COPYRIGHT NOTE: UNDER REVIEW: TO QUOTE, PLEASE, CONTACT THE AUTHOR The Rhetoric of Skinner and Laclau: Critical Approaches to Politics Emilia Palonen, PhD University of Helsinki Contact details: Email: emiliapalonen@yahoo.co.uk Tel: 00-358-40 5077198 18 October 2006 - 1 March 2007: Bauhaus Kolleg, Gropiusallee 38, D-06846 Dessau, Germany Fax: +49 (0)340-6508-404 Acknowledgements: Earlier versions of this paper have been discussed at the University of Essex and Finnish Doctoral School of Politics and International Relations, in 2004, and at the seminar on 'Concepts, Discourse and Rhetoric' at the Collegium Budapest and the 'Politics and Rhetoric' workshop at Manchester Workshops on Political Theory, in September 2006. I would like to thank all my colleagues for their comments on the earlier versions of this paper, in particular Mercedes Barros, Alan Finlayson, James Martin, Aletta Norval, Kari Palonen and Márton Szabó. I also must thank Alejandro Groppo for his course on rhetoric at the Essex Summer School in Discourse Theory in 2004. The Rhetoric of Skinner and Laclau: Critical Approaches to Politics UNDER REVIEW: TO QUOTE, PLEASE, CONTACT THE AUTHOR (emiliapalonen@yahoo.co.uk) Submitted to: Contemporary Political Theory Word count: 6995 Abstract This paper explores the relationship between the work of two intriguing but relatively understudied contemporary political thinkers: Ernesto Laclau and Quentin Skinner. Laclau, coming from a leftist Gramscian and Althusserian tradition, has been a major influence upon post-Marxist thought and the 'theory of hegemony'. His approach has been taken up by the 'Essex school' of ideology and discourse analysis, which draws on continental thought from Derrida to Lacan. Skinner, a contemporary of Laclau’s and a central figure within the nearby 'Cambridge school' of political thought, has reappropriated and redefined Machiavelli and Hobbes as political thinkers and generally promoted republican political thought, political rhetoric and conceptual history. The two thinkers are here located in the same postNietzschean tradition of political rhetoric, pointing out the similarities and compatibility between their approaches. Furthermore, looking at the rhetorical tropes they use and base their political thought upon, I will discuss the applicability of their theories in the context of empirical political praxis. This will reveal some of the crucial insights the authors offer for critical approaches to politics. Keywords: Ernesto Laclau, Quentin Skinner, rhetoric, discourse, political theory, social forums. -The linguistic turn in the study of politics has drawn greater attention to the workings of discourses and rhetoric (e.g. Norval 2000, Finlayson 2004). Writing on renaissance thought, Quentin Skinner has been influential in renewing critical attention to rhetorical traditions of politics – for him rhetoric has offered the way to see how things could, in fact, have turned out differently, be otherwise. He is well known for his work on early modern political philosophy, starting from the Foundations of Modern Political Thought, his work on Hobbes (1996) and Machiavelli (1981), and the concept of Liberty (1998).1 Ernesto Laclau, developing his 'discourse theory', has shifted his emphasis from Derridian and Lacanian thought towards rhetoric – as another reiteration of his theory of hegemony (Laclau 2005). He and Chantal Mouffe authored Hegemony and Socialist Strategy (1985), shaking up Western Marxism and setting an agenda for new social movements.2 He has subsequently developed his theory in the light of the changes in South Africa and Eastern Europe in New Reflections of the Revolutions of Our Time (1990) and Emancipation(s) (1996), before turning his attention to populism in his most recent work On Populist Reason (2005). The attempt to bring these thinkers’ work together may appear to yield an odd combination, setting the work of a post-Marxist political theorist of Argentinean origin whose focus has been upon social movements and revolutions alongside that of a British historian of political thought working on liberalism and republicanism.3 As with any repetition and combination, this will involve a rearticulation – even to the extent that it may appear to contradict common readings of the authors’ aims. The more radical move, in the case of Laclau, is the deuniversalisation of catachresis and the category of hegemony. In the case of Skinner, it means making a connection from paradiastole to catachresis and applying it to political fora beyond the conventional republican tradition. In this, paper, rhetoric is seen as both rhetoricity and tropology rather than as mere parole, speech, writing or even symbols. This enables one to see how forms of thought and political moves being employed in the articulation of ideas. Rhetoric provides a way to understand political moves or processes. The tropes one thinks with matter. One can recognize the crux of the thought of the author by pondering on the trope he or she uses. Furthermore, each trope propose different the forms of political action. Crucially, both Skinner and Laclau have singled out their favourite tropes. Skinner is the theorist of paradiastole, i.e. the ‘crossing of the floor’ or a redescriptive political change, achieved by changing the normative content of a concept. Laclau is a theorist of catachresis, i.e. the ‘naming the unnameable’ or 'giving a name to something that did not already have a name', which may imply the transformation of the discursive field (field of relations and identifications) through an emergence of unity. The first part of this paper links the thought of the two authors, through their writings on rhetoric. The second part analyses the two tropes and discuss the differences and similarities in Laclau and 1 Skinner’s thought, and their approach to rhetoric as political theory. The third part, contesting some preconceptions, discusses briefly the two tropes as they relate to two fora of politics: the parliament and the social forum. Ultimately, the paper suggests that paradiastole and catachresis are complimentary in politics. Perhaps in a Skinnerian vain and as a response to Laclau’s definitions of catachresis, affording particularity to a trope rather than stressing its universality improves our understanding of what is really happening in political action and/as redescription. Crucially, as the discussion shows, paradiastole is an internal moment of catachresis and can be catachrestical, and yet also a political logic separate from catachresis. Post-Nietzschean political thought Crucially, both authors come from the Nietzschean tradition of rhetoric, emphasized in their anti-positivism and anti-essentialism. Here, the discovery of creative subjectivity and the realisation of the relativity of 'truths' is vital. Nietzsche (1974, 180) writes: What therefore is truth? A mobile army of metaphors, metonymies, anthropomorphisms: in short a sum of human relations which become poetically and rhetorically intensified, metamorphosed, adorned, and after a long usage seem to a nation fixed, canonic and binding; truths are illusions of which one has forgotten that they are illusions… And continues later: Only by forgetting that primitive world of metaphors, only by the congelation and coagulation of an original mass of similes and percepts pouring forth as a fiery liquid out of the primal faculty of human fancy, only by the invincible faith, that this sun, this window, this table is a truth in itself: in short only by the fact that man forgets himself as a subject, and what is more as an artistically creating subject: only by all this does he live with some repose, safety and consequence. (84) To answer the question “why rhetoric?” for the two authors, I want to first draw attention to the main similarities between Laclau and Skinner's thought within the Nietzschean tradition, from which they derive a shared insistence upon contingency, the freedom and limits of language, performativity and relationality. Skinner (1999, 70) points out how Nietzsche was describing the method of paradiastolic redescription in his Genealogy of Morals, and its well known passage on how 'ideals are being fabricated'. Although neither of the authors started their careers as 'Nietzscheans', this is where their work can be placed. It is the first moment of combination in my paper. Reading Laclau and Skinner's texts on rhetoric, one of the main differences between the two authors and their approach to rhetoric is that Laclau tends to emphasize the idea of rhetoric as tropology (the study of tropes, figures of thought, models of language) whereas Skinner is more interested in the performative, persuasive aspect of rhetoric. Laclau seeks to form a parallel between his theory of hegemony and the trope of catachresis, which can be seen as emphasising the form of hegemony as a constellation over its character as a process. Indeed, in his latest work, On Populist Reason (2005), Laclau emphasizes the performativity of language – and the process of naming. For Skinner the crucial work on rhetoric is Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes (1996), although perhaps the most tangibly the trope that under focus in this paper paradiastole becomes through in his the work on Machiavelli 2 (1981). Both operate with historical examples, Skinner with intellectual history and Laclau with a collage of historical examples from political struggles. Contingency and language Rhetoric enables us to see the ultimate contingency of things and the power of articulation. Insisting on contingency, both Laclau (1985, 1990) and Skinner's (2002) work have rebelled against their respective intellectual traditions: Marxist and structuralist political thought and history of ideas. Terms are not necessarily tied to meanings. Concepts and discursive constructions are potentially open and they change, they argue. For Laclau there are no a priori political agents, such as 'class'. Both authors emphasize a concept of the political that focuses on articulation as a source of political changes and tool of political action. What is at stake is the process of fixing and unfixing. The persistence of contingency, even in moments of fixity, is crucial to understanding social phenomena. For example, 'society' for Laclau (1988) cannot exist in an exhaustive form or as a 'rational and intelligible object' of enquiry. The society can only exist as an open structure: 'The only democratic society is one which permanently shows the contingency of its own foundations - in our terms, permanently keeps open the gap between the ethical moment and the normative order.' (2000, 86) The emphasis on the contingency of foundations and the impossibility of a fixed societal order is aligned with the argument Skinner makes throughout his work, especially with the concept of liberty in its contexts. The gap between normative descriptions and the world is precisely what he stresses when writing about normative evaluative concepts (2002a, I, 182). To name this commonality, both Skinner (2002b, 51-53) and Laclau take up an anti-foundationalist position. The above implies that ultimately things are unfixed and this is a source of politics and freedom. The rhetoric approach reveals that language, while structuring thought, is also contingent: the fixations are temporary. 'Language, like other forms of social power, is of course a constraint, and it shapes us all', argues Skinner (2002a, I, 7), and continues: however, language is also a resource, and we can use it to shape our world. […] We are of course embedded in practices and constrained by them. But those practices owe their dominance in part to the power of our normative language to hold them in place, and it is always open to us to employ the resources of our language to undermine as well as to underpin those practices. We may be freer than we sometimes suppose. Laclau (2005, 109) also points to this emancipatory quality in language. Language not only forms a limit to contingency but also is limited by its own contingency. The method for contesting the limits for both Skinner and Laclau is rhetoric. Laclau (1988, 6) sees politics as a way to articulate fixity but argues that hegemonic articulations are in turn limited by the necessary unfixity of language and social relations. Skinner (2002a, I, 6) argues for the possibility to escape fixity in articulation, in the introduction to his methodological writings, which I have focused on in this piece. This awareness can help to liberate us from the grip of any one hegemonal account of those values and how they should be interpreted and understood. Equipped with a broader sense of possibility, we can stand back from the intellectual commitments we have inherited and ask ourselves in a new spirit of enquiry what we should think of them. This indicates a process between structures and action – freedom and limits. It also implies 3 that the difference between Laclau and Skinner lies in the fact that Laclau is more interested in the fixing of a new hegemonal account, while Skinner focuses on the dissolution of such fixity. Ultimately, if politics is seen as a cycle between fixing and unfixing, as the present author maintains, Laclau and Skinner are writing about two sides of the same coin. The Artistically Creative Subject As the Skinner quotes above indicate, to emphasize rhetoric means emphasizing performativity over fixed definitions. A similar emphasis upon performativity is present in Laclau's (2005, 97) recent work: A discussion of whether a just society will be brought about by a fascist or by a socialist order does not proceed as a logical deduction starting from a concept of 'justice' accepted by two sides, but through a radical investment whose discursive steps are not logico-conceptual connections but attributive-performative ones. The idea of rhetoric as a performance that has structural effects comes to the fore clearly in Skinner's work, with its focus on the role of orators and the processes of oration as accounting for change through articulation. The orators are being subjected to the constraints of language and at the same time they are Nietzschean 'artistically creating subjects'. Skinner (2002a, I, 7, 182) clearly emphasizes agency over structure and talks about rhetorical redescription emphasizing the role of the subject, the 'innovating ideologist' in the process. His view of rhetoric is centred around redescriptions by orators, which question our existing conceptions of morality and reorganize the normative-ideological terrain through the redescription of virtues into vices and vice versa. Given his poststructuralist background, Laclau hesitates to mention agency, and the notion of subjectivity which would have value in oratorial agency is often left behind structures. Yet, these structures are contingent, the subject positions that can be adopted within the structures are pluralistic and multiple and, thus, subjectivity is not singular and predetermined (Laclau and Mouffe, 1985). The latent openness of the society gives room for different political formations to emerge. Laclau (2000, 78) writes about 'the social organized as a rhetorical space […] because [… it] unduly restricts the tropoi which could be constitutive of social identities.' Following Derrida, he argues that decisions are taken on an 'undecidable terrain', which finally for him makes space for the subject who is not merely a prisoner of the structures (78, 83). Most crucially it opens space for the possibility of change and innovation as articulation. Laclau (and Mouffe, 1985, 134-5) avoids any straight forward answers to his own question 'who is the articulating subject?' but argues that subjects have not been permanently fixed into a system. While elements are distinct from the plural, contingent and overlapping subject positions in discursive formations, they do not inherently belong to discourses but must be articulated. Laclau, drawing on the Gramscian tradition, has retained an appreciation for orators, not mere processes or structures, seizing the moment from Machiavelli to Lenin. This is hardly distinct from Skinner's (2002a) praise for 'innovative ideologists'. Furthermore, Skinner, who has been seen as the theorist of agency, has revised his own theories taking on board the deconstructionist critique regarding the control the author is assumed to have over the text. 'I have become much more attentive to the genres to which the texts are couched, and the nature of the linguistic codes and conventions embodied in them' (2002b, 50) Skinner argues, stressing that to see these he had focused on classical rhetoric. Skinner, like Laclau, is a post-structuralist, in terms of going against the grain of the previous structuralist generation and realising the interplay of contingency and structures. Rather than 4 simply focusing on the agent he is interested in the articulation of changes in a particular context. The analysis goes beyond a single, momentary speech act, to look at changes in the normative-ideological order. These are also the object of analysis for Laclau, who emphasizes 'the social' more than Skinner. The element of persuasion in rhetoric is important for Skinner because it implies the role of an orator, the innovative ideologist in the process of political change (see also Palonen K, 2003), but also a change in the 'social world' or the 'social imaginary' (2002a, 102). Laclau (2004) strongly objects to the idea of rhetoric as (mere) persuasion, because for him rhetoric is tropology, which offers ontological logics of politics structuring of the social. In his recent work, Laclau (2005) advances an argument on the performative aspect of rhetoric, politics and language. Nevertheless, the two aspects of rhetoric – persuation and tropology – are not as distinct as one might think. Relationality On the whole it seems to me that the "right perception" - which would mean the adequate expression of an object in the subject - is a nonentity full of contradictions: for between two utterly different spheres, as between subject and object, there is no causality, no accuracy, no expression, but at the utmost the aesthetical relation. (Nietzsche, 1974, 184) The final aspect of Nietzschean rhetoric to be emphasized is the idea that relationality is not causal. This idea is integral to both Skinner and Laclau’s methods for analysing social, political and historical phenomena. They both oppose positivism and causality. As Skinner (2002a, I, 4) argues 'even if we agree that motives function as causes, there can nevertheless be non-causal explanations of action.' Furthermore, for Skinner, politico-normative concepts have neighbourly relations with others which play a role in the forming and changing their meanings. '[M]any vices are "neighbours" of the virtues.' (184) Drawing on Freud, Laclau's answer to causalism is 'overdetermination' through relationality. He writes, 'if ... the unity of the social agent is the result of a plurality of social demands coming together through equivalential (metonymic) relations of contiguity, the contingent moment of naming has an absolutely central role'. He adds illustratively: 'It is not only that “nationalism” can be substituted by other terms in its role as an empty signifier, but also that its own meaning will vary depending on the chain of equivalences associated with it.' (2005: 227) The tropes of metaphor, metonomy, paradiastole, simile, and catachresis are based on the idea of conceptual similarity and difference, substitution and combination. They imply relationality and demonstrate how things are (being) positioned on a discursive field. Political changes imply changes to the relations between elements and their positioning. Tropes of paradiastole and catachresis Rhetorical figures imply moves. The two tropes, paradiastole and catachresis imply specific political moves. As the focus of this article is on Skinner and Laclau. I will work with the definitions given by the two authors for their respective favourite tropes, instead of discussing the classical rhetoricians’ perspectives towards them. Paradiastole: the trope of normative redescription Paradiastole is a trope of rhetorical redescription. It implies a rhetorical move, where a term is 5 substituted by another term that is generally considered contradictory, implying a change in the normative content or usage. It has typically been the trope for turning vices to virtues, ruthlessness to courageousness etc., or vice versa. Skinner (2002a, I, 183) writes making references to Quintilian: [T]he essence of the technique may thus be said to consist of replacing a given evaluative description with a rival term that serves to picture the action no less plausibly, but serves at the same time to place it in a contrasting moral light. You seek to persuade your audience to accept your new description, and thereby to adopt a new attitude towards the action concerned. As we can see, Skinner is concerned about the performative aspect of redescription. Therefore, what is at stake is not a claim about the arbitrariness of meanings and their replacements as such but one about people promoting and contesting specific conceptions. Again writing with Quintilian he adds: [T]his means that strictly speaking we ought not to describe the technique as a case of substituting one word for another. 'For no one supposes that the words prodigality and liberality mean the same thing; the difference is rather that one person calls something prodigal which another thinks of as liberality.' What we are really claiming is that the res - the actual behaviour - possesses a different moral character from that which our dialectical opponents may have assigned to it. (183-4). In the above quotations the idea of an 'us' and a 'them', the situation of an orator, and that of the proponents and opponents of this act of persuasion become clear. Paradiastole implies a crossing of the floor, where the normative – i.e. ideological – tone of something is changed by its renaming, and thus adopted to another conceptual setting. Skinner continues: '[A]ll attempts to legislate about the 'correct' use of normative terms must be regarded as equally ideological in character. Whenever such terms are employed, their application will always reflect a wish to impose a particular moral vision of the workings of the social world.' (182) In other words, paradiastole is the political logic that imposes a change in what is considered normative, in the field of ideology and discursivity, through the redescription of a specific concept. This is the same terrain upon which Laclau studies political change. Catachresis: naming the 'unnameable' Laclau uses catachresis in (at least) three ways, between which he does not differentiate: as hegemony; the naming of the missing or impossible fullness (2000, 78); and as giving a name to 'an impossible object, i.e. an object which can only exist through the act of naming (2004, 306). For Laclau, 1) catachresis is the use of a figural term where there is no literal term that can replace it (e.g. when we speak of a leg of a chair); 2) catachresis is not, strictly speaking, a figure, for any kind of rhetorical figure sensu stricto can become catachrestical as far as there is no corresponding literal term […]; 3) as any rhetorical figure adds some meaning which could not be transmitted by the direct use of a literal term, all figures are, to some extent catachrestical. (306) First, catachresis is seen as the synonym for 'hegemony', the most central category of Laclau's thought. Related to this, he sees it as the naming of the impossible object, such as society, which also creates it. Finally, in a universalizing move, it can be seen 'a dimension of the rhetoricity itself' (306), as Laclau argues following Patricia Parker (1990). It emphasizes the gap in language between objects and terms. 6 By moulding together aspects of catachresis, however, Laclau obscures the understanding of catachresis as a political logic – which he himself insists it to be. The obscuring is symptomatic of a similar universalization of the category of hegemony in Laclau's writings, which has been subject to critique (e.g. Butler et al., 2000). My comparison of Laclau’s use of catachresis with Skinner's use of paradiastole in this paper aims at exposing the value of regarding catachresis as a particular and not a general logic of politics. Thereby it can be distinguished from paradiastole and the process of hegemony. I will demonstrate it below by connecting the two as tropes of rhetoric. Let me elaborate on catachresis as hegemony. For Laclau hegemony, in the Gramscian tradition, is the catachretical 'naming of the unnameable' in two ways. On the one hand, hegemony entails the idea of a particular element taking the representation of a whole. In this process the whole constitutes itself: a whole is represented only through its component elements. But this constitution is not expressive but grounding: 'the name, as a highly cathected rallying point, does not express the unity of the group, but becomes its ground.' (Laclau, 2005, 231) The naming of the unnameable refers to the contingent relationship between the unifying 'empty signifier' and the elements of the totality and to the artificial way in which the link has been made. To take again the example of the society or the social, for Laclau (and Mouffe 1985, 96) 'the social itself has no essence'. Any meanings are assigned through a process of articulation, partial fixing, where elements of the social only exist in relation to each other through articulatory processes. On the other hand, Laclau develops the idea of the '"hegemonic formation" as an articulated totality of differences', shaped by its limits, something beyond the totality itself, 'the transformation of limits to frontiers' (143). The frontiers are unnameable because they are not fixed but in flux and have no necessary essence. Naming them is an attempt to constitute the totality itself. Their disappearance (to add to Laclau's claim, here we could also talk about forgetting, unnaming) would mean the dissolution of the totality as a political unit. (144) Laclau has universalized the logic of hegemony to account for infinite social and political formations. This logic is, for Laclau (and Butler 2004, 334), the logic of politics. But is catachresis the logic of politics? Distinction and Combination: the specificity of the two tropes Having made the connection between Laclau and Skinner’s approaches to the study of rhetoric through their shared appreciation for the importance of contingency, performativity and relationality, the last part of this paper studies the differences and similarities between catachresis and paradiastole in more detail. These two political logics can be combined both in their theoretical form and in practice. Studying them together, yet with a view to the differences, gives us a more in-depth view of politics than the simple assumption that any of them is the trope of politics. The first part explores their similarity by asking whether paradiastole is in fact catachresis, as Laclau would claim. The second part shows how they work together as interrelated but still separate logics. The aim is to find out the relationship between these two terms. Paradiastole as catachresis? Is paradiastole reducible to the trope of catachresis, as Laclau (2004, 306) claims – arguing that all tropes can be catachrestical? Skinner (2002a, III, 91) quotes Quintilian making a distinction between paradiastole and catachresis: 7 'when an act of temerity is called courage, or when luxury is called liberality, some writers want to say that these are instances of catachresis', as a result they treat the device as one of the tropes. But [Quintilian] explicitly adds that he dissents from this judgement, since it is only proper to speak of catachresis when we adapt a neighbouring term to describe something for which no term exists at all. Instead of two neighbouring terms catachresis implies a term and the lack of a term. But how can we discuss neighbourliness of terms in a situation where only one term exists? The sense of neighbourliness emphasizes a similarity or closeness of terms and objects – the logic of difference (or combination) for Laclau. Paradiastole also plays with difference and similarity: as the trope of renaming it both brings things together and separates them from each other, for instance courageousness from temerity and patriotism from nationalism. Paradiastole, which signals a change in the normative content of a term, is about renaming something already perceived as existing – in a normative and discursive order – with a name that derives from a different discursive camps or has different normative connotations. Therefore it is renaming something that already has a name with something which has already been assigned different normative content. By contrast, catachresis is the operative trope in situations where no name would have pre-existed. Nevertheless, Laclau would argue that paradiastole is catachrestical to the extent that the relationship between names and objects is not fixed, or names do not inherently belong to objects, and that renaming always brings in something new: a paradiastolic process would cause a new constellation, enough changes in the object to be named to make it 'new'. Beyond generalisations, there are two ways of relating paradiastole and catachresis, neigbourliness and 'iteration' to borrow from Derrida. Like paradiastole, catachresis, as the trope of hegemony, implies a neighbourliness between terms, closeness, transformation of terrain and of concept. The naming of the closeness or the simultaneous contestation of distance is a performative politico-linguistic act present in paradiastolic description. To follow Laclau, catachresis transforms the terrain on which it emerges. It contests the situation not by 'crossing the floor' but by bringing in something 'new', something that has not yet been recognized, or named. Though it implies a political change and a transformation of the concepts, there is a lesser degree of newness in paradiastolic redescription, where an already existing concept is replaced by another already existing concept. By way of empirical example we could look at party politics to recognize these two logics. The typical example of Laclau is a popular front emerging and contesting the existing cleavages and dividing lines in politics. Skinner would demonstrate with paradiastole a move of a party, policy or concept from one political camp to another – without necessarily contesting the poles or political camps themselves. In a Laclauian reading of the paradiastolic process, where one name is substituted by another, the substituting terms carries with it traces of the old signified, the object it described. When something described as nationalism is redescribed as patriotism, patriotism also ends up changing. This resembles the idea of 'iterability' in Derrida (e.g. Norval 1997): when we continuously describe nationalism as patriotism, the previous connotations bring traces to the new concept that is the new configuration. For Skinner neighbourliness is tied to the connection between vices and virtues. Paradiastole can be seen as the redescription of something generally considered as a vice into a virtue, or vice versa. But it also creates a new concept: it is not only that the name gained new content, but this something did not exist prior 8 to the process of naming. In Laclauian thinking, when we bridge many concepts like this, we also end up emptying out their particular content by overloading them with new meanings. This is what the process of hegemony does, through one signifier taking the representation of others, whereby Laclau calls it an 'empty signifier'. Therefore, the paradiastolic process is precisely what is at stake in the processes marked by 'empty' (overloaded) or 'floating' (contested) signifiers, where discursive chains are being articulated and their contents contested. Empty signifiers are crucial for the process of hegemony and the creation of unity: this signifier becomes the name of a constellation of elements that as yet has had no name (though, the process of naming may establish the constellation as such). Paradiastole within hegemony The argument here is that paradiastole makes part of hegemony and catachresis, as the hegemonic process is one of articulating meanings into a constellation. Throughout Laclau's work (and especially in On Populist Reason) the important tropological relations are those of logics of difference and equivalence, hegemony or catachresis. According to these logics, elements relate to each other forming by links of similarity and difference, substitution, unity and exclusion. The elements are located on a terrain marked by different relations, antagonism and similarity, whether they are fixed or floating. Laclau (1985, 135) argues that 'hegemony should happen on a field criss-crossed by antagonism' where, however, there is a 'vast area floating elements and the possibility of their articulation to opposite camps' (136). The articulation of an element to one camp rather than another is precisely the task of paradiastole. Paradiastole works within hegemony, but for Laclau, hegemony is something more: 'In order to speak of hegemony, the articulatory moment is not sufficient.' (135) Catachresis and hegemony refer specifically to the emergence of the constellation, the process of unification – dealing with a plurality of objects that are made into one rather than changes in a single element. The catachrestical naming of something that did not exist before – the unforeseen unity and commonality (however vague and incoherent) – happens in the conditions of contingency. Catachresis implies a moment of rupture, which transforms the discursive field and breaks down frontiers and hegemonic structures, and creates a new object. When investigating the process of hegemony, the analysis of political articulations is vital. Paradiastole is a process of articulation of a particular kind: the force which 'swings' elements from one normative-ideological camp to another by turning things to ours (virtues) or theirs (vices) and the force contesting or maintaining the unity and frontiers, the distinction between 'us' and 'them'. It implies confrontation. As the logic of paradiastole brings things together, it is internal to hegemony itself. However, whereas hegemony focuses on the idea of unity, paradiastole works in the particular instances of articulation of elements, as an internal, yet separate logic. In this sense, Skinnerian thought helps us to distinguish between the actual processes of the creation of hegemony and frontiers, reaching beyond the idea of unity to see how elements came together or were separated. In the next section I will explore the consequences of making this distinction, and also of understanding the interplay between these two political logics. Logics of paradiastole and catachresis at work in political fora 9 Are there specific forms of politics that are particularly catachrestical or paradiastolic? Clearly, Laclau is interested in the emergence of new (popular) forces, Skinner in the changes in the meanings of concepts in political articulation and the contestation over signifiers in politics. Furthermore, in contrast to Laclau's vision of larger politico-social transformations and the formation of a theory to explain them, Skinner focuses on the actors and moments of articulation themselves.4 The hypothesis has been that parliamentary politics are particularly paradiastolic and social movement or revolutionary politics catachrestical. This simplifying and essentialist thought relies on the acknowledged political traditions and preferred political examples of the two authors. The preceding analysis nevertheless helps us to reach a different verdict. Namely, the two logics are complimentary – and present in most political praxis. The distinction between the two – instead of molding them together – helps us to understand different processes in politics, different steps in political articulation. Usually, in politics and political analysis, the two aspects are interconnected. The rest of this article accounts for this claim, taking social forums as its main example. Paradiastole, changing the normative meaning of a term or linking it into a different normative setting by its usage, implies a reliance on the idea of at least two separate political camps. Hegemony maintains the idea of a unity which, to exist, requires a frontier: an exclusion. Both presume an ideologico-normative 'us' and 'them', and a contestable and contested frontier, reproduced in the process of articulation. When there is no distinction between, for example, nationalism and patriotism, these two do not constitute a political frontier, but when they are assigned as the descriptions of specific political groupings we can notice a political frontier. 'Crossing the floor' between the camps is a paradiastolic move: turning patriotism to nationalism would be one of them. Hegemony implies the construction – catachrestical naming – of one of the camps and the frontier: this may imply the naming of the camp which as yet had no name as the nationalists or as the patriots. This may include a processes of redescription, even of a paradiastolic nature. These processes can be seen as taking place in a parliament, which Skinner, as a scholar of the republican tradition, would emphasize. The crossing is visualized in most modern parliaments, which have been arranged either in the shape of two opposing sides or a horseshoe. The political parties usually organize around two or more poles. Alliances are usually sought between these poles by unifying particular grievances and values into policy frameworks. Sometimes situations which radicalize the existing alliances and political frontiers emerge. New alliances are formed under new headings. These situations can be seen as catachrestical. Redescriptions, of which some are paradiastolic moves, however, tend to dominate parliamentary politics. The prime moments of catachresis, illustrated through the Gramscian notion of 'organic crisis', when a party collapses and a new one has yet to be born, are natural but rare. Nevertheless, aspects of catachrestical naming may well be present, for instance, in the process of coalition-building or in the naming of political problems and demands. Laclau has been influential in theorizing about new social movements and the unification of their particularistic demands under larger umbrellas. An exemplary political forum of this kind would be the social forum, which gathers different struggles, movements, NGOs and activists under wide headings or punch-lines such as the anti-globalisation movement or 'another world is possible'. When it emerged in Porto Allegre and spread around the world, the social forum movement was catachrestical phenomenon. It transformed the field of politics for these activists, affording them a possibility to conduct politics in a common forum outside parliaments. The naming of the Social Forum movement was a grounding act in itself, 10 subsuming particular struggles under the heading of 'anti/alter-globalisation', which now signified and partially defined them. As in any catachrestic process, anti-globalisation became partially emptied out of meaning because of it had been overloaded by the many particular struggles it ended up signifying. The hegemonic form was ready. With time the Social Forums (SF) in part institutionalized themselves as political fora with clear frontiers and rules, protected by a SF charter. In the process of organizing particular SFs, decisions were made ranging from the choice of their thematic priorities to the venues where the forums were to be held, the groups or speakers invited or excluded, and the composition and form of the organizing committees. In the process different groups around the forum allied with and against each other (see e.g. Bohm 2000, 328-51). The result was a process dominated by the different political logics described above. The hegemonic logic of exclusion and inclusion, naming of the 'people' and the main actors, is embedded within the organising structures of the Social Forums – even if they are supposedly open spaces. Nevertheless, political frontiers are not acknowledged, which makes the transparency of the inclusion/exclusion and crossings-of-the-floor problematic. As Teivainen (http://www.forumsocialmundial.org.br/dinamic.php?pagina=bib_teivo_fsm2004_in) argues, the SFs are politicizing processes which nevertheless have depoliticising effects: Pretending that there are no relations of power that should be made visible within the WSF process is the most harmful of these depoliticizing elements. Even if it is often presented as "not a locus of power", "not an organization", and "only a neutral space", the WSF does have relations of power. It is essential for any reflection on power and democracy in the context of the SFs to realise how the two different but interconnected logics of paradiastole and catachresis function in the social forum process(es). Nevertheless, the virtue of the logic of paradiastole, rather than the catachrestical process, in the SF process would lie in the way in which it can shift the focus from the rather fixed constellations of 'us' (the forum people) and 'them' (the evil outside) to the elements themselves and the process of what is being redescribed. Further, inside the process it would highlight the emerging overlapping different positions of 'us' and 'them'. Instead of insisting on the lack of frontiers we could acknowledge and also accommodate some of the ‘them’ within our own camp, or see the 'us' as a combination of many camps. Instead of focusing on 'our issues' it would be worth exploring how to turn vices into virtues and vice versa – to enable ruptures in the existing hegemony and wider catachrestical changes with those we do not already agree? Distinguishing between these two processes would reveal the multiple overlapping unities – created through a catachrestical logic and connected by paradiastolic moves.5 Despite its catachrestical naming, the SF has already failed in universalising its own concept. For instance, during the European Social Forum (ESF) in London 2003, 'our' and 'their' forums found their expression in events around the 'official' ESF: the free events at autonomous spaces of the 'Beyond ESF' were for many participants the real Social Forum (see e.g. ephemera, 5:2, http://www.ephemeraweb.org/journal/5-2/5-2index.htm): an example of an 'alter-hegemonic' politics grounding and giving expression to a range of things through claiming to represent the struggle the ESF failed to fight. This constellation also contains redescriptions: the virtuous character of the SF has been transformed into a vice and then reappropriated, newly redescribed into one's own camp. On the other hand, acknowledgement of its own failure – the unavoidable partiality of the object and the ultimate 'impossibility of 11 fullness' – would perhaps show the hegemonic character that Laclau emphasizes. Taking rhetoric to the level of political fora, in the 'Beyond ESF' event we can nevertheless recognize the drive for something that both the parliament and the SF have failed to construct: a truly catachrestical political space that would be constantly contested and constructed. To borrow Laclau's (2005, 222) response to the postmodern prophets of the 'end of ideology', we could witness: 'the arrival at a fully political era, because the dissolution of the marks of certainty does not give the political game any aprioristic necessary terrain but, rather, the possibility of constantly redefining the terrain itself.' From the perspectives of both the Skinnerian history of political ideas and Laclauian discourse theory, the contexts in which the two authors find themselves may have influenced their preferred fora of politics, their theories, tropes and choice of interesting political processes. Laclau, coming from the Latin American context where parliamentarism had not properly institutionalized, would have more incentives to focus on popular fronts, movements and revolutionary politics; whereas Skinner, writing in the British and Cambridge setting, would be more interested in political reforms in parliamentary debates than extraparliamentary politics. This does not mean that the thought, political moves and processes they outline would not be transferable to other fora and contexts. Rather, we can say that both authors offer theories that draw on and can be applied to political life. Conclusion Rhetoric supports the idea of contingency, the distance between language and the world of actions and objects. This article has argued that rhetoric informs our outlining of political logics, thinking or moves. We can even relate and compare the thought of two political theorists by looking at their favourite tropes. Paradiastole and catachresis, as examples of rhetorical tropes, are distinct logics even if they can be seen as functioning together, within each other and simultaneously. Seeing them as distinct logics provides avenues for thinking about political action, distinguishing between particular political articulations and contestations. They are indispensable for the analysis of ideologies, normative structures and political phenomena. They also inform about the way in which different political fora function. Despite the interconnectedness of the two tropes, they are tools for comparing different political discourses, movements, and fora – of which only few have been explored here. Tropes are not 'mere rhetoric', in the same way as words is not 'just language'. In fact, what this article hopes to have illustrated is that, in all their complexity, they represent patterns of thought and action which are important as objects of political analysis and political theory. By discussing the two tropes of paradiastole and catachresis I have aimed to bridge the gap between two contemporary political theorists, who otherwise seem to come from different perspectives. By applying the tropes in a contemporary political context, I have sought to illustrate how the thought of the two authors helps us to understand, for instance, how political changes happen, and how difference and unity are being constructed on different fora of politics. This shows how to move beyond the mere declarations of some crucial premises that relate to contingency and the linguistic or rhetorical turn in politics. Notes 12 1. A collection of revised earlier writings by Skinner is published in three volumes under the title Visions of Politics (2002). Here I primarily draw on the first volumme of the work, titled Regarding Method. 2. Mouffe, in her subsequent focus on democratic theory, has since been in contact with Skinner and republican Skinnerians working on the combination republican liberalism and socialism (see also Mouffe 1993 and for discussion Wenman 2003). 3. Laclau (1996) has been discussing Skinner in an essay. 4. The notion of 'pointillism' – which characterized Skinner's theory in contrast to the German conceptual historian Reinhardt Koselleck for Kari Palonen – can be noted also here. (Palonen K, 2003) 5. An example could be 'memory-work' (an account of some of the problems in the ESF memory processes Palonen E, 2006). References Butler J, Laclau E and Zizek S (2000) Contingency, Hegemony, Universality; Contemporary Dialogues on the Left. Verso, London. Bohm S (2002) Movements of Theory and Practice. ephemera 2: 328-351 Critchley S and Marschart O (eds) (2004) Laclau - a Critical Reader. London and New York: Routledge. Finlayson A (2004) Political science, political ideas and rhetoric. Economy and Society 33: 528-549. Laclau E and Mouffe C (1985) Hegemony and Socialist Strategy. London: Verso. Laclau E (1988) Metaphor and Social Antagonisms. In: Nelson C and Grossberg L (eds). Marxism an dthe Interpretation of Culture. University of Illinois Press. Laclau E (1990) New Reflections on Revolutions of Our Time. London: Verso. Laclau E (1996) Emancipation(s). London: Verso. Laclau E (2000) Identity and Hegemony: the role of Universality in the Construction of Political Logics. In: Butler J, Laclau E and Zizek S. Contingency, Hegemony, Universality; Contemporary Dialogues on the Left. London: Verso. Laclau E (2004) Glimpsing the future. In Critchley and Marschart (eds). Laclau - a critical reader. London and New York: Routledge. Laclau E and Butler J (2004) The Uses of Equality (Appendix 1). In: Critchley and Marschart, eds., Laclau - a critical reader, London and New York: Routledge. pp. 329-344. Laclau E (2005) On Populist Reason, London: Verso. Mouffe C (1993) The Return of the Political. London: Verso. Nietzsche F (1975) On truth and falsity in their ultramoral sense. In: Levy O (ed) M. A. Mugge (trans). The complete works of Friedrich Nietzsche Vol. 2. Early Greek Philosophy. New York: Gordon Press, 1873c. pp. 173-192. Norval A (1997) The Frontiers in Question. Filozofski vestnik XVII 2: 51-75. Norval A (2000) Review Article: The Things We Do with Words -- Contemporary Approaches to the Analysis of Ideology. British Journal of Political Science 30: 313-346. Palonen K (2003) Quentin Skinner: History, Politics, Rhetoric. Cambridge: Polity Press. Palonen E (2006) Constructing communities: From National to Transnational and Activist Politics of Memory in Europe. XING 4: 41-44. Also: http://www.xing.at/04/04-xing-4045.pdf Parker P (1990) Metaphor and catachresis. In: Bender J and Wellbery DE (eds). The Ends of Rhetoric; History, Theory, Practice. Stanford: Stanford University Press. Skinner Q (1981) Machiavelli. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Skinner Q (1996) Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 13 Skinner Q (1998) Liberty before Liberalism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Skinner Q (1999) Rhetoric and Conceptual Change. Finnish Yearbook of Political Thought, 3: 60-73 Skinner Q (2002a) Visions of Politics, Vols I-III, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Skinner Q (2002b) On Encountering a past [interviewed by Koikkalainen P and Syrjämäki S]. Finnish Yearbook of Political Thought, 6: 34-63. Wenman MA (2003) Laclau or Mouffe? Splitting the difference. Philosophy & Social Criticism 29: 581–606. 1 2 3 4 5 14