Phil 122 Anderson Study Questions on Rawls’ Chapter Three Section Twenty An overview of the steps the argument will take in Chapter Three. Note his remark that “The argument aims eventually to be strictly deductive.” (104) So, given certain assumptions about the parties in the original position, Rawls is going to try to show that the choice of his principles of justice is the only rational choice open to them. A difficult challenge to say the least. Section Twenty-one Rawls lists the available conceptions of justice that the contractors must choose from: Rawls’ preferred conception (justice as fairness), classical teleological conceptions (e.g. utilitarianism), mixed conceptions which combine the basic liberties with variants of utilitarianism, intuitionistic conceptions (which require balancing a list of prima facie principles), and egoistic conceptions. Reasons for rejecting the egoistic conceptions are given in Section Twenty-three. Much of the rest of Chapter Three is devoted to rejecting the various utilitarian theories. There are other options besides those on this list. Libertarianism is not mentioned, but the system of “Natural Liberty” could be taken as one version of it and has already been rejected. Desert-based conceptions of justice are considered and rejected later in Section 48. Distribution according to need is arguably accounted for by his Difference Principle. Section Twenty-two The circumstances of justice are those conditions under which disputes about justice inevitably arise but are not impossible to resolve. We are not concerned here about crisis situations such as life-boat survival or prison camp conditions. What are the circumstances of justice? Section Twenty-three Any rationally acceptable principle of justice must satisfy five formal constraints. What are those five constraints? Despite their mere formality, these constraints have some important practical implications. What would happen if the conditions of generality and universality were ignored in practice (as in fact they often are)? Rawls argues the formal constraints alone suffice to rule out any egoist principles of justice. What is his argument here? Section Twenty-four What is the motive for putting the contractors in the original position under a veil of ignorance? What sorts of information are the contractors ignorant of? What sorts of information are they permitted to use? Given the veil of ignorance, each contractor is, in effect, forced to choose for everyone. Explain that point. Given that each contractor is forced, in effect, to choose for everyone, it becomes more understandable why Rawls thinks it is possible to achieve unanimous agreement on the principles of justice. Explain. Section Twenty-five Rawls poses a problem for his contractors under the veil of ignorance. They are assumed to be rational agents, but they don’t know their conception of the good (what they will regard as worth pursuing in life). So how can they decide which conceptions of justice are most to their advantage? The answer is they know what the primary goods are and they can be expected to prefer more of such goods rather than less. Another problem Rawls must face is the contractors in the original position appear to be egoists, even though Rawls has already argued that no plausible account of justice can be given based on egoist assumptions. (128) Rawls reply is twofold: (a) The motivation of the parties in the original position does not determine their motivation once the veil is lifted. They are indifferent to the interests of others in the original position but they know they will not be indifferent to the interests of others once the principles are put into play, and their awareness of this fact plays a role in their deliberations. (b) “The combination of mutual indifference and the veil of ignorance achieves much the same purpose as benevolence.” (128) Why? It forces each person in the original position to take the good of every other person into account since they might turn out to be one of those “others”. Section Twenty-six The situation of persons in the original position virtually compels them to accept an equal distribution as the initial default position on justice. Explain. But some inequalities are seen to be rational because they make everyone better off. Give a couple of examples of these sorts of justified inequalities. Granted a case can be made for some kinds of inequalities, that still leaves many different possible principles of justice to choose from. Rawls needs an argument for his two principles over all other candidates. He argues that the two principles would be chosen if the contactors adopted the maximin strategy of choice under uncertainty. What does the maximin strategy involve? Rawls gives three reasons why it would be rational to adopt the maximin strategy in the original position. (i) Given the veil of ignorance, persons in the original position have no way of estimating how likely they are to end up in one of the more favored positions or less favored positions in life. (ii) Given that Rawls’ two principles of justice guarantee a decent life even for the least well off, it would be reckless to take a chance on some more risky principles that could leave him much worse off. Favoring the two principles assures him of a happy life. (iii) The choice of some alternative principles could result in a disastrous outcome, e.g., choosing an aristocracy, but ending up only a serf. Rawls then considers an objection to his argument: the difference principle stipulates that any improvement in the circumstances of the most well off must work to the advantage of the least well off. This appears to prohibit any improvement in the situation of the better off if it means even a trivially small loss to the least well off. Rawls replies that that is only a theoretical possibility, not a realistic worry. How does he support that response? Sections Twenty-seven and Twenty-eight These sections contain one of Rawls’ main attacks on utilitarian accounts of justice. For our purposes we can ignore some of the messy details. The general strategy of the utilitarian in the original position is to try to maximize his expected utility. He will rank the various candidate principles of justice on the basis of estimates of probable gain. For each such principle, he first identifies the main anticipated outcomes, e.g. slave owner, free citizen, slave, (for a principle that allowed such outcomes), the utility or gain associated with each outcome, and the likelihood that he would occupy each of those positions. He then multiplies the utility of each position by the likelihood that he would occupy it and adds up the products. The total sum is his expected utility for that candidate principle of justice. He chooses the principle (or principles) which yield the highest expected utility. Perhaps some numbers will make the general idea clear for a candidate principle of justice that happens to permit slavery. Position Utility of that position Likelihood Expected utility Slave owner 100 3% 3 Free citizen 50 60% 30 Slave - 100 37% -37 Total overall expected utility for that choice of principle: -4 A similar calculation would have to be made for all other candidate principles of justice. Clearly this is a strategy appropriate for a rational gambler. Rawls rejects the utilitarian approach for three reasons. First, given the veil of ignorance, the contractors have no objective way of knowing the likelihood that they will end up in any particular position. So the numbers in the “Likelihood” column above are unavailable to them. Secondly, the parties in the original position are ignorant of their attitude towards risk; to favor the rational gambler’s strategy is unwarranted. (149) Thirdly, Rawls questions the meaningfulness of a single chooser estimating the utilities that go with each representative position (the numbers in the first column). I can perhaps make estimates of the value to me of being a slave owner, a free citizen, and a slave, but how can I estimate the value of being, for example, a slave owner from the perspective of a slave owner, assuming I am not one? This is not a problem for Rawls’ own system of primary goods which are presumed to be of value to anyone regardless of their perspective. Section Twenty-nine In this section Rawls gives several positive reasons why his two principles of justice would be chosen over all of the alternatives. He has already argued that they would be chosen, given that the maximin strategy is adopted. But even if one rejects the maximin strategy, as some of his critics advocate, there are other grounds for favoring his principles. One advantage is those who do agree on his principles can have solid confidence that they will continue to be motivated to abide by them once they are put into play. He calls this the problem of the “strains of commitment”. Both the principle of equal basic liberties and the difference principle lend credence to this claim, since both principles prevent people from being used as mere means to the advantage of others. Utilitarianism, in Rawls’ view, lacks this important virtue for, if a greater overall gain in utility for the whole society can be obtained by sacrificing the interests of some targeted individual or group, then utilitarianism seems to permit it. A second reason for thinking justice as fairness is more reliable is that it tends to generate its own support in the sense that people will become increasingly strongly motivated to support just institutions over time. Rawls appeals to “the psychological law that persons tend to love, cherish, and support whatever affirms their own good. Since everyone’s good is affirmed, all acquire inclinations to uphold the scheme.” (155) Utilitarianism does not contain a similar commitment to affirm the good of everyone. A third advantage of justice as fairness is it gives greater support to men’s self-respect. Once again, it is the fact that “when society follows these principles, everyone’s good is included in a scheme of mutual benefit and this public affirmation in institutions of each man’s endeavors supports men’s self-esteem” (156) Section Thirty The utilitarian that Rawls depicts in Sections Twenty-seven and Twenty-eight attempts to choose the principle with the greatest expected utility; he uses the rational gamblers’ strategy. The classical utilitarian takes a rather different approach. A social system is morally right when an ideally rational and impartial spectator would approve of it from a general point of view, assuming he possesses all relevant knowledge of the circumstances. The ideal observer is thought of as a perfectly sympathetic being. The strength of his approval measures the amount of satisfaction in the society surveyed. The classical principle of utility (maximize net satisfaction in society as a whole) reflects the approvals of the ideal, impartial, sympathetic spectator. Note that on this analysis, there is no element of risk taking, no idea of taking a chance on which person one will turn out to be. Rawls argues the parties in the original position would not opt for classical utilitarianism unless they were perfect altruists, persons whose desires conformed to those of the ideal spectator. But the supposition is really incoherent since a perfect altruist can fulfill his desire (to help someone else satisfy their desires) only if someone else has independent (non-altruistic) desires. Justice, remember, is a problem because people have conflicting desires. The same problem arises if, in place of the ideal spectator, one substitutes the ideal of universal benevolence or the love of mankind. These give no real guidance in situations where the persons who are the object of one’s benevolence or love have conflicting wants or interests.