Elemental Teleology Running head: ELEMENTAL TELEOLOGY Elemental Teleology and an Interpretation of the Rainfall Example in Physics 2.8 Caleb Kinlaw MSc Philosophy The University of Edinburgh 2008 1 Elemental Teleology 2 Abstract This paper proposes an interpretation of the rainfall example in which Aristotle does not himself think that crop growth is the final cause of rain. The grounds for this interpretation will be an ‘elemental teleology’ which affirms that the only final cause of the movements of the elements is the goal of reaching their proper places of rest. Textual evidence for the presence of this doctrine in Aristotle’s thought is examined in the first two thirds of the paper. My interpretation is then offered along with an argument for why it is both possible and preferable to the alternative reading which claims that Aristotle believed that rain falls for the sake of the crops. Elemental Teleology Table of Contents Introduction…………………………………………………………………………….4 Chapter I – Teleology and the Four Elements…………………………………………6 Aitia in Aristotle……………………………………………………………………….6 Final Cause…………………………………………………………………………….7 Function……………………………………………………………………….8 Goal / Event…………………………………………………………………...8 Value…………………………………………………………………………..9 The Scope of Aristotle’s Teleology……………………………………………………10 Change and the Four Elements………………………………………………………...11 Natural Change………………………………………………………………..11 The Constitution of the Elements……………………………………………..14 Elemental Motion……………………………………………………………..18 Teleology and Necessity…………………………………….…………………………20 Simple Necessity………………………………………………...………….…20 Hypothetical Necessity………………………………………………………..22 Does Elemental Locomotion Have a Final Cause? ……………………………………25 Chapter II – An Interpretation of the Rainfall Example in Physics 2.8………………..27 The Difficulty in Physics 2.8…………………………………………………………..27 The Rainfall Example………………………………………………………………….31 Is the teleology of rainfall being questioned? ………………………………...32 The ‘Opposite Effects Argument’……………………………………………..34 Rainfall and Hypothetical Necessity…………………………………………..35 The Seasonality of Rain……………………………………………………….37 Conclusion……………………………………………………………………………..38 Works Cited……………………………………………………………………………40 3 Elemental Teleology 4 Concerning Aristotle’s Teleology and the Elements In Physics 2.8 Aristotle puts forward a ‘difficulty’ concerning causality in nature. Aristotle there examines a ‘materialist’ explanation of natural processes. This viewpoint claimed that rain does not fall for the sake of crop growth. Commentators are divided on the issue of whether or not Aristotle agreed with this claim. I will argue that he did not think that rain occurs for the sake of man’s crops. Aristotle did, however, believe that rain takes place for the sake of something. It will be the position of this paper that Aristotle considered the only final cause of rainfall to be water’s natural tendency to move towards its proper place. The idea that water moves upwards with its natural motion for the sake of reaching its proper place is consistent with an ‘elemental teleology’. Though Aristotle nowhere explicitly says that elemental motion has a final cause1, the extensive textual support for ‘elemental teleology’ within the Aristotelian corpus validates this position. However, the context of the rainfall example lends itself to multiple interpretations. In the text Aristotle presents a viewpoint which claims that processes in nature are not caused by the purpose they serve just as rain does not fall in order to make crops grow. Because Aristotle rejects the central materialist thesis, the denial of final causality in nature, it is often said that the entire text expresses a viewpoint antithetical to Aristotle’s own. The purpose of this paper is to argue that though Aristotle did believe that rain falls for the sake of something, he did not disagree with the materialists’ rejection of crop growth as the final cause of rain. Though referring to the opposing viewpoint as ‘materialist’ is anachronistic it is still an appropriate label. Susan Suave Meyer describes the viewpoint: The opponents whom Aristotle has in mind are the Presocratic natural philosophers (phusiologoi) – especially Democritus, Empedocles, and Anaxagoras. He here homogenizes their views and attributes to them generally the thesis that natural phenomena result of necessity from the activities of the material elements.2 These thinkers neglected the final cause and gave their focused attention to the material and efficient causes. Though such terminology was not available to these thinkers their thought can nonetheless be understood in terms of Aristotle’s classification of causes. It is because they gave primary causal power to the material cause that the title ‘materialist’ is acceptable. My interpretation will be founded on an elemental teleology, the principle that the 1 2 Robert Wardy, ‘Aristotelian Rainfall or the Lore of Averages’, p. 20. ‘Aristotle, Teleology, and Reduction’, p. 792. Elemental Teleology 5 four elements (earth, air, fire, and water) move for the sake of reaching their proper places. Because elemental teleology is the framework through which I will examine the text of Physics 2.8 I will dedicate the greater part of this paper (sections 1 – 6) to exploring the key ideas which constitute this position: the final cause, the elements and their movements. With an understanding of these concepts it will then be possible to interpret the rainfall example in a manner consistent with, and restricted to, the tenets of elemental teleology. This paper is divided into 2 chapters with a total of 8 sections. Chapter I establishes that elemental teleology is Aristotelian in order to justify my interpretation of the rainfall example. The first two sections examine the idea of cause in Aristotle, with a specific focus given to the final cause. Section (3) will consider where the final cause is present in the Aristotelian cosmos. It will be shown that the presence of the final cause is particularly difficult to confirm with regard to the movements of the four elements. In section (4) I will step back to take a look change in general as well as the specific way that the elements change. The discussion concerning elemental changes will introduce the idea of necessity, which will be the subject of section (5). An understanding of necessity will be important for an accurate interpretation of the Physics text because the materialists claimed that processes in nature are necessitated by the matter involved3. I will then return to the question of whether or not the elemental movements have a final cause in section (6). The conclusion reached in that section will affirm that the elements do move with a final cause, and that final cause is reaching the place to which they naturally belong. This ‘elemental teleology’ will be the grounds for my interpretation of Physics 2.8. Chapter II will consist of an examination of the materialist view expressed in Physics 2.8, my interpretation, and reasons in support of my position. It will begin in section (7) by introducing the relevant text. The rainfall example will be interpreted in such a way as to deny that Aristotle thought that crop growth was the final cause of rain. Three reasons will then be given why such a claim is not only possible but also consistent with Aristotle’s view of the final cause in elemental movements. Section (8) will contain the brunt of my argument which consists of the three main reasons in support of the proposed interpretation as well as a response to an important objection: (A) The status of rainfall in its causal relation to crop growth is not being questioned either in the difficulty or in Aristotle’s responding arguments. (B) The ‘Opposite Effects Argument’ put forward in the difficulty is a valid argument. (C) Though rain may be necessary for crops to grow, that does not imply that crop growth is the final cause of rain. The term ‘matter’ would not have been used by Aristotle’s predecessors. Their explanations referred to a cause which Aristotle called the ‘material cause’. For that reason I am using the term ‘matter’ to refer to the specific cause which they made use of. 3 Elemental Teleology 6 (D) Three reasons against accepting David Sedley’s argument4 that the seasonality of rain is evidence that crop growth is the final cause. The paper will conclude with a restatement of my thesis along with a summary of the main points in support of my interpretation. Chapter I – Teleology and the Four Terrestrial Elements 1. Aitia in Aristotle An overview of causation in Aristotle will pave the way for an examination of the final cause. Aitia is the Greek word translated as ‘cause’ in Physics 2.3, where Aristotle puts forward the four types of cause: material, efficient, formal, and final (195a 15) 5. Causes were for Aristotle a means by which to explain something. An aitia was an answer to the question ‘Why?’, or ‘On account of what?’. An explanation of a thing or event will refer to the cause of that thing or event6. To offer such an explanation one must have full knowledge of the cause (An. Post. 1.1 71b7 8-12). Knowledge (scientific) is stated in deductive form, and to demonstrate such knowledge is to form a syllogism “the grasp of which is eo ipso such knowledge,” (An. Post. 1.2 71b 18-19). In such a syllogism the cause can be shown as the middle term which necessitates the conclusion. We know why the Athenians fought the Persians when we understand the aitia of the war (An. Post. 2.11). Aristotle puts forward the following example: 1. Persians attack anyone who raids Sardis. 2. The Athenians raid Sardis. 3. Therefore the Persians attack the Athenians. (An. Post. 94a 35 - b 7) When the first premise is followed by the second the conclusion follows. The term shared by both the first and second premise, ‘raiding Sardis’ is what ‘causes’ the conclusion to follow. The middle term, ‘raiding Sardis’, can thus be considered the efficient cause of the Persian War. Aristotle takes the ‘Why?’ question to be a request for a full understanding of the primary causes of a thing. If we judge the sufficiency of an answer according to the understanding it imparts, we will better understand Aristotle’s conception of ‘cause’. If I am David Sedley, ‘Is Aristotle’s Teleology Anthropocentric?’, pp. 184-187. R.P. Hardie and R.K. Gaye’s translation in The Basic Works of Aristotle, ed. Richard McKeon. 6 When I refer to ‘things’ and ‘events’ in nature, I will not always specify one or the other due to the fact that it will not always matter. Aristotle applies the final cause to ‘things’ such as animals and their parts, as well as ‘events’ such as nest building or reproduction. My arguments will by and large cover both ‘things’ and ‘events’. The concepts often overlap. When discussing the final cause of a ‘thing’ it may make reference to its function, which is an event, or its coming to be, which is also an event. The heart (a thing) exists for the sake of the organism. An understanding of that would require one to recognize the process of how the heart’s activity facilitates the organism’s survival (a process). For this reason I will at times use these terms interchangeably. 4 5 Elemental Teleology 7 asked why I moved my pawn in a game of chess and I reply in terms of the material cause alone (my hand made contact with the wooden piece and changed its location etc.), my reply would rightly be considered unsatisfactory. Aristotle’s four causes distinguish between the different meanings of the ‘Why?’ question and the corresponding different types of answers. The explanation would need to refer also to the strategy which motivated my move (e.g., to gain control of the center of the board). The failure to recognize all types of causation leads to explanations which do not fully explain ‘why’ a thing is as it is. According to Plato in the Phaedo such an impoverished explanation was given by Anaxagoras concerning the arrangement of things. Upon realizing that Anaxagoras’ explanation failed to explain fully why things are as they are, Socrates said that he had failed to provide the causes of such things: My glorious hope, my friend, was quickly snatched away from me. As I went on with my reading I saw that the man made no use of intelligence, and did not assign any real causes for the ordering of things, but mentioned as causes air and ether and water and many other absurdities. And it seemed to me it was very much as if one should say that Socrates does with intelligence whatever he does, and then, in trying to give the causes of the particular thing I do, should say first that I am now sitting here because my body is composed of bones and sinews, and the bones are hard and have joints which divide them and the sinews can be contracted and relaxed and, with the flesh and the skin which contains them all, are laid about the bones. (Phaedo 98b – 99b) As will be seen below, Aristotle expresses similar dissatisfaction with causal explanations given by his materialist predecessors (Phys. 2.8). The point here is that for Aristotle a cause, or aitia, is a full explanatory account of why something is as it is, and not just how. A full explanation will provide the necessary and sufficient conditions for something to come to be in all four senses of the term cause. Such a satisfactory account will require that reference be made to the final cause. 2. Final Cause The final cause is introduced in Physics 2.2 as ‘that for the sake of which’ a thing is done (194b 33). Like in the example above, the final cause can serve as the middle term of a syllogism which necessitates the conclusion. The following syllogism provides an answer to the question, “Why does the house exist?”: 1. A structure is built which serves to preserve one’s goods. 2. The preservation of one’s goods is the function of a house. 3. The structure that is built is a house. (An. Post. 2.11 94b 9-10) The middle term here is ‘the preservation of man’s goods’, which is the final cause of the existence of the house. The final cause thus offers an answer to the ‘why’ question of the Elemental Teleology 8 house’s existence. Identifying the final cause of a house is relatively easy in comparison with finding it in nature. In order to pursue that inquiry one must know exactly what to look for. There are multiple aspects of the final cause which can be gathered from Aristotle’s application of the concept. I would like to highlight three aspects of final causation which will assist in understanding and identifying it in nature. The final cause can be considered in terms of: function, goal and value. A. Function An essential function is a thing’s primary purpose. The function of a thing is sometimes said to be the ‘end’ of its existence: The function of each thing is its end. It is obvious, then, that the function is better than the state. For the end, as end, is the best. For it was assumed that the best and the final is the end for the sake of which all other things exist. That the function is better than the sate and the condition, then, is plain. (E.E. 2.1 1219a 8-11) When something is fulfilling its function it is acting (or causing) in virtue of being itself. The eye is fully an eye when it is actively seeing, because that is its primary function7. Among the many functions performed by an organism, that which is highest is its end. By ‘highest’ I mean the function which is the actualization of the organism’s form. Frog legs may function as an appetizer or as means for jumping. Since the latter function fulfils a key aspect of what it is to be a frog, it is that which is the leg’s primary function. For animals in general the primary function is utilizing the power of perception and locomotion, and for man the exercise of thought is primary as well as perception (NE 1170a 16-17). Given that a thing’s primary function is also its end, it may be said to exist for the sake of performing that function. The sculptor only has being as a sculptor as long as he is able to make sculptures. The fact that the primary function is the ‘end’ of a thing’s existence means that it exists for the sake of performing that function and not the other way around. The eye exists for the sake of seeing, but animals do not see in order to have the capacity of seeing (Meta. 9.8 1050a 1011; D.A. 2.1 412b 10-24). B. Goal / End Any purpose driven action requires an end if it is to avoid becoming subject to an infinite regress of explaining for what sake the action takes place (Meta. 2.2 994b 8-16). One might explain one’s moral choices by appealing to the goal of being happy. If there were no such goal then an explanation of a given moral choice would be subject to an infinite regress, never arriving at a sufficient explanation of ‘why’ the action was chosen. The same is true of 7 De Anima 2.1 412b 10-24 Elemental Teleology 9 any rational activity. For example, the ‘end’ of the boat builder’s activity is the completed boat. Without such an end there would be no reason to begin the process. Monte Johnson says the same goes for intentional activity in general, “Action cannot get off the ground if there is no determinate and ultimate end for the sake of which it is undertaken”8. The cause ‘for the sake of which’ is not necessarily an ‘end’ in the sense of the final stage of a process. It is the ‘aim’ of the process which is fulfilled in the final stage, but it remains present whether or not the final stage is ever realized. If the boat is not successfully completed, the boat still remains the ‘end’ of boat-building activities insofar as it was that for the sake of which the process started. It is helpful to think of the final cause as “that for the sake of which” rather than implying finality or completion. This point is made clear in Metaphysics 5.17 when Aristotle says that sometimes the final cause is both the starting thing and the end of the process. In discussing the meanings of ‘limit’ he says it is, “the end of each thing (and of this nature is that towards which the movement and the action are, not that from which they are - though sometimes it is both, that from which and that to which the movement is, i.e. the final cause)” (1022a 6-9). When a doctor heals a patient the final cause of ‘health’9 is in the doctor’s mind before he cures the patient, and it is instantiated in the patient after he is cured10. Thus the final cause of health, though it is the ‘end’ of the process of healing, is present at the beginning of the change as well as at the end. C. Value. The final cause must be a good for that which it is a cause. Aristotle says: “‘That for the sake of which’ means what is best and the end of the things that lead up to it. (Whether we say the ‘good itself’ or the ‘apparent good’ makes no difference.)” (Phys. 2.3 195a 24-25). The final cause was seen above to be a goal at which a process aims. The goal however must be good for the thing undergoing the process. For, death is a goal in the sense that it is the last stage in a process, but it is not a final cause because it is not a good. David Furley says, “Again, since every animal dies in the end, why should we not say that its life processes are for the sake of death? Aristotle’s answer was that the goal must be recognizably a good.”11 Having distinguished between the goal or end of a process and the value of completing a process we are able to understand why Aristotle considers the final cause to have a dual meaning. Something may exist or occur for the sake of something in two ways 8 Aristotle on Teleology, p. 83. ‘Health’ is here being considered as the idea of health, or the ‘formula’ of health (Meta. 7.7 1032b5). 10 Aristotle says in Meta. Zeta, “But from art proceed the things of which the form is in the soul of the artist,” (1032a 34). Thus in art the form is passed on just as in natural generation. But in art the form exists beforehand in the soul of the craftsman, in natural generation it exists in the parent. David Bostock says, “That ‘by which’ the generation is effected is the same form as is acquired in the generation, but ‘in another’ – in the one case in a material thing (the parent), but in the other in the mind,” (Metaphysics Book Z and H, p. 125). 11 ‘What Kind is Aristotle’s Final Cause?’ p. 66. 9 Elemental Teleology 10 (Phys. 2.2 194a 35-6). It may occur for the sake of reaching the goal or for the sake of attaining a good. Aristotle says, “The phrase ‘for the sake of which’ is ambiguous; it may mean either (a) the end to achieve which, or (b) the being in whose interest, the act is done,” (De Anima 2.4 415b 3-4). So the final cause of constructing the house is both (a) the goal of a completed house and (b) the man whose goods will be preserved. This illustrates the important distinction between “(a) some being for whose good an action is done, and (b) something at which the action aims” (Meta. 12.6 1072b 2-3). 3. The Scope of Aristotle’s Teleology The presence of the final cause is expansive in Aristotle’s cosmos. “Nature never makes anything without a purpose” (P.A. 658a 10). This idea is a leitmotif running throughout many of Aristotle’s physical works12. Does this mean that all things and events in nature have a final cause? The boundaries of what is and what is not included within the teleological realm are not easy to identify. It is for this reason that even today interpretations differ concerning Aristotle’s view of rainfall. A tool which Aristotle uses in order to identify the final cause within nature is his ‘nature-craft analogy’. Many processes in nature are said to be teleological due to the resemblance they bear to processes carried out by people. With regard to final causality Aristotle sees a close similarity between nature and craft. He uses this similarity to support his claims that processes in nature are goal oriented (Phys. 199a 10-20, 33- 199b6, 199b 25-30). He claims that: Further, where a series has a completion, all the preceding steps are for the sake of that. As in intelligent action, so in nature; and as in nature, so it is in each action, if nothing interferes. Now intelligent action is for the sake of an end; therefore the nature of things also is so. Thus if a house, e.g., had been a thing made by nature, it would have been made in the same way as it is now by art; and if things made by nature were made also by art, they would come to be in the same way as by nature. (Phys. 199a 9-15). In craft it is easy to observe that each stage of a process takes place for the sake of accomplishing a goal. The carpenter measures and cuts for the sake of making something with the wood. Likewise, processes in nature which occur regularly and usually lead to the same stage of completion when not impeded have that last stage as the final cause of the process. For example, Aristotle mentions the works of creatures such as ants and spiders (Phys. 199a 23). When we see a spider build a web we have grounds for asserting the final cause to be capturing prey. The craft analogy supports this claim because man also creates 12 The idea that nature does nothing in vain can be found in the following texts: De Caelo 271a 33, 291b 13-14; De Anima 432b 21, 434a 41; P.A. 661b 24, 691b 4-5, 694a 15, 695b 19-20; G.A. 739b 19, 741b 4, 744a 37-8. Elemental Teleology 11 traps to catch food, and such processes are caused by the final stage of the process13. It is not debated that animals and their parts are included among those things that are teleological. Plants are included as well (Phys. 199a 23-30). Plants send down their roots naturally ‘for the sake of nourishment’ (199a29). The natural movements (the precise meaning of this term will be explained below) of animate beings and their parts (most of them) do have a goal, function and value. The goal of the plant spreading its roots is to reach water, the function is to provide nourishment, and the value is the plant’s growth and sustenance. It is neither unreasonable nor contentious to claim that some things in nature should be excluded from the category of the teleological. Aristotle recognized that there are limits to what is included among natural things which exist for the sake of something. Some things do not exist for the sake of anything. The color of your eye, for example, does not exist for the sake of anything. It serves no purpose. But the eye itself exists for the sake of seeing, which is part of being human. “Thus the existence and the formation of an eye is ‘for the sake of something,’ but its being blue is not,” (G.A. 5.1 778a 30). An eye is not blue for the sake of anything, the color is an accidental property of the eye (G.A. 778b). It is accidental that the eye is blue, but it is not accidental that the eye can see. Likewise, when considering the eye as the cause of sight, the eye itself will be the direct cause of sight, while the color will be an incidental cause of sight14. We know, then, that plants, animals and their parts exist and function for the sake of something. We also know that there are limits to the teleological realm and some things do not have a final cause. What remains to be considered is the status of the inanimate things in nature. Do these have a goal, function, and value? Like animate beings, inanimate things in nature do move and are changed. To understand whether or not the inanimate beings are included within the teleological realm requires a detailed analysis of such change. For it is in change that causation can be analyzed. 4. Change and the Four Elements 13 The analogy need not bring intentionality into the works of nature. Aristotle considers craft to be without deliberation. “Art does not deliberate,” (Phys. 199b 27). Therefore it is not necessary to consider a spider’s web to be a product of deliberation. Sarah Broadie claims that the objection that this analogy entails that there is a psychological aspect in natural processes is a ‘non-problem’ for Aristotle’s teleology. She says of the analogy that, “craft is non-psychological in precisely those respects in which craft is most suited to provide the model for nature,” (‘Nature and Craft in Aristotelian Teleology’, p. 398). 14 An incidental cause is one which belongs to the direct cause of an effect ‘incidentally’ (Phys. 195a 35). For example, the direct cause of a sculpture is the sculptor, whether he be Polyclitus or Michelangelo. The direct cause of the Pieta was the sculptor while the incidental cause was Michelangelo. This is because ‘sculptor’ and ‘Michelangelo’ are incidentally related. The person who carved the Pieta could not have been anything but a sculptor, but the sculptor who carved it could have been someone other than Michelangelo. Elemental Teleology 12 A. Natural Change Any change which involves one thing becoming something else can be divided into two contrary states (Phys.1.7), a negative and a positive, each of which share a single underlying matter (G.C. 315b30-33). The movement from one pole to the other may involve a change in a thing’s form and matter, or in a quality of the thing. The former type of change is coming-to-be or passing-away15, the latter type is ‘alteration’ (G.C. 317a 23-29). Because it is impossible for something to come-to-be from nothing16, such a change moves from a negative pole of ‘potentiality’ to the positive pole of ‘actuality’17. That way it is not being asserted that something came from nothing, but that something actual came from something that was only potentially so. Another way of putting it would be to say that a being comes from not-being which has potential for being, but nothing comes from not-being qua not-being. Aristotle says, “For coming-to-be necessarily implies the pre-existence of something which potentially ‘is’, but actually ‘is not’; and this something is spoken of both as ‘being’ and as ‘not-being’ (G.C. 317b 16-18). It is not-being in the sense of a privation, which is ‘not-being’ in a qualified sense (Phys. 191b 16). When one thing comes-to-be another thing, that which it comes from serves as the negative pole of ‘not-being’ or ‘potentially being’, while that which comes-to-be serves as the positive pole of ‘being’, or the actual thing. When a man becomes healthy the change is from disease to health. Disease is the privation of health and might exists in that which is potentially healthy. The positive corollary is actual health. With regard to the elements, when one changes into another the two poles will be similarly present. “Hence whatever the contrasted ‘poles’ of the changes may be – whether Fire and Earth, or some other couple – one of them will be a ‘being’ and the other ‘a notbeing’”(G.C. 318b 12-13). Whenever something comes to be there will always be a reciprocal passing away of what served as the negative pole of the change (G.C. 319a 20). For whatever was potential before the change will no longer be potential and will thus not exist as potentially that thing. This movement between contrary poles can pertain to a thing’s quantity, quality, location, or substance18. The two poles of change must be contraries of a reciprocal nature. They must be related to each other as two extremes on a continuum. For example, white and black are both 15 There are five different ways that something can come-to-be given by Aristotle in Physics 1.7. “Generally things which come to be, come to be in different ways: (1) by change of shape, as a statue; (2) by addition, as in things which grow; (3) by taking away, as the Hermes from the stone; (4) by putting together, as a house; (5) by alteration, as things which ‘turn in respect of their material substance,” (190a 5-9). 16 The famous Parmenidean thesis which “more than any other, preoccupied and alarmed the earliest philosophers,” (G.C. 317b 30). 17 The definition of motion is given in Physics 3.1 as “The fulfilment of what exists potentially, in so far as it exists potentially, is motion,” (201a 10). 18 A change involving a thing’s substance means that whatever comes to be can in no way be considered a property of that which served as the negative contrary (G.C. 320a 1-2). For example, when earth changes into fire, fire is not simply a new and different property of earth. Elemental Teleology 13 colors, and can therefore serve as contraries between changes in color. ‘White’ and ‘line’, however, can not serve as two opposite poles because they are not proper contraries (G.C. 323b 25). In a change there must be something shared between that which is before and that which is after the change. I can’t change anything about an object which I have nothing in common with. Try as I might, I won’t be able to change the location of a something I can’t touch. I only have the possibility of changing the location of a marble if I share with the marble the capacity of making physical contact. If we have that in common, then I can make contact with it. Health and disease are identical in so far as they are each a condition of man’s body. If we consider ‘change’ in respect of that which is going to change and that into which it changes (the before and after product), there must also be involved in change an action and a passion. When I push the marble I am the active agent and it is the passive agent. This active-passive dichotomy is characteristic of all change. The active agent in any change must share with the passive agent something in common of which the active is at one extreme and the passive at the other. Fire can only act on ice because both the active and passive agents are identical with regard to being bodies which have temperatures. Fire can not melt an idea because they do not share the quality of having a temperature or being combustible. Aristotle says, Hence agent and patient must be in one sense identical, but in another sense other than (i.e. ‘unlike’) one another. And since (a) patient and agent are generically identical (i.e. ‘like’) but specifically ‘unlike’, while (b) it is ‘contraries’ that exhibit this character: it is clear that ‘contraries and their ‘intermediates’ are such as to suffer action and to act reciprocally – for indeed it is these that constitute the entire sphere of passing-away and coming-to-be. (G.C 324a 4-9). When two things possessing corresponding contraries make contact with each other, the active thing will assimilate the passive thing to itself (G.C. 324a 11). Because ice is potentially warm, and fire is actually hot, fire will make ice like itself and heat the ice. Not only is this likely to happen, it must happen in the absence of interference (G.C. 324a 13, 324b 9). The active contrary which effects such change in other things which are potentially like itself is called by Aristotle an ‘active power’, which is also a ‘cause’ in the sense that it starts the process of change (G.C. 324b114). For fire, this power is ‘the hot’ (G.C. 324b 19). We may furthermore consider ‘the hot’ to be the very form of fire, for Aristotle also says that the form is the power immersed in matter (G.C. 322a29). Something which comes-to-be comes from a) the underlying matter and b) the privation of that which serves as the positive pole of the change. Consider boiling water as an illustration. Water might be considered the underlying matter. Before it boiled the water was cold, and in that sense it lacked warmth. The coolness then would serve as the privation. The Elemental Teleology 14 corresponding contrary is heat, and when the water heats up the privation (coolness) disappears. The tricky thing is that the substratum can be viewed as both the privation and the matter, or as that which does not survive the change and that which does. This may be easier to understand with an illustration provided by Aristotle (Phys. 190b 10-15). When I learn to play the guitar a change takes place. I was un-musical and now I am musical. I am the subject of the change. ‘Musicality’ is the quality which can be represented by two contraries, one which represents a privation (un-musical) and one which represents an actuality (being musical). The product of the change is musical-me, a composite of form (musical) and subject (me). The subject (me, or man) is like the substratum in that it can be viewed as the matter (the thing undergoing change) or as the privation of the form acquired(the potential of whatever is going to be actual)19. The matter can be viewed as a) that which lasts through the change, or as b) that which contains the privation of the form. In the first sense it is potentially that which it becomes actually, and thus it exists before and after the change. In the second sense it passes away, for the privation no longer exists once the form is actualized (Phys. 192a 25-30). Matter, whether viewed as the privation of or the potential for a form, is always in-formed (G.C. 329a 26). Aristotle says that matter is “the ‘mean’ between the two contraries, and matter is imperceptible and inseparable from them,” (G.C. 332a 36-37) If we consider these different aspects of change we can place them in an order of primacy. The substratum is primary in the strictest sense of the word, for it is not actually a body (G.C. 329a 34). The positive and negative contraries with which matter is bound are primary, but they presuppose the substratum. The physical elements must presuppose both the contrary and the substratum and are thus ‘primary’ in a weaker sense (G.C. 329a35). The elements, then, are not ‘prime matter’20 or the actual contraries such as ‘the hot’ and ‘the cold’. To understand what they are let us now turn to their constitution and the in which they change. B. The Constitution of the Elements All the complex bodies on Earth are composed of these four elements (G.C. 334b 34)21. The fact that the elements are the building blocks of all other physical bodies is their If we consider ‘man’ as the subject it is both the ‘matter’ of the changing thing and the privation of the attribute which is being acquired (non-musical). The subject can then be considered in two sense, though numerically it is one (Phys. 190b23-26). 20 The idea of ‘prime matter’ is controversial and commentators are divided on whether or not such a concept can be found in Aristotle’s thought. For an analysis of the different interpretations see the appendix in C.J.F. William’s edition of De Generatione et Corruption or in W. Charlton’s Physics I and II, both in the Clarendon Aristotle Series. 21 However, in Meteorologica 4.4 381b 24, and 382a 4 Aristotle says that physical bodies are composed of earth and water rather than all four elements. This may be due to a different viewpoint being taken in that work, as claimed by H.D.P. Lee in his introduction, “For in this book all four elements are still involved in the composition of bodies; but two are regarded as active, and therefore 19 Elemental Teleology 15 defining characteristic. In De Caelo Aristotle says, “An element, we take it, is a body into which other bodies may be analysed, present in them potentially or in actuality (which of these, is still disputable), and not divisible into bodies different in form,” (G.C. 302a 16-17). Animate bodies can be analysed into three stages of composition. At the basic level the elements are present. These constitute the ‘uniform parts’ such as blood and bone, which in turn constitute the second level, the non-uniform parts, such as the face and the hand (P.A. 646a 13-24). The form of the living being is identifiable with the highest degree of composition, and it is the soul (P.A. 641a 19). When the soul departs the elements remain, but because these are not the form of the being the organism no longer exists (P.A. 641a 20-21). Plants and animals are ‘complex structures’ which come-to-be and pass-away in a manner which makes it clear that more elemental bodies, such as earth, are the basic building blocks of these structures (G.C. 328b 33-35). A corpse will not retain its complexity and will manifest the basic elements upon its decay22, for ‘dust we are and unto dust we shall return’23. On the flip side of that coin, things also grow and are generated from these elements. Plants and animals are generated when the underlying matter of change has a variety of contraries all mixed together (hot-cold, wet-dry, etc.) in just the right proportion (logos) so as to effect the coming-to-be of the thing (Meteor. 4.1 378b 26-29). These perceptible bodies are characterised also by the tangible contraries which they manifest (G.C. 329b 10). The elements contain actual and potential contraries such as hot and cold, yet they are not themselves identical with any one of these contraries. Fire is hot, yet it is not ‘the hot’, or as Aristotle would put it, the contraries do not “constitute the substance of any thing” (Phys. 189a 30). ‘The hot’ is the active power of fire and it acts on that which is potentially hot. It does not act on ‘the cold’, for ‘the cold’ is its own contrary (Phys. 198b33). Aristotle makes this point with regard to Empedocles’ primary contraries Love and Strife, “For Love does not gather Strife together and make things out of it, nor does Strife make anything out of Love, but both act on a third thing different from both,” (Phys. 189a 25-26). Since we observe change taking place between contraries and these contraries are not acting on each other, there is a ‘substratum’ which is postulated as a ‘third principle’ (Phys. 189a 29)24. The primary pairs of contrarieties are hot-cold and dry-wet (G.C. 329b25). The hotcold pair are active contraries, while the wet and the dry are passive (Meteor. 4.1 378b 12). as efficient cause, two as passive, and therefore as material cause,” (Meteorologica, p. xix). 22 “Things, therefore, that are decaying become first moist and then in the end dry: for it was from these properties that they originated, the moist being determined by the dry through the operation of the active properties,” (Meteor. 4.1 379a 8-10). 23 Gen. 3:19. 24 He makes the same point in G.C. 2.1 saying, “We must reckon as an ‘originative source’ and as ‘primary’ the matter which underlies, though it is inseparable from the contrary qualities: for ‘the hot’ is not matter for ‘the cold’ nor ‘the cold’ for ‘the hot’, but the substratum is matter for them both,” (329a 31-33). Elemental Teleology 16 Hot brings like things together and cold joins together like and unlike things (G.C. 329b 2830). Wet is characterised as that which is easily shaped yet has no shape of its own, and dry is that which has a shape of its own but is not ‘readily adaptable in shape’ (G.C. 329b 33). These are the four contraries from which all others are derived (see diagram)25. These four contraries mix and match resulting in four combinations; four rather than six because any two opposites will not be coupled, i.e. there is nothing that is both cold and hot (G.C. 330a30). These four combinations of contraries attach themselves to matter and result in the four elements (G.C. 330b 2): earth, air, water, and fire (Meteor. 339a 16)26. Fire is the combination of the hot and the dry, earth is cold and dry, air is hot and wet, and water is cold and wet. (G.C. 330b 3-5) (see diagram)27. Water is contrary to Fire, and Earth is contrary to Air (G.C. 331a 2-3). Though each element is a pair of contraries, they are each characterized primarily by one of the contraries: Earth is primarily dry, Fire is primarily hot, Air is wet and Water is cold (G.C. 331a3-5). Aristotle believed that the elements could be perceived to come-to-be (G.C. 331a8). The spark which creates a fire involves a change of what was dry and (perhaps) cold into something that is dry and extremely hot. A thunderstorm on a hot humid day manifests a change from hot humid air into cool wet water. These are grounds for asserting that the elements come-to-be from one another28. Aristotle states this doctrine clearly in Meteorolgica 25 The basic tangible contrarieties are: hot-cold, dry-wet, heavy-light, hard-soft, viscous-brittle, roughsmooth, coarse-fine, (G.C. 329b 19-20). The last three pairs are derived from the dry-wet pair. COLD – Brings together with itself other cold things as well as noncold things HOT Brings together with itself other hot things WET – Easily bounded but naturally without bounds DRY – Not easily shaped, but naturally has shape Fine Course Viscous Brittle Hard Soft 26 In a rather enigmatic remark Aristotle says in De Caelo 4.5 that there are as many kinds of matter as there are simple bodies, “The kinds of matter, then, must be as numerous as these bodies, i.e. four, but though they are four there must be a common matter of all – particularly if they pass into one another – which in each is in being different,” (312a 31-35). 27 “And these four couples have attached themselves to the apparently ‘simple’ bodies,” (330b1-2). Hot Hot Wet Air 28 Cold Wet Hot Dry Fire Cold Dry Wet Water Cold Dry Earth An alternative argument for this fact is found in De Caelo where Aristotle says that it would be Elemental Teleology 17 1.3, saying, “We maintain that fire, air, water, and earth are transformable one into another, and that each is potentially latent in the others,” (G.C. 339b 1-3). These changes are directed according to the contraries which characterize the elements. An element will tend to change into that element which shares that contrary which is its primary contrary. For example, earth tends to change into fire because earth is primarily dry and the only other element which shares that contrary is fire. Likewise, fire tends to turn into air because air shares with it fire’s primary contrary ‘hot’. This results in a cycle of change which is facilitated by complimentary factors’ (G.C. 331a24-35) (see diagram)29. The changes are not bound by these rules however, they simply occur most easily and quickly in this way (G.C. 331a25). “It is evident, therefore, that the coming-to-be of the ‘simple’ bodies will be cyclical; and that this cyclical method of transformation is the easiest, because the consecutive ‘elements’ contain interchangeable ‘complimentary factors’,” (G.C. 331b1-3). The water cycle manifests this cycle. Such a cycle would have been considered by Aristotle a change of water into air, and then back into water (G.C. 338b 6-8). The elements do not recur in the same particulars, but in the same kinds. For example, when there is a thunder shower rain falls, evaporates, and then forms a cloud. When that thunder cloud produces rain it will not result in the exact same raindrops as the shower the night before. The recurring rain will be identical in form but different in number. This is similar to the cycle of generations among man. The grandchild is the specifically the same as the grandfather (they are both human), but numerically distinct (they are different people)30. impossible for an element to be generated from either a) an incorporeal body, or b) a corporeal body other than an element (3.6 305a 14-33). Air WET HOT Water COLD DRY Fire 29 Earth The cycle of transmutation: C.J.F. Williams points out important differences between the water-cycle and generational cycle. The stages of cloud-rain-cloud are not analogous to the generations of man, man-man-man, with each being a different person with a different name. In the water cycle there also has to be a cloud in order 30 Elemental Teleology 18 C. Elemental Motion The elements are what Aristotle calls ‘natural substances’ (De Caelo 298a 29-30, Meta. 1017b 10)31. “All these are called substance because they are not predicated of a subject but everything else is predicated of them,” (Meta. 1017b 12-13). For example, we may say that fire is hot, bright, red, etc. But we would not say of anything other than fire that “x is fire”. It is not predicated of other things, but other things are predicated of it. To be a substance also means that the thing has within itself a principle of motion (De Caelo 268b 2729, 301b 17). Such a principle is characteristic of anything which is natural. For example, a tree is a natural substance and has an internal principle of change. A bed is an artefact and not a natural substance, and therefore does not have an internal principle of motion in virtue of itself. If you planted both a wooden bed and a small acorn tree in the ground only one of them would reveal an internal principle of motion (Phys. 193a 11-17)32. This is because a bed is the product of art rather than nature. In Physics 2 Aristotle says, “All the things mentioned present a feature in which they differ from things which are not constituted by nature. Each of them has within itself a principle of motion and of stationariness,” (192b12-15)33. The elements, as bodies with magnitude, are capable of locomotion (De Caelo 268b 15). Because the elements are simple (not made of parts) their motion will be simple as well (De Caelo 269b 30). Simple locomotion can be of two types, circular or rectilinear (or a combination of the two) (De Caelo 268b 14-15). Rectilinear motion is either towards or away from the centre, i.e. upward or downward (De Caelo 268b 21). The four elements move in a rectilinear fashion34: earth and water move downward, fire and air upward (De Caelo 269a 18, Meteor. 339a 11-16). In the absence of any obstacles the elements will move in these directions (De Caelo 311a 20). Though the elements have within themselves a principle of motion, this does not mean that they move themselves. With regard to locomotion animals are self-movers (Phys. 253a 14). Because their motion is derived from within themselves their movements are for there to be rain and vice versa. Among man however this necessity is not reciprocal; if there is to be a 2nd generation there must be a 1st generation, but not the other way around (Aristotle’s De Generatione et Corruptione, p. 209). 31 The elements are sensible-perishable substances, one of three types of substance given in Metaphysics 7, the other two being: sensible-eternal substances and immutable substances (1069a 30 ff.). 32 Aristotle quotes this example from Antiphon who used it as an argument to say that a thing’s matter is its nature. I am here using the example with the intention of illustrating what a principle of motion is and recognize that I am using it in a completely different way than it was used in the context of Physics 2.1. 33 Nature is defined as “a source or cause of being moved and of being at rest in that to which it belongs primarily,” (Phys. 192b 22-23). When referring to a thing’s ‘nature’ Aristotle distinguishes between two senses of the word: it may refer to the matter of a thing or the form (P.A. 641a 26). 34 The ‘fifth element’ (though actually prior to the others), aither, moves in perfect circular motion, (De Caelo 1.2). Elemental Teleology 19 natural (Phys. 254b 17)35. The power to move one’s self is distinctive only of living things. Such movement can be recognized as self-derived because it is accompanied by the power to stop the motion as well as start it (Phys. 255a 5-7). It is impossible for the elements to move themselves because they are ‘naturally connected substances’ (Phys. 255a 13)36. Self-motion requires composition, a division between an active and passive part. In such motion there is a mover and a moved. Elements are not so divided and therefore depend on an external force to set them in motion (Phys.255a 17). That, however, does not mean that when they do move their motion is not natural. Motion which is not derived from within the moving object can be either natural or unnatural. Any movement towards a thing’s proper place is natural, movement in the opposite direction is unnatural (Phys. 254b 22). The elements move towards their proper place, and thus their movements are natural. The elements have natural places which might be thought of as concentric layers which start in the middle of the earth and spread out towards the heavens. Earth’s proper place is at the centre of the world and thus it moves naturally in that direction. Fire’s proper place is at the extremity of the world and it moves upward away from the centre (De Caelo 296b 9-16, Phys. 230b 10-20). These two bodies are ‘absolutely’ heavy and light respectively. Water is ‘relatively’ heavy compared to air, which is ‘relatively’ light. These two bodies combine the properties of heavy and lightness. Air is relatively heavy compared to fire and relatively light compared to water and earth. For this reason water and air rise and fall in rectilinear movements towards their proper places, which are located in the between the centre and extremity, where the other two ‘absolutely’ heavy and light elements move (De Caelo 311a 15-30). Natural movements are therefore towards these places. Every time fire rises and earth falls these movements are natural because they are moving in the direction of their places of rest. Unnatural movements are in the opposite direction. Both natural and unnatural movement can be seen when a rock is thrown into the air. It first rises unnaturally and then moves back towards is proper place. It stops when it hits the ground not because it has reached the centre, but because it is impeded from moving further. Even when the rock is resting on the ground, because its location remains away from the centre, such rest is unnatural in the same way that its flight upward is unnatural (De Caelo 300a 26). “Just as there is unnatural motion, so, too, a thing may be in an unnatural state of rest,” (Phys. 231a 8). It might be wondered why the four elements do not reach their resting points and Johnson defines ‘natural change’ as the change which happens “in the case of things that have a sate of completion and, concomitantly, the capacity to change into that,” (2005, p.134). Such a state of completion with regard to elemental movements will be discussed below. 36 How their movements are to be explained if not from within themselves is a subject debated by commentators. According to Monte Johnson, this issue more than any other, “has been a source of confusion and misinformation about Aristotelian teleology,” (2005, p.135). 35 Elemental Teleology 20 stratify the world into four layers. The elemental movements are caused by the heavenly bodies, especially the sun. Concerning the sublunary region Aristotle says, “This region must be continuous with the motions of the heavens, which therefore regulate its whole capacity for movement: for the celestial element as source of all motion must be regarded as first cause,” (339a20-25). If the sun had no effect on the atmosphere and terrestrial world the elements would each settle into their places like a jar of oil and water would settle after being shaken. The celestial motions keep them ‘stirred up’ in the changes and processes which we see in nature37. The sun’s continual approach and retreat govern the processes of generation and destruction (G.C. 336b 9), as well as causing the transmutation of the elements to continue (337a 13). The cycle of transmutation, governed by the sun’s movements, is what keeps the elements from separating unto themselves. It is because their movements are natural that each element always moves in the same direction without fail (Phys. 252a 17). If you witnessed a stone floating on water it would be unnatural because water’s proper place is above earth rather than closer to the centre. Does the fact that the elements always display natural motion mean that it is impossible that a stone could float on the water? This line of thought brings us to the idea of necessity in elemental motions. 5. Teleology and Necessity It was mentioned above that fire must melt ice upon contact in the absence of interference. Aristotle makes a similar remark with regard to elemental motions: These arguments make it plain that every body has its natural movement, which is not constrained or contrary to its nature. We go on to show that there are certain bodies whose necessary impetus is that of weight and lightness. Of necessity, we assert, they must move, and a moved thing which has no natural impetus cannot move either towards or away from the centre. (De Caelo 301a 21-26) In the Metaphysics we learn that something can be ‘necessary’ in a few different ways. Something is necessary when it is (A) that without which a being cannot live, or a good can not be attained (health), (B) that which impedes or hinders an impulse or purpose, as when something is forced to act in a certain way due to necessity, and (C) that which can not be otherwise (Meta. 5.5). The last of these senses of ‘necessary’ is the most fundamental (Meta. 1015a 35). When something ‘necessary’ is causal (when it produces an effect), it may be referred to as ‘necessity’ (Meta. 1015b 5). So when it is necessary for the sick person to undergo surgery in order to live, his choice is caused by necessity in all three senses listed above (Meta. 1015a 24). 37 H.D.P. Lee, Meteorologica, pp. 8-9, n. (c). Elemental Teleology 21 A. Simple Necessity That which is necessary, or that which necessarily causes an effect, may be classified as one of two general types of necessity: un-hypothetical and hypothetical (Phys. 199b 34, P.A. 642a 35). The first type of necessity is also called ‘simple’ necessity. This type of necessity is present in any production involving the four elements. As was noted, the elements are natural substances and have natures which consist of an internal principle of movement towards their proper place. The nature of the element refers to its matter and form. The element is the composite of matter and form in its very definition. If it did not have the nature it has it would not be what it is. This implies that the element is, and moves, as it does in a way that is necessary in sense (C) above. Since earth is what it is, it moves downward in the absence of interference. This same necessity applies in mathematics. “Since a straight line is what it is, it is necessary that the angles of a triangle should equal two right angles,” (Phys. 200a 14). The sum of the angles of a triangle necessarily follow upon the nature of a line. Simple necessity can also be seen in syllogisms. 1. A is B 2. B is C 3. Therefore, A is C. The conclusion is a necessary consequent of the two premises which have a single common middle term (An. Post. 94a 25). If A is B and B is C it can not be false that A is C. In a similar way, 1. An element is a natural substance. 2. A natural substance moves in the direction of its proper place. 3. An element moves in the direction of its proper place. If an element did not naturally move in the direction of its place of rest then either (1) or (2) would be false. As it is, we have seen that (1) and (2) are actually true, so (3) follows necessarily. The movement of the element then follows upon the premise that it has a nature and that such a nature involves an internal principle of motion in a certain direction (premises (1) and (2) respectively). When a rock is thrown into the air it moves in two directions, each of which is necessary in an un-hypothetical sense (An. Post. 94b 37-95a 4). The movement upward would be necessary in sense (B). It moves upward due to an external force pushing it in opposition to its natural movement, hindering such movement. When it begins to fall back to the ground it does so because that is its nature and it can not do otherwise. Aristotle says in Posterior Analytics, “Necessity too is of two kinds, it may work in accordance with a thing’s natural tendency, or by constraint and in opposition to it; as, for instance, by necessity a stone is borne both upwards and downwards, but not by the same necessity,” (94a 37). The sum of the angles of a triangle are necessarily 180 degrees because of the nature of a Elemental Teleology 22 line (Phys. 200a 14). Insofar as the lines are the parts which constitute the triangle, they may be viewed as the matter of a triangle. The nature of the matter necessitates an essential characteristic of a material thing. This necessity can be seen in art and nature as well as math. Consider a wall made of bricks and mortar (Phys. 200a 1-5). The bricks are by nature hard, have straight edges, heavy, solid, and do not crumble under heavy weight or changing weather. The mortar is wet, malleable, and upon drying it acts like glue which can also withstand weight and weather. This is the matter of a wall. Now consider the wall. It too is hard, straight, heavy, and can support heavy weight and exposure to the weather. These features of the wall follow upon the nature of the matter in the same way that the angles of a triangle follow upon the nature of a line. Given that the matter has a certain nature, the wall necessarily will be of a certain nature. Placed in a syllogism this could be expressed as follows: 1. A wall is made of bricks. 2. Bricks are hard and heavy. 3. Therefore the wall is hard and heavy. And it is not only the finished product that is determined by the nature of its matter, but the process of its production as well. If we consider the wall again, how would the process of its construction begin? An idiot might begin by throwing the bricks in the air hoping to build it from the top down. The wall, however, can not be constructed in this way because the process must, of necessity, have certain steps taken in a certain order. It is because bricks have straight edges that they must be stacked upon one another with their flat sides making contact. It is because bricks do not naturally adhere to one another that mortar must be placed between them38. It is because mortar naturally holds two flat surfaces together that the bricks are not stacked on their corners. All of these stages, stacking on the ground, spreading mortar, stacking the next row, are in a way determined by the material being used. This determining force is simple necessity. The wall can not be built from the top down, it can not be built any other way than from the bottom up. This is due to the nature of the material. This idea is well expressed when Aristotle says “Necessity is in the matter,” (Phys. 200a 14). B. Hypothetical Necessity The second type of necessity, ‘hypothetical necessity’, is present among processes which have a final cause. Given that animals and artefacts are both finally caused it is not surprising that Aristotle says that hypothetical necessity, “has to do with everything that is formed by the processes of Nature, as well as with the products of Art, such as houses and so forth,” (P.A. 639b 23-25). A wall exists to support a roof. This is the purpose and final cause 38 David Bostock refers to these requirements as ‘laws of matter’ (2006, p. 66). Elemental Teleology 23 of the wall’s construction. For Aristotle, the presence of the final cause implies a different sort of necessity, one based on a hypothesis. It is necessary to build a base before building the top of the wall due to the material being used. This was referred to above as simple necessity. But the presence of the building material is not necessary due to the nature of the matter. It is not necessary for bricks to be at the building site unless such bricks are needed for an intended wall. The materials are necessary, not due to their natures, but on the hypothesis that a wall is going to be built (P.A.. 639b 27)39. If there is to be a wall, then bricks and mortar are necessary. This is itself based on the hypothesis of their being a roof, which is the final cause. Aristotle explains this concept with an example: For instance, why is a saw such as it is? To effect so-and-so and for the sake of so-and-so. This end, however, cannot be realized unless the saw is made of iron. It is, therefore, necessary for it to be of iron, if we are to have a saw and perform the operation of sawing. What is necessary then, is necessary on a hypothesis; it is not a result necessarily determined by antecedents. (Phys. 200a 11-14)40. The difference between hypothetical and un-hypothetical necessity turns on whether or not the process has a final cause. When there is an end, purpose, or value which is serving as a final cause, then the entire process happens for the sake of that end. That means that the bricks and mortar and tools were gathered together only because of the final cause. Without such a goal there would be no way to determine what material is needed, and thus no process and no simple necessity governing that process. This was where, according to Aristotle, some of his predecessors went wrong41. Failing to recognize the importance of the final cause, they witnessed the simple necessity present in nature and art and claimed that it was fully responsible for both the process of production as well as the finished product. For example, such thinkers would say that the wall is what it is only because of the process of its production which was governed by simple necessity. Aristotle says that if these thinkers were seriously committed to this claim then they must account for the wall’s existence by making reference only to the material used. He highlights the absurdity of this view, saying: The current view places what is of necessity in the process of production, just as if one were to suppose that the wall of a house necessarily comes to be because what is heavy is naturally carried downwards and what is light to the top, wherefore the stones and foundations take the lowest place, with earth above because it is lighter, the wood at the top of all as being lightest. This point is made in Physics 2.9 as well, “If the end is to exist or does exist, that also which precedes it will exist or does exist; otherwise just as there, if the conclusion is not true, the premises will not be true, so here the end or ‘that for the sake of which’ will not exist….If then there is to be a house, such-and-such things must be made or be there already or exist, or generally the matter relative to the end, bricks and stones if it is a house,” (Phys. 200a 20-26). 40 The same illustration is used in P.A. 642a 10-12. 41 The accuracy of Aristotle’s presentation of the thought of his predecessors is a subject outside the scope of this paper. 39 Elemental Teleology 24 (Phys. 200a1 5) If you were to ask one of these predecessors why a house has a foundation they would reply that the foundation is made of concrete, and that is the heaviest of all the house-building materials. Therefore it is located beneath everything else. Aristotle’s criticism is emphasizing the fact that when there is a purpose of a thing it must be referred to in an explanation of its coming to be. An important point to take note of here is that the form plays the role of giving a process its direction. This applies to the coming-to-be of a wall or the birth of an animate substance. The direction moves towards the form of the mature specimen. The puppy grows into a dog and not a cat because it has been given that specific form. The defining characteristics of the dog are caused by the form and not just the material or efficient causes. It is the form, not the process, which causes the organism to take its particular shape. This belief is in contrast to Empedocles’, who held that the process of growth determined an organism’s features. For example, Empedocles believed that the backbone is twisted and broken on account of the small space in the womb (P.A. 1.1 640a 20-23). He also thought that organisms shed their teeth because the first set of teeth accidentally grow too early and could not last (G.A. 5.8 788b 11-12). Aristotle believed that the process is determined by what the thing is (G.A. 778b 1-10). Dante poetically expressed this truth, saying, “All things become what they are in their being”42. Aristotle claimed that teeth are shed for a purpose. Teeth are blunted and need to be replaced in order to function properly (G.A. 5.8 789a 9-11). The backbone is broken not due to an accidental aspect of the process of an organism’s growth in the womb, but because a flexible backbone is a feature of what the organism is as determined by its form. In its role as that towards which the change is aimed, the form serves as the final cause. For this reason the formal and final cause are said to be the same. Aristotle says of the two, “Really these first two should be taken as being almost one and the same” (G.A. 1 715a4-9). There is some truth in the thought of these predecessors. Insofar as simple necessity does determine some aspects of the process (P.A. 639b 26)43, an explanation of the cause of the process should account for this fact. The bricks are flat on their sides and so they are stacked on their sides. The mortar is malleable so it is put in the crevices where it can dry and harden of necessity. These steps, caused by the nature of the material, caused the process of the wall’s production to take a certain shape. But because the wall serves a purpose the necessity which is found in the nature of the matter does not afford a full explanation. The 42 Paradiso xx.78. “If a house, or any other End, is to be realized....one thing must first be formed, and set in motion, and then another thing,” (639b 27). 43 Elemental Teleology 25 construction of a wall therefore manifests both simple and hypothetical necessity44. It must be made of brick if it is to serve its purpose (hypothetical), and the construction must take place in a certain manner because the bricks are of a certain nature (simple)45. The important distinction must be made that though the bricks do necessitate that the process be a certain way (it must begin with a base being built before the top), this does not mean that the wall is constructed due to the nature of bricks: Whereas, though the wall does not come to be without these, it is not due to these, except as its material cause: it comes to be for the sake of sheltering and guarding things. Similarly in all other things which involve production for an end; the product cannot come to be without things which have a necessary nature, but it is not due to these (except as its material); it comes to be for an end. (Phys. 200a 5-10) When something has a final cause its production will involve simple necessity due to the nature of the materials being used, but such necessity is ‘subsumed’ by hypothetical necessity, i.e. the bricks are only present because the end is a wall46. 6, Does Elemental Locomotion Have a Final Cause? It has been shown that simple necessity is involved in the movements of the elements. It remains to be shown how hypothetical necessity might be present as well. This turns on the question of whether or not such movements have a final cause. Something is hypothetically necessary if there is a goal to be achieved (P.A. 642a 35). If a process is governed by hypothetical necessity it is due to there being a goal which directs the process. This goal must be just that, a goal and not a haphazard result of a process. John Cooper explains this with an illustration: But (for good reasons) Aristotle does not speak of hypothetical necessity except where the outcome is also a goal: it may be true enough that my window would not have broken when it did if there had not been a heavy wind blowing, but the wind did not blow by (hypothetical) necessity. That is because the window’s breaking was no natural (or other) goal: where something is being pursued as a goal there is some reason to think it will come about, and this 44 This point can also be applied to animals and their parts. Just as the wall is built if the roof is to be supported, so an organ is formed if the animal is to survive. John Cooper defines hypothetical necessity as applied to living things: Summarily stated, an organ or feature of a living thing is and is formed by hypothetical necessity if, given the essence of the thing (specified in terms of capacities and functions) and given the natures of the materials available to constitute it, the organ or feature in question is a necessary means to the creature’s constitution (‘Hypothetical Necessity’, 154). 45 Aristotle recognizes both simple and hypothetical necessity as present in many natural things and events: respiration (P.A. 642a32- b4), hair growth (P.A. 658b 2-7), deer shedding their antlers (P.A. 663b 12-14). 46 David Sedley remarks on the relation between simple and hypothetical necessity, “Natural purpose involves conditional necessity in a way which closely mirrors intelligent purpose. He therefore has much the same reasons as Plato did to treat conditional necessity not simply as coexisting in some kind of equal partnership with simple necessity, but as subsuming it,” (‘Creationism and Its Critics in Antiquity’, p. 183). Elemental Teleology 26 gives point to saying about the conditions necessary for the outcome in these cases, but not the others, that they come about by necessity. 47 We have discussed how the movements of the elements are natural. The question now becomes whether or not such movements are goal directed. The answer seems to be clearly stated in De Caelo 1.8, “If then the bodies have a natural movement, the movement of the particular instances of each form must necessarily have for goal a place numerically one, i.e. a particular centre or a particular extremity,” (276b 30-34). This fact may have been implied by the above discussion which referred to each element having a proper place of rest. Earth moves towards the centre of the world because that is its goal (De Caelo 296b 14). That goal is to actualize its potentiality for being what it is, for its form involves being in its proper place. In De Caelo 4.2 Aristotle says that, “…the movement of each body to its own place is motion towards its own form,” (310a 34). It was also pointed out that since these elemental motions are natural they occur regularly. Earth will always move down in the absence of interference (Phys. 252a 17). Considering then that the elements always move towards their goals, such movement may accurately be explained in terms of a final cause. “Again, whenever there is plainly some final end, to which a motion tends should nothing stand in the way, we always say that such final end is the aim or purpose of the motion,” (P.A. 641b 2426). Aristotle also refers to the elements as having a function: From what has been said it is clear that the difference of the elements does not depend upon their shape. Now their most important differences are those of property, function, and power; for every natural body has, we maintain, its own functions, properties, and powers. (De Caelo 307b 18-21) It was explained previously that when a thing which has a function which is natural, the function serves as its final cause. Thus when earth falls it is fulfilling its function, for an element’s function is its movement (De Caelo 298a 34). The third concept fundamental to anything with a final cause was ‘value’. It may be wondered how the movement of an element is in any sense good. In Physics 8.1 Aristotle proves that there has always been and will always be movement. Motion causes things to come-to-be and pass-away, which is a process which occurs continuously (G.C. 336a 24-26). The dual effect of generation and destruction is consequent of the sun’s ‘motion along the inclined circle’ (G.C. 336a 34). Its approach brings life, its departure brings death. This eternal cycle takes place because Nature seeks to produce life rather than destroy things: Nature always strives after ‘the better’. Now ‘being’ (we have explained elsewhere the exact variety of meanings we recognize in this term) is better than ‘not-being’: but not all things can possess ‘being’, since they are too far removed from the ‘originative source’. God therefore adopted the remaining alternative, and fulfilled the perfection of the universe by making 47 1985, p. 164, n. 2. Elemental Teleology 27 coming-to-be uninterrupted: for the greatest possible coherence would thus be secured to existence, because that ‘coming-to-be should itself come-to-be perpetually’ is the closest approximation to eternal being. (G.C. 336b 25-33). The movements of the elements individually are towards their places of rest. However, they also participate in a sort of circular motion when they mutate into one another. In this way they ‘imitate circular motion’48: That, too, is why all the other things….imitate circular motion. For when Water is transformed into Air, Air into Fire, and the Fire back into Water, we say the coming-to-be ‘has completed the circle’, because it reverts again to the beginning. Hence it is by imitating circular motion that rectilinear motion too is continuous. (G.C. 337 1-7) The value involved in this motion is simply that the elements continue to exist due to their involvement in an eternal cycle. Just as species continue their existence in kind by taking part in a cycle of birth and death, so the elements remain existent due to their cyclical movement49. Johnson remarks on this ‘value’, saying, “In this case, it amounts to an extremely attenuated benefit: a kind of immortality sufficient for the axiological maxim, that it is better to exist than not”50. In the Phaedo Socrates expresses a similar recognition that the study of the process of generation and destruction is also a study of value and what is best for a thing51. The investigation thus far has examined what it means for something to have a final cause as well as where such a cause exists in the Aristotelian cosmos. With regard to animate substances such causation is clearly present. In order to determine if the final cause is also present among elemental movements an analysis has been provided concerning change in general and changes of the elements specifically. This analysis showed that the movements of the elements can indeed be considered to have a final cause. The textual evidence for an ‘elemental teleology’ has been shown sufficiently strong to claim that Aristotle did view their movements as finally caused. This position is summarized by Monte Johnson: The four terrestrial elements (earth, water, air, and fire) are teleologically explicable because their motion can be completed when they arrive at their natural place in the cosmos, and because through cyclical transmutation they resemble the circular motions of the heavenly bodies. 52 This view of elemental movements will now be applied in an interpretation of a particular text in Aristotle’s Physics. For an analysis of Aristotle’s non-metaphysical use of the word ‘imitation’ see Johnson 2005, p. 147148. 49 The parallel argument with regard to animate beings and their participation in the cycle of reproduction is made in G.A. 731b 20-732a 1, and De Anima 415a 23-142b 21. 50 2005, p. 147. 51 “So if anyone wishes to find the cause of the generation or destruction or existence of a particular thing, he must find out what sort of existence, or passive state of any kind, or activity is best for it,” (97c). 52 2005, p.8. 48 Elemental Teleology 28 Chapter II – An Interpretation of The Rainfall Example in Physics 2.8 7. The Difficulty in Physics 2.8 In Physics 2.8 Aristotle wrestles with a materialist account of nature. According to the materialists, all things and events in nature exist due to the nature of the matter (Phys. 198b 16-30) (this will be further explained below). The opening of Physics 2.8 puts forward the materialist viewpoint: Why not say, it is asked, that Nature acts as Zeus drops the rain, not to make the corn grow, but of necessity (for the rising vapour must needs be condensed into water by the cold, and must then descend and incidentally, when this happens, the corn grows), just as, when a man loses his corn on the threshing-floor, it did not rain on purpose to destroy the crop, but the result was merely incidental to the raining? So why should it not be the same with natural organs like teeth? Why should it not be a coincidence that the front teeth come up with an edge, suited to dividing the food, and the back ones flat and good for grinding it, without there being any design in the matter? And so with all other organs that seem to embody a purpose. In cases where a coincidence brought about such a combination as might have been arranged on purpose, the creatures, it is urged, having been suitably formed by the operation of chance, survived; otherwise they perished, and still perish, as Empedocles says of his ‘man-faced oxen.’ (198b1 17-33) The remainder of this paper will consist of an analysis of the materialist challenge and Aristotle’s response to that viewpoint. Special attention will be given to the example of rainfall. The rainfall example is important because it is a rare occasion in which Aristotle discusses in a teleological context an event which involves only the terrestrial elements53. There are different possible interpretations concerning this text and I will argue that Aristotle’s responses to the general materialist viewpoint do not apply to their account of rainfall. I have argued that Aristotle viewed the terrestrial elements as moving for the sake of reaching their place of rest. This being the case, it would be inconsistent if Aristotle fully accepted an explanation of rainfall (water’s movement downward) as caused by its matter alone. So what reason is there for interpreting Aristotle as accepting the materialists’ account of rainfall? I propose that Aristotle viewed rainfall as having the final cause of reaching its place of rest and not crop growth. There are three reasons why such an interpretation is possible. First, Aristotle does not reject the materialist account in toto. Not only does he recognize the explanatory significance of simple necessity but considers it the scientist’s duty to include such necessity in a full causal account. A good example of this is in P.A. 1.1 where he examines the causes of respiration: 53 John Cooper claims this is the only occasion (‘Aristotle on Natural Teleology’, p. 125.) Elemental Teleology 29 Here is an example of the method of exposition. We point out that although Respiration takes place for such and such a purpose, any one stage of the process follows upon the others by necessity…..It is necessary that the hot substance should go out and come in again as it offers resistance, and that the air should flow in – that is obviously necessary…..This example shows how the method works and also illustrates the sort of things whose causes we have to discover. (642a 29- b 4) When Aristotle disagrees with the materialists he is disagreeing with their insistence that simple necessity alone can account for processes which have a final cause. Aristotle says that both causes must be included in an explanation (Phys. 200a 31-b10). Insofar as the movements of the elements involve simple necessity (they move due to the nature of their matter, which can not be other than it is and is thus necessary), the materialist account is accurate54. Aristotle disagrees with their claim that there is no final cause in nature55. If the initial difficulty is broken into parts there are three claims that can be distinguished, “A difficulty presents itself: (A) why should not nature work, not for the sake of something, nor because it is better so, (B) but just as the sky rains, not in order to make the corn grow, (C) but of necessity?” (198b 17-20). The general thesis of the materialists is expressed in (A), the idea being that there is no final cause in nature. The second part, (B), is claiming that corn is not the final cause of crop growth. And part (C) is claiming that rain falls of necessity. It has been shown already that for Aristotle the elements do move of simple necessity (An. Post. 95a 2). He has reason then to accept (C). However, we know that he rejects (A) and therefore would not accept (C) without qualifying it so that hypothetical necessity is present along with simple necessity. But his rejection of (A) does not imply his rejection of (B). This is because (B) is not claiming that the rain does not fall for the sake of anything, but not for the sake of the crops. It is possible that Aristotle accepts (B), that rain does not fall for the sake of the crops. The second reason why it is possible to interpret Aristotle as agreeing with the materialists is the fact that crop growth is unnecessary in explaining the cause of rainfall. If we interpret the rainfall example as involving only an ‘elemental teleology’ then there is no need for Aristotle to propose any further final cause than the element’s proper place of rest. An explanation of the cause of rainfall is adequate so long as it contains reference to a final cause. Viewing the event in terms of ‘elemental teleology’ is sufficient to provide such an explanation. The basic elemental teleology will allow Aristotle to accept that rainfall is 54 David Sedley, who argues that rain does indeed fall for the sake of crops, admits that Aristotle would not disagree with this aspect of the materialist viewpoint. “I think it has to be admitted that the actual mechanics of the elemental change described are Aristotelian: ‘…what goes up must get cold, and what has got cold becomes water and comes down.’,” (1991, p.182). 55 The materialists did recognize the existence of a final cause in theory. However, in practice they neglected it to such an extent so as to make it irrelevant. Aristotle said that if they even mention the cause, “it is only to touch on it, and then goodbye to it,” (Phys. 198b 16). Elemental Teleology 30 teleological while also accepting that it includes simple necessity and does not happen for the sake of crop growth. The final cause of reaching its proper place fulfils the criteria for serving as a final cause and makes an additional final cause superfluous. It was noted above that a final cause can be viewed as both a beneficiary and a goal (Meta. 1072b 1-3). With regard to the elements it has been argued that the final cause is reaching their place of rest. The aim of the movement, therefore, is an element’s proper place. The beneficiary is the element itself, for the involvement in the cycle of transmutation is an imitation of perfect circular motion (G.C. 337a 5). This ‘immortality’ of sorts allows the elements to exist, and the value in that is simply that being is better than not-being (G.C. 336b 29-30). Therefore the elements, not crops or any other natural thing, are the beneficiaries of their own movement. Crops do benefit from rainfall, but that does not mean that rain falls for the sake of crops. A third reason for interpreting Aristotle as agreeing with the materialists’ account is the fact that the final cause of elemental movement is extremely obscure. For that reason any claim of a specific final cause beyond reaching its natural resting place would require a thorough and extensive justification. This is no where present in Aristotle’s responding arguments. In Meteorologica 4.12 Aristotle says that the final cause is more recognizable in some things than others. The distinction between final and material cause is most clear among animals and their parts, less clear with regard to flesh and bone, and even less so among the elements (389b 30- 390a 35). “For the final cause is least obvious where matter predominates” (390a 6). He speaks of a scale with two extremes, those things which have a final cause which is obvious at one end, and those things which have an obscure final cause at the other. The low end of that scale is ‘simply matter’ (390a 7), the high end would likely be animals. He says that a thing’s final cause is identifiable with clarity relative to where on that spectrum a thing lies. The material elements could be assumed to be just one remove from ‘simple matter’. The obscurity of purpose within elemental motion is likely the reason that Aristotle largely focused on animate beings in his discussions of teleology. Allan Gotthelf recognized this fact, saying, “In almost every passage in which Aristotle introduces, discusses, or argues for the existence of final causality, his attention is focused on the generation and development of a living organism,”56.There is reason then to consider the final cause of elemental motion, though definitely present, as less obvious than any other natural substance. In light of this fact it seems unwarranted to claim that the elements have a clearly identifiable final cause other than the most ‘elementary’ final cause which has been established. Considering that a) Aristotle accepts elemental teleology, and b) he claims that 56 ‘Aristotle’s Conception of Final Causality’, p. 207. Elemental Teleology 31 the final cause of elemental movements is more difficult to identify than any complex substance, what reason is there for asserting that Aristotle also believed crop growth to be a final cause of rain? Surely such a precise teleological account involving the substance in which the final cause is most obscure would merit an extensive explanation and justification. Those who say that Aristotle did believe crop growth to be the final cause are under the onus of explaining the absence of such justification. For these reasons I think it is acceptable to interpret Aristotle as accepting the materialist claim that crop growth is not the final cause of the rain. 8. The Rainfall Example Having explained why such an interpretation is possible, it remains to be shown why such an interpretation is preferable to an alternative. Commentators are divided concerning how to interpret Aristotle’s position concerning rainfall. David Sedley57, and David Furley58 argue that he believed that crop growth was the final cause, while Lindsay Judson59 and W. Charleton60 argue against this. The relevant section of the difficulty is the following text: Why not say, it is asked, that Nature acts as Zeus drops the rain, not to make the corn grow, but of necessity (for the rising vapour must needs be condensed into water by the cold, and must then descend and incidentally, when this happens, the corn grows), just as, when a man loses his corn on the threshing-floor, it did not rain on purpose to destroy the crop, but the result was merely incidental to the raining? (198b 17-23) Aristotle responds: Yet it is impossible that this be the true view, for teeth and all other natural things either invariably or normally come about in a given way; but of not one of the results of chance or spontaneity is this true. We do not ascribe to chance or mere coincidence the frequency of rain in winter, but frequent rain in summer we do; nor heat in the dog-days, but only if we have it in winter. If then, it is agreed that things are either the result of coincidence or for an end, and these cannot be the result of coincidence or spontaneity, it follows that they must be for an end. (198b 33-199a 5) A brief note should be made with regard to evidence used by some commentators in support of a teleological reading of rain with respect to crop growth. Both Furley61 and Sedley62 make use the idiom ‘Zeus drops the rain,’ to support their claim that the rainfall example is part of the materialist account and for that reason should be considered antithetical to Aristotle’s own beliefs. Furley points out that the phrase, “Zeus drops the rain” would have 57 1991, pp. 181-187. ‘The Rainfall Example in Physics II.8’, pp. 115 ff. 59 ‘Aristotelian Teleology,’ pp. 344 ff. 60 Aristotle’s Physics Books I and II, p. 121. 61 1989, p. 116. 62 1991, p.185. 58 Elemental Teleology 32 been a common phrase used by the phusiologoi63 by which they mocked the ignorant accounts of natural events which resort to superstition and teleology64. My interpretation does not rely on separating the rainfall example from the general materialist position. Therefore Furley’s reading of the ‘Zeus makes rain’ phrase is compatible with my own. For what matters is not whether Aristotle is voicing his own view concerning rainfall, but whether or not his thought is consistent with the materialist account of rainfall. I happen to agree with Furley that the rainfall example should be read as part of a whole viewpoint which starts at 198b 17 and ends at 3365. I simply hold that this is part of their general viewpoint with which Aristotle would not disagree. What follows are three reasons why Aristotle’s views concerning rainfall should be interpreted as being limited to elemental teleology rather than the belief that crop growth is the final cause. Briefly these are as follows: (A) Upon scrutiny it can be shown that whether or not rain has a final cause is not the subject of debate in the text. There is no need then for Aristotle to commit himself to a specific final cause aside from the one affirmed in elemental teleology. (B) The argument concerning the opposite effects of rain at 198b 21-23 is a strong and valid argument which elicits no response from Aristotle. (C) The necessary conditions for a thing’s survival do not have causal force on that account. Therefore the fact that rain is necessary if the crops are to grow does not imply that crops are the final cause. In conclusion I will respond to an argument put forward by David Sedley66 concerning the emphasis Aristotle places on the seasonality of rainfall. A. Is the teleology of rainfall being questioned? Within the difficulty the arrangement of teeth is being questioned as to its teleological status, i.e. whether or not their purpose is causal. If the rain is serving as a parallel example as the arrangement of teeth, then one could argue that its causality is a matter of debate in the same way as teeth. However, the reference to rainfall in the difficulty may be different from that of teeth. If we consider the position and purpose of the rainfall example within both the difficulty and Aristotle’s response it can be argued that it is not being questioned by either party as to whether or not crop growth is the final cause. What is clearly drawn into question “Aristotle calls them collectively phusikoi, or phusiologoi, ‘physiologers,’ i.e., writers on ‘Nature,’ ‘natural’ scientists,” (A.L. Peck in the Introduction to G.A., p. xvi, n. b). 64 1989, p. 115. 65 This is in contrast to the view of Lindsay Judson, who claims that the materialist viewpoint begins after 198b 19, and does not include rainfall (2005, p. 346). Because the rainfall example is preceded by “A difficulty presents itself,” and because it is phrased as a question I consider it to be part of the materialists view point. 66 1991, p. 184. 63 Elemental Teleology 33 in the difficulty are two things: 1. The workings of nature - “Why should not nature work…” (17) 2. The parts in nature - “Why then should it not be the same with the parts in nature, e.g. that our teeth should come up of necessity” (23-24) The rainfall is not directly questioned as to whether or not it is teleological. I suggest that it is being used as an example of something which is clearly not oriented towards the growth of crops, and in relation to the crops rain fall is a non-teleological process par excellence. As such the materialists may be putting it forward as an assumed common ground between a teleological view and their own. It is upon this example that the materialists hope to extend the agreed upon explanation to other aspects of nature, namely, the parts of animals. They are saying, for example, that in the same way rain is related to crop growth (one is not the final cause of the other), so parts of animals are related to the whole organism. If rainfall is used by the materialists as an assumed common ground then the teleological status of the event has not been questioned. Therefore we do not need to interpret Aristotle’s reference to rainfall in his response as addressing its teleological status. To understand whether or not Aristotle does address the final causation of rain it is necessary to look again at the role which rain plays in the difficulty. It is clear that the materialists are claiming that rain does not fall for the sake of the crops. The example serves as an event in nature which is a paradigm of a naturally necessitated process. In that respect it is serving as a sort of measuring stick, against which other things in nature might be compared. To the extent that something in nature resembles the relationship between rain and crop growth, to that extent purpose is absent in the thing or event. Support for this interpretation is in the fact that Aristotle’s response uses rainfall in the same way as the materialists. He uses it as a measuring stick for identifying chance events. The more consistent something is (like rain), the less likely that it is a chance event. If Aristotle were attempting to make the point that rain itself is teleological then why would he choose an event which can be divided according to seasons? The result being that winter rain appears to happen for the sake of something while summer rain is mere chance. I hold that he is simply using the same event in nature which the materialists used in order, like them, to put forward a premise upon which each party could agree. For the materialists that premise was that some processes in nature do not have a purpose. For Aristotle the premise concerns chance events: We identify chance events according to whether or not they occur invariably or for the most part. Rain serves to illustrate his point precisely because it can be divided according to season and exemplify one event which is regular (winter rain) and one which is sporadic (summer rain). Aristotle is using an agreed upon non-teleological event simply in order to get his opponents to agree to his ‘chance-premise’. He is inviting his opponents to recognize a distinction that we all make every time we complain about unpredictable weather, Elemental Teleology 34 be it a hot spell in early October, or steady rainfall in July (which is rare in Greece). David Furley considers the fact that Aristotle immediately follows the ‘all other natural things’ clause with a mention of rainfall as evidence that rain is an example of a natural thing67. Though I agree that rainfall is natural, I do not think Aristotle intended it to be included within the category in this context. My interpretation is more in line with Allan Gotthelf, who thought that the example was “quoted only to illustrate a generic point about chance: we do not call regular winter rainfall a matter of chance”68. The mention of rainfall is not being put forward as an example of a natural thing, but an example of an event which manifests the difference between chance and non-chance events due to frequency. B. The ‘Opposite Effects Argument’ For the sake of argument let us assume that rainfall is in fact being debated. Any assessment of the difficulty must accept that the debate revolves around whether or not rain has a purpose. The debate does not involve figuring out what that purpose is. The one possible final cause is stated in the difficulty and no alternative is offered in Aristotle’s response. Crop growth is the assumed final cause by each party, that being rejected by the materialists and affirmed by Aristotle (according to this reading). The challenge for this reading is how to account for the argument in the difficulty regarding spoiled grain. The concept of existing ‘for the sake of something’ seems to imply that it exists for the sake of something’s existence, not its destruction. Body parts exist for the sake of the animal’s thriving, not its destruction. The ‘Opposite Effects Argument’ might be formed in the following manner: 1. X is the final cause of Y when Y exists for the sake of X. 2. To exist for the sake of X implies that it does not exist for the sake of not-X69. 3. Y results in X and not-X (ceteris paribus). 4. Therefore Y does not exist for the sake of X. 5. Therefore X is not the final cause of Y. A thing or event in nature which is followed by contrary results cannot be said to exist for the sake of only one of those results. This argument is not countered by Aristotle in his responses in 2.8 and 2.9. I take this as further evidence that Aristotle himself did not view crop-growth as the final cause of rainfall. One might object to this argument on the grounds that grain left on the threshing floor is the result of a mistake. Aristotle argues that mistakes presuppose an end oriented process. For mistakes are recognized insofar as the end was not reached. (Phys. 2.8 199a 20-33). Be 67 1989, p. 118. Furley 1989, p.118 n. 4. 69 Not-X means ‘the absence of X’ 68 Elemental Teleology 35 that as it may, the mistake of leaving grain on the threshing floor was an agricultural mistake, not a natural mistake. It was not a failure on nature’s part when the grain was spoiled. Therefore the mistake only serves as evidence that crop growth is the final cause of agriculture, not rainfall. With regard to rain fall the process of the water cycle is completed whether or not man heeds the warning of thunder clouds. Even when the farmer manages to save all of his grain and reap a full harvest, the natural event of rain yet results in opposite results. The weeds which grow alongside the crops may be destructive to the crops, yet the growth of both plants is a result of the same rainfall. Furthermore, the contrary effects of rain may benefit different organisms in any case. Though detrimental to agriculture, perhaps other animals benefit from flooded grain. If that is the case, then why should one species of organism be singled out as the final cause? This exact scenario is painted by Nikos Kazantzakis in which the ants benefit from the flooded threshing floor: Working in groups of twos or threes, they were carrying away the wheat in their roomy mandibles, one grain at a time. They had stolen it from the plain, right out of the mouths of men, and were transporting it now to their anthill, all the while praising God the Great Ant, who, ever solicitous for his Chosen People the ants, sent floods to the plain at precisely the right moment, just when the wheat was stacked upon the threshing floors 70. Is food production for the ants then the final cause of rainfall? Considering that rain benefits myriad substances it is unclear why just one species should be singled out as the primary beneficiary. David Furley claims that the simple fact that the ‘opposite effects argument’ is present implies that the idea is not agreed upon by each party. For why would a mutually held premise require a supporting argument?71 I disagree with this for two reasons. First, the argument is concerning rainfall alone, not the parts of animals. Yet the rainfall example is part of the single materialist viewpoint. If, as I claim, Aristotle agrees with part of their view (concerning rain) and disagrees with another part, then that part with which he agrees should be put forward in a way which makes its truth convincing. If it were simply presented as an assertion rather than an argument, and if Aristotle were to then agree with it, his agreement would look like an unwarranted concession. Secondly, he does not respond to the argument. All of his responding arguments are targeted at the materialist challenge to teleology among animate natural substances. Though such an argumentum ex silentio is not convincing in itself, the conspicuous absence of a response to the Opposite Effects Argument might be considered evidence that he does not disagree with the materialist account of rainfall. 70 71 The Last Temptation, p. 132. 1989, p. 117. Elemental Teleology 36 C. Rainfall and Hypothetical Necessity It may be objected that natural necessity is not the only necessity involved in rain. For plants can not grow without water. Therefore if plants are to grow then rain must fall. Does this not suggest that rain is hypothetically necessary for crop growth? The problem with this objection is that the necessary conditions for an organism’s survival are not attributed with causal power on account of that fact. It is necessary for a human to have water, therefore rain could be said to be finally caused by man’s thirst. But this is not the case, for a condition necessary for a thing’s survival may be necessary in an un-hypothetical way72, such as the presence of water for living things. Furthermore, the presence of water does not have to take the form of rain. The crops may be irrigated and relatively unaffected by rain. If water is considered to fall for the sake of the crops on account of being a necessary condition for its growth, then we could also include all other aspects of the environment. The temperature could be affirmed to be warm on account of the crops, the altitude, the air purity, the richness of the soil, all these things would then exist for the sake of the plants. Lindsay Judson provides an illustration which relates to the idea that rain is hypothetically necessary for crop growth and therefore crops are the final cause of rain. He says, “Suppose that avalanches regularly cut off access to a certain Alpine valley, and that one of two constantly warring tribes regularly takes advantage of this to regroup in the safety of the valley,”73. In such a situation would we then say that the avalanche is hypothetically necessary for the safety of the tribe, and has that safety as its final cause? Rather we would explain the cause of the avalanche with regard to the nature of the matter (i.e. snow). The final cause would be isolated to the snow’s movement towards its proper place. Without limiting Aristotle’s teleology to the specific nature involved one is on a slippery slope towards a cosmic teleology which sees all things working together for the good of an ultimate beneficiary. Such a position is held by prominent commentators (i.e. David Sedley), but it is not the position of this paper. For the crop’s coming-to-be and growth as a natural substance can be fully explained in terms of its own matter and form. The necessary and sufficient account of its coming-to-be will make reference to its intrinsic cause rather than extrinsic. Lindsay Judson comments on this point: Neither the rain which falls nor the meteorological processes which cause it are primarily responsible for the presence of the seeds or young plants (though of course the fact that rain regularly falls in this particular place may be partly responsible), and the good outcome is not a good for – does not constitute or bestow on – the rain, clouds, etc.74 John Cooper remarks on this point, “If for example it is part of human nature to have the capacity to see then having eyes of some sort is necessary to a human being as part of his nature (see G.A. v 778b16-17), and is not a mere hypothetical necessity,” (1985, p. 152). 73 2005, p. 346. 74 2005, p. 348. 72 Elemental Teleology 37 Rain is extrinsic to crops and therefore need not be included in an adequate explanation of why crops grow. Monte Johnson makes a similar point when discussing the prospect of one animal existing for the sake of another animal, as food for example. Rather than saying that the pig exists for man’s nourishment, any benefit gained by man should be viewed as incidental to the causation of the pig. With regard to this idea he says, “But these ends are not explanatory of the parts or motions (i.e. behaviours) of the animals in question. They are much like the incidental benefits of rainfall in that this kind of benefit has no role to play in the scientific explanation of the natural substance”75. Rainfall would not be included in a scientific explanation of corn because it is an incidental benefit to that natural substance. D. The Seasonality of Rain David Sedley thinks that Aristotle highlights the difference between winter and summer rainfall in his response in order to show that winter rain fall is purposive while summer rainfall is not76. This is inconsistent with my interpretation. As was explained above, I believe he is highlighting the seasonality of rain in order to put forward the ‘chancepremise’ upon which his opponents would likely agree, i.e. the fact that we call irregular events chance and regular ones natural. If we view rainfall in the way I have proposed, as simply an element’s return to its natural place, then the seasonality of the event does not come to bear on whether or not it is finally caused. Its proper place remains the same as does water’s motion towards it. The strength of Sedley’s argument is in the fact that Aristotle goes on to use the seasonality distinction in order to also distinguish between coincidental events as opposed to teleological events. A defence against this objection would have to show that rain, though it exemplifies the difference between chance and purposive events, is not itself considered by Aristotle to be sometimes purposive (in the winter months) and sometimes nonpurposive (in the summer months). Three reasons against Sedley’s view are offered below. If Judson’s avalanche example is convincing, then it might support my reading against the seasonality objection. Perhaps the avalanches were more common occurrences in winter rather than summer. And perhaps the warring tribes made use of the avalanche every single time it happened. If the final cause of the avalanche was never considered to be the protection of the villagers, then the seasonality and frequency of the event does not change that fact. Now let this idea be extended to rainfall. If crop growth was never considered to be the final cause of crops to begin with, the seasonality distinction would not change that fact. Robert Wardy voices a similar idea in response to Sedley’s seasonality argument: To infer that summer showers are accidental and so not for a purpose, Sedley must be relying on Aristotle’s explanation “for it does not seem to rain frequently in winter from luck 75 76 2005, p.9. 1991, p. 184. Elemental Teleology 38 or coincidence, but rather if it rains in August” (198b 36-199a 2). His fallacy results from illicit promotion of “always or for the most part” from a sufficient condition to a necessary condition for natural purpose.77 Secondly, if Aristotle is using the seasonality distinction to say that winter rain falls for the sake of the crops while summer rain has no final cause, then the example of summer heat should be interpreted in the same way. For Aristotle uses both rain and heat as examples of seasonal events. Heat is mentioned immediately after rain but no alternate final cause is provided. It would seem, then, that crop growth is the assumed final cause of each. This, however, is nowhere argued for or even hinted at in the discussion. Crops may indeed benefit from summer heat, but claiming that crops are the final cause of the temperature in summer is a rather bold claim. Thirdly, according to Sedley the seasonality of rain benefits not only crop growth, but ultimately man. Sedley says, “In Attica, winter rain was the only important rain for farmers….If Aristotle is writing at Athens, he is describing the apparently anthropocentric functioning of the weather as it affects local agriculture, with its two staples, corn and olives,”78. I think the ‘elemental teleology’ put forward in this paper is preferable to such an anthropocentric reading due to its conservative claims. Aristotle’s belief in the obscurity of final causes behind elemental motion seems to favour such a conservative approach rather than proposing not just a clear final cause extrinsic to the elements, but a final cause (man) which is nowhere mentioned in the difficulty. For these reasons perhaps Sedley’s seasonality argument does not invalidate my interpretation. Conclusion This paper has concerned itself primarily with Aristotle’s final cause in its relation to the movements of the four terrestrial elements. Elemental teleology proposes that the elements move for the sake of reaching their place of rest. By establishing that such a viewpoint is present in Aristotle I was able to approach the text of Physics 2.8 using elemental teleology as the lens through which to interpret Aristotle’s own position. It was argued that Aristotle rejected the idea that rain falls for the sake of crop growth. This position was claimed to be possible for three reasons: (1) Aristotle did not disagree with the materialist position completely, (2) elemental teleology provides Aristotle with a means of explaining rain fall as purposive without extending the final cause beyond reaching its place of rest, and (3) the obscurity of the purpose behind elemental motion favours a conservative interpretation concerning the final cause of rain. Three reasons were then given why my interpretation is not only possible but preferable: (1) the teleological status of rainfall is not a matter of debate in 77 1993, p.21. 78 1991, p. 186. Elemental Teleology 39 either the difficulty or Aristotle’s response, (2) the ‘Opposite Effects Argument’ is a valid reason for both parties to reject crop growth as a final cause, and (3) the necessary conditions of crop growth do not imply that such conditions are finally caused by crop growth. Finally, a response to David Sedley’s seasonality argument was put forward with three reasons against adopting his reading. With this interpretation I have been able to avoid the conclusion that rain falls for the sake of crops without giving up a global teleology. By approaching the text from the vantage point of an elemental teleology it was shown that Aristotle could accept the materialist account of rain without also accepting their denial of a final cause in nature. Elemental Teleology 40 Works Cited Alighieri, Dante 2007: Paradiso. New York: Doubleday. Aristotle 1979: Generation of Animals. ed. T.E. Page, E. Capps, W.H.D. Rouse, L.A. Post and E.H. Warmington. London: William Heinemann Ltd. Aristotle 1968: Parts of Animals. ed. T.E. Page, E. Capps, and W.H.D. Rouse. London: William Heinemann Ltd. Aristotle 1961: Eudemian Ethics. ed. T.E. Page, E. Capps, W.H.D. Rouse, L.A. Post and E.H. Warmington. London: William Heinemann Ltd. Aristotle 1952: Meteorologica. ed. T.E. Page, E. Capps, W.H.D. Rouse, L.A. Post and E.H. Warmington. London: William Heinemann Ltd. Aristotle 1941: Posterior Analytics, in The Basic Works of Aristotle, ed. Richard McKeon, New York: Random House. Aristotle 1941: Physics, in The Basic Works of Aristotle, ed. Richard McKeon, New York: Random House. Aristotle 1941: De Caelo, in The Basic Works of Aristotle, ed. Richard McKeon, New York: Random House. Aristotle 1941: On Generation and Corruption, in The Basic Works of Aristotle, ed. Richard McKeon, New York: Random House. Aristotle 1941: On the Soul, in The Basic Works of Aristotle, ed. Richard McKeon, New York: Random House. Aristotle 1941: On the Parts of Animals, in The Basic Works of Aristotle, ed. Richard McKeon, New York: Random House. Aristotle 1941: Metaphysics, in The Basic Works of Aristotle, ed. Richard McKeon, New York: Random House. Aristotle 1929: Physics. ed. T.E. Page, E. Capps, and W.H.D. Rouse. London: William Heinemann Ltd. Balme, D.M. 1987: ‘Teleology and Necessity’, in Philosophical Issues in Aristotle’s Biology, ed. Allan Gotthelf and James Lennox, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press pp. 275-286. Bostock, David 2006: Space, Time, Matter, and Form. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Bostock, David 1994: Aristotle Metaphysics Books Z and H. ed. J.L Ackrill and Lindsay Elemental Teleology 41 Judson, Oxford: Clarendon Press. Bradie, Michael and Fred D. Miller Jr. 1999: ‘Teleology and Natural Necessity in Aristotle’, In Aristotle Critical Assessments Volume II: Physics, Cosmology and Biology, ed. Lloyd P. Gerson, London: Routledge, pp. 75-89. Broadie, Sarah 1990: ‘Nature and Craft in Aristotelian Teleology’, Biologie, Logique et Metaphysique Chez Aristotle: 389-403. Charles, David 1991: ‘Teleological Causation in the Physics’, in Aristotle’s Physics A Collection of Essays, ed. Lindsay Judson, Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 101-128. Charlton, W. 1970: Aristotle’s Physics Books I and II. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Cohen, Sheldon M. 1999: ‘Aristotle on Elemental Motion’, in Aristotle Critical Assessments Volume II: Physics, Cosmology and Biology, ed. Lloyd P. Gerson, London: Routledge, pp. 65-74. Cooper, John M. 2006: ‘Aristotle on Natural Teleology’, in Language and Logos: Studies in Ancient Greek Philosophy, ed. Malcolm Schofield and Martha Nussbaum, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 107-129. Cooper, John. M. 1987: ‘Hypothetical Necessity and Natural Teleology’, in Philosophical Issues in Aristotle’s Biology, ed. Allan Gotthelf and James Lennox, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 243-274. Cooper, John M. 1985: ‘Hypothetical Necessity’, in Aristotle on Nature and Living Things: Philosophical and Historical Studies. Bristol Classical Press, pp. 151-167. Freeland, Cynthia A. 1991: ‘Accidental Causes and Real Explanations’, in Aristotle’s Physics A Collection of Essays, ed. Lindsay Judson, Oxford: Clarendon Press., pp. 972. Freeland, Cynthia A. 1987: ‘Aristotle on Bodies, Matter, and Potentiality’, in Philosophical Issues in Aristotle’s Biology, ed. Edited by Allan Gotthelf and James Lennox, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 392-407. Friedman, Robert 1986: ‘Necessitarianism and Teleology in Aristotle’s Biology’, Biology and Philosophy 1: 355-365. Freudenthal, Gad 1995: Aristotle’s Theory of Material Substance. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Furley, David 1999: ‘What Kind of Cause is Aristotle’s Final Cause?’, in Rationality in Greek Thought, ed. Michael Frede and Gisela Striker, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 59-79. Furley, David 1989: ‘ The Rainfall Example in Physics II.8’, in Cosmic Problems : Essays on Greek and Roman Philosophy of Nature. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Gotthelf, Allan 1987: ‘Aristotle’s Conception of Final Causality’, in Philosophical Issues in Aristotle’s Biology, ed. Allan Gotthelf and James Lennox, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 204-242. Elemental Teleology 42 Hankinson, R.J. 1998: Cause and Explanation in Ancient Thought. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Johnson, Monte Ransome 2005: Aristotle on Teleology. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Judson, Lindsay 2005: ’Aristotelian Teleology’, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 29: 341-366. Judson, Lindsay 1991: ‘Chance and ‘Always or For the Most Part’ in Aristotle’, in Aristotle’s Physics A Collection of Essays, ed. Lindsay Judson, Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 73100. Kazantzakis, Nikos 1961: The Last Temptation. London: Faber and Faber. Lennox, James 2000: Aristotle’s Philosophy of Biology: Studies in the Origins of Life Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Lennox, James G. 1999: ‘Aristotle on Chance’, in Aristotle Critical Assessments Volume II: Physics, Cosmology and Biology, ed. Lloyd P. Gerson, London: Routledge, pp. 118126. Meyer, Susan Suave 1999: ’Aristotle, on Teleology on Reduction’, in Aristotle Critical Assessments Volume II: Physics, Cosmology and Biology, ed. Lloyd P. Gerson, London: Routledge, pp. 90-117. Plato 1988: Phaedo. New York: Prometheus Books. Sedley, David 2007: Creationism and Its Critics in Antiquity. Berkeley: University of California Press. Sedley, David 1991: ‘Is Aristotle’s Teleology Anthropocentric?’, Phronesis 36/2: 179-196. Sorabji, Richard 1980: Necessity, Cause and Blame. London: Duckworth. Wardy, Robert 1993: ’Aristotelian Rainfall or the Lore of Averages’, Phronesis 38: 18-30. Wieland, W. 1975: ’The Problem of Teleology’, in Articles on Aristotle, ed. Jonathan Barnes, Malcolm Schofield, and Richard Sorabji, London: Duckworth, pp. 141-160. Williams, C.J.F. 1982: Aristotle’s De Generation et Corruptione. Oxford: Oxford University Press.