his own complex psychological predicament and how he might be diagnosed in a psychoanalytic framework were also points of curiosity. Jacob Golomb, in his introductory essay, explains what he considers to be the two main threads of Nietzsche’s psychological method: firstly the deconstructionist approach which attempts to dislodge our attachments to metaphysical and dogmatic beliefs and secondly what he calls Nietzsche’s enticing psychology which aims to strengthen the will and cultivate authenticity. Connected to these two processes is an emphasis on self-overcoming which involves self-reflection and a genealogical questioning of one’s unconscious motivations. Golomb situates Nietzsche’s emphasis on the import of genealogical reflection on the unconscious as depth psychology and calls Nietzsche’s aphorist writing style an early exercise in psychoanalytic free association. Thus, Golomb points out that depth psychology and the psychoanalytic method were already present in Nietzsche’s philosophy and for this reason, there is need for further scholarly examination of the parallels between Nietzsche and the thinkers working in these fields that he anticipated. In the essays of Part 1: Psychology in Nietzsche the authors concentrate primarily on the position and purpose of psychology within Nietzsche’s work. Both the opening and closing essays look to more general projects; the former by James P. Cadello examines Nietzsche’s comments in Beyond Good and Evil where he characterizes psychology as the “great hunt” and a development of the will to power. Cadello argues that Nietzsche is attempting to dislodge the prevalence of traditional psychological models which function within dualistic systems of truth and value, such as “normal and abnormal, healthy and sick.” He claims that Nietzsche’s psychology is experimental and interpretative, a strategy towards undiscovered human experience that attempts to be without the moral-metaphysical biases’ of other psychological models. In the last piece of this section, Robert Solomon gives an overview of what he construes to be Nietzsche’s celebratory treatment of the emotions. He claims that Nietzsche’s analysis of the negative passions of ressentiment and pity, as well as his presentations of amor fati and will to power (as metaphors for intense emotional experiences) re-instate the worth of the emotional life. 1 Daniel Chapelle, in the second essay of the first part, argues that both the thought of eternal return and the repetition compulsion of transference have the capacity to dramatically shift one’s attitude towards time and mortality. He contends that during the repetition compulsion of transference Nietzsche’s thought of eternal return is activated because it, like eternal return, shifts negative value judgements towards the past and the passage of time so that the events of the past and the act of repression associated with the discovery of mortality are overcome. Chapelle purports that both take a profoundly affirmative and therapeutic stance towards existence that transgress the Judeo-Christian dualistic system of value and open up the possibility for the replacement of it with a new archetypal ontology and cosmology. In “The Birth of the Soul: Toward a Psychology of Decadence” Daniel W. Conway explains Nietzsche’s theory of decadence by way of an analysis of what he considers to be Nietzsche’s “depth-psychological model of the soul” found in his post-Zarathustra work. He argues that in his later works, Nietzsche diagnoses decadence as arising from the ill functioning instinctual systems of the soul which are unable to organize their drives and impulses. Conway further contends that Nietzsche provides no therapies to heal or fix decadent souls. He proposes instead that, according to Nietzsche, those with incompetent instinctual systems must allow the destructive powers of their drives and impulses to burn themselves out. Rochelle L. Millen in the fourth chapter asks whether there is to be found in Nietzsche’s work an accordant view on the psychology of women and suggests that in order to answer this question it is necessary to examine how Nietzsche’s comments on women changed the course of his intellectual life. She examines issues of misogyny and chauvinism by discussing Nietzsche’s personal life as well as the evolution of his writings on women and woman as such. Millen proposes that the significant differences between the remarks of his post versus pre Zarathustra can be linked to difficult experiences with women in his personal life. In the next chapter, Weaver Santaniello examines what she calls “Nietzsche’s Psychogenealogy of Religion and Racism” in Genealogy of Morals. She argues that by exposing the phenomena of metaphysical deceit in our Judeo-Christian heritage, Nietzsche demonstrates how the Christian religion and its virtues fostered racism in 19th century Germany. In this respect, Santaniello proposes that Nietzsche’s psychogenealogy of religion in the Genealogy of Morals traces the psychological origins of anti-Semitism. Lastly, in the sixth chapter, Ofelia Schutte argues that Nietzsche’s re-conceptualization of time as joyful and creative willing offers up a new narrative on both the psychological and moral levels to provide a remedy for decadence and nihilism. The essays of Part 2 Nietzsche and Psychology concentrate mostly on comparative analysis between Nietzsche and one other depth psychologist. A number of the authors also discuss the influence of Nietzsche’s psychological observations on early psychoanalysis more generally. In Chapter 8, Robert C. Holub examines the connection between Nietzsche and Rée’s psychological observations and then how these connections (and departures) came to influence psychoanalysis. Holub argues that although Rée had a significant influence on Nietzsche early work on psychology, which has largely been overlooked, it was only with his break from Rée and his subsequent attempts to intellectually distance himself from Rée that Nietzsche’s most significant contributions to psychoanalysis emerged. In the next chapter, Eric Blondel examines the conceptual similarities between Nietzsche and Freud. He states that both thinkers had a fascination with tragedy which founded many of their observations about human nature: much of ourselves is 2 unknown to us and it is this unknown unconscious part that drives us and makes us victim to these drives. Blondel proposes that both Nietzsche and Freud aimed to act as physicians to the tragic predicament of humankind through the use of language, what Freud called a “talking cure.” Ronal Lehrer authors two articles in this volume, Chapter 10 entitled “Freud and Nietzsche, 1892-1895” and Chapter 12, “Adler and Nietzsche.” In the earlier piece he examines the effects of Nietzsche’s thought on Freud, in the early and mid 1890’s, by looking to their common intellectual influences, shared social networks as well as the parallels between their writings during this time. Although the extent of influence of Nietzsche’s work on Freud cannot be conclusively determined, Lehrer concedes that at minimum the common threads and interests of the two thinkers are worth serious consideration. During his later piece, Lehrer discusses the intellectual relationship between Adler, Freud and Nietzsche as well as the early meetings of depth psychologists of the Vienna Psychoanalytic Society and the presence of Nietzsche’s ideas in this group. He focuses on the connections between Adler and Nietzsche, not only in regards to their psychological observations on the topics of aggression and the will to power, but also in regards to the people who shared a place in both of their lives. In Graham Parkes’ essay on Nietzsche and Jung, he embarks upon a detailed investigation of Nietzsche’s influence on Jung as well as a critical examination of Jung’s seminars on Zarathustra. Parke argues that Jung’s limited reading of Nietzsche, which often attempts to dismiss Nietzsche’s thoughts based on his supposed personality defect (but were likely related to Jung’s own insecurities), prevented Jung from recognizing the senses in which Nietzsche anticipated many of his own thoughts. In the last chapter of the second part, Claude Barbre observes the spiritual friendship that Otto Rank assumed with Nietzsche through the study of his writing. Barbre distinguishes both Nietzsche and Freud as Rank’s most significant mentors; Nietzsche’s ideas informed Rank’s personal philosophical approach to the world early on and later his own work, particularly on the creative will and individuality. In Part 3 The Psychology of Nietzsche and His Readers (Psychobiography) the contributors take part in a number of loosely connected projects which deal with the psychological predicament of Nietzsche himself as well as his relationships with his readers. In Chapter 14, Claudia Crawford argues that Nietzsche was not suffering from megalomania or the approach of madness during the later quarter of 1888, but rather attempted to instigate the transvaluation of all values through his unique styles that she situates as hyperbole, dithyramb, prophecy, legislation and agon. Crawford proposes that Nietzsche was a “redeemer” on par with Socrates and Jesus who became the lived embodiment of his own philosophy and communicated its reality to his readers through his brilliant styles. Deborah Hayden in “Nietzsche’s Secrets” examines the varied and diverse accounts of Nietzsche’s controversial life story, exposing the many contradictory observations that have been made about him by his friends and family as well as biographers and other intellectuals interested in him and his work. For example, she notes the very different accounts of Nietzsche offered by his sister, Elizabeth and his friend, Lou Salomé and then the selective interpretations that biographer have taken on these texts in turn. Hayden demonstrates that it is very difficult to come to any conclusive facts on a number of questions pertaining to Nietzsche’s life, such as his love life, his sexual habits and his health and psychological states, and suggests that in 3 this respect Nietzsche’s life story and its interpretations most accurately exemplifies his theory of perspectivism. In the next piece, George Moraitis considers a number of challenges that readers struggle with in their attempts to understand Nietzsche’s writings. He proposes that readers are met with their own “will to ignorance,” which attempts to protect their familiar belief systems, and their own “will to knowledge,” the drive towards novelty and transformation in reading Nietzsche and are, by the very nature of his work, forced into one mode or another (ignorance or knowledge) . Moraitis suggests that the greatest limitation of contemporary readers (an expression of their “will to ignorance”) is their need to make Nietzsche’s work into a cohesive and reconcilable totality. Lastly, Carl Pletsch closes the collection with his chapter entitled “Nietzsche’s Striving” in which he describes Nietzsche’s personal project of self-overcoming as a self-impelling enactment of genius. He argues that Nietzsche strived to become a genius from the age of fourteen and drew upon the cultural significance of this concept to distance himself from his conservative family background and create himself through intense and ambitious discipline. 3. Characterization The rather ambitious character of this book in that it attempts to examine the place and import of psychology within Nietzsche’s thought from so many different perspectives (philosophical, biographical and comparative) seems problematic at first glance, especially because the psychological in Nietzsche’s work is far from being a simple topic. In this respect, the volume is disadvantaged by its failure to provide sufficient introductory explanation on a number of key issues. Although Golomb explains what Nietzsche’s psychological methodology consists in during his introductory essay, a number of other important definitions are left out. For example, we are not provided with a definition of what depth psychology is, or how depth psychology relates to psychoanalysis, or why this volume chooses to concentrate on particular depth psychologists and/or psychoanalysts rather than others who also were known to be influenced by Nietzsche. Still, the diversity of work to be found here, in combination with the high level of scholarship makes for excellent research material, as well as an interesting read. Particularly in consideration of a number of Nietzsche’s own statements pertaining to the reflective connections between the author’s psyche or personal life and his philosophical writings, it seems fitting that the reader has the opportunity to have direct access in one book to complimentary texts which explore the relationships between Nietzsche’s ideas, his psychological dispositions and his life experiences. Moreover, this collection takes seriously Nietzsche’s expressed aim to be considered a psychologist and in doing so, gives close study to his insights on human consciousness and his influence upon the development of depth psychology. The contributors appropriately come from varied backgrounds: while some are known Nietzsche scholars, others are working psychoanalysts with a keen interest in Nietzsche’s life and thought. As such, the interdisciplinary character of this book allows for a number of nuanced approaches to interpreting and reading Nietzsche. For this reason, it can be a useful jumping off point for beginning to consider the psychological in Nietzsche or doing more detailed research on depth psychology and Nietzsche. Each text has something significant to contribute in its own individual fashion. As such, this volume is a helpful text to add to a secondary reading list for a class that considers any topic related to psychology and Nietzsche. 4 4. Critical Points Most of the essays in this collection do not directly engage secondary sources; they concentrate primarily on Nietzsche’s texts, or in the case of the comparative work, Nietzsche and another depth psychologist or group of them. Other than the texts which make biographical observations, this is a general lack of the collection. However, and even in light of this oversight, the essays do give well documented and researched readings of the works and lives of Nietzsche, Freud and other thinkers associated with them. Moreover, the essays in general present convincing well substantiated arguments that take innovative yet sound interpretative approaches. It is fair to say that the benefits of this collection outweigh its limitations. It is a strong reference material for anything to do with Nietzsche and psychology. Of the essays that stood out most for their originality, readability and/or scholarly rigor were those of Chapelle, Santaniello, Barbre and Hayden. Hayden’s meticulous biographical study of Nietzsche exposes the limitations of other biographers and aptly demonstrates that many of the assumptions that we take for granted about Nietzsche’s life are unsubstantiated. Barbre’s engaging exposition about the deeply affective character of Nietzsche’s aesthetics, perspectivism and writings on the will to power as self-creating on the life and work of Otto Rank is an informative and enjoyable read. Santaniello’s assessment of Nietzsche’s work in Genealogy of Morals as exposing the origins of anti-Semitism is a unique and fascinating interpretation which counters the popular opinion that Nietzsche was an anti-Semite. Chapelle’s treatment of compulsive repetition and eternal recurrence as activating a new psychological way of being which gave Jung and his student James Hillman (and others) the foundation for an archetypal cosmology and ontology is an ambitious and highly creative interpretation of Freud and Nietzsche. Although these are only a handful of the authors, their works exemplify the breadth and quality of this compilation and prove the readable and instructive nature of this book. This collection allows for a useful introduction to Nietzsche in regards in his own psychological theory, his meeting points with psychoanalysis, as well as providing some instructive analysis of his character and life. It exemplifies the diversity of learned approaches that may be taken in contemporary readings of Nietzsche. 5. Further Characteristics Although none of the essays that are part of this collection have been previously published, a number of the authors mention that they have examined the ideas expressed in the essays at greater length elsewhere. For example, Chapelle mentions his book Nietzsche and Psychoanalysis (1993) and Pletsch his Young Nietzsche, Becoming a Genius (1991). Lehrer compiled an extensive bibliography for the entire volume located at its end just before a traditional back of the book alphabetically arranged index. Willow Verkerk 22-08-2009 5