Introduction to Seeing... We are so familiar with seeing, that it takes a leap of imagination to realise that there are problems to be solved. But consider it. We are given tiny distorted upside-down images in the eyes, and we see separate solid objects in surrounding space. From the patterns of stimulation on the retinas we perceive the world of objects, and this is nothing short of a miracle. The eye is often described as like a camera, but it is the quite uncamera-like features of perception which are most interesting. How is information from the eyes coded into neural terms, into the language of the brain, and reconstituted into experience of surrounding objects? The task of eye and brain is quite different from either a photographic or a television camera converting objects merely into images. There is a temptation, which must be avoided, to say that the eyes produce pictures in the brain. A picture in the brain suggests the need of some kind of internal eye to see it but this would need a further eye to see its picture... and so on in an endless regress of eyes and pictures. This is absurd. What the eyes do is to feed the brain with information coded into neural activity - chains of electrical impulses - which by their code and the patterns of brain activity, represent objects. We may take an analogy from written language: the letters and words on this page have certain meanings, to those who know the language. They affect the reader's brain appropriately, but they are not pictures. When we look at something, the pattern of neural activity represents the object and to the brain is the object. No internal picture is involved. Gestalt writers did tend to say that there are pictures inside the brain. They thought of perception in terms of modifications of electrical fields of the brain, these fields copying the form of perceived objects. This doctrine, known as isomorphism, has had unfortunate effects on thinking about perception. Ever since, there has been a tendency to postulate properties to these hypothetical brain fields such that visual distortions, and other phenomena, are 'explained'. But it is all too easy to postulate things having just the right properties. There is no independent evidence for such brain fields, and no independent way of discovering their properties. If there is no evidence for them, and no way of discovering their properties, then they are highly suspect. Useful explanations relate observables. The Gestalt psychologists did however point to several important phenomena. They also saw very clearly that there is a problem in how the mosaic of retinal stimulation gives rise to perception of objects. They particularly stressed the tendency for the perceptual system to group things into simple units. This is seen in an array of dots. Introduction to Seeing (2) This array of equally spaced dots is seen as continually changing patterns of rows and squares. We see something of the active organising power of the visual system while looking at this figure. Here the dots are in fact equally spaced, but there is a tendency to see, to 'organise', the columns and rows as though they are separate objects. This is worth pondering, for in this example we have the essential problem of perception. We can see in ourselves the groping towards organising the sensory data into objects. If the brain were not continually on the look-out for objects, the cartoonist would have a hard time. But, in fact, all he or she has to do is present a few lines to the eye and we see a face, complete with an expression. The few lines are all that is required for the eye - the brain does the rest: seeking objects and finding them whenever possible. Sometimes we see objects which are not there: faces in the fire, or the Man in the Moon. Introduction to Seeing (3) Although we are concerned with how we see the world of objects, it is important to consider the sensory processes giving perception - what they are, how they work and when they fail to work properly. It is by coming to understand these underlying processes that we can understand how we perceive objects. Introduction to Seeing (4) There are many familiar so-called 'ambiguous figures', which illustrate very clearly how the same pattern of stimulation at the eye can give rise to different perceptions, and how the perception of objects goes beyond sensation. The most common ambiguous figures are of two kinds: figures which alternate as 'object' or 'ground', and those which spontaneously change their position in depth. This figure makes the point clearly. Just a set of meaningless lines? No - it is a woman with a bucket washing the floor! Now look again: the lines are subtly different, almost solid they represent objects. The seeing of objects involves many sources of information beyond those meeting the eye when we look at an object. It generally involves knowledge of the object derived from previous experience, and this experience is not limited to vision but may include the other senses; touch, taste, smell, hearing and perhaps also temperature or pain. Objects are far more than patterns of stimulation: objects have pasts and futures; when we know its past or can guess its future, an object transcends experience and becomes an embodiment of knowledge and expectation without which life beyond the simplest is not possible. Here is an example which alternates in figure and ground - sometimes the black part appears as a face, the white being neutral background, and at others the black is insignificant and the white surround dominates and seems to represent an object, a vase or chalice. The well-known Necker cube shows a figure alternating in depth. Sometimes the face marked with the 'o' lies in front, sometimes at the back - it jumps suddenly from the one position to the other. Perceiving and thinking are not independent: 'I see what you mean' is not a peurile pun, but indicates a connection which is very real. Richard Gregory Perception is not determined simply by the stimulus patterns; rather it is a dynamic searching for the best interpretation of the available data. The data are sensory signals, and also knowledge of the many other characteristics of objects. Just how far experience affects perception, how far we have to learn to see, is a difficult question to answer; it is one which will concern us in this book. But it seems clear that perception involves going beyond the immediately given evidence of the senses: this evidence is assessed on many grounds and generally we make the best bet, and see things more or less correctly. But the senses do not give us a picture of the world directly; rather they provide evidence for the checking of hypotheses about what lies before us. Indeed we may say that the perception of an object is an hypothesis, suggested and tested by the sensory data. The Necker cube is a pattern which contains no clue as to which of two alternative hypotheses is correct: the perceptual system entertains first one then the other hypothesis, and never comes to a conclusion, for there is no best answer. Sometimes the eye and brain come to wrong conclusions, and then we suffer hallucinations or illusions. When a perceptual hypothesis - a perception - is wrong, we are misled, as we are misled by science when we see the world distorted by a false theory.