Wolosky EDFN 1 Truth and Lie in Emily Dickinson and Friedrich Nietzsche To be alive – is Power – Existence – in itself – Without a further function – Omnipotence – Enough – To be alive – and Will! 'Tis able as a God – The Maker – of Ourselves – be what – Such being Finitude! (J 677 / Fr 876) 1 Friedrich Nietzsche was an avid reader of Emerson. But the ruptures he opens in Western philosophical culture find surprising echo in another of his contemporaries, Emily Dickinson,. There are strong contrasts between Dickinson and Nietzsche: in place although not in time; in language; in religious context – Dickinson lived in the intense period of Protestant religious revival of the Second Great Awakening and its wrestling match with Calvinism, in which Amherst passionately participated; while Nietzsche's background is Lutheran in a period of increasing positivism to which his university experience exposed him. Not least, there is a contrast of gender and attitudes towards it, with Dickinson's work a major voice articulating senses of women's identities as these were being reshaped in postRevolutionary America, while in Nietzsche, "woman" remains a complex and highly equivocal figuration. Wolosky EDFN 2 Yet there are likenesses. Neither married, although in Dickinson's case this is seen as eccentric deviation and in Nietzsche as philosophical selfaffirmation.2 Dickinson from the age of 30 reclused herself in her home in Amherst with her sister, mother, and father. Nietzsche at the age of 35 left his teaching position at Basel to withdraw into a life of increasing isolation until his collapse into mental breakdown in 1889, living out the last decade of his life in seclusion under the care of his sister and mother. In both cases, the posthumous writings (for Dickinson almost all of her poetry) went into the care of the sisters with whom each lived, with the works of each suffering disjunctive publication, Dickinson's in the context of family feuds and Nietzsche's due to his sister's ignoble interferences. Above all, the two shared certain premises, or perhaps sensibilities, regarding the nature of the world: that ours is a world in continual flux, foundationally a scene of change and multiplicity. Transition, transformation, instability, rupture is the fundamental condition in which, for each, human beings find themselves. Each fiercely, rigorously records and reiterates that their immanent experience is one of profound temporality and inconstancy. "Of this is Day composed," Dickinson writes: "of morning and a noon" that "dower and deprive" (J 1675/ Fr 1692). One of the first aphorisms in Will to Power declares man's "smallness and accidental occurrence in the flux of becoming and passing away" (WP 4).3 The world for each, then, is firstly a world of becoming. As to the world of metaphysical Being that traditionally served as stable anchor and ground for earthly existence, this other "true" world both Dickinson and Nietzsche see as failing adequately to account for, address, or interpret the flux of Wolosky EDFN 3 phenomena. The traditional orders, grounded in metaphysics, for explaining the world's endless transformations seemed flawed and problematic in its claims as well as in its failure to deliver on them. Both Dickinson and Nietzsche thus balance on a volatile edge of metaphysics. Although neither wrote in philosophically systematic ways – Nietzsche's poetic and in particular his aphoristic style is another tie linking him to Dickinson4 – each offers what emerges as a steadfast critique of traditional metaphysical premises, and a dizzying confrontation with the consequences of such critique. Dickinson's responses to the rupture of metaphysical certainty are more ambivalent, more alarmed than are Nietzsche's. What had seemed foundational had, as through a torn veil, suddenly shown empty; while what stance might take its place remained uncertain. The tearing apart of the two worlds – the tearing away of earthly life from, in Nietzsche's words, the metaphysical "unity, Being, aim" (WP 12) that had purported to govern phenomena – at times causes Dickinson to fall into an abyss. In complex negations such as Nietzsche deploys, she calls metaphysical collapse "The Crash of nothing but of All," and cries: "I cling to nowhere till I fall" (J 1503 / Fr 1532). But at other times Dickinson reaches out to embrace the world of phenomena as her true and exhilarating arena. In, for example, the poem "To be Alive is Power" (cited above as epigraph) Dickinson goes far towards a Nietzschean declaration of allegiance not to any "further" world beyond this one, but to "Existence – in itself – / Without a further function." This world becomes a scene of "Power" which, as a way of being alive, is imminent, and therefore limited and conditional: an "Omnipotence – Enough." Such yoking together the absolute term "Omnipotence" with the limiting "Enough" verges Wolosky EDFN 4 on oxymoron, breaking open metaphysical meaning in ways Nietzsche persistently does. "Omnipotence" rather than marking the divine is both granted and sized to the human. We are alive in the world as the arena of our "will." Within this inherent and immanent life and will, the human is "able as a God." As almost always happens in a Dickinson text, the concluding lines complicate rather than clarify. To be alive – and Will! 'Tis able as a God – The Maker – of Ourselves – be what – Such being Finitude! (J 677 / Fr 876) Truncated, with incomplete phrasing and unclear references, the poem leaves obscure who is the "Maker" of "what" and in what sphere. It seems, though, that Dickinson here celebrates a creative power which displaces, even as it imitates, God's. It is we who are the "Maker – of Ourselves." "Such being Finitude" again approaches philosophical oxymoron. "Finitude" and "being" are in traditional metaphysics contradictory terms. But here they are linked. Being is being in and as "Finitude" in this poem. The conditional, finite world is the arena in which we are "alive" and "will," the realm of "power" as selfdefinition and creativity. Dickinson's work, like Nietzsche's, stares into the maelstrom of metaphysical collapse and its consequences. Her work, like his, pursues a critique in which metaphysical premises are shown to be wanting. Her work, like his, provides an anatomy of the implications of such critique, of the kaleidoscopic and assaultive and also transformative and generative energies released by it. Given the world's multiplicity, the problem becomes for Dickinson, as for Nietzsche, how to account for experience as meaningful in Wolosky EDFN 5 human terms, given its endless transfigurations. And this, for both, increasingly turns on language and interpretation itself. For each, reality in its multiplicity and transfiguration ultimately becomes constituted not by metaphysical principles but by representation, interpretation, and the words we use in their undertaking. I. Linguistic Perspective Despite the dispersions of her language both within texts and in her opus as a whole, Dickinson's work pursues systematic steps of metaphysical critique, tracing the reasons or impulses behind her often regretful inability to accept other-worldly accounts of the earth. For Death – or rather For the Things ‘twould buy – This – put away Life’s Opportunity— The Things that Death will buy Are Room – Escape from Circumstances – And a Name With Gifts of Life How Death’s Gifts may compare – We know not – For the Rates – lie Here – (J 382 / Fr 644)5 "Death" here is entry into traditional immortality. As such it offers a series of metaphysical promises: "Room" evokes eternal and infinite place; "Escape from Circumstances" suggests essence as against accident, absolute design as against conditions; and a "Name" promises fixed identity. But, as Nietzsche summarizes in Twilight of the Idols, in a passage that Heidegger cites as encapsulating Nietzsche's metaphysical critique, so here such promises offered by the afterworld reflect not a metaphysical reality but simply Wolosky EDFN 6 the reverse and antidote to temporality, mutability and mortality – that is, the conditions that we find painful in the world we inhabit. Thus writes Nietzsche: The true world has een constructed out of contradiction to the actual world. To invent fables about a world "other" than this one has no meaning at all, unless an instinct of slander, detraction, and suspicion against life has gained the upper hand in us. We avenge ourselves against life with a phantasmagoria of "another" a "better" life. Twilight 484 6 "Room," "Escape from Circumstances" and "A Name" grant us the absolute time and space that we lack in our earthly lives. But the attraction of this compensatory fantasy does not guarantee its truthfulness. Indeed, Nietzsche says that the contrary is the case: The reasons for which this world has been characterized as "apparent" are the very reasons which indicate its reality; any other kind of reality is indemonstrable. . . The true world – unattainable, indemonstrable, unpromisable. . . The true world – unattainable? At any rate, unattained. And being unattained, also unknown. Consequently not consoling, redeeming, or obligating. . . The true world – we have abolished. What world has remained? The apparent one perhaps? But no! With the true world we have abolished the apparent one.7 There is a fatal weakness to metaphysical design. Our position, viewpoint, understanding and experience remain earthly. Any notion of another world is thus based upon and ultimately situated in this one, not the other way around. As Dickinson writes, "The Rates – lie here." The other world in fact suspiciously looks like an inversion, as Nietzsche insists, of the conditions most dreaded in this one. Yet these form our only direct experience. As against these immanent conditions, the other world remains "unattainable, indemonstrable, unpromisable." This world is not the shadow of a higher one, but rather the reverse is true. It is the other world that is a shadow, a lie, projected out of our dark fears. "The Rates lie here" unmasks this lie. The Wolosky EDFN 7 pun on "Rates" invokes both temporality, pacing in time, and value judgment. The measure of value in actuality is "here," not in some other world posited against this one. Such reference to an other world is, then, not truth, but fiction. It is constructed out of what is most disliked in this one world, reflecting this dislike rather than some higher insight, and serving to deny the actual world we inhabit. And what metaphysics calls lie is in fact truth, the only truth we directly experience. The world of phenemena is then not mere appearance, but is as actual as human experience gets, the only actual world. Thus, to deny metaphysical reality is to accept the reality of the earthly world: "With the true world we have abolished the apparent one." Nietzsche raises such questions of truth and lie in Twilight of the Idols and the nachlass variously collected as The Will to Power;8 but they occupied him from the beginning of his philosophical writings, as seen in his earlier essay "Truth and Lying in an Extra-Moral Sense." This essay opens by framing truth and lie in terms that he later calls "perspectivism" – the sense, as he writes in a Will to Power aphorism, that reality "has no meaning behind it, but countless meanings: Perspectivism" (WP § 481). 9 The variability and partiality of perspective is the chastisement with which he opens "Truth and Lying:" If we and the gnat could understand each other we should learn that even the gnat swims through the air with the same pathos, and feels within itself the flying center of the world. . . So too the proudest man of all, the philosopher, believes he sees the eyes of the universe focused telescopically from all directions upon his actions and thoughts.10 Nietzsche's intuition of the variousness of perspective, and of how perspective inevitably frames what we see and understand, is firmly shared by Dickinson, who devotes many poems to how "We see – Comparatively" (J Wolosky EDFN 8 534 / Fr 580). But the greatest distortion of perspective is denying that that is all it is. The biggest delusion, that is, is for a perspective to mistake itself to be more than that, to be absolute comprehension or general truth. Thus in the poem "Who Giants Know, with lesser men," (and Dickinson's terms of measure are notoriously tricky), the "Giants" are those who in fact know that they know less, the "lesser men" those who do not know that they do not know. They mistake their own viewpoint for the whole world's, paradoxically thinking their vision is larger, while the "Giants" see in ways that are more penetrating because they know their understanding is limited. The "lesser" are thus compared to, displayed by, "the Summer Gnat:" The Summer Gnat displays – Unconscious that his single Fleet Do not comprise the skies – (J 796 / Fr 848) Like Nietzsche's "gnat" in "Truth and Lie" who "feels within itself the flying center of the world," so Dickinson's "Summer Gnat" (here almost an anagram for "Giant") wrongly takes "his single Fleet" – that is, either his own group or his own flight, or his own temporal fleetingness – as if he comprised the whole "skies" at large. But perspectivism in Dickinson and Nietzsche ultimately takes shape not in terms of vision, but of language. At issue is not so much how people see but what and how they say. Wallace Stevens writes in one of his aphorisms, "The Tongue is an Eye." This move from eye to speech is pronounced in Nietzsche, and it is deeply consequential. As Richard Rorty anatomizes in Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, the very act of positing knowledge in visual terms is itself metaphysical, assuming the mind to have some reflective power through which sense perception conforms to ideal Wolosky EDFN 9 structures man can perceive as the true Form to which phenomena refer. 11 Yet this vision-model also raises problems of communication and solipsism, problems that become severe once the metaphysical Forms are questioned. The trope of seeing situates comprehension within each individual mind, in ways that can never be fully verified by others, since their interior experience remains inaccessible to anyone outside themselves.12 Implying that understanding is like visual apprehension places it inside each private mind in ways no one else can share, check, or have access to. Perspective becomes a self-enclosed subjectivity to which there is no exit. But language is by definition social. It takes place between people.13 Moving our model of apprehension from a visual grasp to a linguistic exchange relocates formulation from interior space to an interconnecting web or network in which humans are constitutively placed.14 The Nietzschean turn to language has been long recognized as the decisive plunge forward into a post-metaphysical era. It projects the world as something we formulate, indeed reformulate continuously. The formative and indeed originary power of language is, however, already recognized in Emerson and Dickinson. Emerson's "Nature" vigilantly equivocates between giving nature priority or language. When he writes that "we are assisted by natural objects in the expression of particular meanings" meanings seem to be located in the mind, preceding the objects that become instruments of their expression. But he also asserts that "Words are signs of natural facts" and that nature in turn "is the symbol of spirit." This is to place nature as prior to words, and spirit as prior to nature, in a metaphysically traditional semiotic. Wolosky EDFN 10 Or again, he seems to be imagining a back and forth, a back and forth where nature and mind "corresponds" to each other because it is only through mind that nature is known, but also vice versa: "Every appearance in nature corresponds to some state of the mind, and that state of the mind can only be described by presenting that natural appearance as its picture." Yet even this reciprocity is a linguistic one, the mind only able to be "described" through "natural appearance" and vice versa.15 The sense of linguistic activism, of the role of language in shaping representation, is a substratum of Dickinson's poetics. Her work demonstrates the forms of language itself to have a primary role and impact in experience. Thus, in the poem "Talk not to me of Summer Trees," nature does not direct and command "Talk," which instead is linked to "Foliage of the mind:" Talk not to me of Summer Trees The Foliage of the mind A Tabernacle is for Birds Of no corporeal kind And winds do go that way at noon To their Ethereal Homes Whose Bugles call the least of us To undepicted Realms (J 1634 / Fr 1655) Nietzsche writes in "Truth and Lie": When we speak of trees, colors, snow, and flowers, we believe we know something about the things themselves, although what we have are just metaphors of things which do not correspond to the original entities. (TL 249) In Dickinson's text, the "Foliage of the mind" rivals, indeed precedes, that of "Summer Trees," which emerge as its reflection. The world is made in the image of mind, not mind of the world. But the imaging is deeply rhetorical, a matter of language and its arrangements. The "Foliage" becomes Wolosky EDFN 11 "Tabernacle," an invocation of religious language pursued through the text, but one in which other-worldly meanings are re-cast into immanent ones. Thus "Birds" are of "no corporeal kind," winds are "Ethereal," and "Bugles," resonant of Biblical trumpets, "call" to "undepicted Realms." But in each case, not spiritual, but rather imaginary realms are intended. The "undepicted Realms" are not apocalyptic ones but further poetic ventures. Or, even more precisely, what is invoked is not simply imagination, but the paradigms that govern it along with other human relations to the world, and which are above all linguistic ones. The poem not only transforms language, conducting it from the religious sphere to the imaginary, but also concerns language. It deflects "talk" of "Summer Trees" to the "Foliage of the Mind" – where leaves are themselves a traditional trope for pages or texts. In a continuing linguistic imagery the bugles "call," a personification granting to them linguistic action. "Undepicted Realms" is a complex trope. Instead of apocalyptic realms, poetic and linguistic ventures are proposed. Undepicted Realms" suggest a sublime tradition, which points beyond any given depiction – a term connoting both visual image and word description. But in another sense, they point to ever further and renewed depictions. They are "undepicted" as yet, not as an absolute state that exists beyond human achievement or expression, but rather as an ever mobile, ever advancing linguistic pathway, tracing an ever receding, because never final description. For, such finality does not exist. Rather, language marks a limit delineating the world that humans inhabit. It is within linguistic realms that we depict, and then depict again. Not least, the poem is cast as dialogue. The speaker Wolosky EDFN 12 addresses an auditor concerning what can and cannot be talked of, about forms of language and their powers. II. Personification and Negation In the most famous passage from "Truth and Lie," Nietzsche calls the linguistic forms that are decisive in shaping human understanding of the world "anthropomorphisms, " "What therefore is truth? A mobile army of metaphors, metonymies, anthropomorphisms: in short a sum of human relations which were poetically and rhetorically heightened, transferred, and adorned" (TL 250). Nietzsche is supremely aware of the question of viewpoint: how each person sees from within a context and according to a perspective that locates him or her. But Nietzsche probes how viewpoint is itself a figure – a visual image for what is also, indeed firstly, a linguistic praxis. It is the forms of language – grammatical, rhetorical, philological – that articulate categories of understanding, which thus prove to be projected from and within human experience, not perceived or received by us. These categories, whatever form they take, reside in the human. Therefore they can be grouped together under the rubric of anthropomorphism, or, in traditional rhetorical terms, of personification. Personification is often treated as a sub-category of metaphor or simile. It seems to be a kind of comparison, in which something – one term of the comparison – happens to be human, and is compared to something that is not. As metaphor, personification transfers a human attribute to a non-human one. These transfers can register a range or variety of degree, across and respecting a kind of chain of being. Human qualities can be transferred to Wolosky EDFN 13 animals, but also to vegetables or minerals. Or, animate life rather than specifically human attributes can be transferred down to plant or rock. Human attributions can also be extended beyond specific metaphoric comparisons to larger topoi, as in the micro-macrocosmic correspondences that deeply inform not only literary, but religious and also scientific thought. 16 But Nietzsche's analysis of anthropomorphism extends beyond the specific rhetoric and topoi of personification. Rather, he sees it as fundamental to all human language. (Human) language as such is a mode of personification or anthropomorphism. Far from being a discrete trope, a subset of metaphor and simile as a certain kind of comparison, personification is the norm characterizing all language. For language, as spoken by humans, necessarily and ineradicably humanizes. The categories of language are human categories. This is the case not just when there is a clear ascription of human attributes to something non-human, as in personifying metaphors. Our very grammar, our very linguistic structures, which is to say every verb, every adjective, every noun, reflects human interests and orderings. Thus Nietzsche in "Truth and Lying" states that every definition is anthropomorphic through and through and does not contain one single point which is 'true in itself" real and universally valid apart from man. The investigator into such truths is basically seeking just the metamorphosis of the world in man; he is struggling to understand the world as a human-like thing and acquires at best a feeling of an assimilation. . . Such an investigator observes the whole world as linked to man, as the infinitely refracted echo of a primeaval sound, as the reproduction and copy of an archetype, man. (TL 251) The world to humans is a humanized world. The world is a "human-like thing," human seekers experience the world "as linked to man," in relationship to human interests and orders. Wolosky EDFN 14 Thus, if the world seems to correspond to human understanding, this is because humans find in the world what we ourselves have put there. What has been taken to be correlation is in effect tautology: What is the situation of these conventions of language? Are they perhaps products of knowledge, of the sense of truth? Do terms coincide with things? Is language the adequate expression of all realities? Only by forgetfulness can man ever come to believe that he has truth to the above-designated degree. Unless he wants to settle for truth in the form of tautology. (TL 248) Nietzsche here challenges the notion that "terms coincide with things," that language matches a reality predetermined outside it. Language as "adequate expression" presumes that there is a pre-existent external reality that language merely re-presents, as if expression were a secondary effect of a prior determination. This correspondence theory of language posits that language correlates with and repeats an external reality established in itself. Instead, Nietzsche insists that the reason the world seems to match human formulations is because our formulations set up our understanding of the world. This is tautology, not causality. It is, Nietzsche goes on to say, like someone who "hides an object behind a bush and then seeks and finds it there” (TL 251). The world conforms to human understanding not because we grasp it in itself, but because we arrange it, always in relation to our own categories. Reality is not correlated to language; rather it is "language which has worked originally at the construction of ideas." The "thing in itself"(which would be pure, disinterested truth) is also absolutely incomprehensible to the creator of language and not worth seeking. He designates only the relations of things to men, and to express these relations he uses the boldest metaphors. (TL 248) In "Truth and Lie," then, language is formative. Personifying human categories foundationally structure what they represent. But this is a concern Wolosky EDFN 15 of Emily Dickinson's poetry as well. Yet this need not mean that there is utter collapse of meaning: that if there is no absolute truth, all is mere lie. To deny correspondence theory is not to reduce all experience and expression to arbitrary or solipsistic expression. Tautology in this sense is not simply circular. It rather defines the parameters within which human experience takes place as conditioned and finite, as partial and even fragmented.17 If there is no world pre-existing its linguistic formulation, no world of "truth" that language merely reiterates, does that mean there is no world and no meaning? In contemporary terms, the critique of correspondence theory has posited instead a sign-theory in which no signified precedes a signifier. The signifier is not merely the result, effect, vehicle, expression of a prior meaning constituted without language. References do not subsist external to the linguistic forms through which we experience them. Rather, our language formulates our experience. This does mean that experience is never final or absolute, is always represented, is always beckoning to reformulation. But what then regulates the production of language so that it is not merely arbitrary or imposed, both on nature and, crucially, on other human beings? Dickinson suggests that it is exactly the insistence on the limits of claims, on the sense of a space beyond what humans can know or represent absolutely, curtails but also generates particular formulations. Therefore the negative – what is not expressed, attained, granted – emerges as a central site, defining even as – or rather, in that – it limits what is properly human. The poem "The Tint I cannot take – is best –" examines and represents such a dialectic of limitation. Written in the mode of Romantic imaginative Wolosky EDFN 16 power, it nonetheless crosses into this discourse a counter one that resituates imaginative claims. The Tint I cannot take – is best – The Color too remote That I could show it in Bazaar – A Guinea at the sight— The fine – impalpable Array – That swaggers on the eye Like Cleopatra's Company – Repeated -- in the sky – The Moments of Dominion That happen on the Soul And leave it with a Discontent Too exquisite – to tell – The eager look – on Landscapes – As if they just repressed Some Secret – that was pushing Like Chariots – in the Vest – The Pleading of the Summer – That other Prank – of Snow – That Cushions Mystery with Tulle, For fear the Squirrels – know. Their Graspless manners – mock us – Until the Cheated Eye Shuts arrogantly – in the Grave – Another way – to see – (J 627 / Fr 696) Harold Bloom calls this a "poem besieged by perspectivism" within the context of a Nietzschean affirmation in "our faith [in] the existing world" (WP 1046). As an "authentic American Sublime," the poem opens with a characteristic Dickinsonian gesture towards the sublime as standing beyond any actuality – a romance structure where what is not always exceeds what is, with the ideal ever hovering before and beyond whatever concretely exists.18 This is to recognize the realm of imagination as always surpassing what is actual. Yet, as Harold Bloom has theorized, such surpassing entails Wolosky EDFN 17 an element of negation. The imagination doesn't simply fuse or reciprocate with nature, but must counter it in order to open space for its own ventures. Negation is thus imaginatively liberating and positive. But negation also has a limiting function that works across the sublime. The sublime can imply some endless reach of mind into ever greater extents. But it also signals, as in Kant, a confrontation with the unbounded in which the imagination experiences its own limits.19 This sense of negation points to what is beyond as something unreachable, never to be attained. It recognizes transcendence, but not as a second, eternal metaphysical world into which one hopes to enter or reach. Transcendence instead acts as a barrier, resending energy back into a beckoning temporality as the ever receding, ever summoning next moment which ever remains our framework and condition. Transcendence in this sense marks a limit that we, as humans, never cross: a negative transcendence not to be grasped, but instead to stand as guard against our attempts to claim and exceed what ever remains for us finite positions and understanding. Perspectivism in Nietzsche involves not only viewpoint but, more radically, linguistic formulation. But this also resituates perspectivism away from solipsistic subjectivism. Linguistic formulation is necessarily shared. Language, as Saussure underscored, is itself a social institution into which individuals enter and by which they are shaped. Its constructions are common ones, with creativity working through and with common constructions. Each individual version still assumes and depends on shared language usage, as both a limiting function and also a power. "The Tint I cannot Take" interestingly works between visual and linguistic construction Wolosky EDFN 18 and the implications of each. "Tint," "Color," and "sight" all underscore the question of vision and perspective as situating the speaker. But the next stanza's "impalpable Array -- / That swaggers on the eye" at once asserts and cancels the visual dimension: an "Array" can be seen by the "eye," but the "impalpable" cannot. And this second stanza already moves into a sense of language rather than vision as the structure of experience. "Swaggers on the eye" is a personification, granting to "Array" an intentional and human action – indeed, a braggadocio, of overclaiming. At issue is not only seeing but saying. "Like Cleopatra's Company" is a likeness that is not perceptual, but conceptual, made possible and indeed invented through the rhetorical structure of simile itself. The verse then evokes a directly linguistic image: "Repeated – in the sky." Like Nietzsche 's "echo," the act of the seeker as he [she] "contemplates the whole world as related to man, as the infinitely protracted echo of an original sound," the sky repeats the poet, not the poet the sky. Indeed, this second stanza is followed by a quite Nietzschean gesture involving, as in the poem "To be alive – is power" the question of domination and will, again as linguistic phenomena. "The Moments of Dominion" are those when the "soul" experiences creative surge. But "Dominion" here is deeply paradoxical. It involves not expression, but its limit; not possession but its evasion. It happens to "happen" on the soul, rather than being directly willed by it. As an experience of power, it lasts but a "Moment." As Dickinson writes in another poem, "Dominion lasts until obtained" (J 1257 / Fr 1299). And it involves not command of nature, but "Discontent" as nature never in fact corresponds with human desire. A second negation then follows. "Too exquisite – to tell" makes the experience Wolosky EDFN 19 at once linguistic and not so. As with all tropes of inexpressibility, there is a complex paradoxicality of language that declares the inability to name something beyond language.20 Dickinson is balanced on a boundary she thereby defines or marks out, of the extent of linguistic power, and also its borders and limits. The poem continues its rhetoric of personification. "Landscapes" are said to "look" – i.e. to see, not be seen; "Snow" to play a "Prank," "Squirrels" to "know." These transferences of the human again move into linguistic tropes, which again delimit as well as affirming subjectivity. The landscape's "eager Look" turns out to signal something not seen: a "Secret" that is "repressed." The "Summer" is described as "Pleading," a beckoning rather than commanding speech act. The conclusion of the poem again invokes an "Eye," but as "Cheated" and finally as shutting. The desire to see absolutely is rebuked as arrogant. Instead, its mortality is confirmed. The eye's vista shrinks to the "Grave." If there is "Another way – to see," this is left ambiguous between further vision and irony at the desire to gain it. Alongside this chastened visual imagery persists an imagery of language, which is similarly bounded. Our efforts to know what the summer pleads and what snow conceals "mock" us. Our knowledge is not directly of nature but always through linguistic acts that inevitably entail ourselves.21 Against the desire to grasp the world-in- itself, nature remains "Graspless," beyond our comprehension and our possession. In this poem, language does not reflect, nor simply echo external reality. Rather, experience is itself inextricably and at once structured as and through language. Speaking forms the world through words. A prior signified Wolosky EDFN 20 does not determine language as referring or corresponding to it. Yet neither does this leave signifiers arbitrarily unanchored or coercively imposed, as Nietzsche's Will to Power is often taken to imply. Instead, what is traced here is an immersion in or experience of signifiers as the realm of human meaning, the only meaning we finally have, which is also one that is never final. This is not to say that meaning is merely relativist or arbitrary or dominating. Signifiers are not simply, freely, and independently posited. They are instead fundamentally, one might say foundationally linked to each other in chains or networks or, as Nietzsche repeatedly insists in "Truth and Lie," in relationships. Man knows nothing of the "thing-in-itself" but only designates "the relations of things to men and for their expression he calls to his help the most daring metaphors" (TL 248). Such "relations" may seem only expressions of personal human will. But Nietzsche continues: What, then, is for us a law of nature? It is not known to us as such, but only in its effects, i.e. in its relations to other laws of nature, which in turn are known to us only as relations. All these relations thus always refer back only to one another and are absolutely incomprehensible to us in their essence; what we add to them --- time, space, hence relations of succession and numbers, is all we know about them. . . . But we produce these perceptions within ourselves and out of ourselves with the same necessity as a spider spins its web. . we are compelled to grasp all things only under these forms. (TL 253) The fact that we do not know nature "in-itself" does not mean we don't know it at all, or that we just make up what and as we please. While "reality" remains in Dickinson's terms "Graspless" in-itself – as Nietzsche writes, "we are compelled to grasp all things only under these forms" – there are other "manners" in which we do know. These are exactly the patterns that we weave in and through our language, articulating what Nietzsche calls "sums of relations." "These relations," Nietzsche writes, "refer only to one another and Wolosky EDFN 21 are absolutely incomprehensible to us in their essence." That is, they mean only to and for us, not in themselves as some absolute noumena. Yet to and for us they do mean. We conceive them in "relations of sequence," of "time" and "space," which Nietzsche treats, as human categories, as personifications or anthropomorphisms. Whether or not they subsist without us, they are known to us only as we designate them, making out of them, in one of Nietzsche's powerful images in "Truth and Lying," a "new world of laws" in a "sky of ideas." Nor is there any unity or whole. Relations remain multiple. Yet this very multiplicity also prevents them from being merely willful. As Saussure wrote about linguistic signs, despite their lack of essential relation to things outside themselves, their very multiplicity stabilizes a system which, in order to operate at all, cannot shift terms and usages randomly or at will.22 This multiplicity and its regulatory force applies as well to Nietzsche's language theory. Denying any tie to a signified exterior and prior to linguistic formulation does not release the signifier into wanton assertion. While the signifier is untied to a signified independent of it, the signifier is retied to other signifiers. In this net of relationships humans live and mean, in relations to each other that are regulated and not simply assertive or wayward. In Philosophy in the Tragic Age of the Greeks Nietzsche posits the "essential character of primal being as coming-to-be." Being is not fixed and eternal, but everchanging and "indefinite." This "indefinite," the womb of all things, can, it is true, be designated by human speech only as a negative, as something to which the existent world of coming-to-be can give no predicate. We may look upon it as the equal of the Kantian Ding an sich."23 The "indefinite" is a "negative" designation. It is not a "signified." It can be given "no predicate." But this negation is in many ways a defining act. It Wolosky EDFN 22 marks a transcendence as exactly what is beyond grasp. It thus defines our experience as within phenomenal reality, at once limiting and delineating it. Transcendence then is not a failed goal but a regulatory limit. In this light, the opening "Tint I cannot take," which suggests an image of point of view as a kind of coloring of how we see and promising some further viewpoint as yet unattained, comes also to signal, in its negative formulation, the impossibility of any final or absolute vision. Further, "tint" is also a form of engraving, and "tint block" is a term in printing for a "lightly colored background upon which an illustration or the like is to be printed." Visual imagery verges into imagery of printing. But this moves the poem's formulations from interior perception toward a shared world of exchange. Signifiers link together in a network of language that different selves participate in. The move from vision to language redirects the poem from subjectivism to negotiated, mutual and common understanding. Such understanding is never absolute. Rather, intrinsic reality remains "Graspless," resisting our attempts to comprehend it. This is a limitation the poem insists on, concluding in the defeat of any "Eye" which "arrogantly" tries to see absolutely. Instead, the poem declares the world to be a "Mystery" beyond our reach, whose "Graspless manners" – a near oxymoron suggesting a mode of modelessness – demand that we acknowledge and respect what cannot be grasped. III. Veils and Circles: Modest Reflections The linguistic world is one of mutability and participation, not of final command. It remains bounded by limitation and ontological "Mystery." Such Wolosky EDFN 23 "Mystery" is interestingly figured in the poem "The Tint I cannot take" as "Tulle." Tulle in Dickinson is a highly gendered image, closely associated with veils, with the female body itself, and also with language as material event in the imminent world. Feminized senses of "Veil" have been a topic in Dickinson, and also in Nietzsche studies. Regarding Dickinson, the veil has been associated with a problematic of the Gaze, of seeing while not being seen, within a nineteenth century discourse of gendered norms and commodification. 24 Veils and associated images appear in such well-known poems as "Because I could not stop for Death," where "Tulle" represents the speaker's body (J 712 / Fr 479). In "A Charm invests a face," it an emblem of the sublime which warns against exposure as lifting "her Veil / For fear it be dispelled." (J 421/ Fr 430)25 Veil is also expressly a linguistic trope. In "A Single Screw of Flesh" "Veil" figures both as body and as writing – the two in fact as fundamental tropes for each other. In this poem, the poet remains on her "side" of "the Veil" as body, separating the speaker from God – a side she however clutches at, reluctant to let go to pass into another world. But veil is also language, associated with "name" and the danger of losing it in erasure, with the self itself figured as "printed" language (J 263/ Fr 293).26 The topic of Nietzsche's imagery of woman is too vast even to broach here. But, as Derrida has particularly noted, there is a striking figure in Nietzsche of the "veil" as feminine image, associated in complex layers with both truth and lie.27 On the one hand, Nietzsche associates women with "appearance" – "her supreme concern is appearance and beauty" (BGE 232) Here she is an emblem of the world of becoming –in fact, a quite traditional assignment. Woman's place within metaphysical system has persistently Wolosky EDFN 24 been to mark what is not essence, what is not real, what is merely sensual and apparent.28 But in his reassignments of truth and falsehood, Nietzsche can also write: "Suppose truth is a woman" (BGE Preface). Here he implies that "truth" has been through the history of philosophy in fact a fiction, which calling it "woman" exposes. As Derrida writes, "There is no such thing as the truth of woman, but it is because . . . "untruth" is "truth" (51). Nietzsche wrote in the Gay Science: "perhaps this is the greatest charm of life: it puts a golden-embroidered veil of lovely potentialities over itself, promising, resisting, modest, mocking, sympathetic, seductive. Yes. Life is a woman" (GS 339). Derrida comments: "For him, truth is like a woman. It resembles the veiled movement of feminine modesty. . . [a] complicity between woman, life, seduction, modesty, all the veiled and veiling effects." As Derrida's remarks reflect, the veil in both theoretical and historical terms is an icon of modesty, invoking what remains concealed. In women's history, this has persistently involved imposed constraint: a repression in the Foucauldian sense that also activates, conjuring a female sexuality defined from the standpoint of men and denying women's own subjectivity. Nietzsche has been aligned with these as with other Foucauldian trends. His position regarding modesty in any case will differ from Dickinson's. As Derrida writes, Nietzsche may not fall into mere anti-feminism or feminism (57), but Nietzsche generally regards woman from outside, as spectacle.29 Dickinson, in contrast, inhabits her womanhood and speaks from it. Modesty in fact is among Dickinson's most complex tropes, enacted, in both her life and work, as both defiance and embrace. 30 Dickinson gazes not only at, but through the veil: of Wolosky EDFN 25 body, of language, of limitation itself. At issue is the whole question of boundedness and boundaries. This is a question intrinsic to another core Dickinson figure, circumference. Circumference has been largely interpreted in Dickinson as ultimately transcending boundaries into infinity. Jane Donahue Eberwein, who treats the trope extensively, sees it rightly as an aspect of Dickinson's "Strategies of Limitation" but ultimately in order to "explode beyond them."31 Albert Gelpi sees it as an emblem of the absolute self, "more infinite than infinity."32 In his discussion of Dickinson and Nietzsche in terms of "The Rites of Dionysus," Dwight Eddins focuses on "the dialectic between boundlessness and limitation" which circumference evokes. And he, too, ultimately sees Dickinson's as a drive to a Dionysian boundlessness, tracing an "all inclusive circle with the ultimate unity of Dionysian affirmation. There is nothing left outside the circle, no "otherness" anywhere in nature. . . in an ecstasy of omnipotence."33 Yet many of Dickinson's images of "circumference" are highly equivocal. Rather than affirming the transcendence of boundaries, they question that possibility. In the poem "I Saw No Way, the Heavens were Stitched," the self is figured as deeply disoriented. Going out "upon Circumference / Beyond the Dip of Bell" leaves the self precariously suspended. (J 378 / Fr 633). Gelpi cites the poem "Time feels so vast" as affirming continuity between the smaller circle of the self and an infinite circumference (J 802 / Fr 858).34 But the poem registers tension, contest, and discontinuity between smaller and larger, as Time's vastness presents a "Circumference" that threatens to exclude "Eternity." In yet another poem, Wolosky EDFN 26 "Circumference" is trope for "Ignorance," as inspired by the "Sunset" in a vision of "Omnipotence" glimpsed by "Our inferior face" (J 552 / Fr 669). Circumference then is not only a verge into the beyond, but also marks a limit needed to sustain selfhood at all. This is strongly registered in the poem "His mind of man, a secret makes." There Dickinson describes each self as a "circumference / In which I have no part . . . Impregnable to inquest." (J 1663 / Fr 1730). As she also writes, "The Suburbs of a secret / A strategist should keep." (J 1245 / Fr ). Circumference thus stretches on an edge between boundlessness and boundary, but ultimately draws back into the world of limitation. In this it acts like a veil and like negation itself, refusing the desire to exceed into absolute realms. In the poem "Circumference thou Bride of Awe" the figure is clearly feminized (J 1620 / Fr 1636). This poem is most often read as urging possession; but there is also a suspicion against it. 35 The romance desire of the "hallowed Knights" to possess this "Bride of Awe" is suspected, not lauded, as coveting. The phrase "Possessing thou shalt be/ Possessed" makes unclear who possesses whom. Perhaps "Possessing" itself will be "Possessed;" or perhaps there is a mutual implication rather than command of ownership. Above all, "Awe," like "Mystery," projects a powerful boundary in Dickinson, pointing towards a relation to the world as transcending her: not in the sense of a metaphysical other world, but as the immanent world that remains beyond her ownership and command. In this she affirms both selfhood and its limits. 36 Dickinson's circumference may be compared to the core circle image in Nietzsche, the Eternal Return. Just what and how Nietzsche means by Wolosky EDFN 27 Eternal Return has continued to be debated. But one clear implication is that it brings back into phenomena and becoming the value that metaphysics, according to Nietzsche, drained from them. Eternal Return affirms the world of time and change, to the point of embracing their eternal enactment. 37 It draws a circle within this world of time and language, not as mere restriction but as power-generating embrace. In one of Dickinson's most famous texts, it is as language that circle imagery emerges in, "Tell all the truth but tell it slant / Success in circuit lies" (J 1129 / 1150). Is "Truth" here a pre-established Idea that resists expression into partial and inadequate language? An in-itself that, as the poem goes on to say, "must dazzle gradually / Or every man be blind," requiring circumlocution to mediate its overwhelming presence? Or is "Circuit" here not a detour but the only path for telling a "Truth" which only emerges within the tropes and images of its representation? "Success in Circuit lies" itself plays on lie and truth, making them difficult to tell apart: does linguistic circuit lie, or is it the only form of truth we ever experience? Does circuit mark a boundary to be protested and transcended, or a limit to be embraced as both necessary and generative? Yet in the poem, truth only appears, only happens in the world, as slant, as figure. Indeed, the pull of the poem brings truth into the process of language and the language of process. Any attempt to strip away figuration is to try to penetrate to what is "Too bright for our Infirm Delight" – where "Delight" itself inheres in our infirmity, our human imperfection. As Wallace Stevens writes: "The imperfect is our paradise." There are readings of Nietzsche's "Truth and Lie in an Extra-Moral Sense" that see it, in its denial of a signified truth outside of language, as Wolosky EDFN 28 tracing a collapse of all meaning. Nietzsche appears then to be digging out the very ground on which he stands, in a self-undoing of language that undermines meaning itself.38 What then remains, notably in the interpretations of Nietzsche in Foucault and Deleuze, is language as an unanchored proliferation of signs, functioning within exercises of power that emerge as the only continuing principle – indeed, a power that seems to act as a itself a metaphysical principle, the substratum of all that is or occurs.39 In such interpretations, Nietzsche prefigures post-modernism in the sense summarized by Cornel West as anti-foundationalist, anti-realist, as detranscendentalizing the subject, and relativist. But there are other possibilities. West himself suggests that "Nietzsche believed such moves lead to a paralyzing nihilism and skepticism unless they are supplemented with a new world view, a new "countermovement" to overcome such nihilism and skepticism," although West sees contemporary philosophy as having failed as yet to achieve such a countermovement. 40 Some indication of a constructive deconstruction in Nietzsche can be seen in the work of Jean Granier, who argues that "Perspectivism" projects not solipsism but, rather, multiple interpretations. These are generative rather than nihilistic or merely relativistic, exactly in that Nietzsche resists dogmatic insistence on one version as alone true. Nietzsche instead insists on "the impossibility of a definitive interpretation that would exhaust the richness of reality."41 This possible constructive deconstructivism sees the Will to Power not as a selfaggrandizing imposition on others but rather, in accordance with perspectivism, as a partiality of any power. Multiple versions may compete, but, especially when cast in terms of language rather than vision, they would Wolosky EDFN 29 do so in forms and forums of mutual negotiation. The denial of a single truth would become the ground for new interpretive creation, while paying homage to the limitation of each before the versions of others and the greater mystery of the world. Limitation remains pivotal. In the Will to Power, Nietzsche describes nihilism as caused by metaphysics itself, in its faulty and devaluating accounts of experience. "The "meaninglessness of events" he calls the "consequence of an insight into the falsity of previous interpretations, a generalization of discouragement and weakness." But it is not, he goes on, "a necessary belief." Indeed, Nietzsche goes on to describe nihilism as a form of hubris, of "the immodesty of man: to deny meaning where he sees none" (WP 599). Nietzsche urges instead a "plurality of interpretations [as] a sign of strength. Not to desire to deprive the world of its disturbing and enigmatic character! (WP 600).42 Here, like Dickinson, Nietzsche acknowledges a mystery beyond possession in any final form. Beyond any account man gives, the world retains its "disturbing and enigmatic character" – a removal that yet generates our linguistic energy, as both a creative and a conditional force. Thus, Nietzsche's critique of traditional metaphysics does dismiss claims to ground language in a signified truth that exists outside language. Nonetheless, this dismissal of metaphysical truth need not entail either willful imposition of subjective versions or chaotic collapse of all meaning. It may instead point to newly directed structures or modes of signification. These would deny originary forms of "Truth" and would claim that the only shape our world has for us is that of figuration, conducted in language. Language and Wolosky EDFN 30 its figures would then no longer be "lie," since there would be no "truth" to which they need or fail to refer. Towards the conclusion of "Truth and Lie" Nietzsche names the "impulse towards the formation of metaphors" as the "fundamental impulse of man," in which "new figures of speech, metaphors, metonymies. . .constantly show [the] passionate longing for shaping the existing world of waking man. . This impulse seeks for itself a new realm of action . . . in Art" (TL 254). The figures of language impel and conduct the endless human making of "new" realms to inhabit, as the very action of "Art." Art emerges as Nietzsche's focal and defining activity, caught or taut between the drive to form and the everaltering energy that he named in The Birth of Tragedy (written shortly before "Truth and Lie") Apollonian and Dionysian impulses. Dickinson's verse traces this shaping power of trope in both its impulse to order and its refusal of final shape or absolute claim. The world emerges in one sense as an aesthetic venture. In another sense, its mystery, marked as negation, prevents the aesthetic from reducing the world to its own terms, while also generating new forms. In "Truth and Lie," Nietzsche declares: "Nature knows of no forms or concepts. . . but only an X that is inaccessible and indefinable for us." (TL 250). Nietzsche here is unmasking a delusion, the delusion that reality can ever be unmasked. He does so in both disappointment and defiance. Dickinson is never as adamant as Nietzsche. Hers ever remains a "Sweet Skepticism of the Heart / That knows – and does not – know" (J 1413 / Fr1438). As poet, her task is to negotiate the space abandoned by metaphysical certainty with the language forms that never resolve, respecting their own limits, but that venture and create. Wolosky EDFN 31 This aesthetic and indeed specifically linguistic power, as well as the limitations that at once restrict and yet also launch creativity, is traced in one of a series of Dickinson poems of dawn, through the arc of presence and then disappearance of bird's song: At Half past Three, a single Bird Unto a silent sky Propounded but a single term Of cautious melody At Half past Four, Experiment Had subjugated test And lo, Her silver principle Supplanted all the rest. At Half past Seven, Element Nor Implement, be seen – And Place was where the Presence was Circumference between. (J 1084 / Fr 1099)43 The scene of this poem is radically temporal and radically linguistic. The circles of clock measure intensify the condition of becoming, of time and change, as the context for human experience. That experience itself is represented as one of linguistic activism. Against a "sky" that is "silent," the "Bird" figure introduces a "melody" figured as a "term" that is "Propounded" – that is, as language.44 The relation of the bird to the sky is one almost of address or dialogue; yet it remains "cautious," even modest, with the bird explicitly feminized as "Her" in the next stanza. The second stanza does break into power. "Experiment" displaces "Test," subjugating and supplanting "all the rest." The song here asserts what Nietzsche called the "impulse towards the formation of metaphors," one that is not only inescapable, but also defining of human existence in the world. Yet this proves but a moment in an ongoing course that the poem too pursues. Wolosky EDFN 32 The projection of voice in time becomes empty space. "Place was where the Presence was." "Circumference" here marks language balanced on the edge of itself, of what it can, and cannot, offer and accomplish. The art of song is celebrated; but it is also retracted, limited in its power to shape or govern or command a world that is ever changing, every escaping from it. In her writing it emerges as a boundary that both generates power and defines its extent – both as to its reach and what it cannot reach beyond. 1 Dickinson texts will be cited by both the Thomas Johnson and the R.W. Franklin The Poems of Emily Dickinson (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998) poem numbers. The question of textual stability is itself a vexed and complex one, which I will not enter into here. I will say, however, that the textual instability of Dickinson texts concur with the argument in this paper towards the role of language as and in a realm of becoming. 2 As Nietzsche famously said in The Gay Science III: 7 "Thus the philosopher abhors marriage and all that would persuade him to marriage, for he sees the married state as an obstacle to fulfillment. What great philosopher has ever been married?" trans. Walter Kaufmann, (N.Y.: Vintage Books, 1974). Hereafter cited as GS. 3 Friedrich Nietzsche The Will to Power (N.Y.: Vintage Books 1967). Hereafter cited as WP followed by section number. 4 Much has been written on Nietzsche's aphoristic style. See especially Maurice Blanchot, The Infinite Conversation tr. Susan Hanson (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1993). 5 This poem and its metaphysical critique I discussed in Emily Dickinson: A Voice of War (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1984), where my focus was on metaphysical revolt as well as historical conflict. 6 Martin Heidegger Nietzsche. Vol One, trans. David Krell (San Francisco: Harper and Row Publishers, Inc. 1978), p. 202. 7 Friedrich Nietzsche, Twilight of the Idols in The Portable Nietzsche ed. Walter Kaufmann, (NY: Penguin Books, 1954), p. 485. 8 On nachlass questions 9 Cf. a much cited aphorism in Will to Power, where Nietzsche writes that the world "has no meaning behind it, but countless meanings: Perspectivism" (WP § 481). Cf discussion in Lingis and Nehemas. Wolosky EDFN 33 10 "On Truth and Lying in a Extra-Moral Sense" in Friedrich Nietzsche on Rhetoric and Language ed. Sander Gilman, Carole Blair, David Parent (NY: Oxford University Press, 1989) 246-257, p. 246. Hereafter cited as TL. 11 Richard Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1980. 12 Of course one of the Cartesian topics. A central problem in epistemology. Cf Gilbert Ryle eg the ghost in the machine. 13 Another philosophical topic: the impossibility of private language. Wittgenstein. Kripke. Already in Saussure. 14Such location of the human in conversation has become a principal topic in discourse theories, such as Habermas's. Note his critique of Nietzsche, Nehemas; but closes off potential readings. 15 I have discussed Emersonian language theory in "Emerson's Figural Religion," forthcoming. 16 See my "Personification" in The Art of Poetry, (NY: Oxford University Press, 2002). 17 Nehemas's argument here is not consistent re reason not being critical unless via an exterior absolute standpoint. CC to N. 18 Harold Bloom, The Western Canon, (Ny: Harcouty Brace & Company, 1994), pp. 304-309. The sublime of course is a major topic in Dickinson studies. See Gary Stonum, Joanne Fieht Diehl. 19 Kant describes the sublime in Critique of Judgment , as involving "a representation which makes us remark its inadequacy and consequently its subjective want of purposiveness," finding "the whole power of the imagination inadequate to its ideas," II. 26. Lyotard's interpretation of this sublime as a chasm between representation and the unrepresentable is close to what is under discussion here. On the other hand, to Kant the sublime is ultimately a revelation of our own subjectivity, "true sublmity must be sought only in the mind of the subject judging, not in the natural object the judgment upon which occasions this state." As to Nietzsche, he read parts of the Critique of Judgment (CJ) in 1867, but both Kant's sublime and Nietzsche's relation to it are far too daunting a topic to enter into here. For discussion, see: Kevin Hill Nietzsche's Critiques: The Kantian Foundations of his Thought, (NY: Oxford University Press, 2003); Michael Harr, Nietzsche and Metaphysics trans. Michael Gendre, (NY: Suny Press, 1996). 20 Curtius on inexpressibility. See Language Mysticism. 21 As Harold Bloom writes, the poem figures the "limits of her art," "an ungraspable secret, a trope or metaphor not to be expressed." This contrasts Sharon Cameron's reading that "the poem indeed if paradoxically grasps what it claims cannot be grasped," although does see dominion as "redefined as residing only in the momentary, in the particular piecemeal moments reiterated in this poem as both comprehensive and unforgettable." Choosing Not Choosing (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 164-165. 22 Saussure Linguistics 23 Friedrich Nietzsche, Philosophy in the Tragic Age of the Greeks (Chicago: Henry Regnery Company, 1962), p. 47. 24 Lisa Harper offers a sustained discussion of the veil and the Gaze in Dickinson in "The Eyes accost – and Sunder:" Unveiling Emily Dickinson's Poetics," Emily Dickinson Journal 9:1 21-48 Wolosky EDFN 34 25 Significantly, "dispelled" plays on spelling, while, in the poem's conclusion, reiterating the power of what is imagined over what exists, "Interview" combines a trope of vision with that of language: "Lest Interview – annul a want / That Image – satisfies" (J 271 / ). 26 I have discussed "The Single Screw of Flesh" in Emily Dickinson: A Voice of War (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1984). 27 Jacques Derrida, Spurs: Nietzsche's Styles (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1978), p. 65: Nietzsche is "a thinker of pregnancy, which for him is no less praiseworthy in a man than it is in a woman." BGE 232 / GS 72 28 R. Howard Bloch discusses this traditional association with its implications for language and the sign in "Medieval Misogyny," Representations 20, Fall 1987, 1-24. Friedrich Nietzsche, Beyond Good and Evil 29 Eric Blondel, "Nomad Thought," The New Nietzsche ed. David Allison, (Cambridge, Mass: The MIT Press, 1986), 150-175, p. 156. Blondel also discusses the veil in Nietzsche. 30 Cambridge History IV 31 Jane Donahue Eberwein, Strategies of Limitation (Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, 1987), p. 199. 32Gelpi, the Mind of the Poet 97; Gelpi, Mind of Poet 97; 105 "oblivious to the ethical preoccupations of Emerson and Thoreau; 108 cultivation of consciousness her religion In The Tenth Muse, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), Gelpi pursues the psychological meaning of the circumference, as verging into eternity p. 270. 33 Dwight Eddins, "Dickinson and Nietzsche: The Rites of Dionysus," ESQ Vol 27, 2nd Quarter, 1981, 96-107, p. 101. Cf. Northrop Frye, Fables of Identity (NY: Harcourt, Brace & World, 1963) p. 212, where he associates ecstasy with Circumference Eddins focuses mainly on The Birth of Tragedy and reads its Dionysianism as metaphysical, a reading that has been much contested. See David Allison, "Nietzsche Knows no Noumenon," bpimdary 2 9: 3 Spring autumn 1981 295-310 as non-metaphysical. Of course Heidegger famously saw Nietzsche as an inversion of Plato, and hence metaphysical in his antimetaphysics. See Nietzsche. Vol One The Will to Power as Art, trans. David Krell (San Francisco: Harper and Row Publishers, Inc. 1978), pp. 200-20; " the true and apparent worlds have exchanged places, ranks and forms But in this exchange and reversal just that distinction between a true and apparent world is maintained, (p. 622). Heidegger's metaphysical interpretation of Nietzsche considers the "Will to Power" as an in-itself, and eternal return as appearance in phenomena, duplicating traditional ontology. For discussion see Ernst Behler, "Nietzsche in the Twentieth Century," Cambridge Companion to Nietzsche,281-322, p. 312; David Farrell rell, "Art and Truth in Raging Discord: Heidegger and Nietzsche on the Will to Power, boundary 2 4:2 Winter 1976, 378-392. 34 Tenth Muse, p. 269 35 Both Eberwein and Gelpi read this poem as accomplishing Romance possession of knight to bride, a "union of bride and knight, Circumference and Awe" (Gelpi, Mind of Poet; p. 126) "Art pressing perpetually at the limits of mortal expression" as a "knight on a quest for this great boon representing the ultimate reach of human aspiration" circumference as death joined in Wolosky EDFN 35 loving union with Awe" 194 as stronger mysterious force beyond humanly experienced boundaries." 36 Cf the interplay of "possession" and "awe" in: Peril as a Possession 'Tis Good to bear Danger disintegrates Satiety There's Basis there – Begets an awe That searches Human Nature's creases As clean as Fire (J 1678 / ) Here "Possession" is itself a "peril." To think we claim, we own, creates a "Satiety" that is ultimately stultifying. Conversely, the "Danger that disintegrates" "Begets an awe" over what we do not possess. "Human Nature" itself is not unitary nor seamless, but (in an imagery of sewing) riven with "creases." At this poem's center is an apparent tautology, but in fact works as oxymoron: "There's Basis there." For "Basis," foundation, is precisely what is not "there." Neither self nor experience nor world constitutes a stable, possessible ground, but only an incessantly changing position, a disintegrative force dangerous to "Satieties." The final image of "Fire" may recall the Heraclatean one so central to Nietzsche, with fire, as Giles Deleuze notes, a Nietzschean trope of transformation.36 The only "Basis" is one that keeps shifting, launching further standpoints that never, however, securely stand. 37 This is Michael Haar's interpretation of eternal return, Nietzsche and Metaphysics (NY: State University of New York Press, 1996), pp. 28, 31-32. He quotes Nietzsche, "Let us impress upon our life the image of eternity," and comments: "The 'circle' is itself imperfect. The totality of Return is a shattered totality." Cf. Thomas Altizer "Eternal Recurrence and the Kingdom of God" 232-243. check Heidegger. 38 This is De Man's reading in "Rhetoric of Tropes (Nietzsche), 103 – 118. Referring to "Truth and Lie," De Man sees the fact that language is "rhetorical" rather than "representational" 106 as a dissolution of the "literal" and hence any sense of truth altogether: "By asserting in the mode of truth that the self is a lie, we have not escaped from deception" 112. The Nietzsche text is itself one of self-undoing: "The authoritative claims that it seems to makecan be undermined by means of statements provided by the text itself." 117. J. Hillis Miller similarly reads language in Nietzsche as an irresolvable "entangling net," in which he is caught as an "impasse he is attempting to describe" p.42. reading in "Disremembering and disremembering in Nietzsche's "On Truth and Lies in a Non-moral Sense" boundary 2 (Vol. 9, No. 3) Syposium Why Nietzsche Now" (Spring-autumn, 1981) 41-54. 39 Foucault's famous essay on "Freud, Described by Alan Schrift in "Nietzsche's French Legacy" (CC to N): Foucault focused not on the subjects of power but on power relations, power relations in the absence of a sovereign subject; 340 Foucault: Each sign is in itself not the thing that presents itself to interpretation, but the interpretation of other signs. Nietzsche, Freud, Marx in Transforming the Hermeneutic Context 59- 67 Deleuze; Wolosky EDFN 36 40 Cornel West, "Nietzsche's Prefiguration of Postmodern American Philosophy" boundary 2 Vol 9 no. 3, 241-269, pp. 241, 243, 264. . check critical reader 41 Jean Granier, "Perspectivism and Interpretation" in The New Nietzsche 190-200, 194-195, 197. Granier writes other positive readings: cf essays in Yirmiyahu Yovel, ed. Nietzsche as Affirmative Thinker (Martinus Nijhoff Publishers 1986). Other positive readings of Nietzschean nihilism can be found in Alexander Nehamas "Nietzsche, modernity, aestheticism" 223-251 disputes what he takes to be Rorty's view of Nietzsche as abandoning himself to a blind contingency. (231) and mere goallessness. 232 No real world doesn't mean no world, Cambridge Companion to Nietzsche ed. Bernd Magnus and Kathleen M. Higgins (NY: Cambridge University Press 1996) Alan White describes Nietzsche in terms of pluralist models, p. 135. Lyotard, too, reads Nietzsche in terms of multiple and discordant voices. 42 Cf. WP 605 The ascertaining of "truth" and "untruth," the ascertaining of facts in general, is fundamentally different from creative positing, from forming, shaping, overcoming, willing, . . . to introduce a meaning – this task l remains to be done, assuming there is no meaning yet. Thus it is with sounds, but also with the fate of peoples: they are capable of the most different interpretations and direction toward different goals. 43 This is one of the Dickinson poems translated by Paul Celan. I have analyzed it and its translation in "Emily Dickinson and Paul Celan: Trajectories of Mysticism" Ein Vogel, einer, um halb vier: dem Himmel, der da schwieg, den einen Laut trug er ihm an sparsamster Melodie. Das war die Probe. Um halb fu"nf gingsu" ber sie hinaus, und sieh: ihr silbernes Zuerst stach alles andre aus. Halb sieben: weder Element noch Werkzeug weit und breit. Ein Ort hier, dort die Gegenwart, mit einem Zwischenkreis. 44 This linguistic imagery is evident in a companion poem, "The Birds begun at Four o'clock" (J 783) where the the birds' song is described as "Voices" that "multiply."