Issue 2 –2002 Online Journal ARGUMENTATION, INTERPRETATION, RHETORIC Argumentation: an overview of theoretical approaches and research themes Frans H. van Eemeren University of Amsterdam 1 Subject-matter and aims of the study of argumentation Argumentation is a phenomenon we are confronted with daily. We argue all the time for our own views and we react continually to oral or written argumentation put forward by others. Apart from being a verbal activity, argumentation is also a social activity directed at other people. On top of that, it is a rational activity aimed at defending a standpoint in such a way that it is acceptable to a reasonable judge. A person who argues something starts - rightly or wrongly - from the assumption that there is an explicit or implicit difference of opinion with regard to the acceptability of a certain standpoint. By putting forward the constellation of propositions which constitutes the argumentation, the speaker or writer attempts to convince the listener or reader that the standpoint at issue is acceptable. Taking these observations as our point of departure, we can describe the subject-matter of the study of argumentation in the following way: Argumentation is a verbal, social and rational activity aimed at convincing a reasonable judge of the (in)acceptability of a standpoint by advancing a certain constellation of propositions which is designed to justify (or refute) the standpoint. This definition does justice to the 'process-product ambiguity' of the word 'argumentation': it not only refers to the activity of advancing reasons but also to the shorter or longer text that results from it. In general the context will make clear which of the two is the intended meaning. In publications in speech communication and discourse analysis the term argumentation is usually used in this (ambiguous) way while in philosophy and logic the use of the term argument is predominant. The latter term can lead to confusion because it has four different meanings: (1) reason, in the sense of the German Argument, (2) discussion or exchange of opinions, (3) quarrel, (4) form of reasoning in the logical sense, consisting of one or more premises and a conclusion. Although after the appearance of O'Keefe's classical definition paper of 1977 the difference in meaning between (1), (2) and (3) has been given a great deal of attention in the argumentation literature in English, it is particularly the confusion of the meanings (1) and (4) that has been responsible for a great many problems (van Eemeren en Grootendorst 1992a: 60-62). It is important that the study of argumentation incorporates both the pragmatic level which is at stake in meaning (1) and the logical level at stake in meaning (4); but it is at the same time also important to maintain a clear distinction between these two levels. The study of argumentation concentrates on the analysis, evaluation and presentation of the 'point of departure' and the 'organisation' of argumentation. The point of departure consists of all explicit and implicit premises and assumptions that are taken as the starting point in argumentation. The organisation of the argumentation comprises the way in which the various reasons are connected with each other and the standpoint at issue to justify or refute this standpoint. Both in the study of the point of departure and in that of the organisation of argumentation logical and pragmatic considerations play a part. On the logical level a whole constellation of verbal, contextual, situational and other pragmatic factors influencing the course and outcome of the communication process are left unexamined: the way in which the premises concerned are exactly phrased in ordinary language use, who is addressing whom, the precise situation in which this happens, all the things that occurred before, et cetera. Logicians are not generally concerned with argumentation as it is put forward in natural circumstances by somebody who attempts to convince someone else of a certain standpoint, but with abstract 'argument forms' or 'patterns of reasoning' in which a conclusion is derived from a particular set of formalized premises with the help of various sorts of 'logical constants'. To be able to clearly distinguish between the 'valid' argument forms and the 'invalid' argument forms underlying specific specimens of reasoning, they leave pragmatic aspects of argumentative reality outside consideration that are indispensable for developing an adequate theory of argumentation (van Eemeren et al. 1996: 5-12). The general aims pursued in the study of argumentation can be summarized as follows: The study of argumentation aims at determining which soundness criteria a reasonable judge applies when evaluating the point of departure and the organisation of argumentation and at making clear how these criteria are to be applied in the analysis, evaluation and presentation of argumentation. 2 Components of the study of argumentation In argumentation there is always an explicit or implicit appeal to reasonableness, but this does, of course, not mean that each argumentation is indeed reasonable. In practice, an argumentation can be lacking in all kinds of respects. It is the task of argumentation theorists to determine which soundness criteria should be satisfied in the argumentation for the argumentation to be called 'reasonable'. Many argumentation theorists are inspired by logic and they study argumentation for normative purposes. However, there are also argumentation theorists who have a merely descriptive goal. Especially linguisticallyoriented scholars in textual and discourse analysis are, as a rule, only interested in describing how, with varying degrees of success, language users make use of argumentation to convince others. In current research practice both extremes are represented - with Biro and Siegel (1992) on the normative side and Willard (1989) on the descriptive side. Most argumentation theorists, however, take a middle position. Their starting point is that the study of argumentation has a normative as well as a descriptive dimension. In Argumentation, communication, and fallacies (1992a), Rob Grootendorst and I propose a - now broadly accepted - integrated research program. In this program, a theoretical model of acceptable argumentation based on a philosophical ideal of reasonableness has been developed and by means of empirical research it is established how argumentative reality is organized and which problems may occur in it (1992a: 5-6). The normative and the descriptive parts of the research program are connected with each other through a reconstruction of argumentative reality with the help of analytic operations from the perspective of the theoretical model of reasonable argumentation and through the development of methods to improve argumentative practice methodically (van Eemeren 1986, van Eemeren et al. 1993, 1997). A fully-fledged research program of this design has a philosophical, a theoretical, an empirical, an analytic and a practical component. The philosophical component of the study of argumentation involves reflection on the ideal of reasonableness underlying the theorizing about argumentation; the outcome of this reflection is pertinent to the question of when argumentation may be considered sound or not sound. Toulmin (1976) distinguished between three major conceptions of reasonableness: (1) the 'geometrical' formal conception which characterizes the logical approach to argumentation, (2) the 'anthropological' empirical conception, which is prominent in the rhetorical approach to argumentation, and (3) the 'critical' transcendental conception, which lies at the heart of the dialectical approach to argumentation. The differences between these reasonableness conceptions are expressed in argumentation theory in different views of 'sound argumentation'. According to the geometrical conception sound argumentation is equal to a valid argument with true premises; according to the anthropological conception, it amounts to a way of persuading that is successful in a certain cultural environment; according to the critical conception, it comes down to a constructive contribution to the resolution of a difference of opinion. In the theoretical component of the study of argumentation it is, starting from a certain conception of reasonableness, indicated more precisely what reasonable argumentation consists of. Which ways of arguing are acceptable to a reasonable judge? Geometrical logicians will answer this question quite differently from anthropological rhetoricians or critical dialecticians. The theoretical ideal models will therefore vary in these three cases. In the empirical component of the study of argumentation descriptions and explanations are given of the factors and processes involved in producing, interpreting and evaluating argumentative discourse. As a consequence of the different theoretical angles of approach, the emphases may be put differently in the various empirical investigations. The geometriclogical approach has only recently led to an interest in empirical research; and the experiments have so far almost exclusively been restricted to deductive reasoning. The empirical investigations connected with the anthropological approach have so far been dominated by so-called 'persuasion' research aimed at determining the effectivity of the means of persuasion that are brought to bear. In empirical studies starting from the critical approach it is, among various other things, systematically investigated to what extent ordinary arguers' argumentative notions and norms agree with the theoretical ones. In the analytic component of the study of argumentation an attempt is made to create a bridge between the ideal model of argumentative discourse and argumentative reality. The central question is how the text or discussion can be reconstructed in such a way that only those aspects are illuminated that are relevant in the light of the theoretical perspective which is chosen as the starting point. Depending on the approach that is favoured, the reconstructions can vary from formalizing the logical elements to the identifying the persuasive aspects or making explicit the contributions to the resolution of a difference of opinion. In the practical component of the study of argumentation the insights gained in the philosophical, theoretical, empirical and analytic component are being used for developing methods to improve argumentative practice in a variety of (institutionalized and noninstitutionalized) contexts. In this endeavour it is examined how argumentative practice can be positively influenced from a certain approach and how the individual skills in argumentation and the interpretation and evaluation of argumentation can be enhanced. I shall give a brief overview of some important approaches to the study of argumentation. Together with other approaches, with a more limited scope or a less developed research program, these approaches are discussed in more detail in van Eemeren et. al. (1996). Before discussing the various approaches, it is important to emphasize that all modern approaches of argumentation developed in the past decades are highly influenced by classical and postclassical rhetoric and dialectic. Classical syllogistic logic (or 'analytics') has not played such an important role: from the second half of the nineteenth century onwards this logic has been gradually replaced by modern formal logic concentrating on symbolic reasoning by means of formally valid derivations rather than argumentative practice. 3 Influential approaches to the study of argumentation 3.1 Toulmin's model of analysis and Perelman's new rhetoric The study of argumentation, and particularly the teaching of argumentation, has for a long time been dominated by the theoretical contributions of Toulmin and Perelman (with his collaborator Olbrechts-Tyteca). Both contributions were published in the fifties and both intend to offer an alternative for formal logic that should make it possible to make an adequate analysis of ordinary argumentative discourse. Another commonality is that the rational procedure of legal reasoning is in both cases taken as the point of departure. Toulmin's The uses of argument, published in 1958, is mainly known for the model of argumentation presented in this book. This model represent the 'procedural form' of argumentation: the various steps that can be distinguished in the defence of a standpoint. According to Toulmin, the soundness of argumentation is primarily determined by the degree in which the warrant, which connects the data adduced in the argumentation with the claim that is defended, is made acceptable by a backing. The following analysis is an example of a description of argumentation in terms of the Toulmin model (Fig. 1) The procedural form of argumentation is in Toulmin's view 'field dependent'. This means that the steps that are taken - and which are represented in the model - are always the same, irrespective of the kind of subject the argumentation refers to. What kind of backing is required, however, is dependent on the field to which the question at issue belongs. An ethical justification, for instance, requires a different kind of backing than a legal justification. Toulmin concludes from this that the evaluation criteria for determining the soundness of argumentation are 'field dependent'. A variety of serious theoretical objections have been raised against Toulmin's views of argumentation and his model. In addition, in concrete cases the model very often appears hard to apply. Toulmin's definitions, which combine functional and formal differences, are such that data and warrants are in practice difficult to distinguish. The distinction between the two is only really clear in carefully selected examples. And without this distinction the model is in fact nothing more than a newly-clad reasoning scheme from classical antiquity, the 'epicheireme'. All the same the model and the connected idea of field-dependent norms of rationality are still extremely popular. Perelman and Olbrechts-Tyteca provide in La nouvelle rhetorique (1958), which appeared in an English translation in 1969, an inventory of frequently-used 'argumentation techniques'. They regard argumentation as sound if this argumentation adduces (more) assent with the standpoint that is defended among the audience the argumentation is aimed at. Thus the soundness of argumentation is in the new rhetoric measured against its effect on the target group. This target group may consist of a 'specific audience', but it can also be the 'universal audience': the people who are for the speaker or writer the embodiment of 'reasonableness'. Perelman and Olbrechts-Tyteca's theory consists most of all in an extensive list of elements which can serve as point of departure or as argument scheme when constructing the argumentation that should convince or persuade the audience (see van Eemeren et al. 1996: ch. 4). With the help of a 'quasi-logical' argument scheme, which resembles a logically valid argument form in some way, one can, for instance, sometimes achieve the effect that the public considers the standpoint defended in a reasonable way: The club is held to maintain certain regulations and therefore its members are also committed to these regulations. Another way of justifying a standpoint is the use of an argument scheme such as analogy that 'structures reality', so that the audience will conclude that the standpoint that is defended is in a similar way acceptable as a different kind of standpoint which was already accepted for a long time: It is clear from the current lack of discipline and the tolerance with respect to immoral conduct in modern western society that this society is about to come to an end, because the Roman empire too was near to destruction when people lost their sense of order and discipline and allowed immoral conduct to take place. Unfortunately, the descriptions of the various categories distinguished in Perelman and Olbrechts-Tyteca's catalogue of points of departure and argument schemes are not so clear. In some cases the various categories also strongly overlap. These and other problems make it difficult to achieve a unequivocal analysis of argumentation with the help of the theoretical tools provided by the new rhetoric. Neither Toulmin's approach nor the new rhetoric has led to the desired results. This is partly due to the prejudices of these argumentation theorists with regard to logic, which is, without paying any attention to modern developments, equated with classical syllogistic logic. Both Toulmin and Perelman and Olbrechts-Tyteca start, without having any qualms about it, from the assumption that logic has nothing to offer for the analysis and evaluation of argumentation, whereas in this endeavour certain logical insights are indispensable. Because both Toulmin and Perelman and Olbrechts-Tyteca concentrate also exclusively on isolated arguments of reasonings and ignore all pragmatic, contextual and situational aspects, their approaches are certainly no real alternative to the formal-logical approach of argumentation. Neither of the two approaches does justice to the fact that argumentation is a specific form of functional language use which should be treated as such. Until his death in 1984, Perelman remained involved in the new rhetoric, but he did not develop any important new theoretical insight after the publication of La nouvelle rhetorique. His influence is still pretty strong though, in particular in rhetoric and among lawyers. Unlike Perelman, Toulmin has after the publication of The uses of argument hardly been active in the study of argumentation. Instead, he directed his attention to topics of a historical-philosophical nature and problems in the theory of science. At the 1990 conference of the International Society for the Study of Argumentation (ISSA) Toulmin, for once, returned to his argumentation model. He declared that he had come to believe that, unlike he had earlier argued in The uses of argument, not only justifications and backings that are used in argumentation are field-dependent, but also the various contextual aspects and the various forums that are supposed to evaluate the argumentation (1992: 9). 3.2 Informal logic Out of dissatisfaction with the way in which argumentation was treated in introductory textbooks in formal logic an approach to argumentation has been propagated in Canada and the United States from the beginning of the seventies which is known as informal logic (Johnson and Blair 1980, eds. 1994). The main theoretical sources of inspiration were the studies by Toulmin and Perelman en Olbrechts-Tyteca . Since 1978 the journal Informal Logic, edited by Blair and Johnson, has been the speaking voice of the informal-logic movement. In spite of its name, informal logic is not a new kind of logic, but just an approach to the normative study of argumentation in ordinary language which remains closer to the practice of argumentation than formal logic (van Eemeren et al. 1996: ch. 6). Informal logicians would like to develop norms and procedures for interpreting, assessing and construing argumentation. The starting point is that argumentation should be sound in a logical sense (Blair and Johnson 1987). Apart from the fact that it is clear that something else is meant than that the arguments that are used must be valid in a formal-logical sense, it is not yet clear what this means. It is certain though that informal logicians are primarily interested in the relations between premises and conclusions in arguments; it is also certain that their interest is not restricted to reasoning aimed at convincing. Blair and Johnson (1997) have indicated what they have in mind when they speak of an informal logical alternative for the formal criterion of deductive validity. In their view, the premises of an argument have to meet three criteria: (1) relevance, (2) sufficiency and (3) acceptability. These criteria are introduced in Johnson and Blair (1977) and they are, sometimes under different names, adopted by other informal logicians such as Govier (1985), Damer (1987) and Freeman (1988). In the case of 'relevance' the question is whether there is an is adequate (substantial) relation between the premises and the conclusion of an argument; in the case of 'sufficiency' the question is whether the premises provide enough evidence for the conclusion; in the case of 'acceptability' the question is whether the premises themselves are true, probable or in some other way trustworthy. None of the three criteria has been more clearly defined. Informal logic is not yet a fully-fledged theory of argumentation. It is more an approach to argumentation which is still in an early programmatic phase. In all kinds of directions solutions are sought for the various problems. A striking characteristic is that the informal logicians do not pay much attention to the (linguistic) problems of interpretation and reconstruction. In line with their logico-philosophical background, they concentrate on the assessment of arguments. 3.3 Radical argumentativism Starting at the beginning of the seventies Ducrot and Anscombre have developed in an number of - almost exclusively French - publications a linguistic approach to language use and argumentation. Their point of departure is that each utterance contains a dialogue, which is as a rule implicit. This basic idea is further developed in Ducrot and Anscombre's theory of 'polyphony' (Anscombre and Ducrot 1986, Van Eemeren et al. 1996: 312-322). Because Anscombre and Ducrot are of the opinion that every form of language use has an argumentative aspect, they refer to their 'new linguistics', as Meyer (1986) calls this rather extreme theoretical position, as radical argumentativism. The starting points are expounded in three books: Les echelles argumentatives by Ducrot (1980), L'argumentation dans la langue by Anscombre and Ducrot (1983) and Le dire et le dit by Ducrot (1984). Ducrot and Anscombre's descriptive approach is, among other things, characterized by a great interest in words such as 'almost', 'nearly', 'only', 'but'. 'even', 'still', 'because' and 'so', which can serve as argumentative 'operators' or 'connectors' and give the utterances a certain argumentative force and argumentative direction. In a certain context, the sentence 'The ring costs only one hundred euros' can point in the direction of a conclusion such as 'Buy the ring'; the sentence 'The ring costs no less than one hundred euros' points rather in the direction of a conclusion such as 'Do not buy the ring'. According to Ducrot and Anscombre, sentences that express a standpoint always involve an argumentative relation. This can be clarified with the help of a (not highly sophisticated) example used by Nolke (1992) in which the presence of the word 'but' suggests two opposite standpoints in one sentence: 'Paul is rich, but he is married'. On the basis of the first part of this sentence a woman might conclude that it is a good idea to get to know Paul better; on the basis of the second part, however, she might conclude that this is perhaps not such a good idea after all. The fact that these two conclusions point into opposite argumentative directions is caused by the use of the argumentative connector 'but'. This connector is also responsible for the fact that the interpretation of the second conclusion wins. Incidentally, the word 'but' only determines the direction of the conclusion that is suggested by the sentence, not the content of this conclusion. This content is also dependent on the context and the situation in which the sentence is uttered. Whatever conclusion may be drawn in a specific context, the presence of the word 'but' causes in all cases this conclusion to be the opposite of, and also stronger than, the conclusion that has to be drawn from the first part. According to Ducrot and Anscombre the opposite standpoints that in a sentence such as that about Paul are suggested by 'but' select two different 'argumentative principles' which are on a par with the topoi from classical rhetoric (van Eemeren et al. 1996). In the context which is assumed in Nolke's example these are 'The more someone has the property of being rich, the more attractive it is for a woman to get to know him better' and 'The more someone is tied to another woman, the less attractive it is for a woman to get to know him better'. In this case the latter topos has a bigger argumentative force than the first, which is as it were put aside (overruled) by the latter. Thereby the last topos determines the eventual argumentative direction of the sentence, which leads to an implicit conclusion such as 'It is no use trying to get to know Paul better'. 3.4 Modern rhetorical approaches In recent years a powerful revaluation of rhetoric has taken place. The irrational or even anti-rational image of rhetoric which has come into being during the past centuries has now to a large part been revised. And the sharp division between rhetoric and dialectic made in the past appears to require weakening. Several argumentation theorists have become aware that rhetoric as the study of persuasive techniques is not per se incompatible with maintaining a critical ideal of reasonableness. It is remarkable that the rehabilitation of rhetoric in the study of argumentation has started at about the same time in various countries. A considerable time after the pioneering work by Perelman and Olbrechts-Tyteca, Farrell (1976, 1993), McKerrow (1977) and others in the United States have defended the rational qualities of rhetoric. Wenzel (1980) too would like to give rhetoric full credit, but then emphatically in relation with logic and (more in particular) dialectics. In France Reboul (1988) wanted to give rhetoric a satisfactory position in the study of argumentation beside dialectics. The rhetorical features of argumentation he mentions are its being audience-oriented, its presentation in ordinary language, and the status of the premises and the conclusion as at best being plausible. Reboul regards rhetoric and dialectic as different disciplines which also display some overlap: rhetoric applies dialectic to public discussions while dialectic is at the same time a part of rhetoric because dialectic provides rhetoric with intellectual tools (1990). In Germany Kopperschmidt (1989) takes a step further: he argues that, viewing things also from a historical perspective, rhetoric is the central concern of argumentation theorists. The highest reappreciation of rhetoric comes from the Austrian Kienpointner (1991), who defends the relativistic rhetorical conception of reasonableness as a fertile instrument for resolving social conflicts. In the Netherlands Braet (1984) emphasizes the importance of the classical doctrine of status for modern argumentation theory. He compares its various variants with the stock issues which are the basis of American 'academic debate'. Van Eemeren and Houtlosser (1999) aim for an integration of insight from rhetoric into their pragma-dialectical method for analyzing oral and written argumentative discourse. In their view, there is a rhetorical goal corresponding with each of the dialectical stages of the process of resolving a difference of opinion. They think that an argumentative text or discussion can be reconstructed with more subtlety and can be more fully accounted for if it is investigated how strategic manoeuvring takes place in each dialectical stage with regard to the selection from the available 'topical potential' (the possible discussion moves) available in the discussion stage concerned, the adaptation to the wishes of the audience and the use of presentational devices such as figures of speech. 3.5 Modern dialectical approaches To modern dialecticians argumentation is part of a procedure to resolve differences of opinion concerning the acceptability of standpoints by means of a regulated discussion. They attempt to formulate 'problem-sound' rules, that is rules that are instrumental in resolving a difference of opinion. These rules must also be 'conventionally valid' in the sense that they are intersubjectively acceptable to those who would like to resolve their differences (Barth and Krabbe 1982: 21-22, van Eemeren et al. 1996: ch. 9). When designing a procedure for language users who would like to resolve a dispute by means of a critical dialogue, the 'new dialecticians' make, among other things, use of the ideas propounded by Crawshay-Williams and Naess and ideas of Lorenzen, Kuno Lorenz and other member of the Erlangen School (van Eemeren et al. 1996: ch. 3.3, 3.4 and ch. 9.2). The first initiatives towards a new dialectic are worked out in a formal logical direction by Barth and Krabbe and - as a sequel to that - in a pragmatic linguistic direction by van Eemeren and Grootendorst. In From axiom to dialogue Barth and Krabbe (1982) described a formal-dialectical procedure to determine whether a standpoint can be maintained in the light of certain starting points or 'concessions'. The name formal dialectics stems from Hamblin, who had earlier introduced this notion in Fallacies (1970: 253-282). The indication 'formal' refers to the strictly regimented character of the dialogue games developed by Barth and Krabbe. In this endeavour they made use of insights from the formal dialogue logic of Lorenzen cum suis. In dialogue logic an argument is presented as a dialogue game between a 'proponent' and an 'opponent' of a thesis. Together these two parties try to establish whether the thesis can be defended successfully against critical attacks. In the defence the proponent can make use of the opponent's 'concessions': propositions the opponent is prepared to be committed to. The proponent can try to parry an attack on one of his own propositions by defending it directly or by undertaking a counterattack on one of the opponent's concessions. The opponent is obliged to defend a concession that is being attacked. This may lead to a situation in which he or she can do nothing else than accept a proposition he or she has attacked earlier on in the dialogue. According to the rules this then results in the proponent winning the game. The proponent therefore attempts to bring the opponent in this position by skillfully exploiting his or her concessions. If the proponent succeeds, he or she has successfully defended the thesis owing to (and given) those concessions (ex concessis) (van Eemeren et al. 1996: ch. 9). In Speech acts in argumentative discussions van Eemeren and Grootendorst (1984) developed a theory of argumentation, pragma-dialectics, which connects in various respects immediately with formal dialectics, but is also different in important ways (van Eemeren et al. 1996: ch. 10). The agreement is expressed in the term dialectics; the replacement of formal by pragma (short for 'pragmatic') refers to the differences. The pragmatic elements in pragma-dialectics are primarily inspired by insights from the work of 'ordinary language philosophers' such as Austin (1962), Searle (1969, 1979) and Grice (1975); the dialectical elements are inspired by insights from the work of critical rationalists such as CrawshayWilliams (1957), Popper (1972, 1974) and Barth and Krabbe (1982). The metatheoretical starting points of pragma-dialectics manifest themselves in four methodological principles (van Eemeren and Grootendorst 1984: 7-18, 1992a: 9-11). The first principle is 'functionalisation': argumentation is conceived as a 'complex' speech act. The second principle is 'socialisation': argumentation is put into an interactional context. The third principle is 'externalisation': argumentation is immediately connected with the commitments created by the performance of this speech act. And the fourth principle is 'dialectification': argumentation is viewed as part of a 'critical discussion' aimed at resolving a difference of opinion. An important difference between pragma-dialectics and formal dialectics is that the pragmadialectical rules have the status of necessary conditions for resolving differences of opinion, whereas the formal-dialectical rules are production rules for generating rational arguments. Another important difference is that the pragma-dialectical rules apply to the performance of speech acts in the various stages of the critical discussion conducted to resolve a difference of opinion, whereas the formal-dialectical rules pertain primarily to the use of logical constants in making logical deductions. The pragma-dialectical ideal model of a critical discussion is closer to an ordinary discussion in ordinary language than the formal dialogue game. In the pragma-dialectical ideal model of a critical discussion four stages are distinguished: the confrontation stage, the opening stage, the argumentation stage and the concluding stage (van Eemeren and Grootendorst 1992a: 35). In the confrontation stage a participant in the discussion - in the role of 'protagonist' - puts forward a standpoint and another participant as 'antagonist' - expresses doubt concerning the acceptability of the standpoint or contradicts it (in the latter case the situation is already more complicated). In the opening stage, which is in practice often largely implicit, the point of departure of the discussion is determined. Here the question becomes what are the common starting points and which rules are being observed? Then the protagonist advances argumentation in the argumentation stage to defend his or her standpoint and adds, if necessary, new arguments to answer further critical reactions. If the arguments that are advanced lead to the acceptance of the standpoint by the antagonist in the concluding stage, the difference of opinion has been resolved; this is also the case if the protagonist withdraws the standpoint because of the critical reactions of the antagonist. Besides an ideal model of the speech acts that are to be performed in the various stages of a critical discussion by a protagonist and an antagonist who make an attempt to resolve their difference of opinion in a reasonable way, the pragma-dialectical discussion procedure also includes a series of basic rules which together constitute a code of conduct for reasonable discussants (van Eemeren and Grootendorst 1982, 1984, 1992a, 1992c). The problemsoundness of the rules consist in the fact that the maintenance of these rules prevents the performance of speech acts that are obstructions or impediments to the resolution of a difference of opinion. Each violation of a pragma-dialectical rule amounts to an incorrect discussion move. This can happen in each stage of the discussion. The incorrectness involved generally resembles one or more of the well-known fallacies or a similar offence against reasonableness (van Eemeren and Grootendorst 1992a: 102-207, 1992c, 1995a). A clear example is the violation of the 'freedom rule' that the parties are not allowed to prevent each other from advancing standpoint or expressing doubt by discrediting the other party in the way that is known as the fallacy argumentum ad hominem (van Eemeren and Grootendorst 1992b, 1995b). 4 Specific areas of interest in the study of argumentation 4.1 Reconstructing implicit reasons The crucial problems of analyzing oral or written argumentative discourse pertain to 'implicit reasons', 'argument schemes' and the 'structure of argumentation'. Before they can be properly dealt with, it must first be clear exactly which standpoints are being defended and which reasons are given in their defence. This raises the fundamental question of how utterances can be identified as standpoints or as argumentation. In pragma-dialectics, both standpoints and argumentation are defined as (complex) speech acts that are characterized by the commitments assumed by the speaker or writer when performing a speech act. In practice, indications of these commitments are often provided by the presentation of the speech act in a certain context and situation, the reaction given to the speech act and the way in which the discourse is continued (Houtlosser 1998). 'Implicit reasons' (or unexpressed premises) constitute a central problem in the reconstruction of argumentation. How can argumentative elements that have not been expressed explicitly be systematically detected? It was only after 1975 that this problem really started to catch the attention of modern argumentation theorists. As long as the formal logical approach was still dominant, it did not play a meaningful role. In logic the starting point is that arguments have explicit premises and an explicit conclusion, but argumentation in ordinary language also contains all kinds of implicit elements. Van Eemeren and Grootendorst (1981a) argued that the problem can best be approached by viewing implicit reasons (or unexpressed premises) as 'conversational implicatures' and using Grice's derivation scheme for making them explicit. It is clear that this approach has not yet answered all the questions there are. A watertight method for determining systematically a - let alone the - correct reconstruction of an implicit reason is still not available. So much is clear that the goal should not be to find out what the speaker or writer 'really had in mind', but to determine (1) to which proposition in the context and situation concerned the speaker or writer can be held committed which not only (2) makes the argument underlying the argumentation valid, but also (3) adds something to the explicit argumentation. Van Eemeren en Grootendorst speak of looking for the 'pragmatic optimum' (1992a: 64-68, see also van Eemeren et al. 1995). Here is an example: Shawn loves singing, because he is Irish. (Irish people love singing) (pragmatic optimum that constitutes the implicit reason) Each of the three requirements that are just mentioned has its own problems. In the current literature on implicit reasons authors are usually mainly concerned with the question whether 'validity' should be taken exclusively as deductive validity and the question of how implicit reasons can be distinguished from other implicit elements in argumentative discourse. Among those who are in favour of 'reconstructive deductivism' are van Eemeren and Grootendorst (1992a), Thomas (1986), Johnson and Blair (1977) and Groarke (1992); adversaries are Govier (1997) and Hitchcock (1987). The first one who emphasized the importance of distinguishing between implicit reasons and, for instance, presuppositions is Ennis (1982). As a distinguishing feature of implicit reasons he considers their function of bridging the gap between explicit reasons and conclusions. Gilbert (1991) and Blair (1992) try to clarify the bridging function of implicit reasons by making use of the theoretical notions of topos and 'argument scheme'. 4.2 The importance of deductive validity The role of formal logic is discussed in a more philosophical sense with regard to the criteria for evaluating the soundness of argumentation. This discussion focuses on the logical soundness criterion of 'deductive validity'. Deductive validity is the criterion of allowing formal derivation which means that an argument is valid if and only if it is a substitution instance of a formally valid argument form which is such that it cannot be the case that true premises lead to a false conclusion. This is for example the case in the following argument which is bases on the argument form know as modus ponens: Argument: Premise 1: If Peter comes, then Mary comes. Premise 2: Peter comes. Conclusion: Mary comes. Argument form: Premise 1: p --> q Premise 2: p Conclusion: q Apart from the exceptional logical die-hard, none of the present day argumentation theorists still thinks that 'deductive validity' deserves to be in a monopoly position. Following Toulmin and Perelman argumentation theorists have become ever more convinced that the role of deductive validity is relatively modest, although some logicians still argue that logic deserves a central position in a general theory of argumentation. As a model for argumentation in ordinary language formal logic is most fiercely attacked by the informal logicians. To them, this is as it were at the core of their platform. Criticism concentrates on the fact that the notion 'deductive validity' would be a norm that is too strict and therefore inappropriate for evaluating arguments in ordinary language. If this criterion is maintained without any qualification, almost all argumentation is invalid, if only because when arguing in ordinary language there are always some elements which remain implicit. This kind of criticism is most clearly expressed in Govier (1987) Problems in argument analysis and evaluation. Nowadays some informal logicians take a more differentiated stance. Johnson, for one, argues that although informal logic offers the best framework for evaluating argumentation in ordinary language there is also a small role for formal deductive logic when it comes to evaluating implications and inferences (1992: 157). A strong defender of the 'deductivism' so despised by Govier is the, again Canadian, logician Groarke. Groarke argues that all good arguments are deductively valid and that this conception is a fruitful starting point for analyzing and evaluating arguments in natural language. Those who reject every formalism and deductivism, according to Groarke, throw the baby out with the bathwater. He pleads for 'reconstructive deductivism': when making implicit premises explicit one tries to make the argument deductively valid (1992: 117). For practical purposes, van Eemeren and Grootendorst (1982, 1984, 1992a) advocate the same policy in dealing with implicit premises because validating an argument in this way provides the simplest starting point for determining what the suggested relationship between the explicit reason and the standpoint amounts to. The British logician Fisher has a similar view, but his view pertains to the detection of the logical form in the structure of argumentation (1992: 170). 4.3 Distinguishing argument schemes 'Argument schemes' are among the concepts which are studied intensively by argumentation theorists to create an alternative to the formal logical model and its deductive validity norm. The point of departure in these studies is that in argumentative discourse, depending on the argument scheme that is used, various types of argumentation can be distinguished. Each type of argumentation calls for the answering of specific critical questions to evaluate the acceptability of the argumentation concerned. Based on the argument schemes that can be employed in attempting to convince the interlocutor or reader, van Eemeren and Grootendorst (1992a) make a distinction between three main types of argumentation: (1) symptomatic (or 'sign') argumentation, (2) argumentation by comparison (or 'analogy'), and (3) causal (or 'teleological') argumentation. By way of illustration I shall present an example of symptomatic argumentation in which the argument scheme of a sign relation is used (as is indicated by the expression 'is typical of' in the reconstruction of the implicit reason 1.1'): symptomatic argumentation: 1 That restaurant must be expensive. [because] 1.1 It seems to have three stars. [and] 1.1' (It is typical of restaurants with three stars that they are expensive.) argument scheme of a sign relation: 1 For X holds Y 1.1 because: For X holds Z 1.1' and: Z is typical of Y The argument schemes of argumentation by comparison and causal argumentation are as follows: argument scheme of a relation of analogy: 1 For X holds Y 1.1 because: For Z holdsY 1.1' and: Z is similar as X argument scheme of a teleological relation: 1 For X holds Y 1.1 because: For X holds Z 1.1' and: Z leads toY With these three main types of argumentation correspond, resulting from the use of the argument schemes of a sign relation, a relation of analogy or a teleological relation, three different sets of critical questions. In a critical discussion as envisaged in pragma-dialectics these are the critical questions the other party in the discussion is supposed to advance. Of course, each type of argumentation comprises a whole series of subtypes (such as 'pragmatic' argumentation with causal argumentation) that require more and more specific critical questions. Kienpointner (1992a, 1992b) is an author who made a broad inventory of argumentation (sub)types and argument schemes distinguished in the literature and by him. 4.4 Determining the structure of argumentation A central problem in the research concerning the analysis of argumentative discourse is the determination of the structure of argumentation. The argumentation structure of a text, speech or discussion is determined by the way in which the reasons that are advanced hang together and jointly support the standpoint that is defended. An adequate evaluation of the argumentative discourse cannot take place as long as it is not clear what the argumentation structure is. What kind of structural relations can be distinguished? Initially this problem was only dealt with in practical textbooks. Later it also become an important subject in theoretical publications such as Freeman's (1991) Dialectics and the macrostructure of arguments and Snoeck Henkemans' (1992) Analysing complex argumentation. The oldest model for the analysis of the structure of argumentation dates back to Beardsley's (1950) Practical logic; this model is most popular among informal logicians, such as Thomas (1986). In Practical reasoning in natural language Thomas (1986) distinguishes four different structures: (1) 'convergent' argumentation in which two or more reasons support a standpoint independently, (2) 'divergent' argumentation in which one reason supports two or more standpoints, (3) 'serial' argumentation in which one reason is itself again supported by another reason, and (4) 'linked' argumentation in which two or more reasons depend on each other and support the standpoint only when taken jointly. In the pragma-dialectical classification of complex argumentation a distinction is made between (1) 'coordinative' argumentation (with a combined line of defence), (2) 'multiple' argumentation (with separate lines of defence) and (3) 'subordinative' argumentation (with a continued line of defence). This classification is explained in van Eemeren and Grootendorst (1992a) with the help of some examples: We had to dine out, because there was nothing left at home and all shops were closed. (coordinative argumentation structure) It is impossible that you saw my mother last week in Sheringham in Marks and Spencer's , because my mother died two years ago and Sheringham does not have a Marks and Spencer's. (multiple argumentation structure) I need not help you painting next week, because next week I do not have any time because I have to work for an exam then. (subordinative argumentation structure) In spite of the differences in terminology, in the descriptions of the various argumentation structures and in the diagramming, the distinctions that are made in the argumentation literature are about the same. A problem in all approaches is - put in pragma-dialectical terms - the distinction between coordinative and multiple argumentation. Snoeck Henkemans (1992) looks for a solution into the dialogue situation, in which coordinative argumentation fulfils a different function than multiple argumentation. Another problem is the representation in the argumentation structure of counterarguments and hypothetical or suppositional arguments. Freeman (1991) propose a special notational system for these cases. Snoeck Henkemans (1992) also discusses the location of counterarguments and refutations of counterarguments in the argumentation structure. Fisher (1989) pays special attention to the analysis of suppositional argumentation. 4.5 Detecting fallacies By far the most popular topic in the study of argumentation are the fallacies. Virtually every normative theory of argumentation includes a treatment of the fallacies. In some sense the quality of a normative theory of argumentation can even be judged from the degree to which it makes it possible to provide an adequate analysis of the fallacies. Conversely, it stands to reason that giving an analysis of notorious fallacies can in turn be conducive to the examination of the norms of sound argumentation. A major source of problems in the study of fallacies is the logico-centric definition of a fallacy as an argument which seems valid but is not valid, which has been for a long time been adhered to in the so-called standard treatment of the fallacies (van Eemeren et al. 1996: 51-74). In some cases the examples given to illustrate this definition are already inconsistent with this description. Take for instance the fallacy of many questions: 'When did you stop beating your wife?' In this example there is no argument. And, viewed logically, circular reasoning, also known as petitio principii or begging the question, is not invalid. 'Rome is the capital of Italy, therefore Rome is the capital of Italy' is a perfectly valid argument. Since Hamblin (1970) published his book Fallacies there is a general awareness that the standard treatment suffers from crucial shortcomings. Starting already in 1972, the Canadian logicians Woods and Walton have continuously attempted to enhance the level of the study of fallacies (van Eemeren et al. 1996: ch. 8.2). Until the beginning of the eighties their efforts were in the first place logically-oriented: by exploring advanced logical systems, such as modal and deontic logic, they hoped to arrive at a more satisfactory analysis of a number of fallacies. This is the approach they demonstrate, for instance, in their textbook Argument: The logic of the fallacies (1982) and in Fallacies (1989), a collection of their joint papers. Around 1985 a pragmatic turn has been made, particularly by Walton, which resulted in logic (in)validity no longer being the only norm (van Eemeren and Grootendorst 1989). In Arguer's position (1985), Informal fallacies (1987) and a great number of later books (1995, 1996, 1998, 1999) Walton examines by means of case studies in which contexts and situations a fallacy is really a fallacy and when a certain move is in fact not a fallacy at all but a correct discussion move. His conclusion is that there are various types of dialogues, constituting different types of argumentative contexts. In his opinion, fallacies are incorrect dialectical shifts from the one type of dialogue to the other (1992). In Commitment and dialogue this idea is used by Walton and Krabbe (1995) as a point of departure for further theorizing. Walton's change of vision marks a trend among argumentation theorists, and led by Walton, to regard fallacies no longer without exception as incorrect moves. Opposite the 'moderates', however, who are inclined to take due account of 'mitigating circumstances', are the 'orthodox', who fear that this will lead to an unsystematic ad hoc approach. In their - not yet highly developed - epistemic approach, Biro and Siegel (1992), for instance, regard fallacies as failed argumentative attempts to increase our knowledge of the world. The pragmadialecticians van Eemeren and Grootendorst think that any violation of a discussion rule should be viewed as a fallacy that endangers the resolution of a difference of opinion. On the basis of the various discussion rules it can be indicated what exactly went wrong (van Eemeren and Grootendorst 1992a, 1992c, 1995a). A new and different contribution to the study of fallacies are the experimental empirical tests regarding the extent to which the norms developed on theoretical grounds are in agreement with those favoured by ordinary participants in argumentative discourse. Starting from the pragma-dialectical discussion rules, van Eemeren, Grootendorst and Meuffels (together with Garssen and others) have started a series of tests that are aimed at achieving more clarity on this matter. They methodically check whether, and how strongly, different kinds of violations of the various discussion rules are considered 'wrong' moves by ordinary judges (1999, with Verburg 1998). 5 The infrastructure of the discipline The study of argumentation is characterised by its interdisciplinary, or in any case multidisciplinary, character. Its progress depends on contributions from a great variety of fields: philosophy, logic, (speech) communication, linguistics, psychology, sociology, rhetoric, law, etc. Several professional societies promote the study of argumentation. The most important are the International Society for the Study of Argumentation (ISSA) and its associate the Ontario Society for the Study of Argumentation (OSSA), the Association for Informal Logic and Critical Thinking (AILACT), the American National Communication Association (NCA) and its subdivision the American Forensic Association (AFA). These - and other societies and academic institutions - regularly organize conferences on argumentation, which are usually multidisciplinary, and often international. Since 1986 ISSA organizes every four years its general congress in Amsterdam: the "Olympics of argumentation theory". Furthermore, all kinds of argumentation conferences and colloquia are held all over the world, such as the conferences organized by OSSA, the Alta conferences of the American Forensic Association, the Argumentation conference in Venice, sponsored jointly by Wake Forest University and ISSA, special sessions of the International Society for the History of Rhetoric, and the regular symposia on special topics at the University of Amsterdam. Several journals are exclusively devoted to the study of argumentation. The most prominent are Argumentation (since1987), Informal Logic (since 1978, after having appeared until 1984 as Informal Logic Newsletter) and Argumentation and Advocacy (since 1988 the continuation of the Journal of the American Forensic Association, which started in 1954). The journal Argumentation publishes annually an annotated bibliography of publications on argumentation. The following scholarly journals also frequently host studies of argumentation: Communication & Cognition, Communication Monographs, Journal of Communication, Journal of Philosophy, Journal of Pragmatics, Logique et Analyse, Philosophy and Rhetoric, Quarterly Journal of Speech. © Frans H. van Eemeren, 2002 ________ References Anscombre, J.-C. and O. Ducrot (1983) L'argumentation dans la langue. Brussels: Mardaga. Anscombre, J.-C. and O. Ducrot (1986) Argumentativite et informativite. In: Meyer, M. (ed. 1986), 79-94. Austin. J.L. (1962) How to do things with words. London etc.: Oxford University Press. Barth, E.M. and E.C.W. Krabbe (1982) From axiom to dialogue: A philosophical study of logics and argumentation. Berlin etc.: Walter de Gruyter. Biro, J. and H. Siegel (1992) Normativity, argumentation and an epistemic theory of fallacies. In: Eemeren F.H. van, R. Grootendorst, J.A. Blair and Ch.A. Willard (eds. 1992), 85-103. Blair, J.A. and R.H. Johnson (1987) The current state of informal logic. Informal Logic 9, no. 2/3, 147-151. Blair, J.A. and R.H. Johnson (1997) Argumentation as dialectical. Argumentation 1 (1987), no. 1, 41-56. Braet, A.C. (1984) De klassieke statusleer in modern perspectief. Groningen: WoltersNoordhoff. Crawshay-Williams, R. (1957) Methods and criteria of reasoning. An inquiry into the structure of controversy. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Damer, T.E. (1987) Attacking faulty reasoning. 2nd ed. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth (1st ed. 1980). Ducrot, O. (1980) Les echelles argumentatives. Paris: Les editions de minuit. Ducrot, O. (1984) Le dire et le dit. Paris: Minuit. Eemeren, F.H. van (1986) Dialectical analysis as a normative reconstruction of argumentative discourse. Text 6, 1-16. Eemeren, F.H. van, K. de Glopper, R. Grootendorst and R. Oostdam (1995) Identification of unexpressed premisses and argumentation schemes by students in secondary school. Argumentation and Advocacy 31, 151-162. Eemeren, F.H. van and R. Grootendorst (1984) Speech acts in argumentative discussions. Dordrecht etc.: Foris. Eemeren, F.H. van and R. Grootendorst (1989) A transition stage in the theory of fallacies. Journal of Pragmatics 13, no. 1, 99-109. Eemeren, F.H. van and R. Grootendorst (1992a) Argumentation, communication, and fallacies. Hillsdale, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum. Eemeren, F.H. van and R. Grootendorst (1992b) Relevance reviewed: the case of argumentum ad hominem. Argumentation 6, no. 2, 141-159. Eemeren, F.H. van and R. Grootendorst (eds. 1994) Studies in pragma-dialectics. Amsterdam: Sic Sat. Eemeren, F.H. van and R. Grootendorst (1995a) The pragma-dialectical approach to fallacies. In: Hansen, H.V. and R.C. Pinto (eds. 1995), 130-144. Eemeren, F.H. van and R. Grootendorst (1995b) Argumentum ad hominem: A pragmadialectical case in point. In: Hansen, H.V. en R.C. Pinto (eds. 1995), 130-144. Eemeren, F.H. van and R. Grootendorst (1990) Analyzing argumentative discourse. In: Trapp, R. and J. Schuetz (eds. 1990), 86-106. Eemeren, F.H. van, R. Grootendorst, J.A. Blair and Ch.A. Willard (eds. 1992) Argumentation illuminated. Amsterdam: SICSAT/ISSA. Eemeren, F.H. van, R. Grootendorst, S. Jackson and S. Jacobs (1993) Reconstructing argumentative discourse. Tuscaloosa, Alabama: The University of Alabama Press. Eemeren, F.H. van, R. Grootendorst, S. Jackson and S. Jacobs (1997) Argumentation. In: Dijk, T.A. van (ed. 1997) Discourse as Structure and Process. Discourse Studies: A multidisciplinary introduction. Dl. I. London etc.: Sage, 208-229. Eemeren, F.H. van, R. Grootendorst and B. Meuffels (1989) The skill of identifying argumentation. Argumentation and Advocacy 25, no. 4, 239-245. Reprinted in Eemeren, F.H. van and R. Grootendorst (eds. 1994), 119-129. Eemeren, F.H. van, R. Grootendorst, A.F. Snoeck Henkemans, J.A. Blair, R.H. Johnson, E.C.W. Krabbe, C. Plantin, D.N. Walton, Ch.A. Willard, J. Woods, and D. Zarefsky (1996) Fundamentals of argumentation Theory. Mahwah, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum. Eemeren, F.H. van and P. Houtlosser (1999) Strategic manoeuvering in argumentative discourse. Discourse Studies 1, no. 4, 479-497. Ennis, R.H. (1982) Identifying implicit assumptions. Synthese 51, 61-86. Farrell, Th.B. (1976) Knowledge, consensus, and rhetorical theory. Quarterly Journal of Speech 62, 1-14. Farrell, Th.B. (1993) Norms of rhetorical culture. New Haven/London: Yale University Press. Fisher, A. (1989) Suppositions in argumentation. Argumentation 3, no. 4, 401-413. Fisher, A. (1992) The structure of argument. In: Eemeren F.H. van, R. Grootendorst, J.A. Blair and Ch.A. Willard (eds. 1992), 159-171. Freeman, J.B. (1988) Thinking logically. Basic concepts for reasoning. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall. Freeman, J.B. (1991) Dialectics and the macrostructure of arguments. A theory of argument structure. Berlin etc.: Foris/Walter de Gruyter. Gilbert, M.A. (1991) The enthymeme buster: a heuristic procedure for position exploration in dialogic dispute. Informal Logic 13, no. 3, 159-166. Govier, T. (1985) A practical study of argument. Belmont: Wadsworth. Govier, T. (1987) Problems in argument analysis and evaluation. Dordrecht etc.: Foris. Grice, H.P. (1975) Logic and conversation. In: P. Cole en J.L. Morgan (eds. 1975) Syntax and semantics 3: Speech acts. New York: Academic Press, 45-58. Reprinted in Grice, P. (1989) Studies in the way of words. Cambridge-London: Harvard University Press, vol. I. Groarke, L. (1992) In defense of deductivism: Replying to Govier. In: Eemeren, F.H. van, R. Grootendorst, J.A. Blair and Ch.A. Willard (eds. 1992), 113-121. Hamblin, Ch.L. (1970) Fallacies. London: Methuen. Hansen, H.V. and R.C. Pinto (eds. 1995) Fallacies. Classical and contemporary readings. University Park, PA, Penn State Press. Hitchcock, D. (1987) Enthymematic arguments. In: Eemeren, F.H. van, R. Grootendorst, J.A. Blair and Ch.A. Willard (eds. 1987), 289-298. Houtlosser, P. (1998) Points of view. Argumentation 12, no. 3, 387-405. Johnson, R.H. (1992) The impact of the continuum hypothesis on theories of evaluation. In: Eemeren, F.H. van, R. Grootendorst, J.A. Blair and Ch.A. Willard (eds. 1992), 148-158. Johnson, R.H. and J.A. Blair (1977) Logical self-defense. 1st ed. Toronto: McGraw-Hill Ryerson (3rd ed . 1993). Johnson, R.H. and J.A. Blair (1980) The recent development of informal logic. In: Blair, J.A. en R.H. Johnson (eds. 1980) Informal logic. The first international symposium. Point Reyce, Ca: Edgepress, 3-28. Johnson, R.H. and J.A. Blair (eds.) (1994) New essays in informal logic. Windsor: Informal Logic. Kienpointner, M. (1991) Rhetoric and argumentation-relativism and beyond. Philosophy and Rhetoric 24, no. 1, 43-53. Kienpointner, M. (1992a) Alltagslogik. Stuttgart: Frommann-Holzboog. Kienpointner, M. (1992b) How to classify arguments. In: Eemeren, F.H. van, R. Grootendorst, J.A. Blair and Ch.A. Willard (eds. 1992), 178-188. Kopperschmidt, J. (1989) Methodik der Argumentationsanalyse. Stuttgart: FromannHolzboog. Lambert, K. and W. Ulrich (1980) The nature of argument. New York etc.: Macmillan. McKerrow, R.E. (1977) Rhetorical validity: an analysis of three perspectives on the justification of rhetorical argument. Journal of the American Forensic Association 13, 133 141. Meyer, M. (1986) Introduction. In: Meyer, M. (ed. 1986) De la metaphysique a la rhetorique. Brussels: Editions de l'Universite de Bruxelles. Nolke, H. (1992) Semantic constraints on argumentation: From polyphonic micro-structure to argumentative macro-structure. In: Eemeren, F.H. van, R. Grootendorst, J.A. Blair and Ch.A. Willard (eds. 1992), 189-200. O'Keefe, D. (1977) Two concepts of argument. Journal of the American Forensic Association 13, 121 128. Perelman, Ch. and L. Olbrechts-Tyteca (1958) La nouvelle rhetorique: traite de l'argumentation. Bruxelles: l'Universite de Bruxelles. English translation (1969) The new rhetoric. A treatise on argumentation. Notre Dame etc.: University of Notre Dame Press. Popper, K.R. (1972) Objective knowledge: An evolutionary approach. Oxford Clarendon Press. Popper, K.R. (1974) Conjectures and refutations. The growth of scientific knowledge. 5th ed. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Reboul, O. (1988) Can there be non-rhetorical argumentation? Philosophy and Rhetoric 21, no. 3, 220-223. Reboul, O. (1990) Rhetorique et dialectique chez Aristote. Argumentation 4, no. 1, 35-52. Searle, J.R. (1969) Speech acts. An essay in the philosophy of language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Searle, J.R. (1979) Expression and meaning. Studies in the theory of speech acts. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Snoeck Henkemans, A.F. (1992) Analysing complex argumentation. The reconstruction of multiple and coordinatively compound argumentation in a critical discussion. Amsterdam: Sic Sat. Thomas, S.N. (1986) Practical reasoning in natural language. 3rd ed. Englewood Cliffs, N.Y.: Prentice-Hall (1st ed. 1973). Toulmin, S.E. (1958) The uses of argument. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Toulmin, S.E. (1976) Knowing and acting. An invitation to philosophy. New York MacMillan. Toulmin, S. (1992) Logic, rhetoric & reason: Redressing the balance. In: Eemeren, F.H. van, R. Grootendorst, J.A. Blair and Ch.A. Willard (eds. 1992), 3-11. Trapp, R. and J. Schuetz (eds. 1990) Perspectives on argumentation. Essays in the honor of Wayne Brockriede. Illinois: Waveland Press. Walton, D.N. (1985) Arguer's position. A pragmatic study of Ad hominem attack, criticism, refutation, and fallacy. Westport etc.: Greenwood Press. Walton, D.N. (1987) Informal fallacies. Toward a theory of argument criticisms. Amsterdam etc.: John Benjamins. Walton, D.N. (1992) Types of dialogue, dialectical shifts and fallacies. In: Eemeren, F.H. van, R. Grootendorst, J.A. Blair and Ch.A. Willard (eds. 1992), 133-147. Walton, D.N. (1995) A pragmatic theory of fallacy. Tuscaloosa etc.: The University of Alabama Press. Walton, D.N. (1996) Argumentative schemes for presumptive reasoning. Mahwah, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum. Walton, D.N. (1999) Appeal to popular opinion. University Park, Pa: The Pennsylvania State University Press. Walton, D.N. and E.C.W. Krabbe (1995) Commitment and dialogue. Basic concepts of interpersonal reasoning. Albany, NY: SUNY Press. Wenzel, J.W. (1980) Perspectives on argument. In: Rhodes, J. and S. Newell (eds. 1980) Proceedings of the 1979 Summer Conference on Argument. Falls Church: SCA. Willard, C.A. (1983) Argumentation and the social grounds of knowledge. Alabama: The University of Alabama Press. Willard, C.A. (1989) A theory of argumentation. Tuscaloosa etc.: The University of Alabama Press. Woods, J. and D. Walton (1982) Argument: The logic of the fallacies. Toronto etc.: McGraw Hill Ryerson. Woods, J. and D. Walton (1989) Fallacies. Selected papers 1972-1982. Dordrecht etc.: Foris.