NATIONAL QUALIFICATIONS CURRICULUM SUPPORT Philosophy Introduction to Epistemology [HIGHER] The Scottish Qualifications Authority regularly reviews the arrangements for National Qualifications. Users of all NQ support materials, whether published by Learning and Teaching Scotland or others, are reminded that it is their responsibility to check that the support materials correspond to the requirements of the current arrangements. Acknowledgement Learning and Teaching Scotland gratefully acknowledges this contribution to the National Qualifications support programme for Philosophy. © Learning and Teaching Scotland 2010 This resource may be reproduced in whole or in part for educational purposes by educational establishments in Scotland provided that no profit accrues at any stage. 2 INTRODUCTION TO EPISTEMOLOGY (H, PHILOSOPHY) © Learning and Teaching Scotland 2010 Contents Teacher’s notes 4 Introduction 5 Section 1: Section 2: Section 3: What is knowledge? Propositional knowledge claims The tripartite theory of knowledge Problems with the tripartite theory of knowledge Summary: What is knowledge? 7 7 10 12 How is knowledge acquired? Rationalism Empiricism Innate ideas Coherentism Summary: How is knowledge acquired? 13 15 16 21 23 Can knowledge claims be justified? Problems with foundationalist responses (rationalism and empiricism) Problems with rationalism Problems with empiricism Problems with coherentism Summary: Can knowledge claims be justified? 25 25 27 29 30 Course summary (self-evaluation) 32 Glossary 34 Bibliography 36 INTRODUCTION TO EPISTEMOLOGY (H, PHILOSOPHY) © Learning and Teaching Scotland 2010 3 TEACHER’S NOTES Teacher’s notes These notes are designed to provide teachers/lecturers with an accurate and detailed course content for the 10-mark mandatory unit Introduction to Epistemology. Given the lack of student textbooks for philosophy, it is hoped that these notes will help teachers/lecturers to provide their students with resources that cover the course requirements. However, they should not be used as the sole resource for students. Students will benefit from a variety of reading resources and so it is advised that the notes are used in conjunction with other resources. In order to prepare students for the required summative assessments, schools and colleges will need to plan their courses carefully, incorporating suitable formative assessment tasks. The activities in these notes are largely discussion based and are designed to encourage students to participate in philosophical enquiry. Teachers/lecturers are encouraged to use these activities as a basis for developing their own t asks. Some of the questions might be useful for thinking- and discussion-based exercises. Others could be adapted into a form that requires the students to present their own written reflections. Schools and colleges also need to add further written tasks a nd activities that deliberately build towards the unit and final assessments. The notes also include a reflective summary of the course that is designed for students to refer to as they work through the unit. The aim is to encourage students to participate in the process of self-evaluation. It should be noted that this summary is the writer’s own attempt to interpret the SQA Arrangement documents so schools and colleges should take care to ensure that they are satisfied with this particular interpretation . Many students benefit from materials that contain interesting images and graphics. Although some are included in this pack, teachers/lecturers are encouraged to take time to add their own graphics to the resource to help make them as appealing as possible for the students. The glossary at the end of the notes is based on the recently published revised Arrangements document. 4 INTRODUCTION TO EPISTEMOLOGY (H, PHILOSOPHY) © Learning and Teaching Scotland 2010 INTRODUCTION Introduction The word epistemology comes from two Greek words: episteme = knowledge logos = theory (or sometimes translated word) Epistemology is most simply defined as the theory of knowledge. This may sound a bit dull but it is actually a fascinating area of philosophy. Epistemology is the branch of philosophy that studies the nature and limits of knowledge. Epistemology is concerned with the structure and origin of knowledge , and whether claims to have found knowledge are true or false. Which, if any, of our beliefs are true and which are false? Activity Think, pair, share On your own, think about things that you would call knowledge. Think also about things that you would call belief. Make a list of things you would be happy to call knowledge. Make a list of things you would be happy to call belief. Discuss your views in pairs. In groups try to persuade each other that what has been identified as knowledge is actually just belief. Is there anything that everyone agrees should still be called knowledge? Now make a list of what your group concludes can be called knowledge. Try to put together a definition of knowledge. ‘We believe that the conditions of any knowledge claim are … ’ INTRODUCTION TO EPISTEMOLOGY (H, PHILOSOPHY) © Learning and Teaching Scotland 2010 5 INTRODUCTION In this introduction to epistemology, you will be thinking about three key questions: 1. 2. 3. What is knowledge? How is knowledge acquired? Can knowledge claims be justified? 6 INTRODUCTION TO EPISTEMOLOGY (H, PHILOSOPHY) © Learning and Teaching Scotland 2010 SECTION 1: WHAT IS KNOWLEDGE? Section 1: What is knowledge? Propositional knowledge claims We use the word ‘knowledge’ regularly in everyday language. Look at the following examples: I know that Ghana is in Africa. I know how to get to Ghana. I know a lot about Ghana. The English word ‘know’ is used here in three different ways. First of all , we have ‘propositional’ knowledge (knowing that something is true). Secondly, we have knowledge of ‘how to’ do something. Finally, we have personal experience of something (knowledge by acquaintance) . The knowledge that the Higher Philosophy course is concerned with is ‘propositional’ or factual knowledge. A ‘proposition’ is a statement that asserts or denies the truth about something. Activity What ‘propositional’ knowledge claims have you learn ed about at school or college over the past week? In which subjects did you learn about these propositional knowledge claims? How can you be sure that these propositional knowledge claims are true? The tripartite theory of knowledge One of the earliest references to a clear definition of knowledge is recorded by Plato (428/427BC–348/347BC) in a dialogue between two characters, Socrates and Meno. The discussion that takes place concerns the difference between a true belief and a knowledge claim. INTRODUCTION TO EPISTEMOLOGY (H, PHILOSOPHY) © Learning and Teaching Scotland 2010 7 SECTION 1: WHAT IS KNOWLEDGE? In Plato’s 2500-year-old dialogue, Socrates says: ‘True beliefs are a fine thing and do all sorts of good so long as they stay in their place; but they will not stay long. They run away from a man’s mind, so they are not worth much …’ Socrates goes on to say that in order to stop your true beliefs from drifting from your mind you must ‘tether them’. Your beliefs need to be ‘tied down’ by something. Activity In pairs, discuss what is required for you to ‘tie down’ your true beliefs . Socrates’ answer to the question above is simple. In order for you to keep your true beliefs from slipping from your grasp you must ‘tether them by working out the reason’. The key difference between a true belief and knowledge is that any knowledge claim needs to be backed up with reasons. Knowledge is more valuable than true beliefs because a knowledge claim includes the essential condition of justification. Plato’s point is simple. To have knowledge is to have true beliefs that are secured by reasons. These simple observations led to what has become known as the tripartite theory of knowledge. The standard definition of knowledge has been summarised into the phrase ‘justified, true belief’. The three conditions below form what is called the ‘tripartite theory of knowledge, or knowledge as justified, true, belief. 1. The statement has to be true or correspond with a reality outside itself. The first mark of knowledge must be that your propositional statement is true. You can never have knowledge if what you think you know is actually false. For example, I cannot ‘know’ that Glasgow is the capital of Scotland, because it isn’t. 2. The statement has to be believed. For someone to ‘know’ that something is true he/she must have confidence in his/her knowledge claim. Knowledge requires a feeling of confidence about being right. If someone hesitates to offer an answer to a question because they lack confidence, even though they have the right answer, it seems reasonable that they don’t really know the answer at all. 8 INTRODUCTION TO EPISTEMOLOGY (H, PHILOSOPHY) © Learning and Teaching Scotland 2010 SECTION 1: WHAT IS KNOWLEDGE? Edinburgh is the capital of Scotland … or is it Falkirk … no it’s Edinburgh … no it’s … 3. The statement has to be backed up or justified with evidence to support it. This means that while I can occasionally stumble across a true statement, lucky guesses do not count as knowledge. Plato and others after him wished to stress that knowledge is not simply a matter of holding a true belief with some degree of confidence. Philosophers think that in order to have knowledge, you must be able to justify what you claim to know. The tripartite theory of knowledge is making a double claim. F irst, it is saying that in order to have knowledge you must be able to satisfy these three conditions. Second, it is making a further claim that these three conditions are all that are needed. In other words, no further conditions must be met. The tripartite theory of knowledge is, therefore, making the claim that the three criteria (justified, true, belief) are individually necessary and jointly sufficient. Individually necessary … To say that the tripartite theory is individually necessary simply means that for us to have knowledge, we must satisfy each condition. Any knowledge claim that cannot do this cannot be a knowledge claim at all. We simply cannot do without any of the three conditions. Jointly sufficient … This simply means that the three conditions are all that is needed. If it is true that the tripartite theory is ‘jointly sufficient’ and we can show that we have satisfied all three conditions then we can guarantee the success of a propositional knowledge claim. In other words, if you have satisfied all three conditions then you can say with certainty that you have knowledge. INTRODUCTION TO EPISTEMOLOGY (H, PHILOSOPHY) © Learning and Teaching Scotland 2010 9 SECTION 1: WHAT IS KNOWLEDGE? Problems with the tripartite theory of knowledge On the face of it the tripartite theory sounds reasonable. However, philosophers have identified some problems wit h it. The Gettier problem (a problem with the theory itself) This is a problem with the definition itself. In the 1960s , a philosopher called Edmund Gettier came up with some questions and examples that undermined the tripartite theory. In 1967 he published a paper simply entitled ‘Is Justified, True Belief knowledge?’ His paper was based around a number of examples in which he attempted to show that it is possible to satisfy all the conditions and yet still be unable to say conclusively that you had know ledge. Gettier was questioning whether the tripartite theory was jointly sufficient. The examples he and others have subsequently used are known as Gettier type counter-examples. Here are some Gettier-type examples: Example 1 Your teacher has an identical twin. The twin enters the room and you form the justified, true belief: ‘My teacher is in the room’. As it happens, she’s sitting at the back of the room where you hadn’t seen her. But, do you have ‘knowledge’? Example 2 What appears to be a window is really a TV screen relaying recorded images of the outside from a week ago. You look, and form the justified belief : ‘It is raining’. As a matter of fact this is also true. But, do you have ‘knowledge’? These examples illustrate what Gettier called the pr oblem of accidental correctness. The connection between my justification and my belief being true is accidental. The worrying thing about the Gettier examples is that every condition of the tripartite theory has been met and yet we still wouldn’t want to count it as knowledge. What Gettier was getting at was the possibility that the tripartite theory itself is wrong. There have been some attempts to respond to Gettier’s criticism by simply attempting to add further clauses to the tripartite theory of know ledge. However, the extent to which additional clauses are truly successful is a further cause of debate amongst philosophers. 10 INTRODUCTION TO EPISTEMOLOGY (H, PHILOSOPHY) © Learning and Teaching Scotland 2010 SECTION 1: WHAT IS KNOWLEDGE? Activity Try to come up with a fourth criterion of knowledge that removes the Gettier problem. Test your new clause with others in the class. Do you agree with Gettier that maybe the tripartite theory is not ‘jointly sufficient’ after all? The challenge of scepticism (the infinite regress argument) This problem relates to one condition of the tripartite theory. Some philosophers have argued that the ‘justification condition’ can never be fully satisfied. If they are right then the whole idea of finding true knowledge isn’t possible. These philosophers are known as sceptics. Scepticism comes in a variety of formats. 1. Local scepticism is scepticism about some particular type of knowledge claim. For example, the atheist is sceptical about claims to have knowledge of God. Others are sceptical about claims to have knowledge of the supernatural, or of right and wrong. 2. Global sceptics have claimed that the only thing that we can know is that knowledge is impossible. This is extreme scepticism. Some extreme sceptics – also called solipsists – go so far as doubting that we can know anything at all outside our own minds. All we ca n have certain knowledge of is the content of our own minds. Philosophers such as René Descartes and David Hume both recognised that what we may take to be justification may in fact not be justification after all. Think of the people who thought that the Earth was stationary. What more justification would you need than the fact that you can see it and feel it to be stationary? The history of humanity is to a great extent a history of humans discovering that we have got things wrong – that what we had thought was knowledge (sometimes with great confidence and apparent justification) was in fact wrong. Clearly our false knowledge claims were caused by mistaken justifications. So, in order to avoid making errors we need to be careful to justify our justifications. This, however, leads us into a problem that is very hard to solve. Whatever evidence I bring forward to support a propositional knowledge claim is in as much need of support as the proposition itself. I need a justification for my justification, and then a further justification and so on and so on … This INTRODUCTION TO EPISTEMOLOGY (H, PHILOSOPHY) © Learning and Teaching Scotland 2010 11 SECTION 1: WHAT IS KNOWLEDGE? endless search for justification is called the infinite regress argument. The point is that the sceptic claims that since an infinite regress never comes to an end, the original propositional knowledge claim can never be justified at all. Activity In pairs, try to come up with a way to overcome the infinite regress argument. If the infinite regress argument cannot be overcome , can we really say that the tripartite theory of knowledge is individually necessary? The infinite regress argument is difficult to overcome. However, the history of philosophy is filled with attempts to do just that. In fact, most philosophers appear happy with the tripartite theory and would not want to say that knowledge claims are impossible. Most think that this argument can be overcome. The next section will look at some famous attempts to acquire propositional knowledge that survives even the infinite regress argument. Summary: What is knowledge? Epistemology is the theory of knowledge. The conditions required to satisfy any knowledge claim are thought to be justified, true belief (the tripartite theory of knowledge) . The tripartite theory makes the claim that the three conditions are individually necessary and jointly sufficient. Some philosophers have suggested that the tripartite theory of knowledge hasn’t adequately defined knowledge. The two main problems you will need to know about are: – the Gettier problem (if it’s possible to satisfy all three conditions and still not have knowledge then the tripartite theory is not jointly sufficient) – the challenge of scepticism (i.e. if the justification condition cannot ever be satisfied then for knowledge claims to be possible the tripartite theory is not individually necessary). 12 INTRODUCTION TO EPISTEMOLOGY (H, PHILOSOPHY) © Learning and Teaching Scotland 2010 SECTION 2: HOW IS KNOWLEDGE ACQUIRED? Section 2: How is knowledge acquired? Rather than adopting a sceptical view or attempting to revise the tripartite theory, most philosophers have preferred to find ways to justify knowledge claims. Philosophy’s search for ‘certain knowledge’ has been dominated by two distinct groups of philosophers. They are called the rationalists and the empiricists. Both are keen to find a foundation of knowledge that we can know with certainty. Rationalists and empiricists are known as foundational theories of knowledge? They will argue that the infinite regress argument can be defeated if we can find a foundation for all our knowledge claims. This foundation will need to be self-evidently true so that it will make no sense for someone to ask you to justify your foundation. Other philosophers have decided that the search for a certain foundation isn’t a realistic goal. They believe that foundational truths can’t ever be found. They prefer, as you might expect, a non-foundationalist approach to knowledge. For example, coherentists argue that you can call something knowledge if the propositions cohere to a unified body of beliefs about the world. They argue that we can call something ‘knowledge’ if it is ‘highly likely’ that the claim is true. Rationalism Truths of reason are the bedrock on which we build the whole of human knowledge 1 The term ‘rationalism’ comes from the Latin word ratio, which means reason. Rationalism has its roots in ancient Greece with the writings of Plato. In the modern era it was largely a continental philosophical movement, Ren é Descartes (1596–1650) and Gottfried Leibniz (1646–1716) being two of the most influential rationalists. 1 Cardinal, Hayward and Jones, p41 INTRODUCTION TO EPISTEMOLOGY (H, PHILOSOPHY) © Learning and Teaching Scotland 2010 13 SECTION 2: HOW IS KNOWLEDGE ACQUIRED? Foundationalism Rationalism is considered a foundationalist approach to knowledge. Rationalists say that human reason is the key foundation of knowledge. According to rationalists, reason is the primary source of justification. Human reason should therefore form the basis of any attempt to satisfy the justification clause of the tripartite theory. A priori truths According to rationalists, truths can be known a priori. A priori truths are known to be true without any reference to experience. We can check the truth of a claim just by thinking about it. So a priori knowledge is knowledge that we gain just by thinking. Often this means that the justification condition is met merely by reflecting mentally on the meanings of words and symbols. For example: All bachelors are unmarried males. A cat is a feline creature. 2 + 2 = 4. A straight line is the shortest distance between two points. If I am asked ‘How do you know?’ my response will be that we just need to think about the statement to grasp its truth. So it is justifiable a priori. These types of truths are said to be necessarily tr ue. This term is used to describe all those statements which, when you think about it, cannot be anything other than true. Necessary, a priori truth 2+2=4 As was said earlier, rationalists believe that the foundation of any knowledge claim lies in the human mind alone. This means that a significant mark of the rationalist approach to knowledge is through the use of a priori truths. These give the rationalists the certain foundation they are looking for. 14 INTRODUCTION TO EPISTEMOLOGY (H, PHILOSOPHY) © Learning and Teaching Scotland 2010 SECTION 2: HOW IS KNOWLEDGE ACQUIRED? Empiricism We are born knowing nothing and that everything we know must come from our senses 2 The term ‘empiricism’ comes from the Latin word experientia, which means experience. Empiricism can be traced back to the early Greek philosopher Aristotle. In the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries , the main empiricists were three British philosophers John Locke (1632–1704), George Berkeley (1685–1753) and David Hume (1711–1776). Foundationalism Empiricism, like rationalism, is also considered to be a foundationalist approach to knowledge. This means that empiricists have come to think of sense experience as the key foundation of knowledge. According to the empiricists, experience, as opposed to reason, is the primary source of justification. At its simplest, empiricism is the view that everything that we can call knowledge is sourced in our sense experience s. Sense experience should therefore form the basis of any attempt to satisfy the justification clause of the tripartite theory. An empiricist may want to point out that much of our knowledge c laims are inferred from other sources, eg books, teachers etc. However, our sense experiences are immediate and so not inferred from anything else. This means, they argue, that sense experience should be the bedrock or foundation on which all other knowledge must be based. A posteriori truths If experience and not reason is the primary source of any knowledge claim then empiricism will focus its attention on a posteriori rather than a priori truths. A posteriori statements are known to be true (or false) as a result of experience. For example, I know, a posteriori, that the cat is black. After my experience of looking at the cat I can say confidently what colour it is. Unlike a priori truths, the a posteriori truth that the cat is black is not necessarily true. A posteriori truths are only contingently true. A contingent truth is a truth ‘that could have been otherwise’, or a truth ‘that might not have been true and only happens to be true’. Contingent, a posteriori truth 2 The cat is black. Cardinal, Hayward and Jones, p51 INTRODUCTION TO EPISTEMOLOGY (H, PHILOSOPHY) © Learning and Teaching Scotland 2010 15 SECTION 2: HOW IS KNOWLEDGE ACQUIRED? Activity Make a list of four or five a posteriori truths. Are they all contingent truths? Make a list of four or five a priori truths. Are they all necessary truths? Why might someone say that a posteriori truths defeat the infinite regress argument? Why might someone say that a priori truths defeat the infinite regress argument? What truths do you think are ‘superior’: necessary truths or contingent truths? What do you think forms the better foundation for any knowledge claim, a priori or a posteriori truths? Innate ideas The debate concerning the existence of innate ideas is sometimes thought of as the key belief that distinguis hes rationalism from empiricism (traditionally, rationalists being the philosophers who supported the belief in innate ideas). Activity Before we look closely at the belief in innate ideas take time to think a little about your ‘mind’. What exactly is your mind? Is your mind a physical or non-physical thing? Is your mind just a complicated computer? Is your mind different from the rest of your body? If you were born without senses would there be some facts that you could still know? 16 INTRODUCTION TO EPISTEMOLOGY (H, PHILOSOPHY) © Learning and Teaching Scotland 2010 SECTION 2: HOW IS KNOWLEDGE ACQUIRED? Rationalists have traditionally argued that any claim to know something ultimately stems from certain innate truths of the human mind that are unaffected by the senses. Innate truths are ideas believed to be natural to the human mind, ideas that humans have within them from birth. In other words we are born knowing certain things. A common mistake people often make is to confuse innate ideas with instincts. The instinct (sometimes called an innate disposition) that a baby has to cry when it’s hungry is not an innate idea. Animals are also born with instincts, eg some birds clearly have an instinct to fly south in the winter. An innate idea is, if true, something unique to humans. Philosophers like Plato, St Augustine and Descartes have all argued that we are born with certain pieces of knowledge inside us. They support this view because we seem to have knowledge of some facts that go be yond experience. For example, they may say that we have an innate idea of morality. This belief in innate ideas is often associated with rationalists because traditionally they have argued that reason can reveal this knowledge that we have been born with. Possible candidates for innate ideas have included: mathematical and geometrical truths, eg Plato’s view that knowledge is remembered religious truths, eg the existence of a perfect being ‘God’ (Descartes) moral truths, eg St Augustine believed that i deas like ‘murder is wrong’ must be innate language, eg the contemporary American linguist Noam Chomsky argued that humans are born with an innate capacity to learn to communicate through the use of words. INTRODUCTION TO EPISTEMOLOGY (H, PHILOSOPHY) © Learning and Teaching Scotland 2010 17 SECTION 2: HOW IS KNOWLEDGE ACQUIRED? Activity Split the class into four groups. Each group should discuss one of the words below and attempt to come up with a definition or explanation of the meaning of the word. The group must then present their explanation to the rest of the class. Justice Beauty Good Perfection Is everyone in the class happy with the definitions and explanations? What needs to be added to make the definitions better? Is it possible to explain fully the meaning of these words? Does the class agree with the view that we all have a similar grasp of the meaning of these words? Why is it that we know what these words mean but can’t agree on how best to define them? Some rationalists may argue that our instinctive grasp of the meaning of concepts like beauty mean that they must somehow be innate in us. Plato believed that concepts like beauty and justice are not things that can ever be perceived by the senses. He pointed out that we encounter beautiful things but we can’t ever see beauty in itself. Yet, we all know what beauty is. Another example of innate ideas often cited concerns mathematics. In a similar way to concepts like beauty and justice Plato argued that we can come across a pair of things but never the number ‘two’ itself. The claim that mathematical truths were somehow innate and could therefore pro vide us with certainty became the ideal model of all knowledge for the French rationalist René Descartes. An argument against innate ideas (John Locke) An empiricist will argue simply that my knowledge of anything comes only after I experience it. For example, I know what chocolate is because I have seen it, smelt it, touched it and, most importantly, tasted it. After my experience of chocolate, my knowledge of chocolate gets into my mind. An empiricist will argue that all knowledge comes after experience. This means that empiricists reject any belief in innate ideas. They argue 18 INTRODUCTION TO EPISTEMOLOGY (H, PHILOSOPHY) © Learning and Teaching Scotland 2010 SECTION 2: HOW IS KNOWLEDGE ACQUIRED? that our minds contain no knowledge at all when we are born and that everything we know comes after experience. John Locke (1632–1704) is often portrayed as the founder of mo dern empiricism. When discussing human knowledge he explained that our senses first produce mental representations of the world which are then interpreted by our brain. He believed strongly that when babies are born there is no knowledge innate in their minds. Our minds at birth should be considered completely empty of any concepts and beliefs. Locke said that we should think of a newborn baby’s mind as being like a blank piece of paper. The mind at birth is a tabula rasa or blank slate. As our lives develop the mind is stimulated by sensations and experiences which, therefore, form the basis of our knowledge claims. Locke argued in his book An Essay Concerning Human Understanding that there are no such things as innate ideas. His arguments against innate ideas include the following: A child knows not that three and four are equal to seven, till he comes to be able to count to seven, and has got the name and idea of equality…But neither does he readily assent because it is an innate truth…the truth appears to him, as soon as he has settled in his mind the clear and distinct ideas that these names stand for. And then he knows the truth of that proposition [3 + 4 = 7] upon the same grounds, and by the same means, that he knew before that a rod and a cherry ar e not the same thing (Book 1, ch. 2, sec. 16) But alas, amongst children, idiots, savages and the grossly illiterate what general maxims are to be found? What universal principles of knowledge? Their notions are few and narrow, borrowed only from those ob jects they have had most to do with, and which have made upon their senses the frequentest and strongest impressions. (Book 1, ch. 2, sec. 27) Instances of enormities practised without remorse. But I cannot see how any men should ever transgress those moral rules, with confidence and serenity, were they innate, and stamped upon their minds. View but an army at the sacking of a town, and see what observation or sense of moral principles, or what touch of conscience for all the outrages they do. (Book 1, ch. 3, sec. 9) If we attentively consider new born children we shall have little reason to think that they bring many ideas into the world with them. For besides some faint ideas of hunger and thirst and warmth, and some pains which they may have felt in the womb, there is not the least appearance of any settled ideas in them. (Book 1, ch. 4, sec. 2) INTRODUCTION TO EPISTEMOLOGY (H, PHILOSOPHY) © Learning and Teaching Scotland 2010 19 SECTION 2: HOW IS KNOWLEDGE ACQUIRED? Activity Organise the class into groups of four. Each member of the group should read carefully one of Locke’s arguments against innate ideas. They should then try to produce a simple diagram that will help them explain the argument to the others in the group. One member of the group will then attempt to explain the argument to the class. An argument for innate ideas (Gottfried Leibniz) Leibniz presented a famous argument for the existence of innate ideas. He was responding to Locke’s argument that children show no knowledge of innate concepts. Leibniz was attempting to make the point that innate ideas require work to uncover them. It should be no surprise then that there is little evidence of universal principles demonstrated by children. Leibniz believed that humans are born with knowledge of mathematical truisms. He argued that at a particular moment in time we can see two sticks and then know that 1 + 1 = 2. However, he argued that without an innate idea of these mathematical concepts we could only know this at that particular moment. He believed that we are aware of the mathematical truism that 1 + 1 = 2 without the need of empirical evidence: ‘The senses, then, only bring to our attention the innate mathematical truism that we are born with ’ 3. Our minds are naturally ready to understand these truths. Leibniz used an analogy of the mind being like a veined block of marble. A piece of marble has veins that indicate shapes that a skilful sculptor can draw out. 4 Without these ‘veins’ it would be impossible to draw out any clear shape. Leibniz explained that a block of marble may be veined in such a way as to have a sculpture of Hercules ready to be shape d from it. Where the block of marble has the potential to be carved into a particular shape, the mind has a ‘special affinity’ for grasping necessary truths. Leibniz was arguing that ideas and truths are therefore innate in us as a natural potentiality. If our minds did not have the potential to understand mathematics, for example, then all the sense experience in the world could 3 4 G. W. Leibniz, Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, 2009. G. W. Leibniz, Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, 2009. 20 INTRODUCTION TO EPISTEMOLOGY (H, PHILOSOPHY) © Learning and Teaching Scotland 2010 SECTION 2: HOW IS KNOWLEDGE ACQUIRED? not bring us to the truth that 1 + 1 always equals 2. Leibniz believed that the senses can explain the source of contingent tru ths. However, they can’t explain the origin of necessary truths. These necessary truths can only be explained if there are ideas that are innate in us from birth. Activity Do you think it is possible for a blind person to ‘know’ what colour is? Is it possible for a deaf person to ‘know’ what music is? Do you think that humans have a ‘natural potentiality’ for colour? Do you think that humans have a ‘natural potentiality’ for music? Activity Draw a diagram that illustrates the different views that e xist about innate ideas. You should focus your attention on Leibniz’s metaphor of the veined block of marble and Locke’s view that at birth the mind is tabula rasa. Try to use pictures and symbols to help you explain your diagram to others in the class. Coherentism The justification of a belief consists of the way it fits or coheres with the rest of the beliefs that one holds 5 Coherentism is in many ways a response to and rejection of the foundationalist approach to epistemology. Coherentism has be en attributed to the writing of Spinoza (1632–1677), Kant (1724–1804) and Hegel (1770– 1831). More recently, coherentism has been developed into a clearly defined view by writers like F.H. Bradley (1846–1924) and the American philosopher Brand Blanshard (1892–1987). 5 Cardinal, Hayward and Jones, p73 INTRODUCTION TO EPISTEMOLOGY (H, PHILOSOPHY) © Learning and Teaching Scotland 2010 21 SECTION 2: HOW IS KNOWLEDGE ACQUIRED? Non-foundationalism Foundationalism is the belief that our knowledge claims depend on some basic support or foundation. Coherentists reject this idea. They would argue that this search for certain foundational truths is impossible. Knowledge in the real world is not actually dependent on some absolute self -evident fact. Rather than try to find a certain foundational truth, coherentists accept that the search for a complete justification is impossible. The search for absolute certainty is an impossible task. However, the coherentist argues that this apparent need for certainty (a full justification) is not actually necessary. The proper response to the infinite regress argument is to look for a set of beliefs that cohere with the rest of your firmly held beliefs. A coherent set of beliefs is a set of ideas that do not contradict or conflict with each other. If our knowledge claim doesn’t fit well with our other knowledge claims then we can say that it is not knowledge at all. If, however, it does fit well then it is reasonable to conclude that it is knowledge. This means that coherentists are not looking for certain knowledge. Rather, they say we should be satisfied with highly probable knowledge claims. Where foundationalists look for a set of certain beliefs that are built upon a certain foundation, coherentists look for a web of interlocking beliefs. Coherentists expect this coherent web will need to be adjusted as new beliefs are added to it. The new beliefs are only added or old ones remov ed if there is strong evidence that the web needs adjusting. A priori beliefs will therefore play an important part in the building of the web. The belief that the Sun is the centre of the solar system didn’t appear to cohere with many other knowledge claims that existed in the fifteenth century. However, as more knowledge was acquired, particularly the mathematical a priori understanding of how the solar system worked, this radical view could be accepted as other beliefs were rejected. A posteriori beliefs also play an important part in the building of the web . Brand Blanshard argues strongly that a coherent set of beliefs should be grounded primarily in empirical data. The c oherentist, according to Blanshard, is trying to form a systematic ordering of our experience. 22 INTRODUCTION TO EPISTEMOLOGY (H, PHILOSOPHY) © Learning and Teaching Scotland 2010 SECTION 2: HOW IS KNOWLEDGE ACQUIRED? Activity Imagine you are a 6-year-old child. What coherent body of knowledge would lead you to say that you know Santa Clause exists? What body of knowledge would lead you to revise your knowledge claim as you experience different things as you grow older? Activity Which beliefs do you hold that you’d say are at the centre of your coherent web of beliefs, ie which beliefs do you hold are most certain and unlikely ever to be removed? Which beliefs do you hold that you’d say are at the edges of your coherent web of beliefs, ie which beliefs do you hold are least certain and therefore most likely at some point to be removed? Summary: How is knowledge acquired? Rationalists attempt to overcome the problem of the justification c lause by suggesting that the foundation of all certain knowledge claims lie s in human reason. – Rationalists often focus their attention on a priori truths, truths that are necessarily true and discovered just by thinking. – Traditionally, rationalists believe in innate ideas (eg Leibniz’s metaphor of the mind being like a veined block of marble) . Empiricists attempt to overcome the problem of the justification clause by suggesting that the foundation of all certain knowledge claims lie s in sense experience. – Empiricists have focused their attention on a posteriori truths, truths that are contingent. – Empiricists reject the idea of innate ideas (eg Locke’s metaphor of the mind being tabula rasa and his arguments against innate ideas). INTRODUCTION TO EPISTEMOLOGY (H, PHILOSOPHY) © Learning and Teaching Scotland 2010 23 SECTION 2: HOW IS KNOWLEDGE ACQUIRED? Coherentists attempt to overcome the problem of the justification clause by presenting a non-foundationalist approach to knowledge claims. – Knowledge only needs to be ‘highly probable’. – A statement can be called knowledge if it can fit within a coherent body of accepted beliefs. – A priori and a posteriori knowledge claims are thought to play an important part in any claim to have a coherent set of beliefs . – All current knowledge claims could potentially be revised if new information comes to light. 24 INTRODUCTION TO EPISTEMOLOGY (H, PHILOSOPHY) © Learning and Teaching Scotland 2010 SECTION 3: CAN KNOWLEDGE CLAIMS BE JUSTIFIED? Section 3: Can knowledge claims be justified? You know that the infinite regress argument suggests that it is impossible to ever justify fully any knowledge claim. If this argument succeeds then the justification clause of the tripartite theory of knowledge can never be satisfied. We then looked at some famous responses to this sceptical argument: rationalism, empiricism and coherentism. But are these approaches successful? Problems with foundationalist responses (rationalism and empiricism) The foundational approaches tried to find self-evident truths that make the demand for further justification unnecessary. If someone asked you ‘How do you know that a bachelor is an unmarried male ?’ or ‘How do you know that 2 + 2 = 4?’ you would probably ignore the question or at best thin k of it as being silly. These a priori truths are necessarily true so the need for further justification isn’t required. In the same way if someone asked you ‘How do you know the cat is black?’ you would probably also want to ignore the question as your senses clearly can confirm the truth of this self -evident proposition. Problems with rationalism Problem 1: How can we know that there are innate ideas? The belief that humans are born with certain innate ideas in their minds has been a traditional mark of rationalism, but how can you really know with certainty that there are innate ideas? Does Leibniz’s argument prove beyond doubt that innate ideas exist? Locke’s presentation of his famous arguments against innate ideas at least suggests that it is difficult to say with certainty that innate ideas exist. You may be willing to say that Leibniz’s argument is persuasive and that you believe in innate ideas, but can you really ever say that you know with certainty that they exist? INTRODUCTION TO EPISTEMOLOGY (H, PHILOSOPHY) © Learning and Teaching Scotland 2010 25 SECTION 3: CAN KNOWLEDGE CLAIMS BE JUSTIFIED? Problem 2: A priori truths tell us nothing important Rationalists have traditionally also focused their attention on a priori rather than a posteriori truths. The certainty provided by a priori truths is clearly very appealing. However, a simple response to this approach is to point out that they may provide certainty but when you take a moment to think about it, they don’t provide you with much else. The a priori truth that a cat is indeed a feline creature is hardly ground-breaking knowledge. ‘Nothing is bigger than itself’ is also clearly true a priori, but it is really a useless and trivial piece of knowledge. Does this or any other a priori statement really help us to find answers to the great philosophical questions that have occupied the minds of humans for thousands of years? Many philosophers would wish to point out that a posteriori truths, although less certain, are clearly much more useful in the real world. Problem 3: A priori truths can only ever give us indirect knowledge about the world Even mathematical a priori concepts aren’t safe from problems. Activity 2+2=5 Take a moment to discuss this with others in your class. Try to work out why it’s perfectly reasonable to say that the simple sum above is true!! If there are no innate ideas of mathematical concepts then maths is simply a human invention, full of symbols that are invented to represent what we see going on in the universe. Mathematics, therefore, can be anything we want it to be. We have agreed at some point in history that the symbol ‘5’ represents I I I I I or * * * * *. If we had decided that the symbol ‘5’ represents I I I I or * * * * then it would actually be true to say that 2 + 2 = 5. So it could be argued that mathematical a priori truths only ever give us indirect or symbolic knowledge of the world. 26 INTRODUCTION TO EPISTEMOLOGY (H, PHILOSOPHY) © Learning and Teaching Scotland 2010 SECTION 3: CAN KNOWLEDGE CLAIMS BE JUSTIFIED? Activity Some philosophers argue that maybe Descartes and Leibniz were right when they proposed that mathematical concepts are innate. Use the web to investigate modern views that argue that our understanding of mathematics is innate. Even if Descartes and Leibniz were wrong about innate ideas it could easily be pointed out that maths still works. Maths has provided an essential foundation of much scientific certainty. The symbols also, very usefully, allow us to work out the power required to keep planes in the sky and buildings from falling down. Is it really fair to say that a priori truths tell us nothing important about the world? Do you agree with the claim that a priori truths are ultimately trivial? Problems with empiricism If empiricists are right then everything in your mind ultimately comes from moments of sense experience. Although this sounds like a sensible, justified belief, philosophers have presented many problems with this idea. Problem 1: The difference between appearance and reality Most of the time, people take a commonsense realist view that things are , in reality, what their appearance suggests them to be. This view assumes that because we have mental pictures of books, chairs, desks, stairs and tables, then there necessarily exists a physical world where these objects exist apart from our own mental pictures of them. The commonsense realist view also assumes that the physical world continues to exist when we stop directly perceiving the world through our senses, for example when we are asleep or unconscious. It also assumes that this world is knowable to us through our five senses – sight, touch, hearing, taste and smell. But the distinction between the way things are in reality and the way things appear to be is one of the first things philosophers will want to insist upon. Consequently, we have to ask: is the commonsense realist view of the world reliable? Can we trust the evidence of our five senses? Is there a difference between appearance and reality? INTRODUCTION TO EPISTEMOLOGY (H, PHILOSOPHY) © Learning and Teaching Scotland 2010 27 SECTION 3: CAN KNOWLEDGE CLAIMS BE JUSTIFIED? The key problem for empiricists to consider, then, is: How can we know for certain that the mental representations produced by our senses and interpreted by our brain, do in fact correspond to reality? Problem 2: Are some ideas innate? There are many beliefs that dominate human thought, beliefs like justice, beauty, goodness etc. If empiricism is right then it is difficult to explain where these concepts come from. Rationalists often argue that without innate ideas there can be no real explanation for where these strongly held beliefs come from. As mentioned earlier, Plato pointed out that we can never perceive ‘beauty’. So, if empiricism is right, we have a problem of trying to explain where this idea came from. The same could be said for our strongly held convictions about morality. If empiricism is right then does this mean that there can be no knowledge of morality? We can’t perceive ‘goodness’ so if empiricism is right then maybe we can’t ever say that we know that an action is good. Many people are uncomfortable with these conclusions. Problem 3: The trap of solipsism If empiricism is right then all my knowledge claims are based on sense experience. However, if we take this to its natural ending then what we’re actually saying is all my knowledge claims are based on my sense experience. Knowledge claims become essentially subjective. I know what my senses tell me and I know how my mind interprets that sense data, but I cannot know what you are experiencing. The idea that all we can really be cert ain of is the content of our own mind is called solipsism. Empiricism is an attempt to overcome sceptical arguments like the infinite regress argument. However, it could be argued that if we adopt empiricism then we are actually going to end up with the frustrating and radically sceptical conclusion that we can’t know anything beyond our own subjective experiences. Activity In groups, list examples of occasions where our senses don’t give us an accurate picture of reality, eg hallucinations etc. Do these examples mean that we can’t ever trust our senses? 28 INTRODUCTION TO EPISTEMOLOGY (H, PHILOSOPHY) © Learning and Teaching Scotland 2010 SECTION 3: CAN KNOWLEDGE CLAIMS BE JUSTIFIED? Activity Humans can see in colour whereas dogs can only see in black and white. Find out about some examples of visual perception limitations that humans may have, ie what can humans not see? Activity 2500 years ago Plato presented a famous allegory called the cave. In it he suggested that there is a difference between appearance and reality. Investigate Plato’s allegory of the cave. Do you agree with him that humans live in a world of ‘shadows ’? Activity Do you agree with the view that sense experience alone cannot lead us out of the trap of solipsism? Can sense experience confirm that innate ideas don’t exist? Do you think that your understanding of beauty is innate? Problems with coherentism One of the advantages of a non-foundational approach to knowledge is that the difficult search for ‘certainty’ is replaced with a search for ‘highly probable’ knowledge. This makes knowledge a more realistic goal and something that is a bit more workable in the real world. Problem 1: Some beliefs do appear ‘foundational’ Coherentism suggests that knowledge claims need only be ‘highly probable’. This means that we should, in theory, be open to the idea of revising any of our knowledge claims if new evidence arises. However, many people suggest that the rationalist claim that the certainty of a priori truths like mathematics is beyond doubt. If this is the case then the need to potentially revise all INTRODUCTION TO EPISTEMOLOGY (H, PHILOSOPHY) © Learning and Teaching Scotland 2010 29 SECTION 3: CAN KNOWLEDGE CLAIMS BE JUSTIFIED? beliefs seems unnecessary. Whether or not mathematical concepts are only ‘symbols’ of reality, they are nevertheless certain and necessarily true. The empiricists may also want to argue that some a posteriori truths are also beyond dispute. For example, I can know with certainty that my hand hurts when I put it into a fire. It could easily be argued that I simply don’t need any other beliefs to confirm these foundational knowledge claims. Problem 2: How can I know that my current set of coherent knowledge claims are actually true? If knowledge can only ever be ‘highly probable’ then is it really knowledge at all? A few hundred years ago people had a coherent knowledge claim that the Earth was the centre of the solar system. The knowledge claim was revised and today your science teacher will tell you that we know that the Sun is the centre of the solar system. But, if we need to be open to the claim that knowledge may need to be revised at some point then can we ever really say that we know that the Sun is the centre of the solar system? After all, you only really know this because people have told you it at various points in your life. Task Do you agree with the view that ‘highly probable’ beliefs can be called knowledge? Do you think the advantages of coherentism outweigh the problems? So, who is right? The sceptics, who argue that ‘knowledge’ of anything is impossible? The rationalists, who base their knowledge claims on innate ideas and a priori truths? The empiricists, who base their knowledge claims on self-evident a posteriori truths? The coherentists, who base their knowledge claims on sets of highly probable coherent beliefs? Or, maybe a mixture of some or all of these approaches is the best way ahead? Summary: Can knowledge claims be justified? Some philosophers suggest that there are some problems with the rationalist’s approach to finding a foundation of knowledge . – Can we know that there are such things as innate ideas? 30 INTRODUCTION TO EPISTEMOLOGY (H, PHILOSOPHY) © Learning and Teaching Scotland 2010 SECTION 3: CAN KNOWLEDGE CLAIMS BE JUSTIFIED? – A priori truths may well be certain, but do they tell us anything important? – A priori truths can only give us indirect knowledge. Some philosophers suggest that there are some problems with the empiricist’s approach to finding a foundation of knowledge . – Is there a difference between how things appear in our senses and how they are in reality? – Is there some evidence for the existence of innate ideas? – If empiricism is the foundation of knowledge then do we fall into the trap of solipsism? Some philosophers suggest that there are some problems with the coherentist’s approach to knowledge. – It is hard to deny the foundational quality of some beliefs, eg a priori truths. – If I cannot know with certainty that my current set of coherent beliefs are true then can I really say that I have knowledge? INTRODUCTION TO EPISTEMOLOGY (H, PHILOSOPHY) © Learning and Teaching Scotland 2010 31 COURSE SUMMARY (SELF EVALUATION) Course summary (self-evaluation) Unit title: Introduction to Epistemology Student self-assessment summary Number of marks available in exam: 1. Topic: What is knowledge? 10 marks a. Propositional knowledge claims b. The tripartite theory of knowledge: Justified, true, belief. The criteria are taken to be individually necessary and jointly sufficient. c. Problems with the tripartite theory: The Gettier problem (a problem with the theory itself) . Scepticism (a problem with any attempt to satisfy the justification clause). Dates Self-assess,emt I initially found this topic: very hard, hard, OK, easy, very easy Areas I found most difficult were: 2. 32 ‘I can confidently answer exam questions on this topic .’ Date: Topic: How is knowledge acquired? Dates a. Rationalism: some useful knowledge can be acquired through reason alone. b. Empiricism: all useful knowledge is gained through the senses. INTRODUCTION TO EPISTEMOLOGY (H, PHILOSOPHY) © Learning and Teaching Scotland 2010 COURSE SUMMARY (SELF EVALUATION) c. Innate ideas: arguments for and against: Leibniz’s claim that ideas are innate as potentialities and his metaphor of the veiled block of marble. Locke’s metaphor of the mind as a blank sheet of paper and his arguments against innate ideas. Self-assessment I initially found this topic: very hard, hard, OK, easy, very easy Areas I found most difficult were: 3. ‘I can confidently answer exam questions on this topic.’ Date: Topic: Can knowledge claims be justified? Dates a. The infinite regress argument: Foundationalist responses (a priori and a posteriori truths). Non-foundationalist response (coherentism). b. Empiricism (foundationalist sources of justification): Marks of empiricism. Problems with empiricism. c. Rationalism (foundationalist sources of justification): Marks of rationalism. Problems with rationalism. Self-assessment I initially found this topic: very hard, hard, OK, easy, very easy Areas I found most difficult were: ‘I can confidently answer exam questions on this topic .’ Date: INTRODUCTION TO EPISTEMOLOGY (H, PHILOSOPHY) © Learning and Teaching Scotland 2010 33 GLOSSARY Glossary Key term Definition (Try to add at least one other piece of information about the term in the space below each. This may be a further comment that defines the term in more detail, or it may be an example that helps explain it, or ideally both.) A posteriori A knowledge claim that is knowable or justified from experience. A priori A knowledge claim that is knowable or justified independently of experience. Coherentist theory of justification The view that justification depends on how a particular set of beliefs relate to one another rather than on whether a chain of reasoning rests on foundational beliefs. Contingent A reference to something that could have been otherwise. Empirical knowledge Knowledge that is gained through sense experience. Empiricism An approach to philosophy which claims that knowledge is based on sense experience, that knowledge is not innate and that knowledge cannot be discovered by reason alone. Epistemology The study of knowledge, its nature and how it is acquired. Foundationalism A position in epistemology which claims that there are some selfjustifying beliefs that ultimately provide the justification for all other true beliefs. 34 INTRODUCTION TO EPISTEMOLOGY (H, PHILOSOPHY) © Learning and Teaching Scotland 2010 Tick box ( When fully confident that you know, understand and can use this term) GLOSSARY Gettier problem A problem in epistemology first clearly set out by Edmund Gettier. The Gettier problem challenges the claim that the criteria in the tripartite theory of knowledge are jointly sufficient. Innate idea An idea that is inborn and not the product of experience. Necessary A reference to something that could not have been otherwise. Rationalism An approach to philosophy which claims that some knowledge of the external world can be established by correct reasoning and without the use of sense experience. Scepticism The view that knowledge is impossible to attain because it is not possible for any knowledge claim to be properly justified. Tabula rasa/blank slate A reference to Locke’s claim that there are no innate ideas and his metaphor of the mind as a blank sheet of paper. The infinite regress of justification The problem that knowledge claims can never be justified as any attempt at supplying a justification merely makes another claim that in turn also needs to be justified. Tripartite theory of knowledge The theory that knowledge consists of justified, true beliefs and that these criteria are individually necessary and jointly sufficient for knowledge. Veined block of marble Leibniz’s argument that ideas are innate as potentialities. INTRODUCTION TO EPISTEMOLOGY (H, PHILOSOPHY) © Learning and Teaching Scotland 2010 35 BIBLIOGRAPHY Bibliography Cardinal, D, Hayward, J. and Jones G, Epistemology, the theory of knowledge: Philosophy in focus, Hodder Murray, 2004. Lacewing, M. and Pascal, J, Revise Philosophy for AS Level, Routledge, 2007. Popkin, R and Stroll, A, Philosophy, 3rd edition, Made Simple Books, 1993. Warburton, N, Philosophy: the basics, 4th edition, Routledge, 2004. Warburton, N, Philosophy: the classics, Routledge, 1998. 36 INTRODUCTION TO EPISTEMOLOGY (H, PHILOSOPHY) © Learning and Teaching Scotland 2010