Back to Realism Applied to Home Page releva89.doc Australian Journal of Psychology Vol. 41, No.2, 1989 pp, 131-133 On the Relevance of Philosophy to Psychological Research: Fashions Versus Fundamentals John J, Furedy University of Toronto Throughout his paper, and especially in the concluding paragraph, Dr Slezak communicates quite dearly that he found little to admire in my paper (Furedy, 1988). and he may well be right to imply that I have not kept up with the details of the latest fashions in cognitive science. My concern, however, is with more fundamental issues. In this brief reply, I discuss three distinctions that should clarify important differences in our concerns. Psychological Research Versus Psychology The title of my article referred to "psychological research", whereas his title refers to "psychology" The difference is important. The former refers to enquiry that relies predominantly on controlled observation to resolve disputes. These observations are usually based on experiments that manipulate independent variables, but can also be based on nonexperimental methods, as long as those methods use control for the variables under study. Psychology, more broadly conceived, includes areas where the enquiry is less empirically oriented. Psychoanalysis, spate of cognitive psychology, and much of cognitive science may all involve observations, but these observations are not viewed as critical in the resolution of disputes concerning rival theoretical positions. Testing Theories Versus Making Metaphors/ Models: Scientific Procedures Versus Sectarian Apologetics The "computational or information processing approach" has, in Dr Slezak's own words, "become the dominant orthodoxy (italics added) among philosophers in recent times" (p. 127). Fodor, who is one of the workers said to provide "rigorous, technically informed articulation" is approvingly described as "the Pope of MIT High Church Computationalism" (p. 127, italics added]. The theological flavour of these sorts of comments is obvious. Similarly, the cited passage from Johnson-Laird (p. 128) smacks of arguing from authority. Based on passages such as those in Revelation, some theologians have argued that Christ is both the alpha and the omega, and Johnson-Laird tells us that the computer is the “last metaphor”. But last, second-last, or whatever The preparation of this reply was supported in part by a grant by the National Sciences and Engineering Council of Canada. I am indebted to G, B, Biederman, M. Feak, and Christine Furedy for comments. Requests for reprints should be sent to John J Furedy, Department of Psychology. University of Toronto, Toronto. Ontario. Canada M5S l A 1 . Australian Journal of Psychology Vol. 41, No.2, 1989 pp, 131-133 132 JJ. Furedy the ordinal position, the point remains that the computational position is a metaphor, analogy, or model, rather than a genuine, testable theory. Note also that the same passage argues for the computational "thesis' on the grounds that "no one has yet succeeded in refuting" it. However, just as among psychoanalysts, the Freudian thesis had considerable "status" but little testability, so it appears for the computational “thesis”. The distinction, in the end. is whether one is interested in actually measuring cognitive processes, and hence in also differentiating them from other psychological processes (e.g.. Furedy. 1989a, 1989b, 1989c; Furedy & Riley, 1987, 1989; Furedy, Shulhan, & Randall, 1989; Michell, 1988), or whether the interest is only in modelling these processes in such a way that they are, by definition, said to be the "last metaphor for the mind". These arc quite different interests, and in my view, the latter approach does not, in the long run, contribute to psychological research, just because "it is not specific enough to serve as a genuine hypothesis" (Furedy, 1988. p. 77). Differing Conceptions of Philosophy The philosophy that I suggested was relevant for "research and professional psychologists" (Furedy, 1988. p. 7I) is the 250 decades of reflection on fundamental issues. This contrasts with the two-decades view said by Dr Slezak to "have been incorporated into the practice of philosophers" (p.123). This view is grounded on quotations from philosophers who report that "in the mid-seventies I discovered that my patience with most mainstream philosophy had run out" (p. 124), and Dr Slezak also asserts that "with the wisdom of hindsight, philosophers now look with self-deprecating scorn at their own former concerns" (p. 124), But in addition to these "development in the discipline during the past twenty years or so" being rather brief relative to the 2.500 years or so that philosophy has been around, it is also not the case that all philosophers are convinced that this particular "revolution" is soundly based. For example, to take a writer whom I cited in Furedy (1988. p. 74). Heil (1981) has argued in Mind that cognitive psychology of the sort espoused by Fodor (1975) rests on a mistake, and Heil, as far as I know, has not had his philosophical licence revoked. Philosophy, more broadly conceived, deals with reflections an fundamental issues, and those reflections are relevant for "research and professional psychologists" because both the conduct and evaluation of research is influenced by one's (examined or unexamined) position on these issues, i have more recently provided an autobiographical illustration of how such philosophical concerns, and the adoption of some conclusions espoused by Anderson, can influence a particular research programme (Furedy, 1989c), Another more thorough illustration for the implications of Andersonian realism for current cognitive research has been provided by Michel I (1988), while Baker (1986) has provided a philosopher's perspective on the influence of Anderson's philosophical thinking. Finally, a reviewer of Baker's book has suggested that "Anderson's philosophy, especially in its critical aspects, remains a stimulating and expansive body of thought, with clear contemporary import in its censure of those idealist and relativist theses which seem to be enjoying another of their periodic resurgences" (McLaughlin, 1989, p. 95). So the fact that in Slezak and Albury's (1988) book. "Anderson's philosophical concerns are nowhere to be seen" (p. 10) is of relevance only to those who believe that it is more important to have an impact on the thinking of some current psychologists and philosophers, than to propose ideas which, in the long run are sound. Australian Journal of Psychology Vol. 41, No.2, 1989 pp, 131-133 133 JJ. Furedy In my view, then, provided one keeps the above sorts of distinctions in mind, it seems that at least I two points are clear. First, philosophical considerations need to be taken up "if we wish the research enterprise to be genuinely progressive and cumulative from an epistemological point of view" (Furedy, 1988, p. 76). Second, despite its low citation count in the current literature, Andersonian, "Australian" (Baker, 1986) or "direct" (Michell, 1988) realism does have something of interest to say to psychological researchers, to those researchers, that is, who are more concerned with progress in understanding the principles of behaviour than with being at the cutting edge of current cognitive fashions. References Baker, A. J. (1986}. Australian realism: The systematic philosophy of John Anderson. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Fodor, J. (1975). The language of thought. Sew York: Crowell. Furedy, J. J. (1988), On the relevance of philosophy for psychological research: A preliminary analysis of some influences of Andersonian realism. Australian Journal of Psychology, 40, 71-77. Furedy, J. J. (1989a). Arguments for and proposed tests of a revised S-R contiguity reinforcement theory of human Pavlovian autonomic conditioning: Some contracognitive claims. Biological Psychology, 27, 137-152. Furedy, J. J. (1989b). Towards evidentially based, non-circular explanations of human Pavlovian autonomic conditioning as a genuine phenomenon: A realist perspective, Biological Psychology. 27. 191-194. Furedy, J. J. (I989c). On the relevance of philosophy for psychological research: Some autobiographical speculations concerning the influence of Andersonian realism. Australian Psychologist, 24. 93-100. Furedy, J. J.. & Riley, D. M. (1989). Human Pavlovian autonomic conditioning and the cognitive paradigm. In G. Davey (Ed.), Cognitive processes and Pavlov tan conditioning in humans (pp. 1-25). New York; Wiley. Furedy, J. J., & Riley, D. M. 11989). Propositional and response processes as distinguishable and equally important aspects of conditioning: Some clarifications. Biological Psychology, in press. Furedy, J. J., Shulhan, D. & Randall, D.C. (1989) Human Pavlovian HR decelerative conditioning with negative till as US: A review of some S-R, stimulus-substitution evidence. International Journal of Psychophysiology, 7, 19-23, Heil, J, (1981). Does cognitive psychology rest on a mistake? Mind, 90. 321-342. McLaughlin, R, (1989). [Review of A. J. Baker, Australian realism: The systematic philosophy of John Anderson] Australian Journal of Philosophy, 67. 93-95. Michel], J. (1988), Maze's direct realism and the character of cognition. Australian Journal of Psychology, 40, 227-250, Slezak, P. The relevance of philosophy to psychology: Response to J, Furedy. Australian Journal of Psychology, 41, 122-130. Slezak, P., & Albury, W. R, (Eds.), (1988). Computers, brains and minds: Essays in cognitive science. Dordrecht: Reidel/Kluwer. Received 3 April 1989. Australian Journal of Psychology Vol. 41, No, 2, 1989 pp. 131-133