1 Taylor’s Chapter 10 Taylor opens this chapter with claims reminiscent of those he developed in Chapter 9. The phenomenon of language: “that people say things and others understand them”. That words and other signs have meaning is deep, enigmatic, and difficult to understand. The sense of depth comes from the realization that language has to do with what is essential to human life, and from the pervasiveness of meaning in our lives, and the difficulty of getting the phenomenon of meaning into some focus. Meaning is everywhere in the human-made world, even within ourselves as when we speak silently to ourselves. However, there is something in our modern culture that resists this mysterious view of meaning. This resistance comes from our commitment to reason/scientific thought. On this account, language is like other natural phenomena and all we need do is to study it and formulate a theory to explain it (presumably this is what linguistic is all about). As Taylor points out, this was a small part of the agenda of 17th c nominalism; the major part being to find a language appropriate to scientific inquiry. Why should scientific inquiry not find ordinary/vernacular language appropriate to science? The answer is the same we give today, namely it is insufficiently “accurate”; ordinary language misleads (Hobbes’ quote that “words can also be the money of fools”), what we need is a language that directly reflect the empirical world. Language is an instrument (organon) and as an instrument is should be useful and to be useful for scientific inquiry it must reflect (designate) Nature accurately. Now it is Taylor claim that this 17th c nominalism is not merely a view on language it has everything to do with the demise of the universe as a meaningful order (that is an order of “being” which could be explained in terms of the ideas it embodies – in ultimate semiological categories (see Ch. 9). Seventeenth century nominalism went along with the bifurcation of Nature as wholly “disenchanted” and therefore “objective and the selfdefining Self (subject). Our very conception of what language is depends then on our conception of the relation between human nature and nature. On the 17th c view of scientific inquiry, the task is not to identify the “meaning of being” (being has no meaning) but to represent things as they are (as a reality independent of meaning, where meaning belongs to the subject and is therefore “subjective”). Thus, Taylor concludes that the reason we have this nominalist view of language as “representation” is that we are so eager to overcome “projection”/”anthropomorphism”, we are so eager to separate meaning from being in what became the separation of subject and object. The instrument of language is useful because instead of having to deal with the universe as endless particulars, we can in language group/order these particulars into classes assuming of course that classes (words) are clear and distinct (first as “ideas” and later, operationally, as designating particulars). Words signify or designate! Now if we extend this nominalism to include human nature (wherein human beings become the object of scientific inquiry), then speech as a human phenomenon becomes mere sound (to attribute anything else to speech is “projection”). This is then extreme 2 naturalism to understand speech as “sound” as physical in a larger in physical context. Of course, this view of language as “natural” abstracts from anything “inner” whether thought, ideas, feeling, interests, aspiration, etc. and ) hence nominalism leads to naturalism and designativism, and eventually, the elimination of mind altogether. (See Bloomfield or more recently a similar version in Pinker for this entirely modern view). Of course, one can argue that, for example, Chomsky has destroyed this naturalism in linguistics and indeed designativism itself has been radically altered in our century by for example Gottlob Frege’s distinction between meaning and reference (or saying and referring). Frege forced the designativist to recognize that meaning cannot be subsumed under reference alone and in doing so Frege brought the “meaning activity” of the subject back into consideration of the meaning of language. Moreover, once we bring the subject back into meaning we also give up extreme naturalism as a view of reality. What emerges from Frege’s distinction between meaning and reference (the idea that meaning determines reference) is a whole new range of theories of language that would seem to put into question the whole worldview of designativism/nominalism/naturalism. Yet, we must be careful here. For Fregean derived theories of linguistic meaning remain entirely dependent on the notion of representation; that is the function of language remains to frame/encode “information” of (about) a potential or actual independent reality. Thus, the meaning of sentences in “truth conditional semantics” is that meaning can be captured in the concept of “truth” and that truth is a matter of “information” and “information” is only information if it accurately designates the real. Now of course it is well recognized that meaning is more than “information” in the narrow senses, after all we all produce utterances that strictly speaking carry no information but rather give direction, etc. But note that we evaluate the “information content” of all utterances relative to the “informational content” of utterances whose information, or propositional, content is to represent (what is potentially or actually real). On this view the function of language, specifically of words, is to frame representations (informational content) which can then be uttered in numerous ways (using propositional “attitudes” e.g., “think”, “hope”, “believe”, “feel” etc. to “moderate” the informational content). Taylor notes that this instrumental (combinatorial - syntactic) view of language was recognized by von Humboldt early in the 19th c and Chomsky in the middle of the 20th c. and hence the central focus on syntax, as the means whereby we can produce (frame) representation, in a theory of meaning. [Note here that syntax is central because of the instrumental view of language as “framing” representations is simply presupposed in any theory of meaning. But it treats syntax as a formal, mathematical “object” evident to an inquirer quite independently of the language s/he speaks.] Hence, “understanding” language (understanding implies “meaning”) is the understanding of how we represent things in language – and this is faithful to both the 17th c bifurcation of subject-object (Naturalism) and its 20th c epistemologies of science. Thus, there are two features of contemporary theories of meaning, in the Enlightenment tradition: (1) focus on representations (framed in language), and (2) the objectivist (observer stance). These two features are inwardly connected, the objectivist stance allows for the centrality of representation. Meaning is the generation of representations; 3 hence meaning has also been replaced by the notion of “information” (the content of which are representations). Taylor next turns to expressivist theories of meaning: one he traces from Herder and von Humboldt, and also through Hamann, to in our age Heidegger. [Note that designativist theories belong to the Anglo-Saxon world (England and NA) whereas the expressivist theories, roughly, align with continentalist traditions.] Von Humboldt, like Frege, gives priority to speech over language. However, as we will see, the difference between them concerns just what the activity of speech enables. In the remainder of the chapter, Taylor attempts to explore this question of what speech enables, and claims that once we understand better what speech enables (obviously not the framing of representations) we will also see a very different theory of meaning emerge. 1. In speech we formulate things; we bring to explicit awareness what was, before speech, only implicit (“lived”). This is Herder’s thesis. We come in speech to an articulate view of things – someone who expresses is articulate and is able to get the “shape” of things “right” (becomes explicitly conscious in what Taylor calls the “formulation” of things in recognizing them). What does “formulation” enable? a. I can get an articulated view of the matter (focus) b. Once I have this view I can draw its boundaries (contrastively) c. With focus and boundaries, I have an explicit awareness of things 2. Formulation places some matter in the “open” between interlocutors; it puts things in “public” space. This entails the following. a. In speaking we found public spaces, or a common vantage point (not merely communication) b. Language then in founding public space also places what has been articulated in a dialogical context of sociality c. Public spaces make possible forms of institutions indispensable to human life 3. Formulation in addition to articulation and founding of public spaces also the medium in which our most important concerns (truth, knowledge, beauty, faith, love, etc.) belong to us all. This entails the following. a. For example, in distinguishing between anger and indignation we presuppose “standards” or norms (both moral and otherwise) b. This notion of “standards” is closely aligned with then notion of “significance” and this, in turn, reflects directly on significance for the subject/person who in expressing also recognizes these standards c. An expressive theory of language enables the articulation of standards in public space 4 In summary, there are then three things language enables: (1) making articulate, and hence bringing to explicit awareness, (2) putting things in public space, and (3) making significant distinctions among characteristically human concerns. If we examine these three enabling functions of language, Taylor maintains, there will emerge three relevant dimensions of a theory of meaning. Let us examine these three dimensions. 1. The first dimension concerns the role of expression. Language not only articulates but it also expresses. Expression is also pertinent to putting things in public space and formulating significant human concerns. Thus, the activity of speech is not first of all used in describing or representing; rather it is to put something between (public space), to put something “up front”, and “out there”. That is, speech makes manifest (to others and myself – again “public” space). Here what I say, in creating public space, also expresses (makes manifest, display) my “stance”/”attitude” in public space. My speech (tone of voice, choice of words, etc.) is indicative of my disinterest, passion, affection, seriousness, etc. I bear in public space. Taylor is at pain to note that this view is very different if we take speech to be the product of the monological subject whose consciousness of things is then spoken. Such a view, is very different from the first person truthfunctional, designative theory of meaning who speech is intended to convey information s/he has) to another. This is not so much communication which presupposes a common public space as it is information transmission from one to another (and presupposes a public space). Taylor notes, for example, that our suspicion of rhetoric (manifesting/displaying) is a “cardinal sin” in contemporary philosophy, and science, for it seems wholly at odds with our modern aspiration that our language (our speech) accurately depicts or designates beyond time and place. But as Taylor remarks no normal human prose ever approaches this ideal. Of course, science does abstract with austerity from conversational context in which we are concerned with manifesting/displaying, but science can only do so by creating of specialists using a particular technical language dedicated to depiction. Taylor is not one to sidestep this achievement and he readily acknowledges the rationality of designation, of science, and its “languages”, but he also argues that the expressive dimension of language returns again and again even in our most rigorous designation. If we want to eliminate all traces of expression, he notes, we will have to turn to artificial languages. The expressive function of language is also central to the formulation of our most significant concerns because to be sensitive to these concerns is to have articulated the standards that those concerns rely on. Not in the sense that we can describe those standards, rather that we give expression to a sensitivity wherein we articulate those standards. Evidently, such articulation is the expression of personal style of which we neither have 5 explicit awareness nor a vocabulary. If we then consider that such expression opens up a public space our expression is one of our sensitivity to standards that may then be articulated in description. Here, just as in the role expression has in opening public space, expression of our most significant concerns is more fundamental than description of those concerns. By taking proper account of the expressive dimension of meaning, and its role in the function of articulating fundamental concerns and opening a public space, we get a whole other view of language and its boundaries than if we were to focus on the designative dimension alone or as primary. For consider if accept the designative dimension of language as an information-carrying instrument as primary, all other uses of language and all other expressive activities become quite distinct from language in its representational function. [Note only under this condition can linguistics be considered an autonomous discipline and speech becomes unique as an activity of designation.] But if place the expressive function of language as primary then we get a much broader view of language, and on this much broader view of language there may be some hope of understanding its meaning (and the wider sense of meaning as expressive). Language is then no longer seen as merely designative/referential/prose but it becomes part of what Cassirer called “symbolic forms”. 2. The second dimension of meaning that emerges from three enabling functions of language is that all three functions involve different ways of disclosure, of making things plain. Articulating something makes it evident precisely in making it an object of explicit awareness. Articulation in conversation discloses in the sense of putting in it public space, and articulating relevant to our foundational concerns disclose those concerns in the sense that these can be our concerns at all. This disclosure is in a sense to bring to light – or bringing into a clearing - following Heidegger. 3. The third dimension of meaning that emerges from the three enabling functions of language is what Taylor calls the “constitutive” dimension of language. Language does not only serve to describe or represent things, rather there some phenomena central to human life that are partly constituted by language. Consciousness or explicit awareness is constituted in our articulation. The public space is founded and shaped by language, and our typically human concerns exist only through articulation and expression. That means that articulations are crucial to the phenomena of human life. For example, our feelings, those essential to our human concerns, are partly shaped by the way we articulate them. When we offer descriptions of how we feel, our feelings are not unaffected by our articulations, rather our articulations are constitute of our feelings. 6 Of course the articulation of feeling also helps us to understand them and self-understanding itself is constitutive of feeling. Even so feelings cannot be changed at will by the descriptions we offer. Rather feelings are shaped by the descriptions we offer but which seem to us adequate. Similarly, the formulations we offer of our fundamental concerns are also an attempt to get it right – and we realize these formulations may be deep or shallow, deluded or insightful, more or less accurate, etc. Such self-descriptions are constitutive of our feeling (our feelings can be deep or shallow etc.) and concerns. As Taylor notes, it follows that people with very different language skills have very different feelings, aspirations, interests, sensibilities, etc. What is true for feelings and concerns is also true for our relationships with other people. Political and other institutional structures, friendships, relationship of intimacy, etc. are constituted in language. Of these are also relationships that can be analyzed in term of power, property, wealth, ethnicity, subordination, equality, etc, but the point is that these would not be realized without language. Language is essential because these different relationships are in fact different shapes of public spaces established and maintained in language. This is not to say that many relationships are unspoken and part of implicit social practices, but these are necessarily interstitial, always existing within a framework of what is expressed (in many different modes). Without language there would be no implicit common understanding. The “constitutive” characteristic of language is that our language enters into our inner life (of feelings, interests, attitudes, aspirations, etc.), our relationship to others and institutions, and all our social-cultural practices, doing, planning, and actions. Thus, the three enabling functions of language show us that language is the locus of three different dimensions of disclosure or meaning: 1. that language is expressive, and this links it with other modes of expression, 2. that language in articulation makes explicit, and. 3. that language is constitutive, entering into the reality it is about. Now evidently the expressive and constitutive dimensions of meaning, above, are clearly at odds with the truth-functional theory of meaning. Yet Taylor warns us not to be too quick in rejecting a truth-functional theory of meaning. Thus, for example, a truth functional theory might simply claim that it deals with only one dimension of meaning, namely how meaningful utterance are about the world and the situation of human speaker (propositional attitudes such as hope, belief, see, etc.); it can then leave the other dimensions of language to other theories of meaning. Thus, truth functional theorist might simply claim to a division of labor among theories of meaning. 7 Of course, as Taylor notes this kind of division of labor will not work. [The argument here gets complex (pp. 264ff.) but basically follows my lectures on intensionality and how the criteria of extensionality fail (substitution of co-referential expression or identicals and existential generalization) in the context (prefix) of propositional attitudes.] Thus, one can try to apply a truth-functional analysis to sentences in intensional contexts (prefixed by propositional attitudes) – and this might even work for “middle size dry goods” – but truth-functional analysis will not work, that is we cannot set out truth conditions, without some grasp of the “meaning” (expressing, disclosing, and constituting dimensions of meaning) of the language. Or, in other words, the representational function of language is dependent on the expressing, articulating, and constituting dimensions of meaning. Taylor warns us not to excuse the truth-functional account of meaning just because it cannot account for how we identify the truth conditions such that we can evaluate whether the sentence is meaningful. The truth functional theorist will say: “of course, I cannot give a full social-psychological account of how our speech practices correspond to the world; this is to ask too much”. But Taylor’s retorts this reply by the truth functional theorist, while seemingly more modest, is in fact not ambitious enough (at least not if the truth functional theorists wants his analysis to be a viable account of meaning). The kinds of understanding that truth-functional, and hence designativist, theories of meaning lack are the articulating/constitutive uses of language. The reason is straightforward: truth-functional analyses of meaning are objectivist in nature, assuming subject-object bifurcation. Meaning on this account becomes one of formal correspondence between speaking (actually “language”) or the disengaged observer and its truth conditions (the world). But to understand the articulating/constitutive use of language (of speech) is to understand the speaker in context of social practices and concerns. By social practices here Taylor means all those activities, plans, makings, institutions, organizations, etc., that often lack explicit articulation. It is always implicit within our social practices that we have a conception of the subject, freedom, individual violability, etc. If in our society we are not always conscious of this it is only because we also have theoretical formulations of the standards governing these practices. Now in order to understand this social context, we have to (1) understand the context and the difference its makes and, for that, (2) we have to understand what it is like to be a participant in this context, and to arrive at such understanding we have to be engaged in the society/culture. Thus, to understand the meaning of language is to grasp the social practices and the fundamental concerns of that community and to do that is to be engaged in the society/culture in what Gadamer calls a “fusion of horizons”. This is so for the study of history as well (where the culture/society is long gone). Historians not only have to know a long dead language as well as have a firm grasp of his own, but the historian also has to be able to state the differences without distorting one or the other. Evidently, this could be a never ending process of understanding and interpreting – as indeed historiographies cannot differ sharply in their understanding of the past. Clearly all this is incompatible 8 with the detached observer’s standpoint we take in relation to the natural world. For this Enlightenment derived modern designativist position requires neither understanding nor does it present a challenge to our self-understanding. The world only requires explanation and, presumably, the self is never at stake. In contrast, to learn a language one needs to understand the social life and the concerns of those whose language it is. For the historian this requires he read all there is in the language of the past or, if there is no written record to read all there is on the meaning and interpretations of the archeological finding of the past. What happens here, either in studying the past or in learning a new language, is to imagine a new “life form” (Wittgenstein), and life forms cannot be understood from a detached perspective of a monological observer. But to understand ourselves as monological observers exchanging information leaves out everything that is significant to language and speaker of the language - for then there is no public space, no significant concerns, and no disclosure. On such a view, there is clearly is required all other kinds of theories concerning speakers, societies, cultures, traditions, etc. to fill in the blanks. Expressivism puts into question the basic premises of contemporary theories of meaning: namely that meaning can be treated as representation or designation, and that come to understand language, speak, as monological observers. But, as Taylor asks by way of conclusion, does this mean that truth conditional theories of meaning are without value? After all, one of the aims of truth conditional theories of meaning was to explain the boundless creativity of sentence production (of the form ‘s is true iff p’) on the basis of finite means (words). But Taylor replies that the whole notion that vocabulary is finite is itself questionable. For what is most striking about the inventiveness of language is the coinage of new words, new uses of words, metaphorical leaps of all kind as our existing words are full of potential extensions. Now the truth conditional theorist replies that the metaphorical extension of words presupposes some grasp of literal meaning – and what the truth conditional theories is attempt to do is map out the literal meaning since presumably these are basic to all metaphorical extensions, rhetorical shifts, irony, sarcasm, etc., etc. Hence, truth conditional theorists may be said to be committed to the following: (1) that every expression that can be used to characterize things has a literal meaning (or in case of polysemy, meanings) along with derived metaphorical extension; (2) that grasping figurative meanings of these extensions presupposes a literal meaning; (3) by observing the conditions in which speakers speak along with what we might ascertain about their motivational states, beliefs, etc., should permit us to isolate this literal meaning. These commitments also commit truth functionalist theorists to the “primacy of the literal”: (1) all speech acts of whatever kind have at least one literal meaning, (2) this literal meaning is determined by depiction to what these speech acts applies to, (3) literal meaning is primary, and all other meanings are derived from the literal meaning. In fact, as Taylor comment, this is a very parochial and culture and ethno-centered view of meaning/language. It is one that evolved since the Enlightenment such that any other conception of meaning is deemed pre-logical. 9 In fact, Taylor claims that the literal-figurative so dear to designativists has it all wrong. Taylor sees the designative conception of literal meaning as a norm established for a specific purpose within, and indispensable to, a scientific civilization. But instead of viewing as a norm in this way, we have come to understand all meaning, including linguistic meaning, as a matter of representation, and so as an explanation/theory of meaning. But in fact representation is not the only dimension of language; indeed, it is not even the primary one. LPM/Feb. 2009