John Heisel October 9, 2001 The Myth of Personal Identity Good afternoon ladies and gentleman of the Philosophy Club. I am very excited to speak with you today about personal identity. The issue of personal identity has been much discussed, and I am here today to summarize it for you and present you with the theory I believe to be the most acceptable. By the end of my presentation, I would hope that you would agree with me that personal identity is completely and utterly nonexistent. If not, though, I will be presenting some other theories of personal identity that you may find more plausible. Personal identity is an attempt to answer the question of what are persons. We seem to have a good idea of what makes a person by using our senses, but are these senses reliable? Is there anything that identifies us as persons, and more importantly, is there anything that identifies us as unique and distinct persons? Since we think we are able to reidentify persons over time with a high degree of success, the answer would initially seem to be yes. So the question now is what gives people identity, so that they are recognizable as time passes. The first theory I would like to discuss with you is what we call the “thick” psychological theory. This theory posits that a person’s identity is contained in her psychological capacities. The continuance of these capacities over time – character traits, skills, preferences, etc. – is what makes a person the same person. That is to say that person X at time T1 is the same person as person Y at time T2 if and only if person Y at T2 has all of the same psychological capacities as X at T1 and the capacities of Y must be causally connected to those that X had. Causal connection is a very important aspect of the “thick” psychological theory. The addition of causal connection overcomes a fairly obvious fault in this theory. The problem is that a highly skilled doctor could remove and duplicate person X’ brain, return it to X, but put the duplicate into person Y’s head. Persons X and Y would now share all of the same psychological capacities, however person Y’s capacities would not have been properly caused. This lack of causal connection in person Y’s psychological capacities allows the “thick” theory to survive even in this bizarre case. However, this theory does not have a built-in mechanism to fight every potential counterargument. Let’s examine some of the “thick” theories other problems. First, we are aware that memory is fallible. We forget things over time, and our psychological capacities change. Our preferences are a prime example of this change: When I was in high school I subsisted on a diet of frozen pizza and Mountain Dew. Although I still enjoy frozen pizza, I absolutely cannot stand Mountain Dew. According to the “thick” psychological theory, does this mean that I am no longer the same person as I was in high school? What if I lose memories or psychological capacities through an accident? There are well-documented cases of accident victims [especially those involving head trauma] who lose some or all of their memory after their accident. If person X at time T1 with capacities C1 is involved in a car accident and loses his psychological capacities, is person X at time T2 with capacities C2 the same as person X at T1 with C1? It seems absurd to say that these two people are not the same, but according to the “thick” theory, it would seem that they are no longer the same person. These counterarguments are only the tip of the iceberg. Perhaps the biggest problem facing the “thick” psychological theory is fission. The idea of fission is rather simple: an object divides into multiple parts. In this case, we’re going to going to split the psychological capacities of person X and implant them in persons Y and Z, destroying person X’ body. The “thick” psychological theory would suggest that persons Y and Z are both person X. However, we know that two things cannot be identical. Leibnitz’ Law states that two things are identical at a time if and only if they share all the same properties. Persons Y and Z absolutely cannot be the same person, because they are not identical: to start with, they have different bodies. Conversely, if we say that neither persons Y or Z are person X, then we contradict the “thick” theory again: persons Y and Z share all the psychological capacities of person X, so one of them must be person X, but we are committed to saying that neither is person X. Perhaps the strongest argument for psychological continuity is put forth in Bernard Williams’ essay, The Self and the Future. Although ultimately it seems that Williams comes out in favor of a body-based theory of personal identity and continuity, he does present an interesting example regarding psychological continuity. Williams presupposes that a machine could exist that would take a person’s mind and psychological traits and move them to a new body. If person X and person Y consented to this operation, X’ mind would end up in Y’s body and vice versa. Williams further writes that if you approached persons X and Y before the operation and told them that after the operation one of them would be tortured whereas the other would be given $100,000, persons X and Y would choose selfishly to inflict the torture on their former bodies, and reward their new bodies with the money. This would seem to show that people believe that their identity is carried in their minds and psychological traits rather than in their bodies. Another theory of personal identity is the brain theory. As its name suggests, the brain theory posits that personal identity resides in the brain, and that as long as a brain is continuous over time, personal identity is retained, regardless of which, if any, body the brain resides in. We could then say that person X at time T1 is the same person as person Y at time T2 if and only if person Y at T2 has the same brain as person X had at T1. This theory treads much of the same ground as the psychological theory. It does seem to answer some of the questions we have posed to the psychological theory. For example, if our abovementioned accident victim is looked at with the brain theory, we see that he is the same person as he was before, because he still has the same brain. This is true even if he has lost many of his memories and cannot remember his previous experiences. If his body were to become so badly damaged that it could no longer function, doctors could transplant his brain to a healthy body and the person would remain intact. Just as with the psychological theory, where the brain theory really falls apart is with fission cases. If we take a person X’ brain and divide it into two equal parts, destroy X’ body, and put one half of the brain in body Y and the other half in body Z, which of the bodies is person X? The answer is that both bodies are person X: they both have the same brain – that, for argument’s sake, contains the same psychological traits and characteristics, memories, etc. in each half – so they are both person X. However, we already know that two things cannot be identical if they are different in any way. Therefore, neither body Y nor body Z can be person X. Yet if we look at this from another perspective, it seems absurd to say that neither body Y nor Z can be person X. Why is this absurd, you ask? Look at it this way: we know that a person can survive without the full use of his brain. It is well documented. Not being a biologist, I don’t know the minimal amount of brain that must remain for a person to survive, but it does not seem absurd to say that one could survive with only fifty percent of their brain. So how can it be the case that if I were to lose half of my brain I could survive, and yet if my brain were divided into two parts with both parts placed in new bodies I would not survive? In the words of Derek Parfit, “how can a double success be a failure?” Derek Parfit is an anti-realist. So far we have only discusses realist views of personal identity. Realist views insist that personal identity is an objective feature of reality. Anti-realism denies this viewpoint. The main idea of Parfit’s anti-realism is that there is no identity as mentioned in previous theories, there is only survival. Parfit’s vision of survival is that of a relationship of degrees between two person states. Antirealism also provides a handy solution for fission cases. The relationship of degrees works something like this: rather than focusing on the psychological continuity of two person states, we must look at the psychological connectedness of two person states. Because of this idea of connectedness, there is no transitivity between two person states. There is only a degree of a relationship. This relationship allows for persons Y and Z to have a certain degree of relationship with person X, but neither person Y nor Z is identical to person X. This relationship of degrees also helps solve the problem of fission cases. If person X splits into persons Y and Z, persons Y and Z will only share a certain degree of similarity with person X. If we want to identify whether person Y or Z is the same as person X, we can attempt to determine the degree of similarity between X and Y or Z. Whichever of the two has a higher degree of similarity could be identified as X. I realize this may all sound a little crazy at first, but allow me to explain the theory as I understand it and hopefully you’ll all come around to my point of view. First of all, if we deny that personal identity is an objective feature of reality, I think that we’ll realize that we already live our lives in this way. We tend to assume that personal identity is contained in body identity. If we look around at our neighbors, we are reasonably convinced that they are the same people we’ve spoken with every day of our university careers. But I would be willing to bet that every one in this audience has had at least one experience where they attempted to greet someone that fit a certain body identity but did not share the personal identity that you wished. Or, have you ever called someone who had roommates and accidentally spoken to the roommate and not the intended party as if she was the intended party? The point I am trying to put forward here is that we already cannot reliably identify people over time. External appearances can trick us, and we currently have no way of knowing whether a person has the same soul, brain, or psychological content as they did previously. Furthermore, I suggest that we are not the same person on a day-to-day basis. Every day, we are experiencing new things, changing ideas, values, and opinions. Every day, we become less of the person we were the day before. I believe that body X today and body X in ten years will be completely different people, even if no sort of fission as I have previously discussed occurs. This is solely because every day we lose a little bit of who we were yesterday and gain a little bit to make up for it. We’re always connected at each stage in our life, but to say that the person speaking to you today from this body is the same person in the same body that will be flying to London next week is utterly absurd. If one likes, one could reduce the interval of degrees/stages to anything: hours, minutes, seconds. There are no two times that we are the same person: if we refer back to Leibnitz’ Law, we can see this. For person X at time T1 to be the same as person X at time T2, time T2 would have to be the same as time T1, otherwise a relationship of identity could not exist. I believe that we are already living our lives without the specter of personal identity, but that most people either are unaware of this fact, or do not want to admit to it. There are myriad reasons why people would not want to admit to an anti-realist slant on life. One might think denying personal identity would destroy relationships, make emotion irrelevant, and make it awfully difficult to deal with concepts like responsibility, punishment and reward. I would like to argue that adopting an anti-realist stance and denying the existence of personal identity will have absolutely no effect on these concepts, precisely because it is already the case that personal identity is nonexistent, and we’re able to get along just fine. I believe that relationships are interchangeable and temporary. Another bet I would be willing to make is that you have very few, if any, close friends remaining from your kindergarten class. Little Johnny that you used to play with every day in kindergarten has grown into a Big Johnny, whose whereabouts and whatabouts you cannot ascertain. What I mean to point out here is that when Johnny and you attended different schools for the first grade, you made a number of other friends to fill the void Johnny’s departure left in you. What I believe this means is that when you enter into a relationship with someone, you are really entering into a relationship with certain qualities the person has. In looking to make friends, you are looking for a body that possesses certain characteristics that you find attractive and valuable. I don’t think that it really matters in whom you find these characteristics, only that you find them. If the body that possesses these characteristics should go through a change and lose some of the characteristics that drew you to it as a friend, I think that most people would probably gradually stop associating with this body, and would find a new body to take its place. I believe the same is true of romantic relationships: how many of us can say that we are still in love with the first body we ever fell in love with? Those of you that raised your hands – consider yourselves lucky, and hope that it lasts. I would now like to discuss the notion of anti-realism destroying the concept of emotion. This too is utterly absurd. Emotions would still exist in the exact same form they are now. I believe that when we attach an emotion to something – be it person or object – we are really attaching that emotion to a set of qualities and object carries. So to say the Hermann loves Pauline is to say that body H finds a set of qualities on body P to be especially attractive to its sensibilities. Should body P’s qualities change, body H would probably find itself less and less attracted to body P and would find a body R with the qualities it desired to replace body P. So, far from destroying emotion, anti-realism only serves to illustrate how emotion actually works. Another problem that has been raised about anti-realism is the question of responsibility, punishment, rewards, etc. Many realists believe that an anti-realist approach will make it utterly impossible to deal with these values. Obviously, I disagree. The idea of punishment is threefold: to punish a body for an act it committed, to rehabilitate the set of ideas that set the action into being, and to deter further actions based on these ideas. Can anti-realism still achieve this threefold punishment? Yes and no. I will attempt to address all three forms of punishment together, because I believe they are all heavily interconnected. If a body were to fission immediately after a criminal act, can anti-realism still make a decision over which body is to be punished? I believe the answer is yes. For a body to commit a negative action, the body must not only have the idea that the action is acceptable, but must carry a strong enough conviction in that regard so as to carry out the action. It would seem that a psychological study of negative behavior could likely figure out how strongly one would have to hold negative ideas in order to act on them. Arbitrarily, let’s say that the threshold where a negative idea manifests itself into a negative action is a seventy-five percent belief that the idea is acceptable. So, if the body fissions, we could examine the subsequent bodies to see which if any have a percentage of the belief similar to that of the body that committed the criminal act. By this I mean that if body A commits a negative act and his belief that the action was acceptable was eighty percent, we would examine his fissioned bodies B and C to see if they had the requisite seventy-five or more percent of body A’s eighty percent belief. Should the bodies fission further, I believe we can still examine them to see if they hold this relation. If none of the bodies hold this relationship, I would say that it is already unnecessary to punish the body, as it has already punished itself. I believe that if fission were to occur, a significant number of cases would carry enough of the negative ideas and beliefs in the necessary percentages to still achieve punishment, rehabilitation, and deterrence. Finally, how can we discuss survival over time in an anti-realist perspective? My idea is that in an anti-realist environment, most people have the opportunity to live long beyond their physical death, and some people will have the opportunity to become immortal. In the absence of a “real” basis for personal identity, I would like to suggest that the only identity we can possibly have is that of thoughts and ideas. By this I mean not only the ideas that we communicate with others, but also the simple ideas of our own existence. To quote a singer whose name I will not mention for reasons the quote makes obvious, “Here today, gone tomorrow. Don’t need my self remembered, but what I help create and leave behind is important to me.” I think this pretty much sums up how we should think of ideas as containing personal identity. If my body were to die immediately after giving this presentation, I would still live on in some form through all of you who remember any of my words. If you even remember that I existed, then I will still live on. I believe that fission – far from being a case we generally examine as a hypothetical situation – is not only real, but is going on every day. Every interaction, every spread of ideas helps to fission personal identity. If we look at it this way, I lose absolutely nothing when I fission. With every word I speak, I retain all parts of myself and yet simultaneously give parts of myself away. The only problem I see with this view of ideafission as personal identity is that of abortion cases. I am pro-choice and do not think that an unborn baby is a person. However, if one were to accept what I am saying then it would seem that an unborn child is a person, simply because its mother is aware of its existence. This poses a problem for my personal beliefs, but conversely, we must base our beliefs around what is true and not around what we simply like. As I end my presentation today, I would like to say that I hope you have found something interesting to take with you from my presentation. Not just for your benefit, but for my own immortality. I hope that I’ve made some inroads to convincing you that anti-realism is not only the most logical way of looking at personal identity, but that anti- realism is how our world already functions. While I hope I have explained things clearly and succinctly, I am sure that I have created many questions and left many unanswered. As philosophy is always a work I progress, I am always willing to hear critiques of my beliefs and would be more than happy to address any questions or concerns you may have. Thank you.