Presentation at: EXPLORING THE BOUNDARIES OF EXPERIENCE AND SELF: CONSCIOUSNESS AND EXPERIENTIAL SECTION OF THE BRITISH PSYCHOLOGICAL SOCIETY, 10th ANNUAL CONFERENCE. St. Anne's College, Oxford, 15th to 17th September, 2006. The rise and fall of the conscious self: A history of western concepts of self and personal identity John Barresi Department of Psychology Dalhousie University Halifax, NS B3H 4J1 Canada jbarrresi@dal.ca http://jbarresi.psychology.dal.ca Abstract I will trace the history of western conceptions of soul and self from the ancient Greeks to the present. The story line that I will present is based mainly on material covered in two books by Ray Martin and myself: The Naturalization of the Soul: Self and Personal Identity in the Eighteenth Century (Routledge, 2000) and The Rise and Fall of Soul and Self: An Intellectual History of Personal Identity (Columbia University Press, 2006). The basic idea is that from Plato through the church fathers to Descartes there was a rise in the notion of an immaterial, immortal self that is a centre of consciousness and distinct from the material body. Since the eighteenth century, this notion of a separate encapsulated conscious self has increasingly come under attack: first, through empirical approaches to consciousness and the material brain; then through social and developmental approaches to the acquisition of self-concepts. The theoretical notion of a unitary conscious self – one with boundaries between self and world, including one’s body – is a notion with a history in western thought. It began with Plato’s philosophy of an immortal rational soul or self, but had its greatest impetus from Christianity. If it were not for belief in the general resurrection by early Christians, the idea that humans could maintain personal identity into an afterlife might not have become a central notion of western philosophy. At the time Stoic materialism and Aristotelian teleological naturalism were competing philosophical positions. However, the belief in the continuation of persons, including their bodies, into an afterlife, put pressure on Western Christian thinkers to come up with a viable notion of how this would be possible. In the end, they abandoned early notions of the resurrection of material persons, in favour of dualism of an immaterial soul and material body. While the simple, 1 immaterial soul was viewed as unextended and naturally immortal, the body was viewed as extended and divisible, with replaceable parts. Increasingly through the Middle Ages into the Renaissance, the immaterial rational soul became the focal concept of self, and bodily resurrection secondary. By the time that Descartes developed his mechanical philosophy in the th 17 century, he was able to define the immaterial soul as equal to the conscious mind, which he took to be the self. The body became part of the material world that could be accounted for by his new mechanical philosophy, while the self as mind and immaterial soul, was viewed as a simple center of consciousness connected to the body and world, but not really a part of it. While Descartes’ interactive substance dualism quickly came under attack, his mechanical philosophy and its epistemological foundation, nevertheless, set the agenda for subsequent empirical studies of self by defining it as a conscious unity somehow connected to the brain, but not simply understood as a functional activity of the brain. The distinction between consciousness as the essential property of mind and the basis of personal identity and self-continuity that is distinct, at least functionally, from matter, including one’s body and brain, has persisted well into the 20th century. But the original motivation for this concept of a non-material, non-social, individualistic, encapsulated self had its roots in religion, not philosophy or science. The rise of individualism in the 18th and 19th century, combined with the slow decay of religious influence on thinkers, led to a new ‘science’ of consciousness that continued the focus on self as individual mind. Nevertheless, this notion came under attack on several fronts. On the one hand, the idea of personal identity based on consciousness, proposed at the end of the 17th century by Locke, had difficulty dealing with discontinuities in consciousness and the criterion of memory, leading to attacks by Butler, Hume, Reid and others on the notion that personal or self identity could be constructed in this manner. The self that is constructed by memory seemed more a fiction than a real entity. Hume, in particular, claimed that there could be no simple continuous self that is based on consciousness alone. William James, in some sense, culminated this approach, when he suggested that the “thought is the thinker” and that personal identity involved appropriation or taking ownership of thoughts previously owned by other thoughts. Galen Strawson is a recent advocate of this kind of view. While some empiricists focused on continuity of consciousness, materialists like Priestley, increasingly shifted the focus to the body as the basis of personal unity, and self as no more than a developmentally acquired concept. At the beginning of the 18th century, Hazlitt, a student of Priestley, put forward a sophisticated account of the development of self-concepts, while also opposing the notion of real and simple personal identity through time. His view, defended in part through fission examples involving the resurrection, has much in common with Derek Parfit’s philosophy of personal identity developed in the late 20 th century. In the 19th century, partly in response to Darwin’s evolutionary theory, the focus was increasingly on personality or self being based in biology not on a rational self-conscious agent distinct from body. Nevertheless, throughout the 2 century both types of view were current, with a lot of interest in dual personalities and in altered states of consciousness. The net effect of dialogue over these cases was the “discovery of the unconscious” and the development of a dynamic psychology of personality of the sort found in Freud. Another important development during this period was an increasing awareness of the role of social life on self-consciousness. Beginning with Hegel’s discussion of how selfconsciousness arises in the relationship between the master and slave, and continued in Marx’s social materialist philosophy, the social basis of selfawareness increasingly became a part of the developmental story of the origins of self-conceptions. By the end of the century, in the work of James as well as in the developmental psychology of James Mark Baldwin, we see the emergence of a social psychology of self that has dominated much of psychology in the 20 th century. During the 20th century the notions of self and personal identity took multiple theoretical paths in philosophy, psychology, neuroscience and social sciences. The self became fractionated not only between disciplines but also within disciplines. The notion of a unitary self of any sort came increasingly in doubt. During the first half of the century the search for the real self continued on in existential and personality psychology as well as in analytic philosophy, but during the second half of the century, post-structuralist and post-modernist views joined forces with narrative approaches, developmental psychology, neuroscience, and personal identity theory to increasingly shift the focus away from the idea of a unitary, real self to multiple fictional or conceptual selves, and from mental selves to embodied, social selves. The implication of this history for the topic of the present conference is that the notion of a unitary encapsulated, conscious self with a natural boundary separating it from other selves and the world at large, including its own body, is a constructed notion with a history. We are now in the process of dismantling this notion and reconstructing this history. But it is unlikely that we will totally replace the notion of the conscious self with the notion that self is a fiction. For practical purposes, the self has become a necessary concept for social life and we cannot do without it. Still, it will be interesting to see how our theoretical notions of self evolve in the future, particularly with respect to the issue of the present conference on the boundaries between selves and between self and the world. The main difficulty for the future development of theories of self is that there exist in the current literature numerous notions and theories of self that appear mutually exclusive and cannot be resolved into a single central idea of self. So perhaps the only solution that we can hope for is to develop a theoretical taxonomy of self-notions that complement each other rather than conflict with each other. The effort to form such a set of interdependent non-contradictory notions of self may have begun with William James’s heroic effort to analyze self in terms of the stream of conscious experience, where he made distinctions between self as object and self as subject within the stream, with the self as object being analyzed into several types: material self, social self, and spiritual self, while the self as subject resolved itself into the individual unitary thought as thinker, which appropriates previous thoughts in the stream of consciousness. In 3 his analysis, James seemed to presuppose a functional unity to the stream, and that the various categories in his analysis should be taken as conceptual or functional rather than ontological categories. However, it seems that subsequent thinkers who built upon aspects of James’s analysis, took the divisions he made as ontological rather than conceptual or functional, and pursued one or another of his selves as the dominant one. Thus, social psychologists from Mead to Gergen have focused on the self as social, and as constituted in social relations. By contrast, phenomenologists following Husserl have focused on the stream of consciousness, and have analyzed how the self might be a logically necessary notion to account for unity of the stream, or how the self gets constituted by interconnected thoughts within the stream and appears as content within it. However these two splintered directions that emerged out of James’s analysis, are only two of the many theoretically independent traditions currently available, and these two have also fragmented further in numerous directions. In order to survey the current diversity, if only with a brief sampling, it helps to ask three basic questions about the self: What is the self? Where is the self? When is the self? Each of these questions currently generates diverse answers. For: What is the self? Some theorists still hold onto the notion that the self is an immaterial substance; others take more modern views: that it is the whole material organism, or the brain, or a function of the brain, or the stream of consciousness, or a momentary thought in the stream, or a kind of content in the stream, or that there are multiple social selves depending on content in the stream, or that multiple selves are determined by the thoughts of other individuals about a person, or that self is a fictional entity – a linguistic construction. For: Where is the self? Theorists focus on the organism, or brain, or in social arrangements that produce multiple selves, or self might include all that an individual human being can think about or relate to in the universe, or that the self is nowhere, either because it is immaterial or because it is a fiction. For: When is the self? In addition to pre-modern notions of immortality and reincarnation or resurrection, we have modern notions of the life-history of the human being, or the period when the human is conscious of itself as a self, or the links in memory of self, or a moment of self reflection, or the story that a person creates to describe itself, or the time during which the brain is active, or only when the brain is active in certain ways. Three dimensional personal identity theorists believe that the whole person or self exists in the moment, but continues through time, while four-dimensional theorists claim that only person parts exist in the moment, and the self is smeared across time. Although many of these answers are incompatible with each other it seems possible that some of them could be integrated together in a manner that would provide an internally consistent notion of self – perhaps not as a simple unity as thinkers had hoped for in the past, but one that gives theoretical unity to aspects of self phenomena. Dan Zahavi’s and Albert Newen’s talks yesterday give examples of how this theoretical unity may be possible where several notions of self are linked together in a dynamic system that changes in functional properties through human development, without implying that any one notion of self identifies an ontologically ‘true’ self to the exclusion of others. We may just have to live with 4 the understanding that there is no such simple unified soul or self – that such a simple unified self, always was, and only now can be recognized to be, a theoretical fiction, and that any unity of self that exists, if it does exist, must be a complex dynamic unity of functional elements, not a simple unity of a central allpowerful simple self. Stepping back and looking at Western theorizing about the self and personal identity as a whole and what it means, an important part of what it means that theory took the course that it did is that in the West, from the earliest beginnings of theory until fairly recently, thinkers have been preoccupied with elevating the self—the “I”—to an exalted status. The soul was created importantly for this purpose, and when the soul ceased to be useful, the unified self was called in to fill the void. Seemingly very different notions, but essentially the same game: to show that the self—the I—is a demigod of sorts, reigning unopposed over its domain, the human person. From a selfish point of view, much of what matters most to humankind was linked to this demigod: one’s essence, free will, consciousness, personal survival, the defeat of death. What the history of theory thus shows is that there has been a persistent effort, from beginning to end, to make this case—to show that a unified self is a secure repository of many of humankind’s most glorious conceits and aspirations. And what history also shows is that in the face of continuing scientific development, the case for many of these conceits and aspirations cannot be made. In the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, science undermined the soul. The self was recruited to take its place, including providing unity and direction to the human person, as well as being the vehicle for persistence both during life and after bodily death. In effect, science took the I, as soul, out of heaven and in the guise of a unified self brought it down to earth. Like the soul, the self was to be the source of unity, power, freedom, control, and persistence. But the fly in the ointment was analysis. So, soon enough what had been one— the I—became many. What had been real became fiction. And what had been a source of explanations became itself in need of explanation. Analysis has been the self’s undoing. As a fragmented, explained, and illusory phenomenon, the self could no longer retain its elevated status. And it is hard to see how it might ever again regain that status. It is as if all of Western civilization has been on a prolonged ego trip that reality has finally forced it to abandon. If this interpretation is right, then what happens next may be a new phenomenon in history, a kind of dark night of the “soul”: not necessarily a bad thing, but a different thing. So, what does it all mean? The story of Western theorizing about the self and personal identity is not only, but centrally, the story of humankind’s attempt to elevate itself above the rest of the natural world, and it is the story of how that attempt has failed. It is another illustration, as if another were needed, of how pride goeth before the fall. 5