Deliberating Publics of Citizens: Postnational citizenship amidst global public spheres Stacy Smith DRAFT-please do not circulate or cite* Introduction: The years bridging the turn from the 20th to the 21st century have been characterized by forces of globalization: the flow of people and capital and environmental pollutants across national borders poses implications for all aspects of society. In the realm of politics and political theory, questions of rights, sovereignty, and citizenship take center stage. Migrations of people across borders due to economic patterns of global capitalism and political contexts driving refugees and asylum seekers to other states raise thorny questions surrounding the derivation of citizenship rights and status and institutional mechanisms for realizing commitments to universal human rights. Moreover, since the fall of the Berlin Wall in the 1980s, political actors and scholars alike have expressed widespread interest in democracy and civil society. Democracy is viewed by many, across ideological spectrums, as the end of history in terms of governmental forms; democracy is viewed by some as necessary for and by others as an antidote to the forces of global capitalism. And civil society, that sphere apart from the state and, usually, the economy, is commonly viewed as integral to democratic governance. Strong and vibrant civil societies make democracy possible; weak civil societies tend to be connected to authoritarian regimes. While many associations of civil society form within nation states, the context of globalization also entails associations that form across national borders. Consequently, the public sphere, or the sphere of civil society *This essay is forthcoming as a chapter in Citizenship Education in National, Trans-national and Global Contexts (preliminary title) edited by Klas Roth and Nicholas Burbules, Sense Publishers. that consists of people, associations, and organizations engaged in debate and discussion about issues of common concern, also transcends static political borders of states. Thus, according to political theorist Nancy Fraser, it is even “commonplace nowadays to speak of ‘transnational public spheres’” (Fraser, TPS, 1). In this essay, I map the terrain of political theoretical issues surrounding citizenship education that arise in the contemporary context of globalization. In the first section I describe the “withering” of the nation state as the primary political unit and the increasingly associational nature of the international political arena. I then discuss implications of this decentering of the nation state for questions of political sovereignty and national citizenship and make the case for the importance of public sphere theory as the normative core of the concept of civil society. In the next section I draw upon a Habermasian strand of deliberative democratic theory to develop a theory of citizenship that emphasizes the central role of the public sphere, including the relationship between participation in voluntary associations and civil publics along side formal political publics (i.e. states). I argue that deliberative publics of citizens have the capacity to generate collective identities and solidarities based upon democratic participation in communities of fate, versus membership in national groups, and to influence policy making in both state and international arenas. Finally, in the last section, I bring these theoretical considerations to bear on practical implications for citizenship education. I conclude by recommending a complementary model of cosmopolitan, deliberative citizenship education that emphasizes the relationship 2 between the state and the pluralistic public spheres of civil society. According to this model, the task of democratic citizenship education is to provide young people with opportunities to deliberately practice public ways of being that allow publics of citizens to flourish and impact formal political processes, within the nation state and beyond. I make some specific recommendations regarding the organization of schooling and curriculum that are particular to public education in the United States. The Withering of the Nation State and The Rise of Civil Society According to Carlos Alberto Torres, “the question facing us in the process of increased globalization is whether the nation-state and citizenship are withering away.” In Torres’ view, the two concepts—citizenship and the nation state—are necessarily linked because “citizenship has always been associated with the constitution and operation of the modern nation-state” (Torres, AERJ, 2002, 373). In this section I argue that while the nation state is indeed being eclipsed by other forms of political organization, the concept of citizenship should not simultaneously fade away. Rather citizenship should be recast in terms of the changing face of formal political sovereignty, on one hand, and the role of citizenship within the multiple public spheres of global civil societies, on the other. The economic and political realities of globalization, in particular the movement of people as laborers and political subjects across national borders, brings to the fore questions of national collective identity, membership rights, and 3 citizenship status in new and acute ways.1 Within this context, the question of the locus of rights claims is central: rights are granted by nations as political sovereigns, and claimed by citizens of those states. Yet human rights, which transcend national borders, are also claimed by persons and endorsed by national and international organizations. This tension between national sovereignty and universal human rights leads Nuhoglu Soysal to conclude in Limits of Citizenship that the nation-state’s scope of action is constrained such that: the state is no longer an autonomous and independent organization closed over a nationally defined population. Instead, we have a system of constitutionally interconnected states with a multiplicity of membership. [Hence]…the logic of personhood supersedes the logic of national citizenship, [and] individual rights and obligations, which were historically located in the nation-state, have increasingly moved to an universalistic plane, transcending the boundaries of particular nation-states. (164-65; cited in Torres, AERJ, 373) According to Torres, Nuhoglu Soysal’s analysis of the limits of citizenship has implications at three levels. At the first level of citizenship, notions of identity and rights are decoupled. The second level includes politics of identity and multiculturalism. Here, the emergence of membership in the polity is ‘multiple in the sense of spanning local, regional, and global identities, and accommodates intersecting complexes or rights, duties, and loyalties” (Nuhoglu Soysal, 166). The third level is comprised of cosmopolitan democracies, which emerge from the importance of the international system for the attainment of democracy worldwide. Such a system is relatively divorced in its origins and constitutive dynamics from codes of the nation-states (Torres, AERJ, 373). 4 While some political theorists respond to the withering of the nation state with a call to reconstitute its strength, I find such a response empirically unworkable and normatively misguided.2 In my view, the erosion of the centrality of the nation state necessitates attention to two related phenomena: 1) the rise of other formal political organizations. Such organizations include what Nuhoglu Soysal refers to above as the interconnection of states, in terms of international and transnational political organizations (such as the United Nations and the European Union), as well as the potential creation of world-level sovereign powers; and 2) the relationship between these formal political institutions and the public spheres of civil society. Hence, I draw upon the work of Nuhoglu Soysal, David Held, and deliberative democratic theorists such as Seyla Benhabib and Nancy Fraser to meld a conception of postnational citizenship that is both cosmopolitan and deliberative. Although I proceed according to the assumption that the nation state is withering in the context of globalization, I warn against a concurrent withering of the notion of citizenship itself. Allowing the fate of citizenship to be linked to the notion of the nation state will result in a further eclipse of public life in the face of encroaching private spheres of the social, in the form of mass society, and the economic realm, in the form of mass capitalism. The nation state we may be able to do without, but proponents of democracy and the public sphere, as the sphere of freedom and political action in concert, must view citizenship in terms of political identities and participatory capacities that democracy cannot do without. Thus, citizenship needs to be recast, set apart from the nation state, and newly 5 theorized in terms of emerging transnational and perhaps global political structures, as well as the public spheres of civil society. Postnational Citizenship and Civil Society The withering of the nation state sets the stage for the importance of building new theories of citizenship commensurate with new realities of globalization. The conception of citizenship that I develop in this essay emphasizes democracy and situates citizenship in relationship to democratic ideals, in both the formal political realm and the public sphere of civil society—in national, transnational and global contexts. In this section I lay out the contours of a postnational citizenship that is both cosmopolitan and deliberative by taking up two key lines of inquiry: first, the question of the locus of citizenship in terms of the relationship between civil society and formal political arenas and second, the question of transnational public spheres. If the nation state is withering, and citizenship has traditionally been cast in terms of an individual’s political status as a member of the nation state, how should this concept be reformulated in the context of democracy in a global era? A response to this question entails not only empirical claims about salient global trends, but conceptual definitions of politics, and normative claims surrounding democracy and public life. All of these layers of analysis are tied up in contemporary explanations of the realm of “civil society.” The concept of civil society has garnered widespread attention in recent years for a number of reasons, among them the rise of emerging democratic governments in Eastern Europe— 6 and related questions surrounding how to create broader social reforms that will support a political culture necessary for democracy to flourish—as well as the work of normative political theorists such as John Rawls and Jurgen Habermas, (particularly the 1989 English translation of Habermas’s The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere). The sheer breadth and scope of scholarly inquiry has itself produced what Edwards and Foley refer to as conceptual confusion and definitional fuzziness in terms of “civil society” as an analytic concept (Foley and Edwards, in American Behavioral Scientist, 1998). Yet, this fuzziness can be avoided by drawing upon a normative theory of civil society, particularly one that emphasizes both the legitimating and epistemic functions of citizenship within the public sphere (McAfee, in Philosophy and Social Criticism, 2004). A postnational theory of citizenship, commensurate with the emergence of a multiplistic sense of political membership—which Soysal described above as ‘multiple in the sense of spanning local, regional, and global identities, and accommodate[ing] intersecting complexes or rights, duties, and loyalties” (Soysal, 166)—requires new ways of thinking about collective identity, sources of rights and obligations, and relationships between and across civil and political realms. Within this emerging theoretical context, civil society is highlighted for close attention because it is a realm that contains and reflects such multiplicity, while at the same time demonstrating the potentials for fluid and dynamic forms of solidarity and political participation. Cosmopolitan Democracy 7 In his work on cosmopolitan democracy in a global era, David Held argues that the revitalization of democratic politics is both desirable and possible, but poses a daunting challenge. Held sets out a normative case for the core principle of democratic autonomy and offers a conception of cosmopolitan democracy based upon autonomy, and grounded in model with specific institutional structures at both the nation state and international levels that acknowledge networks and emphasize deliberation. Held justifies his model for cosmopolitan democracy by arguing that “in a world of intensifying regional and global relations, with marked overlapping ‘communities of fate,’ the principle of autonomy requires entrenchment in regional and global networks as well as in national and local politics (Held, Models of Democracy, 1996, 358). It is important to note that in Held’s model of cosmopolitan democracy, the role of the nation state is not eclipsed by broader global networks. Rather, the nation state, as well as local political units, are situated within a wide array of political structures and associational networks that reside within and across national, transnational, and global arenas of participation. The nation state is one among many relevant sites of politics, and in my view citizenship, rather than the primary or sole site for political action or citizenship status. And Held emphasizes that his model does not suggest that international and global spheres are, nor should become, the locus of attention for democratic theory or practice. He asserts: If the history and practice of democracy have until now been centered on the idea of locality and place (the city-republic, the community, the nation), is it likely that in the future democracy will be centered exclusively on the international or global domain, 8 if it is to be centered anywhere at all? To draw this conclusion is, I think, to misunderstand the nature of contemporary globalization and the argument being developed here. Globalization is, to borrow a phrase, ‘a dialectical process’: ‘local transformation is as much a part of globalization as the lateral extension of social connections across time and space’ (Giddens, 1990, 64). New demands are made for regional and local autonomy as groups find themselves buffeted by global forces and by inappropriate or ineffective political regimes. Although these circumstances are clearly fraught with danger, and the risk of an intensification of sectarian politics, they also portend a new possibility: the recovery of an intensive and participatory democracy at local levels as a complement to the deliberative assemblies of the wider global order. That is, they portend a political order of democratic associations, cities, and nations as well of regions and global networks (my emphases). In such an order, the principle of autonomy would be entrenched in diverse sites of power and across diverse spatial domains. (Held, 356-57) It is precisely this possibility for the revitalization of localized, deliberative, democratic participation that I seek to elaborate in this essay. Sharing Held’s commitments to autonomy, cosmopolitanism, deliberation and associational networks, I now turn to deliberative democratic theory to explicate the relationship between the associations and networks of civil society and formal democratic politics within state or international institutions. Like Held, these deliberative theorists assert that citizenship within the public sphere of civil society is not a replacement for formal politics. In order words, they are not advocating a collapsing of state/civil society boundaries. Rather, they lay out the ways in which participation in the institutions of civil society—especially in the form of deliberative, public communication—both creates the political culture that supports democratic political institutions and forms public opinion that allows political representatives to make good policy decisions. Citizenship as Civil and Political 9 In her recent explorations of political geography and political membership in a global era, Seyla Benhabib argues for a more associational, reflexive approach to collective identity formation that grounds the definition of citizenship within the realm of civil society, rather than in the nation state. She suggests that we analyze “the experiment of the modern nation-state” in terms of “the formation of a democratic people with a specific history and culture [through] on going reflexive transformation and experimentation with collective identity.” This notion of collective identity then reconceptualizes the “so-called contradiction between human rights and national sovereignty… as the inherently conflictual aspects of reflexive collective identity formation in complex and increasingly multicultural and multinational democracies (Benhabib, “Political Geographies,” Social Research 2002, 560). Moving beyond an emphasis on reflexive collective identity formation within experimental, pluralistic nation states, Benhabib places the locus of this process, the process of creating citizens, within the realm of civil society. She argues: We are more authentically members of a family, of a neighborhood, of a religious community or of a social movement than we are members of a state. While the modern nation-state remains a possible structural expression of a democratic selfdetermination, the complexity of our social lives integrates us into associations that lie above and below the level of the nation state. These associations mediate the manner in which we relate to the state. If we stop viewing the state as the privileged apex of collective identity, but instead, along with Rawls, view it “as a union of unions,” then citizenship should also be understood as a form of collective identity mediated in and through the institutions of civil society (my emphases). In the European context this means: foreigners’ claims to citizenship in a political entity are established not through some hierarchical decision from above, but because 10 individuals show themselves worthy of membership in civil society through the exercise of certain abilities and the fulfillment of certain conditions. Civil citizenship should lead to political citizenship. (Janoski, 1998; Benhabib, “Political Membership,” Social Research 1999, 728) Benhabib’s conception lays out dual aspects of citizenship—both civil and political—and suggests a linear relationship between the two whereby worthy participation in the institutions of civil society earn one the rights of political citizenship granted by a national or transnational organization. While Benhabib’s emphasis on civil citizenship is more fluid than traditional definitions that constrain citizenship status to membership in the state, her emphasis on one’s opportunity to earn status and rights of political citizenship retains more of a liberal emphasis than Nuhoglu Soysal’s conception of postnational citizenship. According to Nuhoglu Soysal, participation is not a choice, but an obligation: “Postnational citizenship confers upon every person the right and duty of participation in the authority structures and public life of polity, regardless of their historical or cultural ties to that community” (Nuhoglu Soysal, LC, 3 in Torres, 371). What these orientations share is a definition of citizenship that is not confined to one’s status vis-à-vis the nation state, but also highlights participation in the broader public life of the polity; that is, the institutions of civil society. Thus, postnational citizenship does not turn away from the political authority of the state, but rather elaborates a broader conception of politics that links the public spheres of civil and political societies. Hence, the role of citizenship within civil society, and the importance of citizen participation in the institutions 11 of civil society for the democratic functioning of political institutions, is a key locus of concern for deliberative democratic theory in a global era. Civil society is important to deliberative democratic theory for two key reasons: 1) civil society is the realm in which a democratic political culture sets the stage for democratic political processes in the formal political sphere; and 2) civil society is the realm in which public opinion is formed and potentially mobilized in order to influence democratic decision making in the formal political sphere. As Noelle McAfee explains: Civil society is the network of all those nongovernmental associations, both formal and informal, that bring people together: from garden clubs to neighborhood associations, churches, labor unions, interest groups, coffee klatches, bowling clubs….People do not necessarily act politically in these associational groups but, through the interrelated associations of civil society, people can develop the capacity to create and articulate public will and direction, to address immediate concerns, and to decide the legitimacy of their governments. At best, civil societies foster an open, democratic culture that helps set their political communities’ direction and hold their governments accountable. … To the extent that civil society provides opportunities for deliberation about public matters (my emphases), public opinion can form and provide means by which to judge the state’s legitimacy. Public opinion can also form about what direction policy ought to take. (Habermas, Kristeva, and Citizenship, 2000, 83-84) According to McAfee the public knowledge generated through deliberation serves legitimating as well as epistemic functions. (HKC, 2000 and PK, 2004). Within Habermas’s communicative theory, idea of the public sphere is both descriptive, targeting conversations between individuals that highlight issues of common concern, and normative, highlighting necessary conditions such as equal access, fair participation, and consent.3 As Jean Cohen asserts: “The concept of the public sphere thus brings together the normative and the empirical, the universal and the particular. It is, in my 12 view, the normative core of the idea of civil society and the heart of any conception of democracy. … I would defend an even stronger claim: the deliberative genesis and justification of public policy in political and civil public spaces respectively are constitutive of the modern form of democracy (Cohen, “American Civil Society Talk,” 1999, 59). If public sphere theory provides the normative core of modern democracy, and modern democracy is cosmopolitan—that is grounded in associations and networks that span local and global arenas, then the concept of the public sphere becomes “transnationalized.” This empirical and theoretical development is both consistent with and a challenge to the revitalization of democracy in a global era. Transnational Public Spheres A large theoretical tension underlies the conception of postnational, cosmopolitan deliberative citizenship that I have laid out thus far. I have claimed that the concept of civil society, particularly the public sphere of civil society, is pivotal to contemporary democratic theory because of decreasing centrality of nation state amidst globalization. Yet, Habermas’s theory of the public sphere depends upon a notion of the state as the center of politics. Nancy Fraser explains: Two ideas—the validity of public opinion and citizen empowerment vis-à-vis the state—are essential to the concept of the public sphere in democratic theory. Without them, the concept loses its critical force and its political point….Yet these two features are not easily associated with the discursive arenas that we today call “transnational public spheres.” It is difficult to associate the notion of valid public opinion with communicative arenas in which the interlocutors do not constitute a political citizenry. And it is hard to associate the notion of communicative power with discursive spaces that do correlate with sovereign states. Thus, it is by no means clear what it means today to speak of “transnational public spheres.” From the perspective of democratic theory, at least, the phrase sounds a bit like an oxymoron. Nevertheless, we should not rush to jettison the notion…such a notion is indispensable, I think, to those of us who aim to reconstruct democratic 13 theory in the current “postnational constellation.” But it will not be sufficient to merely refer to such public spheres in a relatively casual commonsense way, as if we already knew what they were. Rather, it will be necessary to return to square one, to problematize public sphere theory—and ultimately to reconstruct its conceptions of validity and communicative power. (Fraser, “Transnationalizing the Public Sphere,” 2002, 1-2) In response to the theoretical challenges that she has set forth, Fraser recommends two general trajectories for overcoming what she calls “critical disjunctures and mismatches of scale that threaten to undermine public sphere theory” (14). First, she calls for the institutionalization of “new transnational public powers” that should be subject to democratic control and capable of constraining transnational private power. Second, she calls for the institutionalization of “elements of transnational/quasi-global citizenship.” Such a model of citizenship is intended to generate “broad solidarities that “cross divisions of language, ethnicity, religion, and nationality” and to construct “broadly inclusive public spheres in which common interests can be created or discovered through open democratic communication” (14-15). She argues that creating broad solidarities and inclusive publics will require a realignment of relationships “among at least four distinct kinds of community, which do not map onto one another today: 1) the imagined community, or nation; 2) the political (or civic) community, or citizenry; 3) the communications community, or public; and 4) the community of fate, or the set of stakeholders affected by various developments (included here is “community of risk”)” (15). Fraser stresses that these realignments will require institutional renovation and encompass multiple publics that correspond to a multilevel, vertical structure of sovereignty (in contrast to the vertical multiplicity of publics that she offered in her earlier efforts to rethink Habermas’s conception of the public sphere) (15). 14 In this section I have sketched current theoretical trajectories for an approach to postnational citizenship that combines Held’s model of cosmopolitan democracy with deliberative democratic theory’s emphasis on the public sphere as the normative core of civil society. Within this conception of postnational citizenship, democratic politics spans global communicative networks, thus the associations of civil society, transnational public spheres, and world-level sovereign powers are prominent sites for theoretical and empirical research. As Held (1996), Fraser (2002) and others highlight, much of this work is in its infancy. Theoretical and practical challenges abound; namely, for deliberative theory, questions surrounding the creation and legitimization of transnational and world level political organizations (bodies with political public authority) to receive the communicative opinion- and will-formation that takes place in multiple, global public spheres. Such questions are far from resolved. Nevertheless, key areas of attention for citizenship education flow from the theoretical considerations outlined thus far. For instance, themes of cosmopolitanism, public deliberation and communication, and the relationship between participation in the political public sphere of civil society and formal political decision making require further explication. It is to these tasks that I turn in the final sections of the essay. Democratic Citizenship Education: Cultivating Publics of Citizens As Held argues in offering his model for democratic autonomy and cosmopolitan democracy: the jury is unquestionably out on whether such principles and structures will become entrenched across borders. Yet, Held views his work as a political theorist in 15 terms of advocacy; he offers a theoretical model in order “to help establish a new agenda for political thought and deliberation.” Held contends that: “the explosion of interest in democracy in recent times has all too often conceived of democracy in terms of liberal democracy, assumed that democracy can only be applied to ‘governmental affairs’ (and has no place in economic and social spheres), and presupposed that the nation-state is the most appropriate locus for democracy.” He further maintains that questioning these terms of reference, setting out a new agenda, and making the case “for the deepening and extending of democracy within and between countries” are essential developments “if democracy is to retain its relevance, efficaciousness and legitimacy in the centuries ahead” (Held, 1996, 357-360). It is in agreement with Held, and in this spirit, that I now seek to set out an agenda for a cosmopolitan and deliberative conception of citizenship education in the global era. If cosmopolitan democratic theory is in its infancy, as Held asserts, citizenship education theory in this global milieu is embryonic. Yet, the ground is fertile for theory development. McAfee points out that both the place of the “public” in public sphere theory and the capacities and functions of citizenship” have received scant attention, even by deliberative theorists of civil society (“Public Knowledge,” 149; Habermas, Kristeva, and Citizenship, 94). In this section of the essay, then, I flush out broad implications of necessary conditions for fostering democratic competence and a democratic political culture by considering the relationship between educational projects to revitalize political public spheres specifically, and civil society more generally. My analysis seeks to promote theoretical developments in two complementary directions: I 16 consider both the implications of democratic theory for citizenship education and the role of education in recasting and revitalizing democratic politics and practices of citizenship. Publics of Citizens In order to frame a theory of democratic citizenship education commensurate with the challenges posed by contemporary globalization I return to Nancy’s Fraser’s recommendations for transnationalizing public spheres. You will recall that Fraser makes two broad recommendations for rethinking and renovating the public sphere. First, she calls for institutionalizing new transnational public powers. Second, she calls for institutionalizing elements of transnational/quasi-global citizenship, generating broad solidarities that cross identity-based divisions, and constructing broadly inclusive public spheres in which common interests can be identified through democratic deliberation. In order to institutionalize new forms of citizenship, generate broad solidarities, and construct inclusive public spheres, she suggests that relations must be realigned among four distinct kinds of community: the imagined community, or nation; the political (or civic) community, or citizenry; the communications community, or public; and the community of fate, or the set of stakeholders affected by various developments (Fraser, 2002, 15). Whereas Fraser suggests that these four kinds of community are distinct, and do not map onto one another today, I suggest that the Habermasian strand of deliberative democratic theory, which much of Fraser’s work on public sphere theory critiques and extends, contains resources for bringing about the sorts of realignments that she recommends. These theoretical resources are developed in the recent work of political philosopher and deliberative theorist Noelle McAfee. Like Fraser, McAfee grounds her 17 work on the public sphere in a Habermasian conception; and like Habermas, she turns to the tradition of North American philosophical pragmatism as central to the theory’s normative precepts. McAfee draws upon the work of John Dewey, particularly The Public and Its Problems, to elucidate a concept of the “public” commensurate with public sphere theory as the normative core of civil society. In her work, public deliberation is central to democratic theory for both is legitimating and epistemic functions (Public Knowledge, 2004). McAfee’s approach to the idea of the “public” is useful for contemporary public sphere theory because it provides a fluid and dynamic conception of the public capable of realigning traditional relations across communities and generating the broad solidarities that Fraser calls for. Whereas Fraser’s work has emphasized multiple counter publics within the public sphere, McAfee extends Habermas’s focus on social movements as useful terrain for thinking about publics as dynamic forms of energy or “ways of being.” She suggests that “instead of thinking about publics as static or passive entities, we could think of them as forms of energy, made up of a multiplicity of diverse and finite people seeking together to find a path forward. If public is a way of being [it is more akin to electricity than a light bulb] (from David Mathews).” (PK, 153-54) Like Dewey, McAfee grounds the public in face-to-face deliberations, foregrounding the nuance and multiplicity of verbal communication or “winged words of conversation in immediate intercourse” (Dewey, 1954 218 in PK 148). The Deweyian model of public deliberation envisioned by McAfee is commensurate with the experimental, reflexive approach to collective identity advocated by Benhabib as well as 18 the generation of broad solidarities across communities of fate called for by Fraser. As McAfee sees it: …public talk makes possible a “fraternally shared experience” or understanding of political phenomena that are perceived and felt by a public. Dewey observes that when people inquire together about political matters, they create more knowledge of these matters and of themselves as a public (my emphases). This is not merely the result of aggregating their bits of knowledge. Rather, it is the result of being able to weave together the interconnections, dispersed consequences, multiple and sometimes clashing aims that the public can conceive only when it talks together. As the people talk together and begin to fathom the roots and effects of public problems, they begin to form and identify themselves as a public, as actors who might be able to channel and direct public action. (PK, 148) This passage highlights the ways in which public deliberation generates two forms of public knowledge: knowledge about specific issues and knowledge in the form of a sense of collective identity as a public. This sense of collective identity partners with a sense of solidarity, both of which are born from addressing specific problems that arise in the context of shared communities of fate. Yet generation of such publicness—in terms of a choate sense of identity and useful public knowledge—does not come without challenges. The pluralism and complexities that mark globalization are particularly thorny issues. The first issue, pluralism, poses a challenge for public deliberation, and the generation of public knowledge, because people must be able and willing to talk across difference, in order to share their unique perspectives. According to McAfee, this requires a “public way of being:” The view that I am outlining calls for people to leave their enclaves and join with unlike others. In addition to talking across class, race, and religious lines, they need to become open to the many kinds of outlook that proliferate beyond these categories. In other words, the multitude needs to take up a public way of being, which is not that of a realm of friends but of an arena of strangers who must try to see what these others see. We are 19 often among strangers—in a shopping mall, at a street corner, or in an airport –but not with the political imperative of comprehending how consequences of common life affect these others in our midst. This is a major challenge for contemporary politics: finding ways for, as Dewey said in The Public and Its Problems (1954), the inchoate public to become choate. (PK 146) The second issue, complexity, is heightened by contemporary global scale. For Dewey at the turn of the twentieth century, and for us at the turn of the twenty first century, complexity often breeds disenchantment, and bewilderment, and perhaps apathy. Dewey asserts that: “when problems become immense and their consequences difficult to perceive, the problems begin to eclipse the public” and observers lament indifference and apathy. “But apathy, Dewey noted, is best understood as ‘testimony to the fact that the public is so bewildered that it cannot find itself’” (Dewey, 1954, 123 in PK 147); the public is bombarded and inchoate. According to McAfee, Dewey’s solution for helping the public become choate amidst complexity is three-pronged and interconnected: 1) to find itself, the public needs to fully fathom the consequences of human actions and the origins of action; 2) to be able to make such connections, and make good political judgments thereafter, the public needs increased intelligence—the kind of intelligence needed to “judge the bearing of knowledge” (Dewey, 1954: 208-9); and 3) to create this kind of intelligence, “Dewey calls for a ‘practical reformation of social conditions,’ namely people’s reconnection to their local communities, where face-to-face intercourse can occur (Dewey, 1954: 211 in PK, 147-48). McAfee argues that this can occur, and is occurring, through public political forums that emphasize voice in deliberation toward the creation of public 20 identities and public knowledge which will, in turn, inform sound public policy (PK 149-150). It is in these dynamic moves between and across public collective identity formation, public deliberation about specific issues of common concern, and public policy making that relationships are realigned between what Fraser refers to as imagined, political, communications and communities of fate. Public of citizens deliberate and direct communication flows toward relevant political bodies. Within this conception of citizenship, citizenship is not conceived of as simply a status, but rather as agency in the public sphere. Following Habermas, McAfee highlights citizenship in terms of participation in social movements. She explains that social movements in the public sphere of civil society are “examples of new concerns brought to the agenda by the political periphery—the public of citizens (my emphases) Citizens can act as sensors, experiencing new crises and, via the public sphere, raising awareness of these crises as political problems” (HKC, 93). But citizens must not only participate in consciousness raising, they must also be able to generate public opinion regarding solutions and mobilize this opinion to influence decisions within the political system. Habermas describes the function of a deliberative public in the following manner: The public sphere is a warning system with sensors that, though unspecialized, are sensitive throughout society. From the perspective of democratic theory, the public sphere must, in addition, amplify the pressure of problems, that is, not only detect and identify problems but also convincingly and influentially thematize them, furnish them with possible solutions, and dramatize them in such a way that they are taken up and dealt with by parliamentary complexes. Besides the “signal” function, there must be effective problematization. The capacity of the public sphere to solve problems on its own is limited. But this capacity 21 must be utilized to oversee the further treatment of problems that takes place inside the political system. (Habermas 1996, 359 in HKC, 94-95) Deliberation within and across public spheres simultaneously create these spheres as discursive spaces and coalesces publics of citizens capable of generating the public knowledge and opinion necessary for political will formation in the sphere and stage of democratic policy formulation. To summarize the arguments put forward in this section, whether we emphasize Dewey’s language of publics or Habermas’s language of social movements, public deliberation forms the public sphere of civil society, and gives rise to identities and generates forms of public knowledge and opinion; none of these phenomena are confined to state borders or strict distinctions between communities (as posited by Fraser). Public deliberations have the potential make choate a sense of the public, as well as to bring together the public intelligence to generate public knowledge that can inform policy solutions. Strategic knowledge is then also necessary, in order to target generated public opinion to appropriate political decision making bodies. These emphases on creating deliberative publics of citizens suggests a number of tasks for democratic citizenship education: cultivating in young people public ways of being, problem solving and deliberative capacities, as well as the knowledge, understanding and skills to navigate complexities of various levels of political organizations and to make strategic decisions as to where opinion, knowledge, and action should be targeted. Educating Publics of Citizens While many traditional definitions of citizenship conceive of it as a political status linked to one’s membership in a nation state, many traditional definitions of citizenship 22 education equate it with nationalist education and emphasize aspects such as teaching patriotism and the specific history and cultural traditions of particular national groups. Even approaches that do not equate citizenship with nationalist education, generally highlight a state-centered political education: that is, the nation state is centered as the primary locus of politics and emphases include teaching knowledge of rights, laws, and decision making processes within the narrow context of the state. The contemporary context of the global era demands that we move beyond these traditional definitions and decouple citizenship from national education. Not only in the United States, Canada and other large heterogeneous states, but also smaller nation states committed to democratic principles facing increasing pluralism due to economic and political migration.4 This move away from an emphasis on the nation state entails shifts of emphases in citizenship education away from things like national identity, allegiance, and patriotism to multiple roles and complex skills--such as collaborative problem solving and deliberative capacities--necessary for participation in global civil society. While state-centered education has its place, it must be moved from a primary to a complementary role in a model of democratic citizenship education that situates the state as one political form among many; a union among unions. Moreover, democratic citizenship education must be conceived in terms of a broader political education for democratic participation in national, transnational and global public spheres. Two common themes are emphasized in much of the discourse surrounding education for democracy in a global era: universal provision of education and human rights education. While each of these are appropriate and important aspects of 23 democratic education, they are not sufficient in terms of thinking about revitalizing democracy through participation in the public spheres of civil society. McAfee’s account of the role of the public sphere in Habermas’s communicative theory and the concept of the public in Dewey’s pragmatic philosophy suggest a sophisticated and nuanced conception of citizenship capable of navigating the challenges of postnational, cosmopolitan deliberative democracy. McAfee offers a Habermasian theory of citizenship; one that he does not make explicit, but that she draws from the overall outline of his political theory. According to her, the capacities and functions of citizenship would include the following: citizenship should be seen as an intersubjective enterprise; it cannot be carried out by isolated individuals; citizens have to create the space in which citizenship can occur; that is, they have to move beyond their purely private networks and into more public ones, in the process creating and maintaining civil society; from within this civil society, citizens need to create discursive spaces in which they address matters of common concern—that is, they need to create the political public sphere; effective citizenship calls for the ability to “ferret out, identify, and effectively thematize latent problems of social integration” (Habermas 1996, 358); citizens will need to engage in this opinion- and will-formation process spontaneously, without the prompting of formal systems; otherwise channels of communication would flow from center to periphery rather than the deliberative-democrat way, from periphery to center; citizens should be able to bring these issues to the attention of formal legislative bodies “in a way that disrupts the latter’s routines” (Habermas 1996, 358) [McAfee, HKC, 95] In emerging and existing democracies, in more and less pluralistic states, citizenship education commensurate with such functions and capacities necessitates attention to 1) the vibrancy, democratization and educative functions of the institutions of civil society, as well as 2) the role of formal educational institutions, namely schools, in terms of their institutional character and curricular offerings. 24 The Practice of Citizenship in Institutions of Civil Society5 Democratic citizenship education takes place not only in schools, but also throughout the institutions of civil society. It is within civil society that democratic competence is practiced and that a democratic political culture is both created and transmitted. As Held maintains in explaining the relationship between his principle of democratic autonomy and his emphasis on the realm of civil society: If democratic life involves no more than a periodic vote, the locus of people’s activities will be the ‘private’ realm of civil society and the scope of their actions will depend largely on the resources they can command. Few opportunities will exist for citizens to act as citizens, as participants in public life. Democratic autonomy seeks to redress this state of affairs by creating opportunities for people to establish themselves ‘in their capacity of being citizens.’ (Arendt, On Revolution 1963, 256 in Held, 323-325) Vibrant civil societies provide many opportunities for people, including young people, to establish themselves in the capacity of citizenship in terms of inculcating shared principles—or civic virtues—and providing opportunities to develop concrete competencies. Jean Cohen argues that while participation in the voluntary associations of civil society may cultivate civic virtue or build social capital, neither of these functions are paramount to deliberative democracy. She views participation in institutions of civil society in terms of building communicative and democratic competencies—that is, political competencies that play a role in the formation of public opinion. In her view, civil society is a potential as practice grounds for democracy (Cohen, “Civil Society Talk”).6 The potential of civil society is stressed here because democratic competencies can only be generated by specific types of participation in specific forms of 25 associations; that is, institutions of civil society must be democratically organized in order to breed democracy. In order to cultivate democratic autonomy and competence, the institutions of civil society, including schools, must be organized democratically. This is necessary in order to promote the sort of political culture necessary for democracy to flourish. Cohen and Arato assert this thesis in their well-known work Civil Society and Political Theory: …We build upon the thesis of one of the most important predecessors of the pluralist approach, Alexis de Tocqueville, who argued that without active participation on the part of citizens in egalitarian institutions and civil associations, as well as in politically relevant organizations, there will be no way to maintain the democratic character of political culture [my emphasis] or of social and political institutions. Precisely because modern civil society is based on egalitarian principles and universal inclusion, experience in articulating the political will and in collective decision making is crucial to the reproduction of democracy. (Cohen and Arato, Civil Society and Political Theory, 19)7 The democratization of schools as institutions of civil society is a project with many layers and much work to be accomplished. One area ripe for consideration is the function and provision of public schooling. In the current neoliberal context of global capitalism the economic and political functions of schooling often serve the ends of social reproduction in accordance with existing class-based in equalities. The contradictory potential of schools as liberatory vehicles must also be pressed and fought for. Moreover, questions surrounding the organization of schooling must be examined. State-provided schooling, while potentially fulfilling a democratic mandate for universal education, does not necessarily do so in ways consistent with the decentering of the state and the democratization of civil society. State 26 provision of education, whereby schools are arms of the state and bureaucratic structures and relationships reign, needs to be reconsidered in accordance with the normative model of multiplistic public spheres developed in this essay. Deliberative democratic theory offers principles such as subsidiarity and associational governance, advocated by many radical and deliberative democrats, that support alternative models of organization for public schooling—such as public school choice and public charter schools.8 Another crucial element in terms of the democratization of schools as mediating institutions of civil society is student voice. A key part of the institutional renovation necessary in education, in order for democratic citizenship education to be possible, is the inclusion of young people’s voices in structural processes (planning, governance, etc.) as well as curricular and pedagogical practices. Conclusion A postnational, cosmopolitan deliberative theory of citizenship and citizenship education for a global era reconceives both politics and relationship across communities in fluid and dynamic ways that traverse multiplistic public spheres and levels of political organization. Politics is situated in state and international political systems, but also in the informal processes of opinion formation that arise in civil society and influence will formation in the political sphere. As scholars continue to theorize relationships between citizen involvement in voluntary associations and social movements -- civil publics --and political bodies, as well as between civic engagement and political participation 27 and the role of communication in these processes, educators must be preparing young people capable of public ways of being and competent in democratic deliberation. The challenges faced by democracy in the context of globalization require citizens who share commitments to democratic principles, are able to function in an ever-changing, problem-based environments, and have communicative and problem solving capacities. While educators prepare young people to fulfill the multiple roles of deliberative citizenship, they must also practice and exhibit these qualities themselves. Democratic citizenship education in a global era is a daunting task. Current trends in education in most existing democracies are better characterized as neoliberal or neoconservative than as democratizing. Yet, as Torres argues, “social movements have an increasingly powerful voice in arguing against ‘globalization without representation:’ when social movements press schools to live up to their democratic purposes, the struggles alter the relationship of social forces, exciting forces that can weaken capitalism’s social and political hegemony” (Lois Wiener, “Schooling to Work,” in Aronowitz and Cutler, eds. Post-work: The wages of cybernation. 1998, 194 cited in Torres, AERJ, 376). The articulation and implementation of democratic citizenship education is itself a social movement requiring public deliberation and opinion formation, and exertion of pressure on political bodies in order to disrupt the current hegemony. For democratic citizenship education to move from the periphery, where it now sits, toward the center, we will need the “winged words” of educators as public intellectuals and citizens to create publics through face-to-face deliberation, 28 accompanied by strategic action aimed toward political bodies spanning local, national, and transnational arenas. For fuller treatment of these issues see Kenichi Ohmae’s The End of the Nation State (1995) in Torres, AERA 2002; Seyla Benhabib, “Citizens, Residents, and Aliens in a Changing World: Political Membership in the Global Era,” Social Research Vol. 66, No. 3 (Fall 1999) and “Political Geographies in a Global World: Arendtian Reflections” Social Research, Vol. 69, No. 2 (Summer 2002); and Yasemin Nuhoglu Soysal Limits of Citizenship (1994). 2 See, for example, David Miller “Bounded Citizenship” in Hutchings and Dannreuther, eds. Cosmopolitan Citizenship. NY: St. Martin’s Press, 1999. 3 According to Habermas’s definition, which McAfee is drawing upon, “[The public sphere is] a domain of our social life in which such a thing as public opinion can be formed. Access to the public sphere is open in principle to all citizens. A portion of the public sphere is constituted in every conversation in which private persons come together to form a public…Citizens act as a public when they deal with matters of general interest without being subject to coercion; thus with the guarantee that they may assemble and unite freely, and express and publicize their opinions freely…We speak of a political public sphere (as distinguished from a literary one, for instance) when the public discussions concern objects connected with the practice of the state” (Habermas, 1989, 231 cited in HKC, 82). 4 Drawing upon Held’s model of cosmopolitan democracy, Osler and Starkey develop a model of cosmopolitan citizenship that examines national citizenship in the U.K. in context of globalization. Their empirical study highlights multiple identities and realities of discrimination and inequality as reasons for viewing national citizenship in pluralistic democracies as too narrow. They recommend cosmopolitan citizenship as more commensurate with young people’s experience of civic identity. Audrey Osler and Hugh Starkey. Learning for Cosmopolitan Citizenship: theoretical debates and young people’s experiences. Educational Review, Vol 55, No. 3, 2003. 5 Osler and Starkey’s UK study identifies specific local sites of learning citizenship beyond the school as well as physical spaces that young people value as public spaces. Such empirical work can be complemented with the philosophical and normative underpinnings provided by deliberative democratic theory, particularly the ideas of discursive public spaces and concept of the political public sphere as a site for learning citizenship. 6 Cohen makes this argument as a response to, and in disagreement with, Robert Putnam’s use of the concepts of civil society and social capital in his well known research on decline of civic engagement in the U.S. See Robert Putnam, Bowling Alone: The Collapse and Revival of American Community. NY: Simon and Schuster, 2000. 7 Jean Cohen and Andrew Arato. Civil Society and Political Theory. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1992. This commitment to the democratization of civil society is shared by a number of other theorists, although formulated a bit differently by each. See, for instance, Joshua Cohen and Joel Rogers applying ideal norms of deliberation within what Habermas would consider “informal” political spheres in Associations and Democracy. NY: Verso, 1995; Anthony Giddens on “democratizing democracy” in Beyond Left and Right: The Future of Radical Politics, Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1994; Carol Gould’s argument for the democratization of social and cultural institutions in Rethinking Democracy. NY: Cambridge University Press, 1988; and David Held on democratic autonomy and civil society in Models of Democracy. 8 For further discussion of the principles of subsidiarity and associative democracy see Jean Cohen and Joshua Cohen and Joel Rogers. For an argument linking these principles with public school choice, particularly in the form of charter schooling in the U.S., see Stacy Smith, Democratic Potential of Charter Schools. NY: Peter Lang, 2001. 1 29 Deliberating Publics of Citizens: Postnational citizenship amidst global public spheres Stacy Smith Bibliography Archibugi, Daniele and David Held. Cosmopolitan Democracy: An Agenda for New World Order. Cambridge: Polity Press, 1995. Bellah, Robert N, et al. The Good Society. New York: Vintage Books, 1991. Benhabib, Seyla. "Citizens, Residents, and Aliens in a Changing World: Political Membership in the Global Era." Social Research 66.3 (Fall 1999): 709-740. Benhabib, Seyla. "Political Geographies in a Global World: Arendtian Reflections." Social Research 69.2 (Summer 2002): 539-564. Boyte, Harry C. Common Wealth: A Return to Citizen Politics. The Free Press: New York, 1989. Cohen, Joshua, and Joel Rogers. Associations and Democracy . Vol. 1. New York: Verso, 1995. Cohen, Jean L, and Andrew Arato. Civil Society and Political Theory. Cambridge: MIT Press , 1992. Foley, Michael W., and Bob Edwards. "Civil Society and Social Capital beyond Putnam." American Behavioral Scientist 42.1 (Sept. 1998): 124. Fraser, Nancy. "Transnationalizing the Public Sphere." Paper presented at the Public Space Conference. Graduate Center of the City University of New York. Feb. 2002. www.yale.edu/polisci/info/conferences/fraser1.doc Fullinwider, Robert K. Civil Society, Democracy, and Civic Renewal. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 1999. Fung, Archon, and Erik Olin Wright. Deepening Democracy: Institutional Innovations in Empowered Participatory Governance. New York : Verso, 2003. Giddens, Anthony. Beyond Left And Right: The Future of Radical Politics. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1994. "Globalization." Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2002. Gould, Carol C. Rethinking Democracy: Freedom and Social Cooperation in Politics, Economy, and Society. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988. Held, David. Democracy and the Global Order: From the Modern State to Cosmopolitan Governance. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1995. Held, David. Models of Democracy. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1996. Lipman, Pauline. "Making the Global City, Making Inequality: The Political Economy and Cultural Politics of Chicago School Policy." American Educational Research Journal 39.2 (Summer 2002): 279-419. 30 McAfee, Noelle McAfee. Habermas, Kristeva, and Citizenship. Ithaca : Cornell University Press, 2000. McDonough, Kevin, and Walter Feinberg. Citizenship and Education in Liberal-Democratic Societies: Teaching for Cosmopolitan Values and Collective Identities . Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003. Meyer, Heinz-Dieter, and William Lowe Boyd. Education between States, Markets, and Civil Society: Comparative Perspectives. Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 2001. Noelle MeAfee, Noelle. "Public Knowledge." Philosophy & Social Criticism 30.2 (2004): 139-157. Osler, Audrey, and Hugh Starkey. "Learning for Cosmopolitan Citizenship: Theoretical Debates and Young People’s Experiences." Educational Review 55.3 (2003): 243-252. Pearce, Nick, and Joe Hallgarten. Tomorrow’s Citizens: Critical Debates in Citizenship and Education. London: The Institute for Public Policy Research, 2000. Sigel, Roberta S, and Marilyn Hoskin. Education for Democratic Citizenship: A Challenge for Multi-Ethnic Societies. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 1991. Somers, Margaret R. "Citizenship and the Place of the Public Sphere: Law, Community, and Political Culture in the Transition to Democracy." American Sociological Review 58.5 (Oct. 1993): 587-620. Somers, Margaret R. "How to Unthink a Knowledge Culture." The Privatization of Citizenship: 121-157. Somers, Margaret R. "Narrating and Naturalizing Civil Society and Citizenship Theory: The Place of Political Culture and Public Sphere." Sociological Theory 13.3 (Nov. 1995): 229-274. Somers, Margaret R. "What’s Political or Cultural about Political Culture and the Public Sphere? Toward an Historical Sociology of Concept Formation." Sociological Theory 13.2 (July 1995): 113-144. Soysal, Yasemin Nuhoglu. Limits of Citizenship: Migrants and Postnational Membership in Europe. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994. Torres, Carlos Alberto. "Globalization, Education, and Citizenship: Solidarity versus Markets?" American Educational Research Journal 39.2 (Summer 2002): 363-378. Welton, Michael. "Civil Society and the Public Sphere: Habermas’s Recent Learning Theory." Studies in the Education of Adults 33.1 (Apr. 2001): 20-35. 31 Woyshner, Christine, and Joseph Watras. Social Education in the Twentieth Century: Curriculum and Context for Citizenship. New York: Peter Lang Publishing , 2004. 32