[Opmerking: dit artikel is geschreven voor een verzamelbundel met verschillende artikelen van Nederlandse boeddhisme-onderzoekers, werktitel “Buddhist Studies”, onder redactie van Paul van der Velde en Aloys Wijngaard, te verschijnen in 2007/2008. Mijn verzoek aan jullie is om het kritisch te lezen met deze context, en dit lezerspubliek, in het achterhoofd. Een tweede idee is om dit uit te bouwen tot een filosofisch meer uitgewerkt artikel voor het tijdschrift “Philosophy East and West”. Als jullie suggesties hebben voor deze filosofische uitwerking, graag.] André van der Braak 15 februari 2007 Nietzsche and Nagarjuna: skepticism East and West Towards a comparative study The comparative philosopher these days has a much harder time capturing the attention of his audience than the average Western philosopher. First he has to fight a commonly shared skepticism concerning the usefulness of doing comparative philosophy (or intercultural philosophy, or world philosophy, even the terminological confusion poses a problem). Then he has to outline and defend his methodological approach. And, after having outlined the topic of his paper and the issue that he wants to analyze, he has to introduce the non-Western philosopher that he uses in his argument, to his audience. Only then can he start with his actual argument. Therefore this paper on Nietzsche and the second-century Buddhist philosopher Nagarjuna, written for an audience of non-specialists, will be more of a prolegomenon than I hoped for. It has four sections. In section (1) I will defend the usefulness of approaching Nietzsche’s thought from a non-Western, and specifically Mahayana Buddhist, point of view. In section (2) I will introduce the cross-cultural hermeneutical approach that I will be taking. In section (3) I will outline the aspect of Nietzsche’s thought that I want to elucidate in this paper: the relationship between Nietzsche’s no-saying philosophy and his yes-saying philosophy. I will argue that a crucial aspect in this relationship is the notion that he develops in Jenseits von Gut und Bose 209: that of a strong skepticism. This notion is very closely related to his self-imposed task of a revaluation of all values. In section (4) I will introduce Nagarjuna. In section (5) it will be argued how Nagarjuna’s philosophical approach can shed 1 fresh light on what Nietzsche actually means by his practice of strong skepticism. It will be apparent that such skepticism is not only an epistemological stance or practice, but also an ethical and even a soteriological practice, aimed at liberation. 1. Do we need another, ‘Buddhist’, Nietzsche? As the number of Nietzsche-interpretations has mushroomed over the past decades, so have the various ‘Nietzsche’s’. After Nietzsche the ‘Lebensphilosoph’, Nietzsche the Naziphilosopher, the existentialist Nietzsche, the structuralist Nietzsche, the postmodern Nietzsche, why do we need more Nietzsche’s? And why, of all things, a Buddhist Nietzsche? Although Nietzsche wrote in his Nachlass “Ich könnte der Buddha Europas werden”, he continues with “was freilich ein Gegenstück zum indischen wäre” (KSA 10.109). Throughout his work it seems clear that he rejected Buddhism as a life-denying, nihilistic response to the problem of suffering. But more is to be said on this issue. Firstly, Nietzsche’s relationship to Buddhism is more complicated. He paid, as one of the few western philosophers, quite serious attention to Buddhism. The term Buddhismus occurs 173 times in his work sometimes in a performative sense, and sometimes to elucidate his own positions.1 In his early work, Nietzsche considers Buddhism to be a Schopenhauerian nihilism, an illness, a denial of the will. Between 1880 and 1887 he uses the term “Buddhismus” to diagnose the development of nihilism in European culture. He regularly writes about the inevitable development of a new European Buddhism: a longing for nothingness as a result of decadence. Nietzsche calls this a “passive nihilism”. In The Antichrist Nietzsche speaks very positively about Buddhism, but mostly for performative reasons, as a weapon in his war on Christianity. He idealizes Buddhism as a positivistic religion “a hundred times more realistic than Christianity.” (AC 20). Although he still calls Buddhism a form of nihilism, he praises it as an aristocratic and non-moralistic religion. Secondly, there are some gaps in most Nietzsche-interpretations that could perhaps be fruitfully addressed by means of a comparison with Buddhism. Nietzsche is well-known for his scathing critique of the epistemological, ontological and moral foundations of the Western philosophical tradition, which has served as an inspiration for the postmodern deconstructionist movement. He is hailed as a great religious critic, as epitomized in his 1 See my lemma on ‘Buddhismus’ in part I of the Nietzsche Dictionary (van Tongeren 2005) 2 famous dictum ‘God is dead’. But for Nietzsche himself, this critique was only meant as a stepping stone to a new beginning, a radical new way of thinking, an Umwertung aller Werte. Among Nietzsche researchers, a growing recognition is taking place of this postmoralist and postreligious dimension of Nietzsche’s thought (Roberts 1998, Schacht 2000, Urpeth & Lippitt 2000) that can be fruitfully interpreted from Asian traditions (Parkes 1991), especially Buddhist ones. Since the early 1980s the importance has been stressed for a comparative study of Nietzsche and Buddhism (Mistry 1981). In 1998 Robert Morrison published Nietzsche and Buddhism, which unfortunately was limited to Theravada Buddhism, the only form of Buddhism that was known well in Europe in Nietzsche’s time, and which Nietzsche rejected as a form of nihilism (Morrison 1998). Nietzsche’s understanding of Buddhism was not only hampered by the limited familiarity with historical Buddhism in his time, but also by contemporary nineteenthcentury interpretations of Buddhism as a ‘cult of nothingness’ (Droit 2003). Nietzsche researchers such as Graham Parkes argue convincingly that the later Mahayana Buddhism (that only became well-known in the western world after 1900) is a much better candidate for a fruitful comparison with Nietzsche’s philosophy. For Nietzsche, as for Mahayana Buddhism, the formulation of his thought in language belongs to the matter of his thinking to a greater extent than for other philosophers. He knows and makes use of the seductions and traps of language. Not only does the meaning of certain words change with the development of his thought; more than most philosophers, he consciously works with the possibility of ascribing different meanings to the same words through differing contextualisations and the use of various perspectives. 2. Towards a cross-cultural hermeneutical approach Although much has been published on Nietzsche and Christianity, not that much has been said about Nietzsche and Buddhism. The two monographs that have appeared on Nietzsche and Buddhism (Mistry 1981, Morrison 1998) both suffer from two shortcomings. Firstly, they limit their treatment of Buddhism to the oldest school of Buddhism, Theravada. Secondly, they stop at pointing out similarities between the two systems of thought (what Morrison calls ‘ironic affinities’) and possible ways in which Nietzsche’s philosophy was influenced by this knowledge of Buddhism. As interesting and rewarding as these purposes may be, my own 3 goal is different. I want to shed new light on crucial aspects of Nietzsche’s philosophy by new hermeneutical strategies. This would entail doing comparative philosophy in a new way. As Garfield (2002) notes, “The field of comparative philosophy has acquired a deservedly bad reputation of late (see Tuck 1990 and Larson and Deutsch 1989). It has been noted that it too often functions as an arm of Orientalism in the most pejorative sense of that term, as an appropriation of expertise on non-Western traditions by Western scholars, with a consequent disempowerment of their non-Western colleagues. Moreover, it has been noted, comparative philosophy often imports hermeneutical and philosophical methods to the study of non-Western texts that succeed in distorting or simply missing the significance of those texts or the meaningfulness of their claims and arguments in the context of their home cultures. In addition it has been noted that the interpretive lens privileged in most comparative philosophy is distinctively Western. […] As a closely related matter, it has been charged that in comparing philosophical text and views, the Western texts, views, and arguments are typically taken as the standards against which non-Western texts are compared and evaluated. ” (Garfield 2002 p. 152) 2 A more promising approach would be to elucidate forms of Western thought through the lens of non-Western ways of thinking. Such a cross-cultural hermeneutical perspective is advocated by Garfield (2002). The French sinologist Francois Jullien stresses that, through the detour of non-Western philosophies, we can regain access to lost or underemphasized dimensions of our own Western tradition (Jullien 2004). Western philosophy has always only questioned itself from within. But however radical this questioning may be, it always remains within the limits of an implicit understanding from which certain positions may emerge. To step back from the Western tradition and criticize it from without can allow us to assume a more truly global position. Understanding is only possible when we are far enough from our object to see it more completely. Therefore, cultural distance can make things visible to a somewhat removed interpreter that remain hidden for an interpreter immersed in the same philosophical tradition. Just as we can read Plato with greater understanding than Plato himself ever could, so Nietzsche can be read with greater understanding through a nonWestern lens. This quote is from the section ‘Metahermeneutic preliminaries’ of chapter 8 of Garfield (2002), entitled: Western Idealism through Indian Eyes: a Cittamatra Reading of Berkeley, Kant, and Schopenhauer. In this chapter he retells the development of western Idealism from the perspective of the Indian Buddhist mind-only school. Methodologically my own work is indebted to his approach. 2 4 Such a confrontation could be a major breakthrough in the fusion of Western and nonWestern horizons. A much-needed common horizon can be a background for genuine collaboration and conversation in a joint philosophical venture. The possibilities for such a venture are enormous. The enlargement of the world scholarly community and the range of texts and resources on which it can draw promise a greater philosophical depth and rate of progress. 3. Nietzsche’s skepticism Nietzsche is well known for his skepticism. An excellent overview is given by Poellner (1995). Not only does Nietzsche declare that it is impossible for us to know reality as it is in itself (epistemological skepticism), he even goes as far to doubt the very notion of a ‘reality in itself’ (ontological skepticism). Our metaphysical ideas don’t represent a fundamental truth, but only the dynamics of the constructive process by which we generate a conceptual world within which we can live. There are no extra-linguistic realities, no “being” to which our “true” ideas ultimately correspond. For Nietzsche, however, his skepticism is not only a philosophical position. His philosophical skepticism is accompanied by what we could call a psychological skepticism: our cherished notions that have sustained our western culture, such as “truth” and “being”, are being diagnosed as expressions of a negative valuation of existence. With the skeptical deconstruction of such notions, the world begins to look valueless and meaningless. Nihilism looms large. But Nietzsche’s philosophy doesn’t simply consist of an attack on metaphysical and epistemological traditions. His genealogical writing creates a new kind of hermeneutic that goes beyond taking epistemological issue with traditional ideas. Rather, those ideas are seen as having a disguised meaning that is symptomatic of a certain valuation of life. Nietzsche doesn’t accept nihilism as an inevitable outcome. He searches in his work to find a breakthrough to a new mode of affirmation. Nietzsche the skeptic who concludes that “there is no truth” must therefore be distinguished from Nietzsche the visionary, whose third period is animated by a vision of a state beyond nihilism, a vision that can transfigure our relationship to life itself into an affirmative one. Nietzsche’s new experimental philosophy seeks a new spiritual vision not grounded in metaphysical illusions. 5 For Nietzsche, therefore, skepticism doesn’t have the last word. In his work we can find a skeptical critique of skepticism where Nietzsche diagnoses the philosophical position of skepticism as motivated by a weakness in willing, a nihilistic inability to affirm existence. In Beyond Good and Evil aphorism 208 Nietzsche calls skepticism “the most spiritual expression of a certain many-sided physiological temperament, which in ordinary language is called nervous debility and sickliness”. In aphorism 209 he opposes such a weak skepticism with “another and stronger kind of skepticism”, “the skepticism of daring manliness”. “This skepticism despises and nevertheless grasps; it undermines and takes possession; it does not believe, but it does not thereby lose itself; it gives the spirit a dangerous liberty, but it keeps strict guard over the heart.” Such a strong skepticism is not just part of a philosophy that is a theoretical enterprise. It should give rise to a radically altered vision of philosophy as a revaluation of all values. Philosophy thus gains an existential dimension and turns into a soteriological enterprise, aimed at a liberation of the individual, enabling him to live in the world without being hypnotized by conceptual essences such as “truth” and “being”. Truthfulness requires that we find a way to live with the continual realization that our perspectives give us nothing but “lies” and “illusions”. In this way the word truth takes on an ethical meaning. A person’s strength and courage are revealed by the degree to which he can endure the truth that all meanings and all values have disintegrated, along with the notion of “being” and its religious correlate, “God”. In aphorism 210, Nietzsche says that the philosophers of the future must be such skeptics. They are not only great critics, but are also able to create values. In this way they can execute Nietzsche’s post-skeptical project of a revaluation of all values. Therefore, although Nietzsche’s radical skepsis seems to culminate in epistemological nihilism ("God is dead"), he ultimately thinks it possible to overcome this nihilism. He differentiates between strong and weak skepticism. Strong skepticism refers to a new truth practice based on perspectivism and will to power, aimed not at discovering static truths about reality, but at becoming a truthful person. In this sense this new truth practice has a strong ethical component. It is connected to a process of self-cultivation. In order to elucidate and evaluate this new truth practice of strong skepticism, a comparison and confrontation with the philosophy of Nagarjuna could be useful. 6 4. Nagarjuna It is unfortunate that Nietzsche was not familiar with the writings of the second-century Buddhist philosopher Nagarjuna, one of the most important figures in the early development of the philosophical tradition of Mahayana Buddhism. He is the founder of the Madhyamika school, a rich skeptical tradition, startlingly similar to the Western skeptical tradition, in respect of its aims, methodology, and philosophical problematic (see Garfield 1990). Although Nagarjuna certainly was a historical figure, not much is known about his life. He is widely considered to be the most influential Buddhist philosopher after the Buddha himself. Nagarjuna is clearly a soteriological writer. His aim is to liberate his readers from a psychological clinging to their own thought constructions (and therefore what they take to be a real multiplicity of substantial things in the world) which generates the suffering that Buddhism describes, connected with greed, desire and all forms of attachment. Liberation from suffering takes place through a form of self-cultivation, which enables one to view the world without compulsively needing to take refuge in limiting perspectival stances. It is instructive to consider the context in which Nagarjuna was operating. In the centuries after the death of the Buddha (traditionally placed at 480 B.C., but according to recent research perhaps as late as 400 B.C., which would make him a contemporary of Socrates), Buddhist philosophical schools developed (perhaps as a consequence of contact with post-Alexander the Great Greek colonists in North-West India). Although the Buddha himself had emphasized the non-metaphysical character of his teaching (he repeatedly refused to answer questions on metaphysical topics), gradually a Buddhist scholastic developed which systematized the basic Buddhist teachings: dukkha (all phenomena are unsatisfactory), anitya (impermanence) and anatman (non-self). In their philosophical Abhidharma-writings, various schools constructed an ontology of becoming. They described reality as a flux of dharma’s, insubstantial momentary “constituent factors” of human experience and of the entire mental and material world. These dharma’s are the only type of entity that truly exists, they claimed. Reality is irreducibly plural, and consists of ever-changing configurations and constellations of dharma’s. The world of becoming, as we find it in the Abhidharma writings, seems not all that different from the world as will to power, as some Nietzsche-interpretations claim to find in Nietzsche’s writings. But Nagarjuna rejects this ontology of becoming. In his main work, the Mulamadhyamika-karikas (MMK, Fundamental Verses on the Middle Way) Nagarjuna negates the separate existence of dharma’s. For him all phenomena are “empty”, i.e., without independent self-existence. This is however not an ontological statement, but a soteriological 7 one. It is intended to liberate the reader from the conceptual framework of the Abhidharma. Since the MMK consists almost entirely of a series of seemingly very cryptic refutations, it lends itself to many interpretations. Just as there are many Nietzsche’s, there are many Nagarjuna’s. His method involves the dialectical deconstruction of the central categories by which language seduces us into accepting its “thought constructions” as realities. Nagarjuna uses the Buddhist logical form of the tetralemma: A, not-A, both A and not-A, neither A nor not-A. Through a method of reductio ad absurdum he proves that all four horns of the tetralemma lead to incoherent conclusions. In this way, Nagarjuna not only negates every possible positive assertion, he also negates the negation of that assertion. Nagarjuna examines twenty-seven different thought categories (the 27 chapters of MMK). In every case he examines the dichotomies by which we characterize our world (origination and extinction, permanence and impermanence, identity and difference, enlightenment and unenlightenment) and shows that we cannot logically accept either category. One of the categories that Nagarjuna deconstructs for example, is that of ‘existence”. To say that things exist would be an eternalistic, substantial view. To say that they don’t exist would be a nihilistic view. Ultimately things neither exist, not do not exist. But also that view turns out to be logically incoherent. Nagarjuna concludes that the fundamental categories are characterized by “emptiness” (sunyata). Nagarjuna himself claims to hold no philosophical views whatsoever. Everything he writes serves as upaya, a Buddhist notion that can be translated as “skillful means”. Philosophical perspectives only serve to bring the reader beyond thought constructions to liberation. The concept of sunyata is not an ontological concept. It can’t be hypostasized. Sunyata is a soteriological concept, a liberating concept with therapeutical value. Nagarjuna distinguishes two types of truth: conventional truth, which is based on intersubjective agreement between participants in a language game, and ultimate truth. But “ultimate truth” does not refer to a self-existent dimension of reality beyond the everyday. Rather, it is everyday reality viewed from a radically different perspective. The only difference between an awakened and an ignorant person is this realization of “emptiness”. 5. Nietzsche and Nagarjuna Nietzsche and Nagarjuna both battled the dogmatic philosophies of their time. Nietzsche fought the metaphysical views of Plato and German Idealism on one hand, and the ‘weak skepticism’ of scientific positivism and empiricism on the other. Nagarjuna fought both 8 metaphysical Hinayana Buddhist schools, as well as more skeptical empiricist Buddhist schools. Both show that “true reality” and “true knowledge” are fictions, that there are no facts but only interpretations, and bring thought to an aporia. Two concepts in Nagarjuna’s philosophy can be used to further illuminate certain obscurities in Nietzsche’s notion of a strong skepticism. The nature of the suspension of belief or “positionlessness” is explicitly characterized by the non-concept of sunyata. Such a concept is lacking in Nietzsche’s philosophy, which makes it easier to misinterpret him. Also, Nagarjuna clarifies the relationship between skeptical methodology and the role of convention by using the notion of upaya. There are several passages in Nietzsche’s work that we can interpret as a description of a strategy of upaya. In The Antichrist 54 for example, Nietzsche first stresses the importance of skepticism: “Great spirits are skeptics. Zarathustra is a skeptic […] A mind that aspires to great things, and that wills the means thereto, is necessarily skeptical. Freedom from any sort of conviction belongs to strength, and to an independent point of view.” (AC 54). Then he goes on to describe making use of convictions as upaya: “Conviction as a means: one may achieve a good deal by means of a conviction. A grand passion makes use of and uses up convictions; it does not yield to them--it knows itself to be sovereign.” (AC 54) For both Nietzsche and Nagarjuna, strong skepticism is not a goal in and of itself, but only a means to an end. Nagarjuna is, just like the Buddha, a physician who diagnoses his opponents as being poisoned with philosophical dogmatism. The pill is skeptical inquiry. But when the poison is purged, the inquiry is no longer necessary. In the same way Nietzsche makes use of convictions and perspectives, not as a goal in itself, but in a performative sense. The point of skepticism is not just to fight dogmatical convictions. The goal is to create as much doubt as possible in the values that have up until now been seen as true, in order to make room for new values. Those new values can only be created by the philosopher of the future, of which Zarathustra is a prime example. Strong skepticism is a truth practice that serves as an example of philosophizing with the hammer. Both for Nietzsche and Nagarjuna, the practice of strong skepticism can fruitfully be interpreted as part of their approach to philosophy as a soteriological practice, culminating in the transformation and liberation of the individual. For Nagarjuna, being a Buddhist thinker, such a conclusion would not come as much of a surprise. To interpret Nietzsche as a soteriological thinker will undoubtedly raise more eyebrows. Yet in my doctoral dissertation I have attempted to argue exactly this position (Van der Braak, 2004). 9 What would be the perceived goal of such a soteriological practice? For Nagarjuna, liberation would refer to the ability to live fully and directly in the world without the mediation of representative thinking and conceptualization. Sunyata, like phenomenal existence, is epistemologically and metaphysically groundless. As Martin puts it: “It is not metaphysics, not empiricism, but the inexpressibility and non-duality of things seen in their immediacy at the point of the groundless-ground prior to thought” (Martin 1991). For Nietzsche, a revaluation of values should result in a yes-saying, affirmative relationship to life. Such a transformation is outlined, according to Nietzsche himself, in Thus Spoke Zarathustra. But this would be the topic of an entire different study altogether. Literature references - Braak, André van der, Hoe men wordt, wat men is. Zelfvervolmaking, zelfoverwinning en zelfvergetelheid bij Nietzsche, Damon, Budel, 2004 - Braak, André van der, “Buddhismus”, in: Nietzsche-Wörterbuch Band 1, hrsg. von der Nietzsche Research Group (Nijmegen) unter leitung von Paul van Tongeren, Gerd Schank und Herman Siemens, pp. 419-433, de Gruyter, Berlijn, 2005 - Droit, Roger-Pol, The Cult of Nothingness: the philosophers and the Buddha, University of North Carolina Press, Chapel Hill, NC, 2003. - Garfield, Jay, Epoche and Sunyata: Skepticism East and West, Philosophy East and West, volume 40, no. 3, pp. 285-307, 1990 - Garfield, Jay, Empty Words: Buddhist Philosophy and Cross-Cultural Interpretation, Oxford University Press, 2002 - Jullien, Francois, Detour and Access. Strategies of Meaning in China and Greece, MIT Press, 2004. - Larson, G.J. and Deutsch, E. (eds), Interpreting across Boundaries: New Essays in Comparative Philosophy, Motilal Banarsidass, Delhi, 1989 - Martin, Glen, Deconstruction and Breakthrough in Nietzsche and Nagarjuna, in: Nietzsche and Asian Thought, Graham Parkes (ed.), pp. 91-111, University of Chicago Press, Chicago and London, 1991 - Mistry, Freny, Nietzsche and Buddhism. Prolegomenon to a comparative study, De Gruyter, Berlin/New York, 1981 - Morrison, Robert, Nietzsche and Buddhism: A Study in Nihilism and Ironic Affinities, Oxford University Press, 1998’ 10 - Parkes, Graham, Nietzsche and Asian Thought, University of Chicago Press, Chicago and London, 1991 - Poellner, Peter, Nietzsche and Metaphysics, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1995 - Roberts, Tyler, Contesting spirit: Nietzsche, affirmation, religion, Princeton University Press, Princeton, 1998 - Schacht, Richard (ed.), Nietzsche’s Postmoralism: Essays on Nietzsche’s prelude to philosophy’s future, Cambridge University Press, 2000 - Tongeren, Paul van, Reinterpreting Modern Culture: an introduction to Friedrich Nietzsche’s philosophy, Purdue University Press, West Lafayette IL, 2000 - Tongeren, Paul van, Nietzsche-Wörterbuch Band 1, hrsg. von der Nietzsche Research Group (Nijmegen) unter leitung von Paul van Tongeren, Gerd Schank und Herman Siemens, pp. 419-433, de Gruyter, Berlijn, 2005 - Tuck, A., Comparative Philosophy and the Philosophy of Scholarship. Oxford University Press, New York, 1990 - Urpeth, Jim and Lippitt, John (eds), Nietzsche and the Divine, Clinamen Press, 2000 11