NORMATIVE FORCE AND THE POSSIBILITY OF ERROR: A REPLY TO DOUGLAS LAVIN 0. Introduction Any account of the normative force of practical reason must account for the received distinction between rational and mechanical force. It is a philosophical platitude that there is a difference between an agent’s responsiveness to reason and the workings of a machine, and it is only when we are subject to rational rather than mechanical force that we can be held responsible. This distinction is often understood in terms of a requirement that normative, but not mechanical, force leave open a possibility of error. That is, it is often thought that the difference between mechanical and normative (or rational) force is that it is possible to violate the latter kind of rules, but not the former. In his 2004 piece “Practical Reason and the Possibility of Error,”1 Douglas Lavin takes up the thought that a complete account of normative force must leave open the possibility of error. He calls this requirement the “error constraint.” In particular, Lavin argues that any account of the normative force of practical reason must leave open the possibility of a failure to comply, lest we collapse the distinction between rational and mechanical force. He then concludes that it follows from this that there can be no such thing as an essentially rational will – that is, the requirement that normative force leave open the possibility of error precludes the possibility of a being who can’t but will in accordance with the norms of practical reason, but who is subject to them nonetheless. I propose to take up Lavin’s argument more carefully. In particular, I propose to examine in some more detail precisely what possibility of error is required by an account of the normative force of practical reason, how this requirement might relate to the distinction between rational and mechanical force, and whether or not it does in fact lead to the impossibility of a perfectly rational will, as Lavin would have it. I conclude that the distinction between rational and mechanical force does indeed require that we admit a certain kind of error, and that this does indeed rule out the possibility of a certain kind of perfection, though these conclusions are much narrower than the ones that Lavin advances. Let us now consider Lavin’s argument in more detail. I. The Possibility of Error At the heart of Lavin’s argument lies the thought that the distinction between rational and mechanical force requires that we allow for the possibility that we violate rational, but not mechanical, rules. For Lavin, unless we leave open the possibility that we violate rational (or practical) principles, we cannot maintain the distinction between normative and mechanical force. In particular, he takes it to be an adequacy condition on a theory of practical reason that it leave open the possibility of a distinctively practical failure to comply with its dictates; it is always possible, he argues, that we are “imperfectly hooked up”2 with a practical principle in a way that cannot be explained in terms of the theoretical errors of having the wrong principle in mind, or of misunderstanding or miscalculating how the world is. To be sure, these errors are also always possible, and they may also result in actions that violate the dictates of practical reason. Moreover, they may indeed be errors proper in the sense that we may well be mistaken for, say, taking 1 2 Ethics, 114:3, 424. Hereinafter “Lavin.” Lavin, p.427. this to be the relevant principle, or, say, taking that to be the way the world is; we are indeed responsible not only for the successful execution of the actions required by practical reason, but also for correctly divining its requirements. However, over and above the possibility of practical defects resulting from these kinds of errors, Lavin takes there to be a further, distinctively practical kind of failure that lies specifically in the misuse of our practical faculties, and that can occur even when, theoretically speaking, we have reasoned correctly.3 It is the possibility of this kind of error that Lavin takes to be a condition on a complete account of practical reason. More specifically, for Lavin, we must keep this possibility open on pain of collapsing the distinction between rational and mechanical force. It is only because it is always possible for us to practically fail, in addition to the possibility of reasoning badly, that we can distinguish between agency and action, on the one hand, and, say, the movements of the planets, the replication of a cell, the building of a beehive, and so on, on the other. Absent the possibility of the relevant type of failure, there could be nothing further to which we could appeal to distinguish between agential and mechanical activity, and in virtue of which we can hold the agents, but not machines (or other objects in the natural world) responsible for their actions. Hence the conclusion that the error constraint, so construed, stands as a condition of adequacy on a complete theory of the force of practical reason. Finally, Lavin argues, it follows from this requirement that there can be no such thing a perfectly rational will. In particular, he argues, the requirement that a theory of the force of practical reason leave open the possibility of practical error forecloses the possibility of an agent who can’t but will in accordance with the practical law, but who we take to be subject to its authority nonetheless.4 So conceived, then, his account may well rule out the possibility of a holy or divine will. If Lavin is correct to insist that there is such a thing as a distinctively practical error of the kind described above, then he is right to conclude that where there is a being for whom such an error is impossible, we cannot say of such a being that she is subject to the authority of practical reason, or that she can be held responsible in the relevant sense. This much follows immediately from what has come before. But is he right to assume that such a creature is impossible? Is it true that holding such a being accountable to the norms of practical reason would be like holding a machine responsible? Can we really not say of such a being that she is subject to the practical law, on pain of collapsing the distinction between normative and mechanical force? Let us examine Lavin’s argument in more detail. II. A Perfectly Rational Will Lavin puts the intuition behind the impossibility of a perfectly rational creature as follows. 3 Although he does not specify this, I take it that Lavin also intends to exclude vicious acts as possible sources of error for the purposes of his error constraint. 4 Lavin actually extends his conclusion to exclude the possibility of a being with no capacity for pleasure or desire, and one who, though she is not essentially perfect, happens to get things right every time. I am suspicious of these extensions as well as his narrower conclusion, discussed above. In the interest of brevity, however, I will set aside my objections to these further conclusions. No mere mechanism can be under a principle or follow a rule; such a thing might only be the locus of mere regularity. But a would-be perfectly rational will – something whose will is in a state of perfection and thus which can’t really go wrong – must amount to no more than a strange sort of mechanism or automaton.5 He then continues, “the claim is that principles can be no more than ‘merely descriptive’ of a perfectly rational will, just as physical laws are no more than ‘merely descriptive’ of the trajectories of asteroids and planets.”6 The thought here seems to be that where a being cannot but will in accordance with the practical law in a way that makes a distinctively practical error impossible, this being no longer stands in relation to these principles as an agent does to reasons; instead, in such a case, principles are reduced to mere descriptions of her activities, as physical laws might describe the motions of the planets or the workings of a machine, and, whatever we might say about the force of practical reason, we can agree that it can be distinguished from merely mechanical force. My central worry with Lavin’s objection to the possibility of a perfectly rational agent is this. It is not clear that where an agent cannot but will in accordance with the practical law, we cannot properly say that she is not responsible or subject to it at all, and that she is like a mere machine. Consider, for example, the rules of theoretical reason. It might turn out that it is psychologically impossible for us to, say, believe p and not p (in the same thought), or, say, it might be impossible for us to fail to take modus ponens to be a valid rule of inference, and so on. If this were so, then we couldn't but follow these rules of rationality. Nonetheless, it seems to me that we would still say that we are judging well, or that we are rational when we deny contradictions or infer correctly. The mere fact that we cannot but judge in accordance with these rules does not seem to render them inapplicable in this context, nor does it exempt us from responsibility when we do. Nor, further, is it sufficient to conclude that we are acting as mere machines. To put the point slightly differently, we are happy to continue to say that we are properly subject to the norms of rationality even though the possibility of violating them is an open question; nothing about the impossibility of violating them seems to impugn their normative status. It seems to me that we might say something similar about a perfectly rational will. If the possibility of agents who cannot but judge in accordance with the rules of rationality does not impugn the normative force or the rules of reason, then it seems that the possibility of an agent who cannot but will in accordance with the rules of practical reason does not undermine the normative force of the latter types of reasons either. Just as the mere fact that a given event could not but occur is not sufficient to conclude that it did not occur in accordance with a rule, nor is the mere fact that that we could not but so will sufficient to conclude that we are not subject to the practical law. If there is a relevant difference between thought and action, it does not seem to lie here. The norm/mechanism distinction does not seem to rule out the possibility of a being who cannot but will in accordance with the practical law. This said, however, the possibility of at least one kind of error must indeed remain open if we are to maintain the distinction between rational and mechanical force. This is the possibility that, despite our best efforts, our attempts at compliance are foiled because the world has interfered. That is, it is always possible that, even though I did all that I 5 Lavin, p.443. id. explaining Korsgaard’s discussion in “The Normativity of Instrumental Reason,” p.240. 6 could do, my charity falls into evil hands, my kindness is interpreted as insult, my helpfulness results in harm, and so on. In short, it is always possible that the world fails to cooperate; the force of reason alone cannot rule out this possibility. In this respect, it seems that Lavin is correct to insist on the possibility of a certain kind of error, namely an error that results from the world going awry, despite my best plans. It also seems to be true that any account of normative force must leave open the possibility of this kind of error, on pain of mistakenly according to norms causal efficacy. Normative force cannot, on its own, effect material compliance; the mere fact that the world ought to be a given way is not sufficient to make it so, and any account of normative force that collapses this gap does indeed collapse the distinction between normative and mechanical force. Furthermore, this is a distinctively practical error in the sense that it is one that arises in virtue of the distinctively practical nature of the norms in question. Insofar as these norms set standards for the natural world, there is always a possibility that their demands are not met. Note finally that, the requirement that we leave open the possibility of this kind of error does indeed rule out the possibility of a certain kind of perfect agent, namely, one who can guarantee successful compliance with the practical law by mere force of will. There can be no one for whom appreciation of the practical law alone is sufficient for success. This follows immediately from the possibility of error requirement as conceived above. If we take the possibility that the world fails to cooperate with our best-laid plans to be a practical error, then it seems that a complete account of the force of practical reason does indeed require that we leave open the possibility of a certain kind of practical error. However, it is not clear that this is the kind that Lavin has in mind in advancing his argument. This is because although the world going awry may certainly result in error in the sense that it may well result in a failure to satisfy the requirements of the practical law, and although this error may be a practical one in the sense that it is one that arises in practice rather than through the exercise of our theoretical capacities, it is not necessarily an error that we can attribute to the agent. Recall that the possibility of error that must be left open by an account of the normative force of practical reason is the possibility that, despite my best attempts, success eludes me because of facts about the world that are beyond my control. Here, however, we would not say that the error is mine; instead, where failure ensues even though I have done all that I could do, we must conclude that I acted well. It is true that my lack of success might cause us to doubt whether I did indeed do all I could do, and whether my failure did truly arise through no fault of my own. This is especially so when I have repeated failures, or when I frequently plead bad luck in the face of failure. But this is just to say that we are often in doubt as to whether or not our initial conditions hold; it is not to say that we ought to withhold praise when they do hold. Hence, the requirement that we leave open the possibility that the world goes awry does indeed rule out the possibility of a certain kind of perfection, namely, that of an agent who can guarantee success by mere appreciation of the rules. This much does indeed follow from considerations of the force of practical reason alone. However, it does not, on its own, rule out the possibility of an agent who consistently does all that she can do to comply, and this may be all that is needed in order to say that she has gotten things right. It thus seems that the error constraint so construed is not on its own sufficient to rule out the possibility of someone who always does well. There is one final possible error that I can think of that Lavin might have in mind. He might think that there is an additional source for error in action but not thought that leaves open the possibility that I have willed correctly, and that doesn't amount to the world failing to cooperate. He might think that there is a gap between willing an act and doing all I can do to execute it. This gap leaves open a source for error in practical but (perhaps) not theoretical reason, and any account of the force of practical reason that rules out the possibility of this error treats the relationship between the will and action as that of mere mechanism since it takes the mere fact of willing to guarantee action. This error may well be the distinctive kind of practical error whose possibility Lavin is trying to preserve. Errors of this type play a prominent role in discussions of practical reason, most significantly in discussions of moral motivation. Moreover, it seems like the kind of error that Korsgaard is after in her rejection of instrumental reason that Lavin takes as his starting point. If this is right, however, what does it have to do with the possibility of a perfectly rational will? Even if it is true that the mere fact of willing cannot guarantee action, why does it follow from this that we must also rule out the possibility of a perfectly rational will? It seems to me that it is only if we make the impermissible assumption that the relationship between the will and action is guaranteed that this inference to a perfect will can go through. But this assumption is precisely what Lavin is denying. More generally, however, must an account of the force of practical reason really leave open the possibility of this error? Are we really treating the relationship between will and action as that of mere mechanism if we rule it out? Is it right to assume that such cases cannot be redescribed either as cases of my not willing or as cases of the world failing to cooperate? Consider again the difficulty. The worry here is that where we take the mere fact of willing to guarantee action, we are impermissibly according to the will mechanical rather than normative force. But, as we have seen, the error we make when we elide these two is to mistakenly attribute causal efficacy to normative principles. This is a mistake since, as we have seen, the mere fact that a norm dictates how the world ought to be is not sufficient to make it so; it is always possible that the world fails to cooperate. If, however, this really is the problem with ruling out the possibility of doing all I can do despite having willed the action, then it seems that this error can indeed be redescribed as the world going awry. There is no new kind of error that arises here. If I am correct in my analysis, then there is no special kind of practical error that is required by consideration of the force of practical reason alone over and above the possibility that the world fails to cooperate. As we have seen, however, this kind of error need not always impugn our responsibility; where failure results from facts about the world, my actions may yet be praiseworthy, or, at the very least, they may not be blameworthy. If this is correct, however, it might seem that we have lost our grip on the very thought that started this discussion, namely Korsgaard’s objection to Humeanism that no theory of practical reason can rule out the possibility that we act irrationally. If, as I have suggested, the only kind of error that we must leave open is one that can leave my responsibility intact, then what are we to make of her suggestion that I might always act irrationally? If all we can say is that the world has failed to cooperate, then how can we attribute this error to me? In virtue of what might was say that I have acted irrationally? This objection moves to quickly; we need not give up on Korsgaard’s point just yet. Recall again her claim.7 She famously argues that the mere fact I am subject to a reason cannot guarantee compliance. It is always possible that I fail to do as I ought, even on pain of irrationality. Her worry is that by making the existence of reason dependent on the existence of motivation or desire, Humean accounts of practical reason mistakenly require that reasons have causal force. Her point here is that we may well have reason to act independently of facts about our respective psychologies or our actions; the mere existence of a reason need not effect material changes in the world, including psychological ones. Nor, conversely, can we divine the existence of a reason just by inspecting our psychologies; in this respect, she insists, reason and motivation can come apart. My point here is that we may well describe such an error as the world failing to cooperate; we need not appeal to any special error of the will in order to make Korsgaard’s point, so conceived. Moreover, this particular error can be attributed to me, or, more specifically, to my irrationality, since we take certain failures of the world – say, e.g., my failure to execute certain actions given certain states of mind – to be failures in my practical rationality. Again, we need appeal to nothing further than the possibility of such an error in order to explain the normative force of practical reason. Conclusion If the foregoing analysis is correct, then it seems that Lavin is correct to insist that the distinction between normative and mechanical force requires that we leave open the possibility of error, and that this requirement does indeed rule out a certain kind of perfect being. However, as I have tried to show, this is not quite the kind of perfection that Lavin intends to rule out. At the very least, it seems that we ought to draw a narrower conclusion about the impossibility of a perfectly rational being than the one that he draws; not all kinds of perfection are excluded by the error constraint. Nonetheless, even on this narrower account, I suggest that we can still account for the possibility of irrationality that got this discussion off the ground. See especially Christine Korsgaard, “Skepticism about Practical Reason,” Journal of Philosophy 83 (1986): 5-26. 7