Shamir, Background Materials 1 BACKGROUND MATERIALS BEFORE READING THE DRAFT CHAPTER ANTI TRAFFICKING IN ISRAEL: NATIONALISM, BORDERS, MARKETS HILA SHAMIR Dear readers, The chapter you are about to read is part of a book titled GOVERNANCE FEMINISM: AN INTRODUCTION, co-authored with Janet Halley, Prabha Kotiswaran, Rachel Rebouche and myself. Some of the background for this chapter will be provided in other chapters of the book. To assist reading this chapter as a stand-alone, please find below an expanded glossary of terms. The terms I explain are Governance Feminism, Trafficking, Feminist positions on sex work, and Neo-abolitionism. Thank you for taking the time to read the chapter! Hila Governance Feminism Taken from the DRAFT introduction to: Janet Halley, Prabha Kotiswaran, Rachel Rebouche and Hila Shamir, GOVERNANCE FEMINISM: AN INTRODUCTION (Minnesota University Press, Forthcoming 2014/5) [ footnotes omitted]. Feminists now walk the halls of power. By no means all feminists: some forms of feminism disqualify their proponents from inclusion in the power elite. But you can get a job in the UN, the World Bank, the International Criminal Court, in the local prosecutor’s office, and the child welfare bureaucracy for espousing dominant strands of feminism. Exactly what forms of feminism “make sense” to previously entirely male power elites, find their way into legal institutions, and change legal thought and legal operations? Whose NGOs get funding from international aid and development agencies and from ideologically-driven private donors? Once feminists gain a foothold in governance, what do they do there and which particular legal forms are they most heavily invested in? What are the distributive consequences of the partial inclusion of some feminist projects? Where does feminism succeed in mainstreaming its policies and does this success also bear some traceable systemic costs? Can feminism foster a critique of its own successes? We have dubbed our topic Governance Feminism (GF). We mean by that every form in which feminists and feminist ideas get incorporated into state, state-like, and state-affiliated power. Shamir, Background Materials 2 In the first section of this Preface, we explain what we mean by governance. In the second we explain what we mean by feminism. In the third we present a range of attitudes feminists have adopted to the surprising experience of wielding power, and offer a way of talking about that power that seeks to describe it accurately while leaving plenty of room both for affirmation and critique. In the final section, we set forth the traditions of critique which we find most useful for assessing GF. 1. Governance Feminism Many terms have been invented to describe particular phases of GF: state feminism, carceral feminism, femocrats, Special Advisors on Gender Violence … the list is long. Each of them focuses on a specific governmental form – in the list we just gave, the state, the penal state, state bureaucracy, legally authorized experts, respectively -- which feminists and feminism have found to be at least somewhat hospitable. We have selected as an overarching term governance feminism in order to embrace them all: any form of state, state-like or state-affiliated power is, we presuppose, capable of being infiltrated by feminists and feminist ideas. Like many other students of the contemporary legal order, we are struck by the real-world proliferation of forms of organized power that break the bounds of the classically imagined state., and like them we find the term governance useful to describe the resulting expansion of institutional forms and social practices. These are forms of power that operate immanently as well as top-down; that facilitate and inherit state power from outside the state; that shimmer back and forth across the private/public distinction. All of international law has this interstitial character, however much it mimes the trappings of state power, and it has been an extraordinarily fecund site for the invention of new modes of power: the reporting system that most treaty bodies substitute for adjudication, for instance, has produced an immense discursive network of text exchange in which a huge array of players can manage and mediate treaty-based norms. But states when they appoint commissions to examine and report on controversial problems, hire private contractors to execute governmental functions, and incorporate –sometimes even “certifying” as superlegitimate – so-called Non-Governmental Organizations or NGOs to do their propaganda and fact-generating functions. GF arose precisely when national governments and international governance bodies were increasingly incorporating non-traditional political actors, such as NGOs and experts of various civil society associations, in their governance structures and decision-making processes. Internationally, feminists helped to foment this trend in a wide array of concerted efforts ranging from the UN Conferences on Women to intense advocacy the international criminal tribunals addressed to the Yugoslavian and Rwandan conflicts. Domestically these efforts included, for example, concerted pressure to institutionalize domestic violence and trafficking law reforms, to police Shamir, Background Materials 3 deadbeat dads, to extend rights to reproductive health services, and to convert rape from forced sex into unconsented-to sex. At first we thought that the flagship GF successes were all concentrated on sexual violence and envisioned law as primarily punitive (what Elizabeth Bernstein calls “carceral feminism”); and indeed this formulation describes a great deal of national and international GF today. Indeed, the appetite of many strands of feminism for government through prohibition and punishment is one of the most striking features of GF today. Male sexual wrongdoing – sometimes exemplified by rape, sometimes by prostitution – is understood to be crime and to require prosecution, conviction, and intensely stigmatizing and painful punishment. But the subjects of GF include women in the workplace, women seeking to have children or end pregnancies, women in the family, women on corporate boards and women in the public sphere, and GF seems to accommodate feminists of all stripes. GF has thus hefted every legal tool imaginable, somewhere, sometime. The forms in which feminists exercise power have thus tracked the vast expansion of public/private alliances which now govern human life at every level, from the local to the international and back. Indeed, in our account, GF and governance-throughNGOs co-constituted themselves starting in the late 1980’s. The rise of the NGOsphere and of international GF were not merely coincident in time: they fostered and shaped each other. GF has also been highly productive of feminism as a governmental savoir or “power/knowledge” in the Foucaultian sense. The .most obvious and study-able form of this is the appointment of legal officials and private advisors specifically for their ability to produce feminism as governmental reason. Feminism as expertise is personified in UN Special Rapporteurs on Gender Violence, the Special Advisor to the Prosecutor on Gender Violence at the International Criminal Court, and the Outside Consultative Group on Gender to the World Bank. In the US, an entire industry advises employers and universities on compliance with Title VII and Title VIII sexual harassment law: ever since the Supreme Court gave organizations a defense in court if they administered sexual harassment claims rationally, feminist rationality on unwanted sexual conduct has become a necessary element of legal compliance. %%add NG and feminists within the NG movement, Sturm, employment. As these feminist govermentalities become legal, social, cultural and/or ideological common sense, they disappear into the light of common day. Studying them is like watching a drop of water hitting the larger pool of water below: at first we see ripples, but soon the surface is perfectly smooth and the drop dissolves into the whole. The specifically feminist character of the legal intervention disappears. And many legal orders demand this neutrality in exchange for legitimacy: feminist judges, Shamir, Background Materials 4 feminist policy makers, feminist experts must obey the rituals of rule of law, objectivity and legal rationality to stay in power. They often don’t look feminist at all to the genealogically innocent eye. Studying GF that has reached this stage of incorporation can be difficult. For instance, a vast range of jobs at the national and international level now make feminism of one sort or other their qualifying expertise. GF functions as a full employment act for Women’s, Gender and Sexuality Studies graduates. But as this process unfolds, the specific feminist impulse that gave rise to these new jobs fades, the feminist idea-set of the job gets routinized, and bureaucratic motives take over. Joanne Sandler, a major figure in UN Women, noted in 2012 that she “ … now meet[s] an increasing number of ‘career’ civil servants – from within the UN system or from government or academia – who join UN Women or gender units of other UN organisations to advance their careers.” These new GFeminists deserve the name not because of their feminist ideology or feminist passion for justice but because of the institutional mandate they serve. As this process enters its third decade, GF has been, in some cases, highly successful in changing laws, institutions and practices. None of us would have academic jobs or the time and resources to study GF if these successes had not buoyed us throughout our upbringing and our careers: by reducing sexual violence through criminalization and stigma, by opening opportunities in education and the professions, by making marriage and other forms of intimate partnerships more equalitarian in the distribution both of work and of property, GF has made us possible. But in our view it has also done considerable damage: many GF projects, some of them described in detail below, strike us as terrible mistakes. And many feminist visions of emancipation have been left at the station when the governance train took off: what Kerry Rittich calls the “selective incorporation” of feminist ideas into governmental power selected some real duds while leaving some diamonds in the dust. One reason to study GF is precisely to take stock of these changes across their full range. In other words, GF has produced immense changes, most of them positive, in the lives of women, who enjoy more equality, more autonomy, and a greater share of the world’s wealth because of feminism in power. But there are costs. Women benefit differentially; some are harmed; and conflicts among feminists about what worlds to imagine are prematurely settled. Merging into the mainstream can efface the feminist fingerprints on important governance projects and preclude intra-feminist politics about them. It can consolidate a particularistic, identity-based project, sometimes at the expense of alternative affiliations that ignore the siren call of victimization and identity as prerequisites for legal intelligibility. Some of the best things within and about feminism get left out. For all these reasons, recovering the specifically feminist ideas that animate GF strikes us as an urgent project – but one which, we think, should be approached with scholarly care and political vision. Shamir, Background Materials 5 2. Governance Feminism Feminist ideas and feminists travel. The remarkable success of GFeminists in international organizations like the UN and the World Bank, in the Rome Statute establishing the International Criminal Court, and in treaty commitments ranging from the Convention on the Elimination of Discrimination against Women and the Palermo Protocol against Human Trafficking, means that law itself is a transmission vehicle for GF and thus for feminism. Also the NGO-sphere, powered by government grants, deep-pocketed private donors and internet activism, move feminist norms and practices around the world, from many centers of feminist production to innumerable local sites of feminist engagement. And in locales across the world, local feminisms thrive and welcome, grudgingly accommodate and resist these feminisms coming from “outside.” The study of GF is necessarily a comparative project, tracing genealogies of transmission – of production and reception – from the international to the local and back again, from center to periphery and back again, from the ivory tower to the street and back again. And because feminism now takes governance forms, the struggle over production, transmission and reception of feminist people, ideas and practices is achieved not only through their intrinsic charisma: sometimes it happens at the end of a gun. This book is structured to give examples of the ways feminist ideas travel. [SET OUT THE CHAPTERS] For all that we emphasize local sites of feminist production all over the world, the ascendency of the US in the post-Soviet era means that, within GF, Unitedstatesean feminisms have a salience and transportability that feminisms emerging elsewhere don’t enjoy. Indeed, Unitedstatesean feminism, like US citizens, has a passport that can travel almost everywhere without applying for an entry visa: this very salience and transportability have made Unitedstatesean feminism a little deaf to its own limits and to the intense resistance it has provoked among some nonUS-based feminists. What we are about to describe is thus both a Model and an AntiModel. Still, we think it worthwhile, right at the outset, to sketch the tools available within Unitedstatesean feminism pretty starkly. At certain points, this examination necessarily tracks alliances between Unitedstatesean feminists and those from elsewhere. Unitedstatesean feminism is a sustained disagreement about sex, sexuality, gender and the family among people who share a central, sometimes pivotal or indispensable, commitment to the emancipation of things F – women, femininity, female or feminine genders, mothers, daughters … the list is long. But patterns are discernible. Feminisms that accentuate power hierarchies differ from those that see cultural values as the key; and feminisms that discern inequality rather than domination speak very differently about injustice and emancipation from each other Shamir, Background Materials 6 and from feminisms that attend to maldistribution. Each of these emphases comes in various radical and mild forms. Feminisms that see men, male domination or masculinist values as the problem differ from those that see everyone’s gender as the problem. Feminisms that emphasize sex and sexuality as the problem read different traditions and identify different realities than those emphasizing reproduction and the family. Finally, feminsms that can take on board that there are other problems in the world than m/f, gender, or their variants -- that are just as committed to working on race or colonialism or global warming – are very different from those whose basic thought rule is that all “intersecting” power or cultural bad-things must ultimately be understood as part of the problem and of the solution proposed by feminism. To make it even more complicated, American feminists often carry all these ideas in their consciousness as ambivalences and contradictions that they see no need to resolve into logical purity. And finally, feminist internal critique flourishes – in some zones more than in others – and we value it so highly that we give special attention in this Introduction to its forms, methods, and special capacities. In the rest of this section we name and describe some of those contestant theories. We leave out many important forms of contemporary feminism that work in the media of culture: fashion, internet and social media, art, literary criticism;religion, food politics, wellness and healing, pedagogy … the list could go on and on. We mention here only those that have a noticeable will to power in a governmental form and therefore can be expected to show up as new forms of governance feminism. These include liberal feminism; dominance feminism in its two forms, cultural feminism and power feminism; critical-race, intersectionality and postcolonial feminism; gender-transitivity feminism; and Marxist/socialist/materialist/labor feminism. Of these, the three that have made it deepest into governance today are liberal feminism and dominance feminism in its two forms, cultural and power feminisms. We follow our thumbnail synopsis of them, therefore, with a section on the alliances they have formed with each other as they seek to meet the conditions required for admittance to the power table. What is Human Trafficking under International Law? Taken from: Hila Shamir, A Labor Paradigm for Human Trafficking, 60 UCLA LAW REVIEW 76, 84-91 (2012) [footnotes omitted]). Human trafficking has garnered significant national and international attention in the last decade. Yet the legal interest in trafficking is by no means a new trend. In 1904, an international treaty on trafficking was adopted, followed by conventions signed in 1910, 1921, 1933, and 1950. This first generation of anti- trafficking conventions reflected an understanding of trafficking that differs from the term’s contemporary application. Albeit refraining from an explicit definition of human trafficking, these instruments sought to address what was known at the time as the “white slave trade” Shamir, Background Materials 7 the movement of women and girls across borders for the purpose of prostitution. The second, contemporary wave of anti-trafficking instruments began in the 1990s, culminating in the introduction of the Trafficking Protocol under the aegis of the UNODC in 2000. The protocol adopted a comprehensive and broad definition of trafficking, covering the experiences of both men and women in forced labor, servitude, slavery or slavery-like practices, and organ removal, within or beyond the borders of their countries of origin. Under article 3 of the protocol, trafficking comprises three components: (1) a particular action—“the recruitment, transportation, transfer, harbouring or receipt of persons”; (2) certain means for carrying out the action—“the threat or use of force or other forms of coercion, of abduction, of fraud, of deception, of the abuse of power or of a position of vulnerability or of the giving or receiving of payments or benefits to achieve the consent of a person having control over another person”; and (3) the end purpose of exploitation. The protocol defines exploitation sweepingly to include, at a minimum, “the exploitation of the prostitution of others or other forms of sexual exploitation, forced labour or services, slavery or practices similar to slavery, servitude or the removal of organs.” This broad definition is considered one of the protocol’s most significant achievements in that it is gender neutral and extends beyond sex trafficking to include various types of labor market exploitation, even when within the borders of the victim’s own country. Although the protocol’s trafficking definition attempts to clarify the forms trafficking can take, there is still some ambiguity regarding the purpose and means components of the definition. To begin with, the term “exploitation” is not defined in the protocol, creating uncertainty as to the conditions under which exploitation amounts to trafficking. Likewise, the elements listed under the means component are not defined, raising the question of the level of coercion and abuse of power required to satisfy this factor of the definition. It is quite clear, of course, that not all detrimental employment practices should be identified as trafficking, and that a certain “seriousness” threshold, accepted by the majority of activists and scholars, must be met for a practice to be considered trafficking. Yet the precise contours of this threshold are unclear, and so uncertainty remains as to what exactly constitutes trafficking. Despite this definitional vagueness, the national and international experience with applying the international definition has given content to the means element of the definition. For example, it is now quite clear that physical coercion is not required for a practice to constitute trafficking and that relatively subtler forms of intimidation suffice. Indeed, the practices of withholding wages or identification papers, continually threatening to expose a worker’s undocumented status to authorities, and using indebted labor (bonded labor or indentured labor) are all understood to satisfy the means element. Moreover, abduction or deception regarding the type and nature of work (for example, a false promise that upon arrival the woman will work as a waitress when actually she is forced into prostitution) are not the only behaviors that Shamir, Background Materials 8 may lead to human trafficking. In fact, many migrant workers who were trafficked appear to have voluntarily embarked on their journeys, seeking paid employment in a line of work they had agreed to join in advance. Trafficking is often recognized in circumstances of exploitation and manipulation that relate not only to the type of work one is made to engage in but to the working conditions in an agreed upon type of work. This includes situations in which a worker agrees to do a certain job, yet does not consent to some of the working conditions, such as restrictions on freedom of movement, long working hours, excessive wage deductions, delayed payment, and low wages. Human trafficking emerges, therefore, as a combination of labor rights violations, where each one alone might not amount to trafficking. There is a great diversity of human trafficking contexts. Indeed, various labor sectors, such as construction, agriculture, domestic work, and sex work, have been identified in the last decade as tending to include trafficked labor. Trafficking can be found in private homes in the United Kingdom in the abuse of Filipina domestic workers employed through special guest worker visas. It includes the situations of workers in traditional debt bondage systems in South Asia, in which repayment of the debts incurred by previous generations is part of the workers’ terms of employment. Children forced to beg in the streets of Senegal and the age-old practice of enslaving men, women, and children in Mauritania are also manifestations of human trafficking. Other trafficked persons are the male Thai workers on pineapple farms in the state of Washington, who are forced to live in inhumane conditions and are effectively imprisoned, and South Asian migrant construction workers in Bahrain, whose wages are often withheld and passports confiscated and who are exposed to unsafe housing and physical abuse. Trafficking can be found in the French sex industry, in which Eastern European women are held in debt bondage, as well as on Thai fishing boats, where Cambodian workers are subjected to violence, intimidation, imprisonment, and precarious working conditions. Yet despite this breadth of contexts and the multifaceted manifestations of trafficking, global attention and enforcement efforts remain focused to a large extent on the movement of women and girls across borders into the sex industry. Indeed, the term “trafficking” is often conflated with prostitution. The Trafficking Protocol’s provisions, including its definition of trafficking itself, were the product of deliberations between states, intergovernmental organizations, nongovernmental organizations (NGOs), and a coalition of various UN agencies that took place in Vienna during the meetings of an ad hoc committee (under the auspices of the UNODC) known as the Vienna Process. The most well-documented struggle in the Vienna Process was waged among different feminist NGOs over the protocol’s view of consent in relation to prostitution. The battle over the nature of prostitution— whether it is work like any other work or violence against women—completely engaged the feminist bloc and diverted NGO attention away from other critical aspects of the protocol being negotiated— in particular, issues of human rights and Shamir, Background Materials 9 labor rights. The NGOs’ preoccupation with prostitution distracted their lobbying efforts away from other issues and enabled the states’ security interest in curbing illegal migration to determine most elements of the protocol. The protocol sets three main categories of state obligations, commonly referred to as the “3 Ps”: prevention of trafficking, protection of victims from trafficking, and prosecution of traffickers. The protocol’s strongest obligatory language refers to the criminalization of trafficking, the protection of borders, and the collaboration between state parties on victim repatriation. With regard to victim protection, the protocol uses mostly nonbinding formulations. Its emphasis on a transnational crime framework greatly influenced state behavior and led to the proliferation of laws criminalizing trafficking and, possibly, to the strengthening of border control. In fact, the criminalization of trafficking was the most common measure undertaken by states after ratifying the protocol. This reflects the fact that states were chiefly concerned with transnational crime and illegal migration and not human rights or workers’ rights. Accordingly, the protocol’s most impactful component ended up being the transnational crime framework it established, which focuses on the challenge faced by states in dealing with criminal networks that cross national borders. Alongside this transnational crime framework, however, the protocol also promoted a human rights framework to anti-trafficking, particularly in its implementation dynamics. As explained above, its language allowed for a broad definition of trafficking that encompasses many, if not most, contemporary forms of labor exploitation. Moreover, during the Vienna Process, a coalition of NGOs and UN agencies managed to ensure that the protocol set standards regarding the protection and support of trafficking victims. In contrast to the strong obligatory language relating to criminalization and border control, however, the victim protection and assistance clauses are formulated in mostly discretionary language. Government delegates from destination countries (countries to which persons are trafficked) rejected proposed mandatory obligations to safeguard the human rights of nonnationals, preferring instead to leave such protections to states’ discretion. And indeed, the central victim protection and assistance clauses in the protocol (articles 6, 7, and 9) use discretionary, nonbinding language. Although the protocol’s human rights victim–centered framework contains important preventive and protective measures directed at both the pretrafficking and posttrafficking stages, it fails to address in any meaningful way the working conditions in the labor sectors in which people are trafficked or the structural labor market components that enable trafficking. Indeed, in the negotiations over the Trafficking Protocol, there was almost no representation of a labor approach to trafficking, which is thus similarly almost completely absent in its implementation. Feminist Positions on the Regulation of Sex Work and Sex Trafficking Shamir, Background Materials 10 Taken from Janet Halley, Prabha Kotiswaran, Hila Shamir & Chantal Thomas, From the International to the Local in Feminist Legal Responses to Rape, Prostitution/Sex Work and Sex Trafficking: Four Studies in Contemporary Governance Feminism, 29(2) HARVARD JOURNAL OF LAW & GENDER 335, 338-339 (2006) [footnotes omitted] There is a wide range of regulatory modes specific to sex work and sex trafficking regimes, differently affecting the players we see as the key “stakeholders” in the regime: the sex worker, the pimp, the john, the brothel-keeper, and the landlord. Thus we will distinguish four “ideal types” of regulation: A complete criminalization regime criminalizes all aspects of sex work, so that both the sale and purchase of sex by the sex worker and the john, and all third party involvement (of the pimp, the brothel-keeper, and the landlord) can be prosecuted and punished criminally. An abolitionist or partial decriminalization regime decriminalizes the activities of sex workers alone, but criminalizes involvement of other actors in the sex industry, including customers. As we understand it, the term “abolition” is adopted to claim an analogy with 19th century American antislavery abolitionism. Decriminalizing sex worker involvement in sex work is motivated, in this formulation, by the assumption that sex workers are vulnerable victims of systematic patriarchal exploitation, and that at minimum the state should protect them by not criminalizing their sex work activity. Complete, as opposed to partial, decriminalization involves the repeal of any special criminal legislation dealing with sex work. Various activities involved in sex work can still be prosecuted as criminal offenses under generally applicable laws. Legalization involves complete decriminalization coupled with positive legal provisions regulating one or more aspect of sex work businesses. The typical options include labor law, employment law, zoning of sex businesses, compulsory medical check-ups, licensing of sex workers, etc. As far as we know, there is no GF project in sex trafficking/prostitution to promote complete criminalization; but feminists have differed sharply over the other four models. One striking agreement that emerged early in our conversations was that Gfeminists -- though they differ intensely, often bitterly -- all imagine their favored criminal law reform to operate by eliminating precisely and only the conduct it outlaws. This observation holds whether the method prefered is abolition or decriminalization: both are imagined to be directly liberatory for women. In our view however, all of these regimes can be given enhanced/intensified enforcement, on one hand, or weakened/partial enforcement, on the other; and different degrees of intensity can be exhibited even at the same moment by various administrative, judicial, and executive authorities. The complexity of the resulting bargaining endowments is considerable. We also take it as given that it would be rare to find any Shamir, Background Materials 11 of the “ideal typical” sex work regimes operating in its pure form. Rather we look for complex law-in-action/law-in-the-books contingency. The result is, we think, an exciting new research paradigm for feminists and non-feminists alike. We offer some thoughts on that in the conclusion. The Neo-Abolitionist Position on Sex Work in the US Taken from: Janie Chuang, Rescuing Trafficking from Ideological Capture: Prostitution Reform and Anti-Trafficking Law and Policy, 157 UNIVERSITY OF PENNSYLVANIA LAW REVIEW 1655, 1664-1669 [footnotes omitted]. Representing one main faction in the prostitution-reform debates are the neoabolitionists, an unusual alliance of feminists, neoconservatives, and evangelical Christians. The neo-abolitionists believe that prostitution is exploitative and degrading to women, a form of violence against women that should be abolished. Leading feminist thinkers in this camp include U.S.-based feminists identified with Catharine MacKinnon and sometimes referred to as “radical feminists,” including Kathleen Barry and Sheila Jeffreys. These feminists recognize no distinction between “forced” and “voluntary” prostitution. In their view, choice and consent are not possible because prostitution is an institution of male dominance and results from the absence of meaningful choices. Women who (believe they) choose prostitution suffer from a “false consciousness,” the inability to recognize their own oppression; whether or not these “prostituted women” seemingly consent, prostitution involves a violation of a human being. While some feminist neo-abolitionists very recently have begun to move away from this position by conceding the possibility of voluntary prostitution, they nonetheless support abolition on the ground that voluntary prostitutes represent only a small minority of “prostituted women.” Joining these feminists in their neo-abolitionist advocacy efforts are conservatives and evangelical Christians. Unlike their feminist allies, conservatives and Christian neo-abolitionists believe the wrong of prostitution lies in its departure from traditional social values rooted in heterosexual, patriarchal marriage and family, with sexuality expressed only within those confines. For conservatives and some Christian activists, women’s place is in the home rather than in the market; hence prostitution is “an issue of conscience and morality rather than of income possibilities and labor.” In contrast, liberal or moderate Christians may embrace women’s participation in the market— so long as the domestic sphere retains symbolic, if not actual, male headship—and apply a pro-business model of bringing women out of prostitution and into the (legitimate) service market. The varying perspectives underlying the feminist-conservativereligious coalition thus diverge over why prostitution should be abolished—to challenge patriarchal structural inequality or to sustain it. The neo-abolitionists are united, however, in strategically embracing the label “abolitionist” in a conscious effort to invoke an analogy to the nineteenth-century Shamir, Background Materials 12 campaigns to abolish the transatlantic slave trade. The “abolitionist” reference also revives early-twentieth-century feminists’ efforts to eradicate “white slavery,” which initially referred to the “system of licensed prostitution in existence throughout much of Europe and parts of the United States.” Perceiving prostitution as an international problem, these early feminists focused their attention and rhetoric on the international “traffic” of women and girls. The “white slavery abolitionists,” of whom Josephine Butler is most renowned, felt that “government-licensed prostitution institutionalized the oppression and corruption of women and was not successful in stemming the spread of venereal disease.” But “white slavery” soon became synonymous with all prostitution, licensed and unlicensed, and what began as a feminist movement against state regulation and licensing of prostitution ultimately became a broader “social purity crusade to abolish prostitution” writ large. Fueled by conservative attitudes toward women’s sexuality and concerns over a link between prostitution and disfavored racial minorities, the movement targeted the “export” or “‘trafficking’ of ‘white’ women from Europe and North America for the purposes of prostitution” by foreign or immigrant men in the colonial nether regions of Asia, Africa, and South America. Though the “white slavery” phenomenon “eventually proved to be far smaller and [less] []significant than popularly depicted,” the movement yielded a series of international laws on “white slavery” and “trafficking” beginning in 1904 and culminating in the 1949 Convention for the Suppression of the Traffic in Persons and of the Exploitation of the Prostitution of Others (1949 Convention). As Diane Otto explains, “[b]y constructing the ‘problem’ as one of slavery rather than prostitution, these instruments projected the idea that European women could not conceivably ‘consent’ to sex work, especially not with foreign clients.” Although the rhetoric equating prostitution with trafficking and slavery made it into international law, the 1949 Convention had little impact on the behavior of states, including on their interactions with each other on the issue. Few states were signatories, and the treaty lacked an effective monitoring mechanism to ensure state compliance. Modern-day anti-prostitution feminists and their conservative and religious allies have resurrected the abolitionist rhetoric, targeting prostitution on a global level. As Jeffreys explains, prostitution is unequivocally damaging to all women, in that if one woman is a prostitute, all women can be treated as prostitutes. Because “voluntary” prostitution is almost certainly an ontological impossibility, the failure of states to prohibit prostitution violates women’s right to sexual autonomy. […] Neo-abolitionists embrace the power of criminal law to combat prostitution and generally favor the toleration approach. They believe in the expressive role of criminal law to stigmatize the buyers of sex as socially or morally tainted: in their opinion, pimps, brothel owners and managers, clients, and any third parties who assist women to travel and work in the sex industry should be prosecuted for rape, trafficking, or both. Meanwhile, whether because they are victims of male patriarchy or because they are victims of social deviance, women prostitutes should not be Shamir, Background Materials 13 penalized themselves but instead should be the target of rescue and rehabilitation efforts. Because prostitution is (almost always) coerced or forced, anti-trafficking laws are a legitimate vehicle for pursuing abolition of prostitution. The definition of trafficking should eliminate any distinction between forced and voluntary prostitution, thus enabling its application to prostitution writ large.