1 Questioning the limits of representation This changes everything. We essentially have been attacked at home. This will affect everything we do. We are changed forever.1 The world has changed now out of all recognition because of this.2 We’ve witnessed a turn in history, and in the way the United States will look at the world for a long time to come.3 September 11, 2001 will always be a fixed point in the life of America.4 According to what seems to have become a dominant view, “9/11” represents an “event” that has somehow changed the world. As such, it can be seen as a central reference point in time, which separates “before” from “after”, and “what is to come” from “what has been”. Implicit in this view is also often a call for a new way of thinking and reasoning. Everything has Senator Chuck Hagel, in Tony Locy, “‘I Can’t Describe It. It Was Horrible’: Eyewitnesses to Horror Left Grasping for Words after Attacks from the Air”, USA TODAY, September 12, 2001. 2 Lord Robertson, NATO Secretary General, in Stephen Castle, “Robertson: World Changed Out of All Recognition”, The Independent, September 14, 2001. 3 Morton Abramowitz, in David Von Drehle, “World War, Cold War Won. Now, the Gray War”, The Washington Post, September 12, 2001. 4 George W. Bush, “President’s Remarks to the Nation”, September 11, 2002, available at: http://www.whitehouse.gov/news/releases/2002/09/20020911-3.html, accessed on July 14, 2007. 1 12 changed and no longer can traditional approaches to the order of things be applied. Different threats are emanating; different fears must be dealt with; a different war has to be waged; a different form of security is emerging; a different role of the sovereign state; a different take on the geopolitical map is necessary. But it also suggests that “we” have changed, and that the United States has changed because of this. So much has changed and all of it seems to come down to this “thing”, the “thing” as the “event”, and the “event” as “9/11”. However, the question of what this supposed “event” really means and what it actually refers to can in many ways be seen as highly ambiguous. Is it the idea of having been attacked “at home” that provides the main content of this “event”? Is it an “act of war”? Is it images of people jumping out of the windows from the World Trade Centre? Or is it the experience of running away from the burning Twin Towers and the Pentagon building? An endless list of examples could be added to these. And the question is how all of those examples can be translated into one single and coherent “event”. In other words, what is it that makes the idea of “9/11” or “September 11” as an “event” possible in the first place? One way of addressing this question would be to point to the idea of representation, and specifically the idea of re-presenting what has happened. According to this view, “9/11” can be understood as a sign or a symbol, referring to something specific that has happened in a particular moment in time. As such, this sign can also be said to provide a common denominator to which various aspects of what has happened are linked. As a sign or a symbol, “9/11” represents the unity of what has happened, incorporating everything into the notion of one single “event” or a coherent whole, which functions as a starting point for something to come as well as a breaking point that separates what is to come from what has been. At the same time, however, the idea of representing what has happened along these lines can also be seen as highly problematic. For example, how can it be assumed that the reality of what has happened, whatever it might be, can be represented by simply referring to the “event”, or to the date of 13 “September 11, 2001”? How can the meaning of this reality, its place in time, its beginning and end, and its role in a wider context be determined by trying to place everything within this kind of unity or whole? And how can all the possible dimensions and aspects of what has happened be mediated or represented in this way? On the basis of these questions it could be argued that the very idea of representation, and the assumptions underlying this idea require a more thorough and critical examination. How can representation be understood as a method for determining the meaning of things? What is the relationship between representation and general claims about knowledge? And what are the potential problems and limits posed by representation? The aim of this chapter is to address these questions. And the overall objective of doing so, then, is to question the adequacy of relying on a representational mode of thinking when trying to understand ideas about the “event”. Moreover, by questioning representation the aim is also to explore the possibility of thinking “outside” representation, and to see what the implications of doing so might be for thinking about the “event”. The chapter is divided into two main parts. The first part looks at how the idea of representation and its underlying assumptions can be analysed as well as criticised. The starting point for doing so will be the work of Claire Colebrook, which considers the emergence of representation as a philosophical idea but also different attempts to challenge it. According to Colebrook, whereas the emergence of representation can be traced back to the onset of modernity, and to the work of philosophers such as Descartes and Kant, the main critiques and challenges to representation can be found in the work of philosophers such as Jacques Derrida, Michel Foucault, and Gilles Deleuze, often associated with poststructuralist philosophy. In order to examine these critiques in more detail the first part of the chapter will also look at how the respective work of Derrida, Foucault and Deleuze set out to criticise the philosophical idea of representation. Whilst poststructuralist philosophy implies a strong challenge to the idea of representation it can also, according to Colebrook, be said to open up space for alternative modes of thinking. In the second part of the chapter I 14 will turn to Deleuze’s philosophy in order to see how one such alternative mode of thinking is articulated and developed. And I will do this by focusing on how Deleuze’s concepts of “difference”, “multiplicity” and “transcendental empiricism” seek to overcome the limits of representation. On that basis, I will then return to the problem of how to understand ideas about “9/11” as an “event” in the conclusion. 1.1 A critical analysis of representation According to Colebrook, the emergence of representation can also be said to constitute the “threshold of modernity”. 5 As such, representation has two main aspects or dimensions, one political and one epistemological. According to the first, representation can be linked to a notion of “selfrepresentation”, which emphasises the need to represent oneself as well as to be re-presented in order to have an identity, gain recognition, autonomy and self-determination. The subject, in this sense, needs to be represented in order to become a “political” subject, since there is nothing that grants it the status of being a part of a political community unless it is in one way or another represented.6 According to Colebrook, this idea of representation can be linked more specifically to the ideals of the enlightenment and to the ways in which those ideals sought to free the “human” from notions of a “divine law, ancient right, tradition or heavenly fiat”. 7 The problem with such notions was that they assumed rights and laws as given outside of human interaction, which meant that they had to be constituted externally to “man”. Against such a view, the enlightenment thinkers argued that rights and laws must emanate from “man’s” ability to represent himself. If laws are not given externally to individuals, the latter must have the responsibility as well as the freedom to use their rational capacity in order to determine the laws. 8 For this reason, the idea of “man” being able to 5 Claire Colebrook, Philosophy and Post-structuralist Theory: From Kant to Deleuze, (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2005), p. 1. 6 Claire Colebrook, “Questioning Representation”, SubStance, 29 (2), 2000, p. 51. 7 Colebrook, Philosophy and Post-structuralist Theory, p. 3. 8 Ibid., p. 8. 15 represent himself comes down to a view of individuals (“men”) as autonomous, rational and responsible beings. As such, they are assumed to have the freedom and right to represent themselves rather than just being represented. And it is also on the basis of this assumption that the idea of “representative democracy” becomes so important: The inextricably intertwined motifs of autonomy and representation are the promise of modernity. Man becomes autonomous when he recognises that all external injunctions are human representations; and democratic representation is possible only for an autonomous self. Further, subjects become autonomous selves, and institute their autonomy, through democratic representation.9 What makes this idea of representation particularly “modern”, according to Colebrook, is the explicit notion of an autonomous subject, which is also what takes us to the second, epistemological, aspect of representation. In brief, this aspect can be linked to the assumption that knowledge only can be given through the subject’s ability to represent the “world”. Consequently, there is no meaning of the world “in itself”, which is somehow directly given. The only way it is possible to know something about the world is through representation. This idea of representation, as a primary condition for knowledge, has strong connections with Kant’s philosophy, in relation to which Colebrook makes the following observation: It makes no sense to claim to know a pre-conceptual world in itself that would ground our judgments. Any such world in itself would only be known through our concepts. Knowledge and judgement must recognize representation as an essential condition. Rather than regarding our judgements about the world as justifiable by appealing to some pre-representational real, we have to accept the finitude of our knowledge.10 9 Ibid., p. 9. Colebrook, “Questioning Representation”, p. 52. 10 16 In Kant’s philosophy, the finitude of our knowledge suggests that the world cannot be immediately experienced, and consequently that it cannot be immediately known. Experience is not related to the thing “in itself”, or the “world”; it is only related to particular objects, which are given to a particular point of view. The knowledge of these objects, therefore, has to be based on a form of experience that is directly linked to a point of view. And according to Kant this is made possible by the “ordering and unifying power of the subject”. 11 Hence, it is through this unifying power, i.e. the representing subject that objects of experience can linked to a process of representation. Only in that way is it possible to create a basic condition for knowledge, which consists of representation as a ground for determining the meaning of things. In this way, representation can also be said to constitute the necessary limits for knowledge: Representation marks a limit, a point beyond which knowledge cannot go: a recognition of the point of view of knowledge. For knowledge’s very possibility lies in perspective, point of view, position and finitude: the necessary consequence of the fact that if thought is to know some thing then it must be placed in a position in relation to that thing. Because knowledge relates to what is other than itself, it is situated in a relation, such that what it knows is not immediately present but must be re-presented.12 Knowledge is thus never immediately given; it always has to be given to a point of view and through the process of representation. The primary condition for the possibility of knowledge, therefore, is the very act of representation, which is performed by the subject. In this way, as Colebrook notes, the “subject describes nothing other than the way in which the world is given”.13 In other words, the subject does not refer to a pre-given substance 11 Colebrook, Philosophy and Post-structuralist Theory, p. 28. Ibid., p. 2. 13 Ibid., p. 208. 12 17 or being in the world but only to the very condition for determining the content and meaning of things in the world. The subject, in this sense, has to be separated from externally existing objects because of its unique capacity to represent those objects. According to Colebrook, the idea of an independent subject can also be seen as one of the main problems with representation. For if representation constitutes a primary condition for knowledge it then follows that the subject itself must be regarded as an integral part of representation, not as an independently existing entity, but rather as an effect. However, rather than seeing it as an effect, representation places the subject at the centre of discourse, as a ground or a foundation for making knowledge claims as well as generalizations. The paradox of this underlying assumption is something that Colebrook refers to as the “error of anthropologism”: To take what is as a representation is to recognise thought’s contribution to the world: the world is never given in itself, but as given is always given in a certain way or according to a logic. To place this logic within the subject is the error of anthropologism: taking a particular being or a part of the world as the ground for the world in general.14 This idea of the subject’s role in representation is also what constitutes a common point of departure for various critiques of representation. Colebrook discusses different kinds of critiques in this context. There are, however, three philosophers that she mainly focuses on: Derrida, Foucault and Deleuze. Even though their ideas in many ways differ from one another, they can all be said to share a critical engagement with representation. And for Colebrook, this engagement is mainly characterised by the critique of origins and foundations that is often expressed by pointing to the ways in which representation “comes to stand in for some grounding logic or condition”.15 In order to explain this critique in more detail, and why the idea of 14 15 Ibid., p. 248. Colebrook, “Questioning Representation”, p. 48. 18 “grounding” should be seen as a problem, I will now look at how Derrida, Foucault and Deleuze deal with the question of representation respectively. Derrida: representation and the “metaphysics of presence” Derrida’s critique of representation focuses to a large extent on the role of “difference” in representation. In Derrida’s philosophy this includes the articulation of a (quasi)concept, which he calls différance. According to Derrida, différance is “neither a word nor a concept”.16 As such it does not possess a pre-determined content or meaning, and it has “neither existence nor essence. It derives from no category of being, whether present or absent.” 17 Hence, Différance does not function in order to represent the meaning of objects through language, but can rather be said to offer a way to “account for the active production of language and discourse”.18 To understand the production of language and discourse it is useful to first look at Derrida’s critique of the work of Swiss linguist Ferdinand de Saussure. According to Saussure, the role of language can be understood by the different ways a “signifier” is used to denote a “signified”. While the signifier stands for the sound-image, the signified is the concept or the idea.19 On this basis, Saussure develops the concept of the “sign”, which he uses in order to bring the signifier and signified together. And whilst Derrida recognises the importance of introducing the different elements of the signifier and the signified, he clearly rejects the introduction of the sign as a way of bringing them together.20 According to Derrida, this move is deeply embedded in the tradition of “western metaphysics”, according to which the aim is to uncover the true meaning of things “outside” language and discourse. In Saussure’s writing this happens, according to Derrida, by giving the signified an essentialist quality, as “a concept signified in and of itself, a concept simply present for thought, independent of a relationship to Jacques Derrida, “Différance”, in Margins of Philosophy, translated by Alan Bass, (Brighton: Harvester Press, 1982), p. 3. 17 Ibid., p. 6. 18 David Howarth, Discourse, (Buckingham: Open University Press, 2000), p. 40. 19 Ibid., p. 19. 20 Jacques Derrida, Positions, translated by Alan Bass, (London: Continuum, 2002), p. 19. 16 19 language, that is of a relationship to a system of signifiers”.21 In this way, Saussure has to assume that there is a reality outside language, which can be represented by the sign. The implication of this assumption, according to Derrida, is that the sign becomes yet another metaphysical concept, which relies on the presence of a “transcendental signified”. 22 But this begs the question of where the meaning of the signified is supposed to come from in the first place and how it can be represented. For Derrida, however, there can be no satisfactory answer to this question, simply because the signified concept “is never present in and of itself, in a sufficient presence that would refer only to itself. Essentially and lawfully, every concept is inscribed in a chain or in a system within which it refers to other concepts, by means of the systematic play of differences.”23 According to Derrida, then, there is no essential meaning of the signified that somehow can be discerned through the signifier. There is only a “play of differences”, which produces different effects of relating the signifier to the signified. Crucially, within this play of differences, there is no meaning as such, neither present nor absent. According to Derrida, “nothing, neither among the elements nor within the system, is anywhere ever simply present or absent. There are only, everywhere, differences and traces of traces.”24 And this is also what the quasi-concept of différance refers to: a play of differences that consists of “traces of traces”, with no original content or meaning. Moreover, Différance can be said to consist of two different elements or forces: “spacing” or “differing” and “temporization” or “deferring”. 25 These elements imply that there is no “being-presence” of things, which then can be re-presented. There is only a “differing” and “deferring” of presence, which means that any attempt to unite the signifier and the signified through the metaphysical concept of the sign is ultimately impossible. It is impossible 21 Ibid., p. 19. Ibid., p. 19. 23 Derrida, “Différance”, p. 11. 24 Derrida, Positions, p. 26. 25 Derrida, “Différance”, p. 18. 22 20 because there will always be a differing and deferring of presence in the process of signification, which means that the metaphysical concept of the sign only can be used to represent that which is present in its absence. According to Derrida: The sign is usually said to be put in the place of the thing itself, the present thing, “thing” here standing equally for meaning or referent. The thing represents the present in its absence. It takes the place of the present. When we cannot grasp or show the thing, state the present, the being-present, when the present cannot be presented, we signify, we go through the detour of the sign. (…) The sign, in this sense, is deferred presence.26 The “present” can thus only be said to exist on the basis of a metaphysical assumption, which itself lacks a foundation. Hence, instead of referring to a “real” or “pure” presence, Derrida argues that it is only possible to refer to a “metaphysics of presence”, which symbolises an “irrepressible desire” for the presence of a signified.27 In order to get away from this notion of presence, Derrida argues that rather than constantly trying to anchor the true meaning of things in language we have to accept the constantly misplaced meaning of things. And this can also be seen as one of the main purposes of différance, as it seeks to maintain “our relationship with that which we necessarily misconstrue, and which exceeds the alternative of presence and absence”.28 One of the main implications of this view, it can be argued, is that the presence and absence of meaning have to be regarded as nothing but effects of différance.29 In other words, they have to be regarded as effects of the play of differences, or the differing and deferring of presence. One such effect is the subject, or the idea of a “being” of the subject. According to Derrida, the 26 Derrida, Ibid., p. 9. Jacques Derrida, Of Grammatology, translated by Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak, (Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1976), p. 49. 28 Ibid., p. 20. 29 Derrida, “Différance”, p. 21. 27 21 subject is never present as such; it rather “depends upon the system of differences and the movement of différance”, which means that it “is constituted only in being divided from itself, in becoming space, in temporizing, in deferral”. 30 Consequently, there can be no subject, which then functions as the true origin for representation. The subject is only an effect of the play of difference, or the differing and deferral of presence. Following Caroline Williams, “the concept of effect signals an opening up, a deconstruction, of all causality to difference; it produces differential relations, multiple effects”. 31 These multiple effects can, yet again, be explained by différance as a play of differences, which always lacks formal differences between already established “things”. Referring to the play of differences, of traces of traces, of signifiers without a signified – différance highlights the very impossibility of establishing a ground or foundation for meaning: There is no essence of différance; it (is) that which not only could never be appropriated in the as such of its name or its appearing, but also that which threatens the authority of the as such in general, of the presence of the thing itself in its essence. That there is not a proper essence of différance at this point, implies that there is neither a Being nor truth of the play of writing such as it engages différance.32 So, rather than trying to provide a foundation for the subject, Derrida shows how the subject is perpetually deconstructed, as an effect of différance. Hence, the subject should never be conceived of outside the “play of différance”, which also means that it cannot function as a metaphysical ground or foundation for meaning.33 Meaning is always constituted through the production of language and discourse, as an effect of différance and the play of differences, never by an independently existing subject. 30 Derrida, Positions, p. 29. Caroline Williams, Contemporary French Philosophy: Modernity and the Persistence of the Subject, (London: Continuum, 2001), p. 133. 32 Derrida, “Différance”, p. 26. 33 Ibid., p. 11. 31 22 Foucault: representation and the emergence of “man” In a similar way to Derrida, Foucault criticises the idea of a transcendent ground for representation. In Foucault’s work, this critique emerges from his analysis of modernity, and specifically the creation of “man” as a contingent solution to the problem of truth at the end of the 18th century. According to Foucault, this period involved a shift in the role of language, a shift that marked a break between the classical age and modernity. In brief, this break can be understood in relation to the problem of relating “words” to “things”, which, according to Colebrook, also can be seen as the main focus of analysis in Foucault’s book The Order of Things, or Les mots et les choses, which literally means “Words and Things”. As Colebrook notes, “this, alongside the English title, raises the question of the relation (the ‘and’ or ‘order’) between words and things”.34 According to Foucault, the relation between words and things constitutes as a philosophical problem, to which there have been different ways of responding in different historical contexts. In the classical age, for example, Foucault notes that the role of language was mainly active, and that words were assumed to have a direct correspondence to things: As long as language was defined as discourse it could have no other history than that of its representations: if ideas, things, knowledge, or feelings happened to change, then and only then did a given language undergo modification, and in exactly the same proportion as the changes in question.35 In this context, Williams notes that “the role of language is to articulate, reveal and seek out similitude in the order of words and things”. 36 In the classical age language was thus primarily used to unite differences, by inscribing an order of discourse that amounted to sameness and identity. 34 Colebrook, Philosophy and Post-structuralist Theory, p. 163. Michel Foucault, The Order of Things: An Archaeology of the Human Sciences, (London: Routledge, 2002), p. 256. 36 Williams, Contemporary French Philosophy, p. 161. 35 23 However, this symbiotic relationship between words and things began to fall apart towards the end of the 18th century. And the main reason behind this change, according to Foucault, was the increasing complexity of the objects of knowledge that no longer could be accommodated within the dominant Western episteme. Foucault refers here explicitly to “labour, life, language” as the main examples of objects that were undergoing this transformation and that consequently started to move beyond the scope of immediate representation.37 The outcome of this transformation was that the relationship between words and things began to crack, or more specifically that the objects suddenly were placed beyond the reach of words. As Foucault explains: The space of order, which served as a common place for representation and for things, for empirical visibility and for the essential rules, which united the regularities of nature and the resemblances of imagination in the grid of identities and differences, which displayed the empirical sequence of representations in a simultaneous table, and made it possible to scan step by step, in accordance with a logical sequence, the totality of nature’s elements thus rendered contemporaneous with one another – this space of order is from now on shattered: there will be things … and then representation, a purely temporal succession, in which those things address themselves (always partially) to a subjectivity, a consciousness, a singular effort of cognition, to the ‘psychological’ individual who from the depth of his own history, or on the basis of the tradition handed on to him, is trying to know. Representation is in the process of losing its power to define the mode of being common to things and to knowledge. The very being of that which is represented is now going to fall outside representation itself.38 Despite the transformation of objects, and despite initially being placed outside language and beyond an immediate relationship with words, the new 37 38 See Foucault, The Order of Things, chapter 8. Ibid., p. 260. 24 objects were eventually seen as a new “element” that was “introduced into the analysis of language”. 39 In this way, instead of being excluded from language, the new objects changed the very function of language. According to this change, words could still be used to reflect the meaning and order of things. However, the way in which they did so was not through an immediate or symbiotic relationship with things, but rather by being determined by “man” as a transcendent subject. According to Foucault’s analysis, “man” was thus invented in order to provide an origin of thought, from which it was then possible to transcend as well as represent the true meaning and order of things. It is important to point out, then, that the idea of “man” as a transcendent subject is not something that has always existed. It can rather be understood as “a quite recent creature”, which emerged towards the end of the 18th century. 40 For this reason it also has to be noted that the idea of “man” should not be seen as external to the historical context in which it is produced.41 Nor should “man’s” position be seen as external to the discourse “he” is assumed to master. Rather, “man” as a transcendent subject has to be understood as an effect of this discourse, an effect that nevertheless might acquire the role of a subject. In order to analyse this role it is therefore important to begin by getting “rid of the subject itself”, as well as to problematise and question rather than just assume the existence of an essentialist subject as the natural ground for language and representation.42 Moreover, the important task following this problematisation is to examine the discursive practices that constitute the subject as a ground. According to Foucault: If there is one approach that I do reject, however, it is that (one might call it, broadly speaking, the phenomenological approach) which gives absolute priority to the observing subject, which attributes a constituent 39 Ibid., p. 256. Ibid., p. 336. 41 Ibid., p. 265. 42 Michel Foucault, “Truth and Power”, in Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews and Other Writings, edited by Colin Gordon, (Essex: Harvester Press, 1980), p. 117. 40 25 role to the act, which places its own point of view at the origin of all historicity – which, in short, leads to a transcendental consciousness. It seems to me that the historical analysis of scientific discourse should, in the last resort, be subject, not to a theory of the knowing subject, but rather to a theory of discursive practice.43 Following this critique of the subject, Foucault also criticises the idea of a metaphysical outside reality. In the same way as “man” is not external to the discourse “he” is assumed to master, “things” never correspond to a reality that is outside discourse. Rather, things always have to be understood as immanent to the “discursive practices” that produce the specific relations between “words” and “things”. Foucault thus argues (in a similar way to Derrida) that the dualistic form of representation as a method for determining the true meaning of things is deeply problematic. It is problematic because it has to rely upon the idea of separating between subjects and objects as independent and pre-established entities. But instead of seeing them as independent, Foucault’s analysis shows how subjects and objects can be viewed as mutually constituted, or how they are produced by discursive practices in different historical contexts. Deleuze: representation as illusion According to Deleuze, one way to understand the logic of representation is by looking at how conceptions of the “general” relate to ideas about the “particular”, or how generalisations are made on the basis of particular cases. 44 The connection between generalities (or general laws) and particulars relies on the assumptions of “resemblance” and “equivalence”, which render the possibility of examining particular cases by referring to 43 Foucault, The Order of Things, p. xv. Gilles Deleuze, Difference and Repetition, translated by Paul Patton, (London: Continuum, 2004), p. 44. 44 26 their correlative resemblances and status of equivalence under the horizon of general laws.45 According to Deleuze, by thinking in terms of generalities and particulars most philosophical ideas can be said to operate within the limits of representation. Consequently, it is mainly within those limits that concepts of philosophical discourse are deployed. One such concept, which is central to Deleuze’s philosophy, is “difference”. In one sense, Deleuze’s philosophical project is focused on rethinking the concept of difference. But it also includes a critique of how the concept of difference traditionally has been used. This critique focuses mainly on how difference tends to be used in order to represent differences between particular cases of perception, as well as to make comparisons between those cases. This happens, for example, by pointing to analogies and resemblances: As a concept of reflection, difference testifies to its full submission to all the requirements of representation, which becomes thereby “organic representation”. In the concept of reflection, mediating and mediated difference is in effect fully subject to the identity of the concept, the opposition of predicates, the analogy of judgement and the resemblance of perception.46 By tying difference to resemblance and analogy its role or function becomes subordinated to the principle of identity. However, according to Deleuze, this subordination can only lead to a world of representation, which is based on nothing but a pure illusion. More specifically, Deleuze refers to this as a “transcendental illusion”, which means that it relies upon the assumption of an ontological being that grounds knowledge in relation to a metaphysical notion of an outside reality: A good example of this can be found in the philosophical idea of the “moral law”, a universal law that is established by generalising particular cases on the basis of their resemblances and equivalences. Ibid., p. 5. 46 Ibid., p. 44. 45 27 Representation is a site of transcendental illusion. This illusion comes in several forms, four interrelated forms which correspond particularly to thought, sensibility, the Idea and being. In effect, thought is covered over by an ‘image’ made up of postulates which distort both its operation and its genesis. These postulates culminate in the position of an identical thinking subject, which functions as a principle of identity for concepts in general.47 Two central themes in Deleuze’s critique of representation can be found here. The first is what Deleuze refers to as an “identical thinking subject” and the second is the notion of “identity for concepts”. According to Deleuze, both of these themes are crucial for understanding representation as a site of “transcendental illusion”. Specifically, they are crucial for understanding how the “different” and “disparate” are reduced to mere notions of sameness, resemblance and common sense. Following such notions, difference has to be cancelled in favour of a superior form of identity, in relation to which difference is treated as something that can be qualitatively known. However, according to Deleuze, difference can never be known as such, which is why the idea of subordinating it to identity also has to be regarded as deeply problematic. It is problematic because in order to determine the meaning of difference, and to make it conform to the requirements of representation, it is unavoidable to submit thought to some kind of illusory ground. One such illusory ground relates to the notion of a pre-established subject who is capable of transcending and representing the meaning of objects in accordance with an external reality. An example of this notion can be found in René Descartes’ philosophical statement: “I think, therefore I am”, which seeks to establish an ontological foundation in the form of a thinking subject.48 In doing so, there is also an attempt to represent particular cases, and to make them conform to a general law by positioning an ontological being of the subject as an ultimate ground or foundation. But according to Deleuze, the idea of such a ground or foundation should be seen 47 48 Ibid., p. 334. Ibid., p. 164. 28 as highly problematic; partly because it tries to generalise what it means to think and what it means to know: “It is because everybody naturally thinks that everybody is supposed to know implicitly what it means to think.”49 Instead of taking such a generalisation as given, Deleuze problematises it by pointing to the way in which the thinking subject is placed outside the world, whilst at the same time having the capacity to make truth claims about the world. According to Deleuze, this idea is enabled by a particular “Image of thought”, which seeks to provide an essentialist ground for knowledge by assuming a “pre-philosophical” element of “common sense”: Postulates in philosophy are not propositions the acceptance of which the philosopher demands; but, on the contrary, propositional themes which remain implicit and are understood in a pre-philosophical manner. In this sense, conceptual philosophical thought has as its implicit presupposition a pre-philosophical and natural Image of thought, borrowed from the pure element of common sense. According to this image, thought has an affinity with the true; it formally possesses the true and materially wants the true. It is in terms of this image that everybody knows and is presumed to know what it means to think.50 According to Deleuze, the very logic of representation relies upon a traditional image of thought, which despite lacking a foundation functions as a general ground for thought and knowledge. As such, this ground plays a crucial role in philosophical discourse, and it provides the basis for separating the subject from externally existing objects. In doing so, this ground can also be seen as the basis for thinking in terms of universality: “The classical image of thought, and the striating of mental space it effects, aspires to universality. It in effect operates with two ‘universals,’ the Whole as the final ground of being or all-encompassing horizon, and the Subject as 49 50 Ibid., p. 166. Ibid., p. 167. 29 the principle that converts being into being-for-us.”51 Following this classical image of thought it is for example assumed that a relationship between the subject’s perception and the concepts that are used to describe the objects of perception can be established, which means that representation is based on the authority of the subject to determine the correspondence between objects and concepts: With representation, concepts are like possibilities, but the subject of representation still determines the object as really conforming to the concept, as an essence. That is why representation as a whole is the element of knowledge which is realised by the recollection of the thought object and its recognition by a thinking subject. 52 In this way, representation requires the notion of a thinking subject, which functions as the ground for making truth claims about the meaning of objects. The notion of a thinking subject must therefore be presupposed in representation, as must the separation between the subject and an external world. Representation, in this sense, is always “equivocal”, which means that it consists of two separate planes: the thinking subject and the outside world. 53 As Colebrook explains: “transcendence is equivocal: positing a being that is – the outside world – and a being that knows or represents – mind or ‘man’.” 54 The latter thus functions as a ground for the former, enabling “man” to transcend an outside world in order to represent the meaning of particular objects. But the question, then, is how such a distinction is made possible in the first place, and how the hierarchical relationship between “man” and the world or mind and matter can be explained. For Deleuze, the answer to these questions cannot be found in a search for origins or foundations. Rather, they require a more radical 51 Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari, A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia, translated by Brian Massumi, (London: Continuum, 2004), p. 418. 52 Deleuze, Difference and Repetition, p. 240. 53 Gilles Deleuze, The Logic of Sense, translated by Mark Lester, edited by Constantin V. Boundas, (London: Continuum, 2004), p. 288. 54 Claire Colebrook, Gilles Deleuze, (London: Routledge, 2002), p. 95. 30 approach to thought and experience, according to which the separation between the subject and the world, and the hierarchical relationship between mind and matter have to be understood in terms of a production. Later in this chapter we shall see exactly what this approach to thought and experience implies, and how it can be used to challenge the limits of representation in order to think about the “event”. Suffice it to say here that Deleuze clearly rejects the equivocal and dualistic form of representation, which he sees as nothing but a pure illusion that relies upon a ground that ultimately lacks a foundation. Beyond representation? Derrida, Foucault and Deleuze can all be said to provide critiques of representation. And despite the differences between their critiques they all share the view of representation as something that necessarily has to rely upon that which is absent: a pure presence, the signified, an autonomous subject, etc. Representation is thus criticised for lacking an ultimate ground or foundation upon which it nevertheless seeks to determine the true meaning and order of things. On the basis of this critique, an important question is whether we are stuck in the representational paradigm, or whether it might also be possible to think outside or beyond it. According to Colebrook, the poststructuralist critique of representation can indeed be said to imply another mode of thinking, which is evident by the ways in which this critique often issues in an apocalyptic or utopian projection of a point beyond representation, a radical homelessness in which thought no longer locates itself within a totality, logic or scheme. And this freedom from grounding or totality would also overcome a sense of the world as being or presence, in favour of a continual becoming, effect, or non-presence. Against the location of thought within the point of view of a representing subject, this anti-representationalism strives to think beyond all subjectivism.55 55 Colebrook, “Questioning Representation”, pp. 48-9. 31 According to Colebrook, the idea of thinking “beyond all subjectivism” can also be found in the critiques of representation offered by Derrida, Foucault and Deleuze. Following those critiques, the point is not to analyse representation from a representational point of view but rather from a position that itself can be located outside representation. In Derrida’s work, for example, there is the (quasi)concept of différence as the free play of differences. And in Foucault’s work, there is the notion of power relations as something that cannot be represented but is rather “active, ungrounded and multiple”.56 However, it is in Deleuze’s philosophy that the most explicit attempt to think outside representation can be found. This attempt relates specifically to his concept of “transcendental empiricism”, which highlights the role of different processes and movements, of for example thought, sense and experience, which are located beyond the level of subjects and objects, and independently of the ways in which subjects and objects tend to be separated from one another. These processes and movements can also be linked to a “plane of immanence”, which refers to a pure flow of life and experience that lacks any direct correspondence to a transcendent point of view. As such, this plane constitutes a starting point from which it is then possible to see the emergence and production of something new: All processes take place on the plane of immanence, and within a given multiplicity: unification, subjectifications, rationalizations, centralizations have no special status; they often amount to an impasse or closing off that prevents the multiplicity’s growth, the extension and unfolding of its lines, the production of something new.57 The plane of immanence thus seems to offer a way of thinking about productions or constructions, not of concrete “things” but rather of what 56 Colebrook, Philosophy and Post-structuralist Theory, p. 165. Gilles Deleuze, Negotiations: 1972-1990, translated by Martin Joughin, (New York: Columbia University Press, 1995), p. 146. 57 32 Deleuze refers to as “multiplicity”, which is the “real element in which things happen”.58 And even though there will always be different attempts to unify and rationalise things and thereby prevent the lines of a multiplicity from unfolding these attempts will never result in independently existing “things”, or in something transcendent that has been released from the plane of immanence. According to Deleuze, “there’s nothing transcendent, no Unity, subject (or object), Reason; there are only processes, sometimes unifying, subjectifying, rationalizing, but just processes all the same”.59 Deleuze’s insistent focus on processes can also be seen as particularly useful when trying to think further about the “event”, especially if the purpose of doing so is to challenge the notion of “events” as independently existing objects that exist in a fixed moment in time. However, this does not mean that for example Foucault’s concept of power relations is not useful when thinking about “events”. In fact, there might be very good reasons to look more closely at this concept later on in the thesis. And in a similar way, it can be argued that Derrida also offers an interesting way of thinking about that which happens outside the representational realm. In relation to the idea of signification, for example, Derrida develops the concept of force, which does not stem from language itself but rather expresses the “other of language”.60 However, even though this dimension can be found in Derrida’s philosophy, it seems to me that it does not figure to the same extent or at least not as explicitly as in Deleuze’s work. In this way, there appears to be a limit in how far Derrida goes in trying to conceptualize the “other of language”, in terms of for example experience and thought. Again, this is precisely why Deleuze’s philosophy can be seen as so interesting, because it offers a richer and more thorough alternative to articulate a dimension “outside” language and representation, not just in terms of an abstract force, 58 Ibid., p. 146. Ibid., p. 145. 60 Jacques Derrida, “Force and Signification”, in Writing and Difference, translated by Alan Bass, (London: Routledge, 2001). For a further discussion on the similarities between Derrida’s and Deleuze’s respective approach to language, see Alan Bourassa, “Literature, Language, and the Non-Human”, in Brian Massumi (ed.), A Shock to Thought: Expression after Deleuze and Guattari, (London: Routledge, 2002). 59 33 but more concretely in terms of what really happens there. In the remainder of this chapter I hope to make this point clearer by looking at Deleuze’s concepts of “difference”, “multiplicity” and “transcendental empiricism”. 1.2 Deleuze’s empiricism and philosophy difference In order to explain Deleuze’s transcendental empiricism and its implications for thinking about the “event” it is first necessary to examine in more detail his critique of representation. Specifically, what needs to be examined is how this critique also involves an attempt to rethink some of the concepts that representation relies upon. As we saw in the previous section, one of these concepts is “difference”. Here, then, I will look at how Deleuze develops his own concept of difference and how this concept also can be linked to Deleuze’s “transcendental empiricism”. Difference and multiplicity Going back to Deleuze’s critique of representation, it can be argued that one of the main aims of this critique is to free thought from the illusion of transcendence, which Deleuze sees as inherent in representation. For Deleuze, as long as thinking takes place within a world of representation there will always be limits imposed on thought, limits that are constituted by a traditional “Image of thought”. As was explained earlier, this image relies upon the idea of separating an autonomous subject from independently existing objects. And following this idea, the superior “I” of the subject functions as the highest ground for determining the meaning of those objects, thus constituting the very essence of thinking. In this way, Deleuze notes: “‘I think’ is the most general principle of representation.”61 In other words, it is the notion of “I think” that unifies the objects of representation and provides the foundation for their meaning. And as we saw in the previous section, the consequence of this unification is that difference is subordinated to identity and similarity, which means that “difference becomes an object of 61 Deleuze, Difference and Repetition, p. 174. 34 representation always in relation to a conceived identity, a judged analogy, an imagined opposition or a perceived similitude”.62 According to Deleuze, there are in particular two philosophers whose ideas have contributed to this understanding of difference: Plato and Hegel. One of Deleuze’s main criticisms of Hegel’s philosophy is that it forces difference into a subordinated and negative role. This follows from Hegel’s view of “dialectics”, according to which difference is affirmed only to the extent that it reflects upon the identity of contraries and oppositions. As such, difference is subordinated to identity and “reduced to the negative, incarcerated within similitude and analogy”. 63 Identity, in this sense, functions as a higher ground or metaphysical foundation for thinking about difference. “Difference is the ground, but only the ground for the demonstration of the identical.”64 According to Deleuze, this way of thinking can also be found in Plato’s philosophy, and especially when considering the relationship between essence and appearance, the original and the image, and model and copy in Plato’s philosophy: The model is supposed to enjoy an originary superior identity (…) whereas the copy is judged in terms of a derived internal resemblance. Indeed, it is in this sense that difference comes only in third place, behind identity and resemblance, and can be understood only in terms of these prior notions. Difference is understood only in terms of the comparative play of two similitudes: the exemplary similitude of an identical original and the imitative similitude of a more or less accurate copy.65 The only conceivable differences are consequently those that are already based on a relationship between the original and the copy. But in addition to these terms there is another concept in Plato’s philosophy that Deleuze 62 Ibid., p. 174. Ibid., p. 61. 64 Ibid., p. 61. 65 Ibid., p. 154. 63 35 highlights: the “simulacrum”. Rather than being the imitation of the original, the simulacrum refers to the imitation of appearances. As such, the simulacrum is merely a “copy of copies” and lacks any connection whatsoever with superior “forms”. For this reason, the simulacrum has an inferior role in relation to the original copies, representing nothing but “bad copies”. Accordingly, in Plato’s philosophy the aim is to assure the “triumph of the copies over simulacra, of repressing simulacra, keeping them completely submerged”, as well as to prevent them from “climbing to the surface, and ‘insinuating themselves’ everywhere”.66 Plato can, in this sense, be seen as complicit in the process of suppressing difference by forcing it to comply with superior forms and hierarchical identities. Against this suppression, Deleuze seeks to overturn the Platonic world of representation by reversing the relationship between the original and the copy. And the way he does so is by giving the simulacrum a completely different role. Instead of merely seeing it as a “bad copy”, which has to be excluded from the relationship between the original and the copy, Deleuze gives the simulacrum a superior role. For Deleuze, overturning Platonism thus implies “denying the primacy of original over copy, of model over image; glorifying the reign of simulacra and reflections”.67 Hence, contrary to Plato, Deleuze finds in the simulacrum a “positive power”, which gives difference another role than simply being subordinated to identity and resemblance. Lacking identity of any kind, the simulacrum consists only of differences, which exist without ever being tied to notions of the same and the similar: Simulacra are those systems in which different relates to different by means of difference itself. What is essential is that we find in these systems no prior identity, no internal resemblance. It is all a matter of difference in the series, and of differences of difference in the communication between series. What is displaced and disguised in the 66 67 Deleuze, The Logic of Sense, p. 294. Deleuze, Difference and Repetition, p. 80. 36 series cannot and must not be identified, but exists and acts as the differenciator of difference.68 We are now getting closer to Deleuze’s own concept of difference, which follows from the simulacrum and the idea of freeing difference from the constraints that are imposed on it by the relationship between model and copy. And what we are left with as a consequence of this seems to be the different and the disparate as such, without any prior connection to identity. Deleuze makes this point in the following way: Let us consider the two formulas: “only that which resembles differs” and “only differences can resemble each other”. These are two distinct readings of the world: one invites us to think difference from the standpoint of a previous similitude or identity; whereas the other invites us to think similitude and even identity as the product of a deep disparity. The first reading precisely defines the world of copies or representations; it posits the world as icon. The second, contrary to the first, defines the world of simulacra.69 What Deleuze seems to suggest here, then, is that by refusing to subordinate the simulacrum to the relationship between model and copy it is also possible to refuse subordinating difference to the same and the identical. Following the simulacrum, it is difference as such that matters, not the original and the copy, and not identity and resemblance. Identity should therefore no longer be regarded as primary but only as secondary. More specifically, it is secondary in relation to a form of difference that does not relate to anything but itself. In this way, Deleuze develops the concept of difference by suggesting that difference has to be thought of as difference in itself, ungrounded and without the possibility of making analogies. 70 As such, difference can also be described as all there is, which means that it lacks a 68 Ibid., pp. 372-3. Deleuze, The Logic of Sense, p. 299. 70 See Difference and Repetition, chapter 1. 69 37 general background or context against which it is possible to make comparisons between separate cases. According to Deleuze: “It is always differences which resemble one another, which are analogous, opposed or identical: difference is behind everything but behind difference there is nothing.”71 In a similar way to how Deleuze seeks to overturn Platonism he also points to the possibility of reversing the Hegelian system of oppositions by suggesting that it is not “difference which presupposes opposition but opposition which presupposes difference, and far from resolving difference by tracing it back to a foundation, opposition betrays and distorts it”.72 When thinking difference in itself it is thus crucial to detach it from any ideas about oppositions, since the latter only have the effect of distorting difference. To prevent it from being distorted, it is necessary to affirm the disparate and formless being of differences as such rather than tying them to dialectical oppositions. One way of doing so can be found in Deleuze’s notion of “repetition”, which he sees as nothing but a continuous process of repeating difference rather than the same. According to Deleuze: Repetition is the formless being of all differences, the formless power of the ground which carries every object to that extreme ‘form’ in which its representation comes undone. The ultimate element of repetition is the disparate, which stands opposed to the identity of representation.73 Repetition for Deleuze thus expresses a power that eludes any particular forms. As such, it also disables the idea of representation. Since the latter relies on the existence of the original as a superior form, which then can be represented by providing a faithful copy of it, if you take away the original it makes no sense to provide such a copy. According to Deleuze, the original as 71 Ibid., p. 69. Ibid., pp. 62-3. 73 Ibid., p. 69. 72 38 well as the copy disappears in the abyss created by repetition as the formless ground in which everything comes undone. When developing this idea of repetition, Deleuze draws heavily upon Nietzsche’s concept of the “eternal return”, which Deleuze refers to as a selective process that only brings back the different and dissimilar rather than the same or identical: The eternal return does not bring back “the same”, but returning constitutes the only Same of that which becomes. Returning is the becoming-identical of becoming itself. Returning is thus the only identity, but identity as a secondary power; the identity of difference, the identical which belongs to the different, or turns around the different. Such an identity, produced by difference, is determined as “repetition”. Repetition in the eternal return, therefore, consists in conceiving the same on the basis of the different.74 Following the eternal return, the same and the identical will never return; it is only difference that will return. Difference, in this sense, can be seen as primary in relation to identity, which means that identity comes after difference, as a product that emerges from the “formless being of all differences”. Moreover, Deleuze suggests that “the eternal return is a force of affirmation”.75 As such, it affirms the different and the disparate instead of the same or identical, with the latter remaining as nothing but an illusion and the former lacking any kind of identity, similarity or centre on which it is organised: Difference must become the element, the ultimate unity; it must therefore refer to other differences which never identify it but rather differenciate it. Each term of a series, being already a difference, must be put into a variable relation with other terms, thereby constituting other series devoid of centre and convergence. Divergence and 74 75 Ibid., p. 51. Ibid., p. 141. 39 decentring must be affirmed in the series itself. Every object, every thing, must see its own identity swallowed up in difference, each being no more than a difference between differences.76 When difference is understood in relation to the eternal return it is possible to see it less as a category than as a process.77 This process involves the communication between differences, or between the different and the different, constituting what Deleuze refers to as “multiplicity”. According to Deleuze, multiplicity does not designate a relationship between the many and the one; it is rather “an organisation belonging to the many as such, which has no need whatsoever of unity in order to form a system”.78 So, instead of an ordered system that is focused on the many and the one, multiplicity consists of indeterminate differences, which “do not add up to a totality, and do not refer to a subject”.79 In this way, difference can be said to function as a primary force, without being tied to a pre-determined direction, a given place and time, or the being of a subject. Hence, Deleuze argues that multiplicities “imply no prior identity, no positing of a something that could be called one or the same. On the contrary, their indetermination renders possible the manifestation of difference freed from all subordination.”80 Deleuze also suggests that multiplicity has to be understood as “virtual” rather than “actual”. The virtual in Deleuze’s philosophy is not opposed to the “real”, and neither is it something artificial or simulated. On the contrary, the virtual is more real than anything else. And the main reason for this is that the virtual does not suppress difference in favour of identity, but refers only to the indeterminate relationship between differences, or between the different and the different. As it expresses a freer role of difference, the 76 Ibid., p. 68. Paul Patton, Deleuze and the Political, (London: Routledge, 2000), p. 39. 78 Deleuze, Difference and Repetition, p. 230. 79 Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari, “Preface to the Italian Edition of A Thousand Plateuas”, in Gilles Deleuze, Two Regimes of Madness: Texts and Interviews 1975-1995, translated by Ames Hodges and Mike Taormina, edited by David Lapoujade, (New York: Semiotext(e), 2006), p. 310. 80 Deleuze, Difference and Repetition, p. 231. 77 40 virtual eludes representation as well as a systematic order of knowledge and regularities. Transcendental empiricism By developing the concepts of multiplicity and difference in itself, Deleuze seeks to overcome a notion of philosophy as something that is mainly reactive and representational, and whose ultimate goals are to determine the meaning of things, to find solutions to problems, and to discover the true in opposition to the false. This latter notion of philosophy suggests that thinking itself is only possible if it takes place against the background of that which is already given, and to find solutions to the problems that have already been presented to us. In this way, as Deleuze notes: We are led to believe that problems are given ready-made, and that they disappear in the responses or the solution. Already, under this double aspect, they can be no more than phantoms. We are led to believe that the activity of thinking, along with truth and falsehood in relation to that activity, begins only with the search for solutions, that both of these concern only solutions. This belief probably has the same origin as the other postulates of the dogmatic image: puerile examples taken out of context and arbitrarily erected into models. According to this infantile prejudice, the master sets a problem, our task is to solve it, and the result is accredited true or false by a powerful authority.81 The “dogmatic image” that Deleuze refers to here can thus be said to have the effect of reducing thought to finding solutions, discovering truth and establishing common sense understandings. But in contrast to this image, Deleuze’s philosophy of difference and multiplicity has a completely different aim, which is to discover the active and creative conditions for thought. Crucially, these conditions are not to be found in representation or recognition but rather in the very “act of thinking and in thought itself”.82 81 82 Ibid., p. 197. Ibid., p. 176. 41 In Difference and Repetition, Deleuze writes: “Something in the world forces us to think. This something is an object not of recognition but of a fundamental encounteri.”83 The object of this encounter, then, is not referring to any possible solutions to an already given problem but rather to the processes by which the problem itself is given as a problem. This requires that we move away from any kind of external conditions for thought, and away from the idea of a transcendent regulative ideal, which grants us knowledge and provides common sense understandings. In other words, we must abandon the field of transcendence and replace it with a “transcendental field” or a “plane of immanence”. The “transcendental”, in this sense, refers to something very different than “transcendence”. Whereas the latter refers to that which is “external” to experience, the former concerns that which is directly experienced or given. In this way, the “transcendental” can paradoxically be said to imply an “immanent” conception of experience, which seeks to move away from the illusion of transcendence, or the idea of transcending a reality of the “world” from the viewpoint of an autonomous subject or a superior “I”. As Daniel W. Smith notes, “transcendental philosophy is a philosophy of immanence, and implies a ruthless critique of transcendence”. 84 And as we saw in the previous section, this critique is directed against the ways in which difference is subordinated to identity, and how this subordination implies a process of unifying and totalising the conditions for knowledge. Against this view, Deleuze articulates a purely “transcendental field”, which, contrary to transcendence, does not attempt to reflect or represent that which is outside experience. Rather, it seeks to articulate a form of experience that is directly given, not to an autonomous and pre-established subject but only given as such. This notion of experience thus seeks to elude a superior viewpoint as well as the consciousness of a pre-established subject. 83 Ibid., p. 176. Daniel W. Smith, “Deleuze, Kant, and the Theory of Immanent Ideas”, in Constantin V. Boundas (ed.), Deleuze and Philosophy, (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2006), p. 47. 84 42 Instead, it relates to what Deleuze refers to as the “impersonal” and “preindividual” elements of experience: We seek to determine an impersonal and pre-individual transcendental field, which does not resemble the corresponding empirical fields, and which nevertheless is not confused with an undifferentiated depth. This field cannot be determined as that of a consciousness. (…) [W]e cannot retain consciousness as a milieu while at the same time we object to the form of the person and the point of view of individuation. A consciousness is nothing without a synthesis of unification, but there is no synthesis of unification of consciousness without the form of the I, or the point of view of the Self. What is neither individual nor personal are, on the contrary emissions of singularities insofar as they occur on an unconscious surface and possess a mobile, immanent principle of auto-unification through a nomadic distribution radically distinct from fixed and sedentary distributions as conditions of the syntheses of consciousness.85 One of the most important concepts according to this idea of a transcendental field of experience is “singularity”, which Deleuze defines as the “pre-individual, pre-personal and a-conceptual”. 86 As such, singularity can also be said to express a realm that is prior to the idea of a unifying or superior I, and disconnected from a pure consciousness of the subject. Singularity relates to experience as such, without a pre-established subject who experiences. As Colebrook explains, “we might say that there just ‘is’ experience, without subjects or objects, inside or outside…a pure flow of life and perception without any distinct perceivers”.87 So, rather than an already present subject who thinks and experiences, there is only thought and only experience. 85 Deleuze, The Logic of Sense, p. 118. Ibid., p. 63. 87 Colebrook, Deleuze, p. 74. 86 43 Developing this idea of experience further, Deleuze and Félix Guattari refer to a “plane of immanence”.88 When introducing this plane they seek to get away from the ontological assumption of having two separate planes, mind and matter, according to which the former transcends the latter in order to represent an external material world. So, rather than having two separate planes, the plane of immanence locates the being of the subject as well as the being of an outside world on the same plane: a plane that consists solely of impersonal and pre-individual elements of thought and experience. Everything thus becomes part of these elements, making the “outside world” and the “subject” into integral elements of the very processes of thought and experience. This means, furthermore, that the plane of immanence should not be put in opposition to something that is assumed to exist externally or prior to it. For example, it would be misleading to interpret the plane of immanence as immanent to something or someone. 89 Doing so would inevitably reintroduce the distinction between the being of the subject and the being of an outside world and bring us back to the illusion of transcendence and representation yet again. In order to avoid this illusion, it is necessary to understand immanence as immanent to nothing other than itself. In this way, empiricism has to start with experience as such, without a primary distinction between the internal and the external, the subject and an outside world. Singularity can be seen as an element or a force that is prior to ideas about an individualised or personalised form of being. This means that in a similar way to the idea of reversing the role of difference in relation to identity, the singular functions as a reversal of a presupposed ontological “being” or “unity” of the subject. The implication of this reversal is that the unity or identity of the subject no longer can be seen as a primary ground or foundation for experience. Rather, identity has to be seen as something that is produced as an effect of experience. The singular, therefore, has no unity or identity, and it cannot be translated or generalised into particular notions 88 Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari, What is Philosophy?, translated by Graham Burchell and Hugh Tomlinson, (London: Verso, 1994), chapter 2. 89 Ibid., p. 45. 44 of “common sense”. As something that is completely impersonal and preindividual, the singular escapes any such notions. The representant says: “Everyone recognises that …”, but there is always an unrepresented singularity who does not recognise precisely because it is not everyone or the universal. “Everyone” recognises the universal because it is itself the universal, but the profound sensitive conscience which is nevertheless presumed to bear the cost, the singular, does not recognise it. The misfortune of speaking is not speaking, but speaking for others or representing something.90 In the process of establishing “common sense” understandings, through recognition and representation, the singular is always in a sense suppressed. So, in order to release the singular from this suppression it is important to refuse the generalised notions of “common sense” and instead let the singular play a different role. In brief, rather than trying to reduce it to a determinable object of experience, the singular should remain an indeterminate and indiscernible element of experience. As such, the singular is no longer allowed to fall back on an external background or context, which makes it disappear among determinable objects and identifiable differences. The singular remains singular by eluding any such differences and by connecting instead with “nondialectizable” differences, or with a form of difference that can only be conceived of as difference in itself. Singularity, in this sense, does not possess any kind of unity or identity, object or entity; nor can it be contained within notions of “common sense” or “good sense”. Rather, it highlights a completely different “logic” of sense – one that John Rajchman describes in the following way: It is a logic of “sense” prior to any established “truth-values” and public agreements, or prior to “I think” or “we think”, always ramifying or proliferating in unexpected ways. It is a logic for thinking not in terms of generalities and particularities, but rather in terms of singular ideas, 90 Deleuze, Difference and Repetition, p. 176. 45 complications and “complex themes” – not in terms of identities and oppositions but rather of “differences” over which we can’t quantify and interstices between given distinctions or with what is not yet and never completely “ontologically determined”.91 Following this understanding of Deleuze’s “logic of sense” it is important not to think of singularities, or singular ideas, in terms of mere generalities or particularities. They should rather be thought of as “complications” or “complex themes”. In this way, singularity can also be related to “multiplicity”, since it rejects the opposition between the many and the one and instead highlights a system that affirms the many as such as well as difference in itself, where the different relates to the different and never to dialectical terms and systems of opposition. Hence, the singular does not rely upon a prior identity but can rather be said to provoke the dissolution of identity. This follows once again from Deleuze’s take on the eternal return, which only allows the different to return, whilst excluding the same and the identical. According to Deleuze: Repetition in the eternal return never means continuation, perpetuation or prolongation, nor even the discontinuous return of something which would at least be able to be prolonged in a partial circle (an identity, an I, a Self) but, on the contrary, the reprise of pre-individual singularities which, in order that it can be grasped as repetition, presupposes the dissolution of all prior identities.92 The singular should thus not be confused with either the particular or the identical. It relates instead to an active and creative process, which enables experience and thought to encounter something that is yet to be known. And it is precisely this indeterminate element of thought and experience that is crucial when trying to understand Deleuze’s attempt to develop a transcendental form of empiricism. 91 92 John Rajchman, The Deleuze Connections, (London: The MIT Press, 2000), p. 52. Deleuze, Difference and Repetition, p. 176. 46 At one point Deleuze suggests that the aim of transcendental empiricism “is not to rediscover the eternal or the universal, but to find the conditions under which something new is produced (creativeness)”.93 To do so it is moreover important not to begin with ideas about some abstract unity, such as “the One, the Whole, the Subject”, which then is given the task of explaining. 94 Instead of letting the abstract explain, Deleuze argues, the abstract “must itself be explained”. And one way of doing so is to begin by looking at the various processes and movements through which the abstract is produced. Also, it is the very nature of these processes, as something that is constantly moving rather than static that has to be examined. In doing so it might then be possible to understand how different kinds of ideas emerge, and how notions of the Whole, the One, and Identity are produced. So, rather than taking these notions for granted, Deleuze’s transcendental empiricism provokes an examination of how they are produced and made possible in the first place. As such, it can also be seen as an interesting alternative to a representational mode of thinking. As pointed out earlier, the latter is both limited and problematic since it assumes a prior distinction between subjects and objects as it seeks to unveil their nature through the establishment of “common sense” understandings. Deleuze’s philosophy takes us in a completely different direction, forcing us to think of very different kinds of questions. To conclude this chapter I will discuss what some of those questions might be and how they can be used in order to think further about the “event”. Conclusion The problem set out in the introduction was how to understand ideas about “9/11” as an “event”. According to those ideas, “9/11” constitutes a central reference point in time, which separates before from after and what is to come from what has been. In this sense, “9/11” appears almost like an object Gilles Deleuze, “Preface to English Edition”, in Gilles Deleuze and Claire Parnet, Dialogues II, translated by Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam, (London: Continuum, 2006), p. vi. 94 Ibid., p. vi. 93 47 or a whole, which is located in a particular point in time and placed within a larger historical context. At the same time, however, exactly what this “event” refers to and what it means can be seen as highly ambiguous. Part of the aim of this chapter was to question the idea of representation as a method for understanding this problem. Following Derrida, Foucault and Deleuze, it was pointed out that the limits of a purely representational mode of thinking can be explained by the ways in which it ultimately has to rely on something that is absent: an autonomous subject of reason, a pure presence, a metaphysical outside reality, etc. As such, representation can also be understood as a form of “illusion”. One such illusion, then, is to think of “9/11” as an independently existing object or unitary whole, which is used in order to refer to something specific that has happened in a particular moment in time. It is an illusion that is based on the idea of an autonomous subject of reason that is capable of transcending an outside reality and representing the meaning of that reality. But the question, then, is how it might be possible to think about “9/11” as an “event” without having to rely on the illusion of representation. One way of doing so would be to follow Deleuze’s attempts to reverse representation, through the development of a transcendental form of empiricism. This form of empiricism implies that instead of starting with the subject/object dualism of representation, it is possible to think of a “plane of immanence” or a “transcendental field” of singularities, according to which there is neither a prior distinction between the internal and the external, nor between the subject and the outside world. There is only a pure flow of experience without a pre-established subject who experiences. As such, experience is also something active and creative rather than reactive and representational; it eludes notions of resemblance and similarity and affirms only indiscernible differences, which are not subordinated to identity and express difference in itself. Hence, transcendental empiricism does not begin with some abstract unity, such as the One or the Whole, which then is given the task of explaining. Rather, it is the One or the Whole that itself needs to be explained, not in terms of a rational unity or totality but as a “multiplicity”: 48 The essential thing, from the point of view of empiricism, is the noun multiplicity, which designates a set of lines or dimensions which are irreducible to one another. Every “thing” is made up in this way. Of course a multiplicity includes focuses of unification, centres of totalization, points of subjectivation, but as factors which can prevent its growth and stop its lines. These factors are in the multiplicity to which they belong, and not the reverse.95 Following this understanding of empiricism it is thus necessary to look at the ways in which each supposed “thing” is produced, as well as to study the impact of different kinds of lines, processes and movements. Crucially, however, this kind of study should not be limited to ideas about the mere “construction” of “things”. As Brian Massumi has argued, the reason for rejecting such ideas is that they often tend to favour a static view of culture and society, rather than emphasising the ongoing processes and movements from which culture and society continually emerge: Ideas about cultural or social construction have dead-ended because they have insisted on bracketing the nature of the process. If you elide nature, you miss the becoming of culture, its emergence (not to mention the history of matter). You miss the continuum of interlinkage, feedforward and feedback, by which movements capture and convert each other to many ends, old, new, and innumerable. Some kind of constructivism is required to account for the processual continuity across categorical divides and for the reality of that qualitative growth, or ontogenesis: the fact that with every move, with every change, there is something new to the world, an added reality. (…) Perhaps “productivism” would be better than constructivism because it connotes emergence. 96 95 Ibid., p. vi. Brian Massumi, Parables for the Virtual: Movement, Affect, Sensation, (London: Duke University Press, 2002), p. 12. 96 49 The kind of “productivism” Massumi calls for here thus focuses on processes as such and not on the static conception of some constructed “thing”. This way of thinking about processes can in many ways be seen as “Deleuzian”. In a similar way to Deleuze, Massumi argues that the aim of thinking and writing is not to “represent” or “describe”, for example by trying to uncover something that is assumed to be hidden. Rather, the aim should be to embrace the inventiveness that is embedded in the processes of thinking and writing. This requires, moreover, a certain degree of “experimentation”, the aim of which is not to uncover an essence but to create different ways of thinking about a problem. This can be done, for example, by inventing concepts or by making new connections and constellations of concepts. Doing so is crucial in order to avoid mere repetitions of the “same”, or “applying” the same concepts and the same constellation of concepts over and over again. Only that which is different returns and, consequently, the concepts used to think about the different must also be different. Concepts do not have a pre-determined essence or meaning, which then can be applied objectively in order to explain something. Concepts are combined and refigured in different ways because they are involved in the very processes of thinking and writing. This idea of concepts can also be found in Deleuze and Guattari’s approach the role of concepts in philosophy. According to Deleuze and Guattari, philosophical concepts are not “waiting for us ready-made” but must always be created and refigured in different ways.97 Only in that way is it possible to escape the limits of representation and the illusion of transcendence. The role of concepts in philosophy, therefore, is not to represent the meaning of “objects” or “things”, which are assumed to exist externally to language. Rather, concepts must themselves be considered as active events, which have the potential to open up space for new ways of thinking. In this way, explanations become more like experimentations and creations, which, as Massumi argues, will hopefully add something new to reality. “To think productivism, you have to allow that even your own logical 97 Deleuze and Guattari, What is Philosophy?, p. 5. 50 efforts feed-back and add to reality, in some small, probably microscopic way. But still.”98 As was noted earlier, the aim of transcendental empiricism is to explain the abstract rather than letting the abstract explain. The abstract, in this sense, is not a universal but a multiplicity, which consists of lines, processes and movements. Deleuze himself constantly introduces new concepts and new constellations of concepts in order to explain how different kinds of multiplicities work and how they are organised. Explaining the abstract is thus not the same as trying to explain the objective nature of an independently existing “thing”. Rather, to explain the abstract involves the creation of new concepts and constellations of concepts, which in their own unique ways contribute to a way of thinking about that “thing” – not as a determinable object or a coherent whole but as a set of lines and relations. It is with this approach in mind that I also intend to create a way of thinking about the “event”. Going back to the example of “9/11” as an “event”, this implies first of all moving away from the idea “9/11” as a given starting point, which then can be used in order to explain what it refers to or represents. Instead of doing the latter, it is necessary to ask how this abstract “thing” itself can be explained. In this way, the “event” cannot be treated as a starting point but has to be seen as a problematic whole, which itself requires critical examination. And the focus of such an examination, then, should be on how the “event” is produced, and what sorts of processes, lines and movements are involved in that production. When addressing the question of how to understand the production of “events” it is important to emphasise that the point is not to come up with an objective way of thinking about that production. Rather, following the idea of experimentation, the point is precisely to create a way of thinking about that production. And even if the concepts that are used to do so have been used in similar ways and in similar constellations before, the point is still to make new constellations and new connections. Where this leads me is uncertain, but so it has to be. “If you know where you will end up when you 98 Massumi, Parables for the Virtual, p. 12. 51 begin, nothing has happened in the meantime.”99 Experimentation requires one to be open towards the unexpected and to follow unpredictable paths, rather than some calculable formula. Hence, what comes out of this does not correspond to a pre-determined solution that is just waiting to be discovered. Rather, whatever comes out of this will be the result of an experimentation, which can be connected with earlier experimentation and which hopefully will lead to yet more experimentation. 99 Ibid., p. 18. 52