ON ISOID RELATIONS AND THEORIES OF IRRATIONAL NUMBER BY P H I L I P E. B. JOURDAIN. I call a relation which is reflexive, symmetrical, and transitive an isoid relation. Such relations come prominently forward in t h e work of P e a n o * and his school. The closely connected subject of "definition by a b s t r a c t i o n " has been especially treated by Burali-Forti and more recently (1907) by P a d o a ; the writer last named develops some of the conclusions previously reached by Russell. Russell f pointed out a means whereby, given t h a t a stands in an isoid relation to b, an entity can always be defined which has a one-many relation to all such b's as stand in the isoid relation spoken of to a. Russell called the principle which is based on this construction t h e " principle of abstraction." I wish to point out t h a t Russell uses, in a manner apparently not quite free from arbitrariness, different methods for the construction of such entities according as he deals with integer numbers (cardinal or ordinal) or real numbers, and to initiate a discussion as to why these particular forms should be used in preference to others. I n connexion with this, I will discuss certain points in t h e theories of irrational number. I. Consider t h e case of cardinal numbers. W h e r e u, v, ... are classes which have the isoid relation of what Cantor called " equivalence," and what Dedekind and Russell called " similarity," to each other, Russell constructed a many-one relation between t h e similar classes and an entity, z, which is, in conformity with the views of Frege and Weber, " t h e cardinal n u m b e r " of all these classes. B u t Russell also remarked t h a t other particular $'s are possible : "...la démonstration donne une façon dont ceci p e u t se faire, sans prouver qu'il n'y a pas d'autres façons de la faire." I n fact, we shall, in t h e case of real numbers, meet with a different construction of S and z. B u t Russell's proof of his proposition 6. 2 does not make t h e n a t u r e of t h e existence-theorem clear. T h e n a t u r e of existence-theorems is, in essentials, t h e same throughout mathematics ; in t h e present case what we do is J : W e show that, * Cf., for example, my paper on " T h e Development of the Theories of Mathematical Logic and the Principles of Mathematics," Quart. Journ. of Math. 1912, pp. 272, 280, 282-3, 284, 293-4, 302-4. t " S u r la logique des relations," Rev. de Math, vu, 1902, propositions 6. 1, 6. 2 ; The Principles of Mathematics, Cambridge, 1903, pp. 166, 219-20, 305, 314, 499, 519; cf. L. Couturat, Les Principes des Mathématiques, Paris, 1905, pp. 49—51, 77. X I use Russell's notation of the paper referred to. ON ISOID RELATIONS AND THEORIES OF IRRATIONAL NUMBER 493 if xRy, by choosing z to be px (which = py), the relation e is an example of an S. In Russell's proof this does not seem as clear as it might be. II. Russell's second construction of an entity which justifies the principle of abstraction is in his theory of real numbers. Here he takes a definite member out of the class of classes between which an isoid relation subsists, so that the relation between the classes in isoid relation and the new entity obtained by the principle of abstraction is the same isoid relation as that which correlates the classes spoken of, and is not e, as it was before. In the case of real numbers, the isoid relation is the relation which is practically the same as that which Cantor has called " Zusammengehörigkeit" and which Russell* has translated "coherency." The entity chosen by Russell is what Pasch and Peano called a " segment " of rational numbers. III. It may be remarked, by the way, that the chief advantages of the principle of abstraction seem to be the avoidance of the necessity (1) of introducing new indefinables and (2) of redefining equality ; and the advantage, mentioned in the book of 1903f, of enabling the existence-theorems to be proved is comparatively unimportant. If we apply this second method to the theory of cardinal numbers, we need, among all the classes similar to u, one specialized one. Thus we should have the results that u is similar to its cardinal number, instead of, as in the theory of Russell, u is a member of its cardinal number. We will return to the consideration of this theory. IV. If, now, we attempt to define the real number belonging to a class of rational numbers by a method analogous to that which Russell has employed to define the cardinal number of a class, we would arrive at the definition as the class of those classes of rational numbers which are coherent to u. It seems to me that there is no particular advantage in defining a real number as a class of such classes over the definition as a segment, or vice versa. V. Let us now consider if there is, among all classes which are similar to a given class u, a specialized one which can therefore be used as a definition of " the cardinal number of u." The method which immediately suggests itself is to start with the null-class and define the cardinal number 1 as the class whose only member is the null-class. Then 2 may be defined as the class whose members are the nullclass and 1 ; and so on. It is visible that, in this way, we would get a one-one correlation of cardinal numbers with ordinal numbers ; but, on the other hand, there is a rise of type at each step, so that it would appear that we would be unable to define any of the transfinite cardinal or ordinal numbers. However, it must be remarked that the rise of type is of a different nature from the rise of type which is treated at length by Russell. There would appear to be no objection to the definition of types whose order is a limit of lower orders. The distinction between the hierarchy of types which I have indicated and the hierarchy which Russell has treated is, in a way, analogous to the distinction that there is between limits in the case of ordinal numbers and those in the case of * Principles, p. 283. t P. ix. Cf. Whitehead and Russell, Principia Mathematica, Cambridge, 1912, p. 4. 494 P. E. B. JOURDAIN cardinal numbers ; or again between û)W in Cantor's notation and the cardinal number Ko exponentiated by ü0, or the ordinal type a exponentiated by the ordinal type ß (Hausdorff and myself). It seems that there would be no difficulty, then, in extending the series of Alephs beyond Xw and the series of ordinal numbers beyond û)W. It is known that Russell's theory of types puts a limit to the series of Alephs and ordinal numbers at these points. VI. It has appeared from somewhat careful historical investigations of mine that irrational "numbers" were based by Cauchy on geometrical foundations, but that later there grew up, in some text-books, a would-be arithmetical theory in w^hich the irrational numbers are defined as the limits of series of rational numbers which have no rational limits and which are convergent. Since the " convergence " of a series was usually defined by means of a presupposed limit, the circle was obvious, and it was the avoidance of this circle which seems to have given rise to the theories of Weierstrass and Cantor*, and perhaps also of Méray. When, however, the "convergence" of a sequence (sv) is defined without assuming the existence of a limit, by means of the well-known criterion there is no circle, but the assumption of existence appears even more clearly. In the analogous case of the Dedekind-Peano theory, this assumption was rightly emphasized by Russell f. On the other hand, Russell \ seems to neglect the advance made in the avoiding of the circle. This advance lay, perhaps, rather in the fact that mathematicians began to see the necessity of attending to fundamental questions than in the fact that an obvious logical error was not committed. Still, almost certainly the error did not seem so obvious about 1870 as it does now. In Russell's theory§, which was anticipated by Paschi|, the selection of the entity defined as the real number appears somewhat arbitrary. There is, quite ready to hand, another entity, which is formed in a manner analogous to that in which the entity which Frege and Russell called " the cardinal number " of classes which are in the isoid relation of similarity is formed. It would, further, appear that this was the entity which Frege fl indicated as the real number belonging to certain classes of rationals. In any case, there is a difficulty in admitting that Russell's entity or this entity is the real number corresponding to a given segment of rationals. Many entities, no one of which seems to have any special advantage over the others, can be defined by " the principle of abstraction." VII. It may be remarked that theories of irrational numbers do not depend upon limits** in the sense that irrationals are defined as limits. If limits are defined * See Cantor, Math. Ann. xxi, 1883, pp. 566, 568. f Principles, 1903, pp. 270, 280—285. î See Ibid. pp. 278, 280—285. § Ibid. pp. 271—275, 285, 286. || Einleitung in die Differential- und Integralrechnung, Leipzig, 1882 ; see especially p. 1 1 . It is a curious fact that Pasch seemed so unconscious of the merits of this definition that later (Grundlagen der Analysis, Leipzig and Berlin, 1909, p. 98) he abandoned his definition by defining (or postulating) an irrational number as a new "thing," somewhat as Peano did. IT Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik, Breslau, 1884, pp. 114—115. ** Cf. Russell, op. cit. pp. 277-278. ON ISOID RELATIONS AND THEORIES OF IRRATIONAL NUMBER 495 before irrationals are introduced (as they usually are, for pedagogical reasons, because some limits are rational), to define an irrational as a limit would be to commit the circle referred to. In Peano's introduction of the conception of a limit, on the other hand, a " limit " and a " real number " are merely two names for the same thing ; thus limits are not introduced at first for rationals alone, but are "defined by abstraction," as Peano and Burali-Forti would say, as new entities*, and this " definition " leads to Russell's definition or to the one given in the fourth section. VIII. In his remarks on Dedekind's axiom, Russell *f quoted his criticisms J on Couturat's account of Dedekind's axiom, given in Couturat's De l'infini mathématique^. Now these criticisms are very much to the point à propos of Couturat's mistaken version of the axiom, in which the point dividing the Dedekindian sections is said to be both greater than all the numbers of the lower section, and less than all the numbers of the upper section. But it does not seem always to be relevant to Dedekind's own statement. IX. The following points seem worthy of notice in the theories of irrationals : (1) Dedekind's theory had not for its object to prove the existence of irrationals I] : it showed the necessity, as Dedekind thought, for the mathematician to create them. In the idea of the creation of numbers, Dedekind was followed by Stolz; but Weber and Pasch showed how the supposition of this creation could be avoided: Weber defined real numbers as sections (Schnitte) in the series of rationals; Pasch (like Russell) as the segments which generate these sections; (2) In Weierstrass's theory, irrationals were defined as classes of rationals. Hence Russeli'sIT objections do not hold against it, nor does Russell seem to credit Weierstrass and Cantor with the avoidance of quite the contradiction that they did avoid ; (3) The real objection to Weierstrass's theory, and one of the objections** to Cantors theory, is that equality has to be re-defined; (4) In the various arithmetical theories of irrational numbers there are three tendencies : (a) the number is defined as a logical entity—a class or an operation—, as with Weierstrassft> Weber, Pasch, Russell and Pieri; (b) it is "created," or, more frankly, postulated, as with Dedekind, Stolz, Peano, and Méray; (c) it is defined as a sign (for what, is left indeterminate), as with Heine, Cantor^, Thomae, * Cf. Archiv der Math, und Phys. (3), xvi, pp. 36—37. f Op. cit. pp. 279—280. % Mind, N. S., vi, 1897, p. 117. § Paris, 1896, p. 416. |i Cf. Russell, op. cit. p. 280. IT Ibid. p. 282. ** Not made by Russell, ibid. p. 284 ; cf. p. 285. f t I have referred elsewhere (Archiv der Math, und Phys. (3), xiv, pp. 306, 311) to the merits of Weierstrass's theory, which were unappreciated by Frege (Grundgesetze der Arithmetik, II, Jena, 1903, pp. 149—154). XX It is a remarkable fact that Cantor was a nominalist as regards real numbers (Math. Ann. xxi, 1883, pp. 589—590), and rejected with scorn the nominalistic thesis in the case of integers (Zur Lehre vom Transfiniten, Halle, 1890, pp. 16—18). 496 P. E. B. JOURDAIN Pringsheim. I will not consider here the geometrical theories, in which, as with Paul du Bois-Reymond, a real number is a sign for a length ; (5) In Russell's theory it appears to be equally legitimate to define a real number in various ways. I do not propose the alternative form I have suggested as in any way superior to Russell's own, but merely to show the need of some further discussion. Finally, I would remark that Russell's later work seems to show that the advantage claimed in 1903 for the definition of certain numbers as classes, viz. that an " existence-theorem " can be asserted of them, cannot be maintained. Russell's " existence," in fact, which does not apply to relations such as the rationals unless a relation is a class of couples, does not relate to the question of what mathematicians usually call the " existence " of real numbers.