CHAPTER TWO NARRATIVES A map of the world that does not include Utopia is not ever worth glancing at, for it leaves out the one country where humanity is always landing. - - - Oscar Wilde1 Individual and social identities are created, transmitted, revised and undermined through narratives and practices. Narratives tell people who they are, what they should aspire to become and how they should relate to others. They are invariably linear, as they are structured around a plot line that imposes a progressive order on events, selecting and emphasizing those that can be made supportive or consistent with it. Frank Kermode suggests that to make sense of the world we "need to experience that concordance of beginning, middle and end which is the essence of our explanatory fictions."2 Practice is repetitive behavior that is widely shared and culturally regulated. It can be sub-divided, as Montesquieu famously did, into manners [manières], norms [moeurs] and laws [lois].3 Narratives and practices are often designed to uphold existing social, religious, political and economic orders. Practices serve these ends when they become habitual.4 Charles Taylor maintains that practice not only fulfills rules, but gives them concrete shape in context. Practice is “a continual ‘interpretation’ and reinterpretation of what the rule really means.”5 Change in actual or fictionalized practice can threaten existing orders so institutions have a strong interest in regulating them, just as their opponents do in changing them to reflect reformist or revolutionary ends.6 The same is true of narratives. In early modern Europe, the Catholic Church, which had propagated Latin Vulgate translation of the Old and New Testaments, voiced strident opposition to vernacular translations. The first printed English language translation, John Tyndale's 1525 , was banned in England and English clerics visiting the continent bought and burned all the copies they could find.7 Narratives and practices interact in complex and still poorly understood ways. Narratives often describe or critique existing practices. They introduce and encourage new practices, generate support for them or attempt to destabilize existing ones. Practices sometimes reinforce existing narratives, as does the reading of scripture in churches and synagogues. New practices encourage new narratives, even new narrative forms. The boundaries between text and practice are blurred as there is considerable overlap. Postmodern literary theory has further muddied the waters by categorizing as texts what formerly would have been described as practices.8 Narrative has long been a vehicle for social analysis. In the late eighteenth century, David Hume insisted that history is functionally indistinguishable from novels and epic poetry because it is made meaningful by fictional emplotment; a mere recital of past events being nothing more than a chronicle.9 In the nineteenth century, William Dilthey, hoping to bridge the growing gap between what would become known as the humanities and social sciences, made the case for a sociology of biography.10 Social science nevertheless developed more in opposition to the humanities than in collaboration with it. Margaret Sommers aptly describes narrative as social science's “epistemological other.”11 It is an ideographic mode of representation that is discursive and generally atheoretical, in contradistinction to social science’s quest for theory based on quantitatively testable propositions. Beginning in the 1980s, researchers in psychology, legal theory, organizational theory, anthropology, medical sociology were nevertheless drawn to narrative because of what it revealed about the understandings people had of themselves and their social worlds.12 In recent years, comparative politics and 2 international relations have turned to narratives for much the same reason. This interest and the rise of constructivism as a paradigm, parallels and reflects widespread recognition of the importance of identity politics. As constructivism emphasizes the central importance of intersubjective understandings, it directs our attention to narratives and practices as locales where such understandings arise, spread and are challenged. Over the course of the millennia we have witnessed dramatic shifts in narratives and practices. At the macro level, these shifts raise problems about the continuity of cultures, just as the reworking of ife stroies does about the continuity of individuals. At the analytical level, this evolution poses conceptual challenges. We must exercise great care about using one culture’s categories and understandings to study identity construction and maintenance in other eras and cultures. Variations in how people understand, construct and theorize identity -- or do not theorize it all -- are nevertheless a valuable analytical resource. They allow us to study the present in comparative perspective and thereby develop a more comprehensive understanding of identity narratives and practices and the conditions that shape them. Humanists describe different kinds of narratives, study how they work and the projects for which they are utilized.13 My interests overlap with theirs in part. I want to know why certain kinds of narratives are used to propagate or probe identities, but also what they have to tell us about the process by which people and institutions form, reconfigure and re-order their identifications. Narratives are absolutely critical to the sense of selfhood felt by individuals and attributed to social collectivities. Paul Ricoeur maintains that people come to know themselves only indirectly by means of cultural signs, most notably narratives of everyday life. “Narrative mediation underlines this remarkable characteristic of self-knowledge.”14 We may be hard-wired 3 to think this way as experiments show that people will construct narratives to impose order on unconnected events and images.15 We not only tell stories about ourselves but about others.16 This phenomenon is reciprocal and generates narratives and counter-narratives. Not infrequently, our narratives are influenced by others. We cannot understand the various ways Jews, the Irish, AfricanAmericans or women have come to define themselves without taking into account how others have stereotyped them.17 Identity is thus a kind of bricolage that builds on life experiences, cues from others and reflections on both.18 This is true for groups, institutions and countries, not only individuals. Constructivist scholarship indicates that “great powers” and “civilized states” are social categories, whose markers and boundaries have steadily evolved since their creation. The narratives that construct these identities help to shape how people think of their countries and how they should behave.19 Life narratives only rarely take the form of written autobiographies. The most prominent early example was St. Augustine’s, penned in the fourth century of the Common Era.20 Autobiography became a popular genre in the eighteenth century. More often, life narratives are piecemeal and inchoate. They take the form of internal dialogues and real or fictional conversations with others.21 In modern times, novels, plays and films have also served as vehicles to present life experiences and to construct identities. People often identify with their characters and sometimes even seek to emulate them. Romanticism and its core project of discovering and expressing oneself was effectively propagated by the best-selling novels of Rousseau and Goethe.22 Shared experiences and common understandings of them sustain communities as well as individuals.23 Seminal works on nationalism -- by Hans Kohn, Carleton J. H. Hayes and Karl W. 4 Deutsch -- maintain that a shared past, based on territory, language, religion, history, or some combination of them, is the foundation of nationality.24 Deutsch defines a people as “a community of complementary habits of communication.” Stylized representations of the past have the potential to create a “we feeling,” and hence a sense of community among those who internalize these narratives.25 At least as far back as Herodotus, students of community have recognized the largely mythical nature of such narratives. Fictional origins and historical events are retrospectively woven into master narratives to “invent” a people and provide them with a distinctive and uplifting past.26 In this chapter and the next, I examine two of the earliest and most successful master narratives: the Old Testament and Iliad. The former helped to create and sustain a strong sense of community among Jews and the latter among Greeks. Narratives that construct or propagate identities often do so self-consciously. This is true of many autobiographies and for the Iliad and the Old Testament. Augustine wrote his autobiography and Rousseau and Goethe their novels to advance religious, philosophical and cultural projects. Goethe was amazed at his success and horrified at the suicides that his novel prompted; “copy cat” suicides are generally described as the “Werther Effect.”27 The Old Testament and the Iliad were collaborative projects, transmitted initially by word of mouth and not written down until centuries later. Changes in their language, contents and style tell us something about the evolving nature of the projects they were used to advance. Personal life narratives are equally creative products, although we may be unaware of the extent to which we edit, reinterpret and even invent memories to support them. Collectively, narratives track the evolution and relative appeal of different kinds of selfidentification. This is rarely the goal of any single narrative, some academic studies aside, but an unintended system level effect of many individual narratives. Political theorists have studied 5 philosophical tracts and literature to fathom the emergence of individual identity.28 Historians have done the same with national movements and identities. International relations scholars have relied on a variety of texts to identify and analyze competing national narratives. Ted Hopf uses newspapers, official discourse, popular novels, film reviews, and memoirs to track the identity discourse in the late Soviet Union and first years of post-Cold War Russia. He discovered four distinctive narratives, each of which frames Russian relations with the West and “Near Abroad” differently and vies for supporters among the public and government officials.29 Stefano Guzzini analyzes the revival of geopolitical discourse as a response to post-Cold War identity crises in Russia, Eastern Europe and Turkey. In these countries, previously established national identities have been challenged from within and without. Geopolitics has been mobilized to circumscribe boundaries and provide justifications seemingly more acceptable to public opinion and third parties than narrow definitions of national interest.30 As these examples illustrate, narratives can be partisan or analytical about identity. The most common analytical narratives track the rise, fall, uses and consequences of particular identities. This approach was pioneered by Greek tragedy, whose characters are constructed as archetypes. They can be considered thought experiments as they create uni-dimensional, and hence unrealistic, characters to probe the individual and social consequences of their identities. Modern novels have characters with inner lives and distinctive personalities but many also explore, problematize or advocate specific identities. Cervantes’ Don Quixote, published between 1605 and 1615, and generally regarded as the pioneering modern novel, parodies chivalry and honor-based quests. By showing their absurdity, even madness, it seeks to undermine traditional aristocratic identities, anchored in honor codes. Early English novels, notably those of Richardson, Fielding and Steele, describe newly emerging roles and identities 6 that would come to be associated with the bourgeoisie. In chapter five, I make the case that the three operas on which Mozart and librettist Carlo Da Ponte collaborated critically examine ancien régime and the Enlightenment identities. Relatively few narratives probe the concept of identity itself. In the Introduction, I noted two such works: Thomas Hobbes’ Leviathan and Robert Musil’s, A Man Without Qualities. Bracketing the modern era, Hobbes and Musil make the case that identity is a purely social construct by peeling away the roles and practices into which people have been socialized. Underneath, both authors contend, there is nothing but raw appetites. Several of the texts I examine implicitly probe the concept of identity and a few do so explicitly. Most of the latter are science fiction novels. They raise the question of what it is to be human by problematizing existing makers and boundaries between humans and other species. My focus on identity directs my attention to three related kinds of narratives: golden ages, utopias and dystopias. They have been used to construct, propagate and analyze identity. They make their respective appearances in eras of change when new justifications for order were required and new hopes kindled about the possibility of transforming or even transcending traditional identities. In the West, the respective popularity of golden age, utopian and dystopic narratives is an excellent barometer of belief in progress and the relative appeal of religious versus secular foundations of order. I will nevertheless argue that many, if not most, utopias are anti-modern in orientation. Utopias are elite narratives and generally optimistic about the prospect of a better life in this world. Dystopias, another elite narrative, are quintessentially pessimistic. Golden ages are popular, pessimistic narratives as they trace the irreversible decline of the human race. The 7 Christian reading of the Garden of Eden nevertheless embeds a deeper optimism because it holds out the prospect of rebirth and life in heaven. Since the ancient Greeks, a major tradition of Western thought has regarded active participation in society as a precondition of human fulfillment. One of the common goals of utopias, from Plato to the present day, has been to design societies that successfully integrate people into society. Utopias foster harmony and happiness. Their critics maintain that their harmony is superficial and socially costly as utopias are achieved and maintained by repression from above and suppression from within. Critics read many utopias as dystopias, as I do in chapter four with The Magic Flute. Golden ages can also be read as dystopias, and for many of the same reasons. Chapter five, which examines the post-Enlightenment German reconstruction of ancient Greece as a golden age, offers such an interpretation. In the conclusion, I will argue that these opposed readings can be attributed to the strategies utopias employ to address the tensions between reflexive and social selves. These strategies in turn reflect different understandings of what it is to be human. Golden Ages, utopias and dystopias are only some of the narratives used to interrogate practices. Others include stories of creation, states of nature, social contracts, ideal type deductive systems and genealogies. They rely on a range of strategies to evoke a set of favorable responses from diverse readers. I have chosen golden ages, utopias and dystopias over other narrative forms for several reasons. Many of the texts that I examine (e.g., the Iliad, Aeneid, Magic Flute, Looking Backward, Left Behind) have had far wider audiences than political or philosophical tracts. Next to the Old Testament, the Iliad is arguably the most influential text of Western culture.31 These works have influenced popular as well as elite conceptions of self. 8 A common feature of golden age, utopian and dystopic narratives is their ability to distance us from the world we know by creating fictional ones in which, with a little imagination, we can situate ourselves. Sheldon Wolin notes the “impossibility of direct observation” of social alternatives and therefore the essential role of imagination as a “means for understanding a world [one’] can never know in an intimate way.”32 Golden ages, utopias and dystopias create and draw us into such worlds, emotionally and intellectually, and by doing so offer otherwise inaccessible vantage points on our worlds.33 Immersion in alternate worlds encourages us to reflect upon and question practices and identities in our society that we may have taken for granted. Reflection can arouse or focus desires for change. It can also strengthen our commitment to existing practices and identities when alternative worlds convince us that change is likely to impoverish us physically, emotionally or psychologically. Golden ages and utopias are instantiations of ideal worlds, and dystopias of their opposite. For most of human history, these worlds were important vehicles for advancing normative claims. Counterfactuals also serve this end, but in a narrower instrumental sense.34 One can always make the case for a better or worse outcome if another course of action had been followed. Better and worse ultimately depend on some notion of best and worst. Normative claims accordingly require ideal worlds. In Western culture, golden ages and utopias were created in part for this purpose. In the early modern era, they were joined by state of nature narratives and later, by the additional modes of argumentation. State of nature narratives are counterfactual extrapolations to get at phusis [nature] by stripping away nomos [convention]. They purport to describe human nature uncorrupted, or at least unshaped, by society, and use it as the template to construct social orders. The legitimacy of these orders and the principles on which they rest depend on their supposed fit with human 9 nature. From Hobbes on, state of nature narratives played a powerful role in the development of the liberal paradigm.35 Contemporary examples include Nozick’s explicit appeal to a state of nature and Rawls’ use of the original position as a conceptual analog.36 Following Rousseau, the state of nature is sometimes portrayed as capturing the original historical condition of humankind. More often, states of nature are thought experiments intended to highlight what their authors believe to be the most fundamental attributes of human nature. Hobbes arguably fits this model as does Rawls, who makes no claim that his original position could exist in practice. To get to the state of nature it is essential to do away with some features of the world in which one resides. As Hegel observed, philosophers cut away various human traits and related behaviors and what they leave behind and emphasize are subjective choices that reflect their cultural setting and ideology.37 States of nature are Rorschach Tests that tell us more about their authors than they do about the character of humankind. Three other modes of moral argumentation emerged in the modern era: Kantian deontology (and its Rawlsian variant), utilitarianism, and deliberative democracy or discourse ethics. Discourse ethics claims to be more concerned with process than with ends, at least in a direct way. Unlike the Kantian criterion of universalism, these normative conditions are, or are at least purported to be, far less determinative, and accordingly do not require an ideal world. Discourse ethics is reflexive, making rules themselves a subject to argument, and thereby hoping to encourage fairer and more open-ended dialogues. Discourse ethics nevertheless assumes egalitarian reciprocity and universal human respect, neither of which Seyla Benhabib contends, have enough substantive content to specify a singular ideal framework.38 The presuppositions of universal human respect and egalitarian reciprocity are themselves based on a prior, underlying 10 conception of the good, which, of necessity, rests on some idea of an ideal world. The “should," as always, requires some image of a better and attainable society. Although states of nature, and subsequently utilitarian frames, have dominated philosophical and political narratives, utopias endure. It is interesting to ask why some authors choose to use them in lieu of other formats to advance normative arguments. One reason may be their rhetorical potential and ability to reach wider audiences. In the 1960s, Aldous Huxley’s Island, an attempt to critique contemporary society by means of a utopia, attracted considerable attention among the well-educated general public.39 The same was true of B. F. Skinner’s Walden Two, which became something of a bible for many young people.40 Utopias also have a subterranean existence. Many scholarly narratives, discourse ethics, for example, smuggle them in without acknowledgment. This is also true of golden ages. Sociobiology’s unrealistic description of hunter-gatherer societies and, until quite recently, anthropology’s portrayal of Neolithic societies as largely peaceful "uncorrupted" worlds, are cases in point.41 The American anthropological community is overwhelmingly anti-war and evidence of a peaceful past offered some justification for the claim that humanity could and should return to its “natural” state of existence. GOLDEN AGES Arthur Lovejoy and George Boas, coauthors of the classic account of golden ages, consider them expressions of either “chronological” or “cultural primitivism.” The former describes an idyllic world that never was, while the latter rhapsodizes about earlier, simpler societies in which life is imagined to have been more tranquil and satisfying. Both discourses reflect discontent with contemporary life and tend to become prominent in eras when change 11 makes life more difficult for people.42 Some students of golden ages insist that “cultural primitivism” is the product of urbanization. Northrop Frye reads the story of Cain and Abel in a similar light; the murder of Abel, a shepherd, by Cain, a farmer, symbolizes the “blotting out of an idealized pastoral society by a more complex civilization.”43 Moses Finley suggests that the description of the Garden of Eden in Book Two of Genesis is an implicit critique of what are often considered the two principal evils of society: competition for women and for wealth.44 Conflict over women must hark back to the emergence of the species, but that over wealth, Finley insists, requires a prior division of labor and is accordingly associated with development and "progress." It seems fair to say that golden ages reflect a desire to escape from hierarchy, injustice and all that is understood to be confining and corrupting. Golden ages of all kinds typically do away with technology and often dispense with private property, laws, meat eating, money, armies and warfare. Order is maintained by individual self-control in response to “natural” human impulses. Such worlds are moral, but in a different sense from real worlds. Virtue, in the eyes of Romans and Christians alike, is the avoidance of temptation.45 "Primitive" peoples appear virtuous only because they have not been exposed to the many temptations of civilization. The emphasis on natural virtue may explain why golden ages are placed so far back in the past or so far away geographically if set in the present day. Greeks and Romans imagined distant lands populated by peoples who lived simple, stress-free lives. In the Iliad, Zeus turns away from the unremitting violence of the Trojan Plain to the far north and the land of the noble maremilking Albii, “the most decent men alive.”46 Pliny characterizes the land of the Hyperborians as a pastoral utopia; there are no seasons, seeds are sown and harvested on the same day and Hyperborians die only when they tire of life.47 Sir John Mandeville’s Blessed Isles, like the 12 mythical Atlantis, lie somewhere beyond the Pillars of Hercules and are inhabited by a godly and innocent people whose virtue offers a sharp contrast with the corruption of Europeans and their religions. In the age of discovery, Europeans continued to imagine paradises in uncharted seas, no doubt influencing Thomas More to place his Utopia in this setting Alternatively, like Rousseau and Gauguin, they glorified the lives and virtues of the peoples that European voyagers actually encountered. Golden ages are common to Judeo-Christian and Greek culture and in both cases appear to have roots in earlier Mesopotamian myths and texts. The Greek word for paradise [paradeisos] most likely derives from Median paidaeza, meaning “enclosure.” It can be broken down into pari, signifying “around” and daeza, meaning “wall.” In Persia, it was frequently used to describe enclosed gardens. Paidaeza is a loan word in Akkadian, Hebrew and Aramaic, and best known to us from the English word “paradise,” a synonym for the Hebrew gan Eden [Garden of Eden] in Genesis 2-3.48 Earlier Mesopotamian texts reveal no conception of a golden age but do reflect the “cultural primitivism” of Lovejoy and Boas. The Sumerian epic, Gilgamesh, describes the life of the adventures of Gilgamesh and Enkidu. Our most complete text (in Akkadian) is from the 7th century BCE, and Gilgamesh may have been an historical king in the 27th century BCE. The people of Uruk are unhappy with Gilgamesh, who is a harsh ruler and deflowers engaged women. Aruru, the goddess of creation, conjures up the wild-man Enkidu. He roams the wilderness with animals who treat him as one of their own. Shepherds are terrified by him, and in response to their fears, Gilgamesh sends the temple prostitute Shamhat to seduce Enkidu. She comes onto him disrobed and provocative and they make love for seven days, after which the wild animals flee from him. Enkidu has no recourse but to enter human society, learn to speak and use his knowledge of the wild to support himself as a hunter.49 He 13 quickly becomes the sidekick of Gilgamesh and loses his life on one of their adventures. There is an obvious, if superficial, parallel to Adam’s corruption by Eve in the Garden of Eden. For the Sumerians, however, Enkidu's pre-civilized existence, while it may have invoked nostalgia for the simpler life, was certainly not a life they envied or wished to emulate. Urban Sumerians, the epic’s audience, looked down their noses on their impoverished, unlettered, and unsophisticated country cousins. The Torah's description of Eden is first presented in Genesis, 2-3 and a variant appears in Ezekiel 28:12-19. Adam and Eve live well in Eden without having to work. They have a simple lifestyle without clothes or crafts and do not appear to eat meat. They are ignorant of shame and moral distinctions. Eden is an ideal state of existence in contrast to the hardships, sufferings and uncertainties of real life. It is recognizably fictional as people in pre-literature pastoral societies suffered all the same tribulations of post-exile humanity. Paradise assumed a wide range of meanings over the ages. For Christians, the Garden of Eden became closely connected to the Kingdom of God, or Heaven. Early Christian writers interpreted Eden literally and metaphorically, producing wildly contradictory accounts.50 Modern readings generally understand it as a golden age narrative. Some Christians have come to view the expulsion favorably as it set humanity on the path to independence and self-knowledge.51 For ancients and modern believers alike, Eden offers the sharpest contrast to the world in which real people live. Everything is possible that is not in real quotidian life. Augustine even imagined that Adam, when still in paradise, could raise and lower his penis at will and procreate with Eve without penetrating her.52 The Eden story appears to suggest that Earth was created as a paradise for humans who failed to recognize how well off they were and were expelled for violating the Lord's injunction 14 not to eat fruit from the Tree of Knowledge. It is significant that curiosity appears to have driven Adam and Eve to break the one taboo established by their deity. Curiosity and the pursuit of knowledge are the basis for technology, improvements in the quality of life and ultimately, of reflection about the nature of the world and the human condition. There can be little doubt that then, as now, cultures, and many individual people, were highly ambivalent about curiosity and where they thought it led. It is a primary catalyst for change, which is most often regarded as threatening, politically and psychologically. Change, when it occurs, inevitably gives rise to nostalgia among those who do not share in its benefits and provides an important motive and audience for golden age discourses. The film "Goodbye Lenin" offers a powerful and comic illustration of this phenomenon in the former East Germany. The most conservative reading of Genesis 2-3 supports the contention that human beings should not only bend to divine will, but to higher human authority as well because they neither know what is best for them nor can effectively overcome temptation. This is the traditional Roman Catholic interpretation, which posits original sin as the consequence of inadequate resolve in the face of temptation. Not surprisingly, Augustine attributed such lack of resolve to curiosity.53 His explanation gives rise to a conundrum: why would an all-knowing and omnipotent deity create human beings with such a flaw, and one moreover, that would lead them to rebel against him at the very outset of their existence? Traditional Jewish readings of the serpent, apple and expulsion emphasize free will and choice and are more tolerant of human failings. Eden is the first of many examples in the Torah and Jewish liturgy in which humans succumb to intellectual, sexual or material temptations but are encouraged to try yet again to live up to higher standards of behavior. For Christians and Jews alike, the struggle for selfimprovement is understood to be a defining characteristic of human beings. 15 Nietzsche recognized that the wealth of texts far exceeds the intentions of their authors or even the cultures that produce them.54 As Oscar Wilde put it: "When the work is finished it has. . . an independent life of its own, and may deliver a message far other than that which was put into its lips to say."55 More recently, Stanley Fish observes that good texts point away from themselves to ideas and feelings they cannot capture. They invite readers to enter into a dialogue and to create a “community” between author and reader that transcends generations. 56 Golden ages have functioned this way over the ages. They may have been created to justify the status quo; the Eden myth was certainly used this way for two millennia by the Roman Catholic Church.57 Leibniz’s invention of monads and his description of his world as the best of all possible ones is a secular version of this argument, although one advanced by a deeply religious man.58 The Garden of Eden and Hesiod’s ages of man serve as a bridge between nature and culture, pre-history and history and fantasy and reality. Their ability to inspire fantasy was undoubtedly an inspiration for utopias that seek to transform the world to recreate something as satisfying as the Garden of Eden. Golden ages, like so many other human creations, thus carry with them the possibility of inspiring projects diametrically opposed to their authors’ intentions. Tradtional Jewish and Christian readings of Eden attribute the decision to eat the apple and gain knowledge to curiosity. The Enlightenment yoked curiosity and reason together as the driving forces of human betterment. This shift finds its quintessential expression in Arthur C. Clarke’s clever riff on the Garden of Eden myth. His City and the Stars depicts a utopia many millennia in the future: a city where the conditions for human happiness, including de facto immortality, have been provided by its founders. Human beings have been genetically programmed to accept the city’s life style, but even futuristic science cannot rid them of curiosity and a streak of rebelliousness. The consequences of one man’s violation of the city’s strictest 16 taboo -- avoidance of the outside world -- leads to his cleverly engineered departure from “Eden” and subsequent adoption of a more “natural” life that includes mortality.59 Clarke provides subtle hints throughout the novel that the city’s founders intended such rebellion and actually programmed the periodic creation of individuals with characters that would make them dissatisfied with paradise. City and the Stars highlights a fundamental truth, one known to the ancient Greeks: paradise in any form is inherently unstable because it is static. Such societies must exist in splendid isolation, untouched and uncorrupted by contact with the outside world. For this reason, Plato situated his Kallipolis and Magnesia at the peripheries of Greece and the original European utopias were located on distant and largely inaccessible islands. Even in isolation, an ideal world would not remain stable for very long, as Plato acknowledges in his Republic. Human curiosity and desire for material goods and higher status lead some people to act in innovative and destabilizing ways. Adam Smith, a typical Enlightenment thinker in this regard, maintains that this drive “comes with us from the womb.”60 If so, no degree of socialization and stipulated order can effectively suppress these instincts; there will always be people who are dissatisfied and willing to explore new experiences and arrangements. Expulsion from the Garden of Eden, as some modern Christians contend, was perhaps inevitable and beneficial.61 Greek myths, like their Hebrew counterparts, reveal deep ambivalence about progress. Prometheus, whose name means “forethought” in ancient Greek, was a Titan. He was famous for his intelligence and theft of fire from Zeus to give as a gift to humankind. Zeus punished Prometheus by chaining him to a rock in the Caucasus where his liver was eaten every day by an eagle or vulture but regenerated every night. Heracles ultimately killed his avian tormentor and freed Prometheus from bondage. Early Greek texts alternatively praise or blame Prometheus for 17 setting humanity on the road to civilization, innovation and technology.62 Zeus punished men more generally by having Hephaestus mould the first woman whose descendants would henceforth torment the male of the species. In his Theogony, Hesiod does not give this woman a name, but she may be Pandora, whom he identifies in Works and Days. When Pandora first appears before gods and mortals, “wonder seized them” as they looked upon her. But she was “sheer guile, not to be withstood by men.”63 Zeus sends Pandora to Prometheus’ brother Epimetheus with a jar from which she releases “evils, harsh pain and troublesome diseases which give men death.”64 Pandora is an analog to Eve in that she brings suffering to mankind, although she does so through no failing of her own but on the instructions of the leading deity. The Pandora myth functioned as another prop for misogyny, although its more fundamental purpose, as with the Garden of Eden, was to serve as a theodicy. If the world and human beings were created by a benign god or gods worthy of respect and worship, the existence of evil and suffering are anomalous and require an explanation. Golden Ages – at least the original Western ones – admirably serve this end. The Greeks and Jews nevertheless resolve the anomaly somewhat differently. The Prometheus and Pandora myths suggest that humans are the playthings of gods, not all of whom are benign. The Garden of Eden exonerates the deity by making Adam and Eve’s expulsion and subsequent life of hardship the result of their decision – an exercise of free will -- to disregard the one restriction imposed on them. Both sets of myths attempt to reconcile human beings to life as they find it. The Greek myths further suggest that efforts to control one’s environment or escape from its sufferings are only likely to produce more suffering. They became the foundation for the tragic vision of life elaborated by later Athenian playwrights.65 18 Unlike their Jewish counterparts, Greek myths distinguish contemporary men from their predecessors. In the Iliad, Nestor refers to an earlier generation of superior and stronger men.66 Pindar laments the old days of “superheroes.”67 The fullest account is given by Hesiod in his Works and Days, which describes a paradise in which a “golden race” once lived like gods, free from toil and grief. They never aged or wearied of feasting. They lived in peace with one another and did not work because the earth yielded its bounty spontaneously. When they died in ripe old age it was as if they went to sleep.68 This golden age was set in the time of Cronos, before he was overthrown by his son Zeus. The golden age degenerated into one of silver as its people gave way to a new race that was less perfect, physically and mentally. They had shorter lives and were more belligerent. Zeus ultimately destroyed them because of their impiety. A third race, of bronze, was created. It was more violent and cruel, although superior to their predecessors in brawn and brains. The bronze race destroyed itself by its intemperance and violence. It was followed by the age of heroes, who were superior to their predecessors, and were reborn after death on the Island of the Blessed. A fifth race, human beings, constitutes an iron age. They continue the decline temporarily interrupted by the age of heroes. Humans are the weakest and least intelligent but most quarrelsome of races. They suffer because they are governed by force instead of justice. They succumb to old age and all of its infirmities, if they live that long. Their lives end with unpleasant deaths. By using a sequence of metals, each less valuable than the other, Hesiod indicates a steady decline in the quality of races.69 Separation of golden ages from the present by multiple races suggests that there is no going back. Golden ages are ambivalent about technology and reflect the attitudes of the societies that produced them. Progress is sometimes considered a boon for mankind, and fire was readily 19 accepted by humans when it was offered to them by Prometheus. But progress is also a catalyst for nostalgic narratives. This was true in ancient Mesopotamia, Israel, Greece and Rome and also post-industrial revolution Europe and Japan.70 In Hesiod’s account, only the iron race has agriculture. Romans considered agriculture a blessing and a curse. It sustains the human race but was closely connected with war. Roman citizens were farmers and soldiers, and exchanged plows for swords as circumstances required. Many Roman authors, Virgil among them, linked agriculture and manufacture, and described both as forms of warfare against the natural world.71 In the Middle ages and Renaissance, Eden was taken as evidence of decline; people were thought to be short-lived and short in stature in comparison to their Edenic and biblical predecessors. The closing lines of King Lear affirm that the young "Shall never see as much nor live so long."72 In the Merchant of Venice, Lorenzo contrasts the permanence of the moon with the body, "this muddy vesture of decay."73 The Enlightenment and counter-Enlightenment reveal a similar ambivalence about progress, although the positive and negative features of progress are now advanced by different individuals or schools of thought. Modern interpreters of Hesiod and Vergil have tried to reconcile their seeming contradictions about progress by every obvious strategy: they sequence positive and negative takes, suggest these authors modified or revised their views over time, find hidden keys that reconcile apparent inconsistencies and describe one of the opposing positions as concessions to political pressure or attempts to appeal to different audiences. This ambivalence, we shall see, is equally characteristic of our world and of the future worlds that science fiction creates. UTOPIAS 20 Utopias are forward looking and motivated by reformist, even revolutionary projects. The distinction between utopias and golden ages is nevertheless not hard and fast as the Garden of Eden and Hesiod’s golden age have occasionally been mobilized for reformist ends.74 These two kinds of narratives are connected in another sense: it is difficult to imagine utopias in the absence of the inspiration provided by golden ages.75 Utopias do not arise spontaneously in cultures with no tradition of golden ages. Ernst Bloch considers utopias a means of expressing the belief that something is wrong or missing in present-day life.76 Other discourses also serve this function. In my view, what most effectively distinguishes utopias from golden ages is their starting assumption that people can make the future better than the present. Utopias are offered as model societies in which individual happiness and collective harmony are achieved by means of institutions and practices that rest on and reinforce what their authors depict as universal human traits and aspirations. They invariably incorporate the principle of equality and de-emphasize material goods and their use as status symbols.77 In some utopias, property and women are held communally.78 Utopian authors often assert or imply that their imaginary worlds are realizable in practice; this is a common feature of nineteenth century socialist utopias. Others are offered as ideal type worlds that can provide inspiration and direction for improving, although never perfecting, the societies in which authors and readers reside. George Logan astutely observes that utopias, like their golden age predecessors, assume that a world without evil is impossible so long as competition over property and sexual partners exists.79 The first utopias are Greek. Homer’s account of Phaeacia in the Odyssey has utopian characteristics. It is isolated, rich, peaceful, offers boundless hospitality to visitors and plies the sea in ships that do not need rudders because they are steered by men’s thoughts.80 Plato’s 21 Republic offers the first detailed depiction of a utopia. His Socrates acknowledges early on that the Republic is nowhere on earth but in heaven.81 Like most utopias, it is explicitly based on a set of underlying assumptions about human nature, needs and motives and the corresponding belief that they can be harmonized with the right institutions, practices and indoctrination. Plato’s Kallipolis is more sophisticated than many subsequent utopias in three important ways. He addresses the problem of origins: how one gets to a near-perfect society from the deeply flawed one in which creator and readers reside. Plato acknowledges the difficulty of this transformation by introducing the noble lie. To hide their society’s human design and encourage loyalty to the city by all its citizens, the founders agree to tell subsequent generations that they are all brothers “born of the earth.”82 This lie also serves as the basis for collective as opposed to individual identities. Plato recognizes that Kallipolis cannot be isolated permanently from contact with the outside world and that some of these contacts will be hostile, especially if the republic is successful, increases in population and needs to conquer additional territory.83 Most importantly, he understands that societies are never static and will evolve regardless of rules and precautions introduced by their creators and enforced by their guardians. The last two characteristics would hasten the dissolution of Kallipolis. Innate curiosity and contact with foreigners would introduce new ideas and provide incentives for change and corruption. Plato’s Kallipolis is unusual in another respect. It is less a model for society than for the individual. Plato describes a city but offers it as a collective representation of a well-ordered human psyche, with its philosophers embodying the drive of reason. The constitution Plato lays down for Kallipolis is similar in all important respects to what he believes is best for the individual. That constitution is derived from first principles by philosophers whose wisdom comes from their holistic understanding of the good. They know how to order the life of the 22 polis to the benefit of all citizens regardless of their particular skills and intellectual potential. They rely on guardians to impose correct opinion on the polis and enforce its rules, including its provision of denying citizens, as far as possible, contact with outsiders.84 Plato and Aristotle -and Rawls, if we want a contemporary example -- offer their fictional worlds as ideal ones toward which we must aspire, individually and collectively, but which we are unlikely ever to achieve. Their worlds serve as templates that we can use to measure how our lives and societies live up to our principles. As Plato might put it, even imperfect knowledge of a form can motivate citizens and cities to work towards its actualization. Partial progress can generate enough virtue to sustain reasonable order in both. In antiquity, all utopias are agricultural. They have small populations, hierarchical political structures and do little more than meet the minimum material needs of their inhabitants.85 In other ways they are quite radical. Kallipolis extends equality to women and does away with the traditional family. Iambulus’ Heliopolis is an island populated by almost hairless, ambidextrous giants who live in kinship groups and are furnished with all of their needs by a bounteous nature. In each kin-group, the oldest man serves as a king and is obeyed absolutely by his juniors.86 From our perspective, such societies are neither ideal nor just. Lewis Mumford observes that these imaginary worlds incorporate unpalatable features of their authors’ societies. “It was easier for these Greek utopians to conceive of abolishing marriage or private property than of ridding utopia of slavery, class domination and war.”87 Even Plato’s guardians live off of the involuntary labor of others, Moses Finley, a life-long socialist, hastens to point out.88 Utopias nevertheless provide political theory with access to abstract realms that offer vantage points on one’s own world. Not everyone was attracted to this strategy. The Stoics, 23 who looked forward to the brotherhood of all men, at least in an abstract kind of way, turned their backs on society and utopias too for the most part.89 Modern utopias begin with Thomas More, who coined the word “utopia.” Born in London in 1478, he became a page in the household of Henry VII’s Lord Chancellor, John Morton. He was a lawyer, author, humanist scholar, and in the latter connection, a friend of Erasmus. He served as Lord Chancellor from 1529 to 1532, and in this position was responsible for burning numerous Protestants at the stake. He was beheaded in 1535 after refusing to sign the Act of Supremacy recognizing Henry VIII as Supreme Head of the Church in England. Utopia was conceived in Flanders in the summer of 1515, where More was serving as part of a trade mission. In Antwerp, Erasmus introduced him to Peter Giles, and the discussions in Utopia can reasonably be assumed to be a fictional elaboration of those between More and Giles. In 1516, More published Utopia in Latin. An English edition appeared posthumously in 1551, and translations followed in other European languages before the end of the century. Utopia is a recently discovered island in the New World. The imaginary explorer who describes it is Raphael Hythloday; his surname is an invented compound that in Greek means “nonsense peddler.” Utopia is a compound word where the “u” stands for the Greek “ou,” signifying no or not, and the “topia” to “topos,” or place. Utopia means “no place” or “nowhere.” If we substitute the Greek prefix “eu” meaning “good” or “well,” for the “u,” it translates as “good” or “ideal” place.90 So More’s society should be understood as ideal but imaginary. More models his commonwealth on Plato and Aristotle, both of whom regarded autarky as essential. He isolates his commonwealth and gives it sufficient, size, population and resources to make it entirely independent and powerful enough to protect its independence and even to establish a regional hegemony. Plato and Aristotle insist that the happiest life is one of virtue. 24 This requires leisure for contemplation and, for Aristotle, civic participation as well. In the ancient world, such a life was only possible for a small elite, supported by the labor of many others. More breaks with his Greek mentors in banning private property and any kind of special privileges; in Utopia everyone works and shares a similar level of prosperity. Striking too, given its author's intensely partisan involvement in the religious controversies of his day, is the religious freedom of Utopia. All denominations, even the small Jewish community, are allowed free exercise of their faith, but atheists are not tolerated. In practice, religious freedom turns out to be meaningless because everyone is under enormous social pressure to participate in community rituals and is deprived of the interiority that make beliefs meaningful. Like Plato’s Republic, Utopia emphasizes the value of order and discipline, which is achieved and maintained at the expense of individual freedom. Utopia appears to resolve some of the key problems that plagued More’s Europe; nobody is hungry, homeless, ill-clothed or socially isolated, unless they are a criminal. More considers private property the source of all social ills. However, Utopia's communism is not intended as a coherent, workable program but as a vehicle for exposing the greed and selfishness of English society. The commonwealth is egalitarian but authoritarian. The government periodically redistributes the population within families, cities and between Utopia and its colonies. There are no locks on doors, but little privacy and little to no down time. People are expected to spend their odd free hour listening to epistolary lectures or doing volunteer labor. There are no bars, coffee houses or private places for singles to meet. There is no sexual freedom beyond the choice of mates and stiff punishments are imposed for adultery. Sex is considered a lowly bodily activity akin to defecation and the scratching of itches. To travel, citizens need permission from the authorities. Everyone wears the same simple clothing and shame is brought to bear against 25 people who sport finery or jewelry. This is part of the general strategy of reducing differences among individuals to deprive them of individuality. Sameness is stressed in clothing, food, architecture and the layout of deliberately interchangeable cities. There are, however, hierarchical distinctions between generations and genders. Utopus aside, we never learn the name of a single citizen. To their credit, Utopians detest war, get on well with neighbors, but are not above colonial conquests to accommodate their growing population. They employ foreign mercenaries to do their fighting, indicating a double standard with regard to citizens and outsiders and undoubtedly leading to social conflicts that never surface in the book. More’s ethics represent something of a fusion of Stoic and Epicurean beliefs. He relies on the epicurean rule of choosing the greater over the lesser pleasure, for individuals and the state. Toward the end of the book, More acknowledges that many of Utopia's customs are absurd and others he would “wish rather than expect to see.”91 He does not believe that good institutions or leaders with good advisors can solve pressing social problems because they are manifestations of the underlying tensions and inequalities of society. Hythloday offers the example of capital punishment for theft, arguing that people will continue to steal as long as they are hungry, and they will be hungry as long as aristocrats and their retainers exploit their labor to provide income for foppish luxuries.92 Quentin Skinner was among the first to recognize that More’s Utopia is at odds with humanist orthodoxy and “embodies by far the most radical critique of humanism written by a humanist.93 Utopia, and the dialogue that precedes it, are vehicles for addressing contemporary ethical and political controversies. One of these concerns is the relationship between morality and expediency, which the Stoics believed could be reconciled. Machiavelli takes them to task in the Prince, written in 1513 but not published until 1532, in which he demonstrates that 26 honestà is often at odds with utilitas. Only if the two could be made fully compatible, would it be possible to construct a commonwealth that would always act morally. Utopia might be regarded as a thought experiment and its loose ends taken as evidence -- admittedly, planted by the author --that morality and expediency can only be reconciled in part. Stephen Greenblatt offers a more germane reading given my focus on identity.94 Following Burckhardt and Michelet, he argues that discourses in early modern Europe reveal a growing selfawareness of identity, something that can be shaped, manipulated and performed. More's History of Richard III indicates that role playing of this kind was widespread and that even ordinary people were not taken in by it, even if they had to pretend that they were. More used his notable political skills to achieve and hold onto the highest office in the land until the religious ground shifted underneath him.95 He would have agreed with Machiavelli that the social world was upheld by conventions in which nobody really believed. Humanist-inspired reforms were doomed to fail because political life was irrational, if not insane. Utopia reveals More's deep unhappiness with his public and family lives and the roles that they compelled him to perform. He built a house in then rural Chelsea as a retreat where he could partially escape from his roles and develop his thoughts. Utopia explores the possibility of a more radical alternative. It takes social conditioning to a new level, leaving no possibility of inner retreat or the private spaces that make it possible. Privacy is prevented by the denial of free time, near-constant surveillance and social conditioning that encourages people to feel shame for seeking solitude or individuation in any form.96 More understands interiority and autonomy as distinguishing features of modernity. He is most sensitive to their negative consequences and designs a world that nips modernity in the bud. Inner life, with its potential for alienation and social disruption, is all but excluded. Utopia is a fantasy of self-annihilation that represents a 27 figurative attempt to overcome the tension between its author's active inner life and his confining public roles. It is a self-serving fantasy in a second sense as More confided to Erasmus in a 1516 letter that he imagined that the Utopians elected him king in perpetuity. The egos of Utopians are destroyed to inflate that of their creator.97 The seventeenth century witnessed a very different kind of utopia with the publication of Francis Bacon’s New Atlantis. Written in 1626, it builds on Plato’s tale of the imaginary island of Atlantis.98 Bacon’s Atlantis, called Bensalem, is set in the “Southern Ocean” and possibly inspired by tales of Portuguese explorers about the New World. It represents a radical philosophical break with earlier utopias as its inhabitants use science and engineering to conquer nature and provide a longer, healthier and happier life. Following Bacon’s regimen of experimentation and inference, Bensalem’s citizens have developed techniques to isolate and protect themselves from outsiders and to control the weather and surrounding waters. As with the ancients, reason plays a central role, but of a very different kind. Its purpose is no longer to discover what constitutes the happy life, but to master nature and improve the human condition. More’s New Atlantis and Novum Organum are rebellions against Aristotelianism and its attempt to explain everything by means of deduction from first assumptions. From our vantage point, New Atlantis, like Utopia, embodies a paradoxical ethical code. The sailors blown off course are allowed to come ashore and visit Bensalem only after they swear that they have not killed anyone within the last thirty days, even in self-defense. When freed from the quarantine, they encounter a generally benign and non-expansionist society that has learned to live with its neighbors and to incorporate occasional outsiders. The authorities are nevertheless prepared to kill anyone who does not assimilate effectively, and would execute sailors who violate their rules. Intended or not, New Atlantis encourages readers to conclude that 28 science can be used “rationally” for benign and malign human ends. Bacon’s Great Instauration published in 1620, was intended as an introduction to the Novum Organum, his unfinished treatise on the scientific method. It was to be a comprehensive study of how science could produce knowledge about the physical and social world. Jerry Weinberger rejects Bacon’s claim that it was beyond his strength to finish this work. He maintains that Bacon left clues about his method for intelligent reader.99 This subterfuge was motivated by Bacon’s recognition, common to authors of later dystopias, that political science was the most dangerous science and had to be “secret and retired.”100 In Bacon’s New Atlantis, technology is treated as an unalloyed blessing. By the early nineteenth century, utopias offer sharply contrasting views on science and economic development. Some condemn them as the twin curses of modernity. Their authors create utopias by going back to what they imagine was a simpler, more satisfying, better regulated, premodern life-style. Louis Sébastien Mercier’s L’an deux mille Quatre Cent Quarante, published in 1771, outlaws foreign trade on the grounds that it stimulates desire for luxuries, the thirst for gold, sustains the slave trade and saps the health of the French people and their society. Snuff, coffee and tea, described as “natural poisons," are likewise banned. The transfer of scientific knowledge from country to country is nevertheless welcomed as an end in itself and not seen as a spur to economic development . In contrast, Henri Saint-Simon, in his “Sketch of a New Political System,” published in 1819, understands that technology and economic development go hand-in-hand. His House of Commons establishes a “Chamber of Invention,” whose 300 members are composed of scientists, engineers, poets and other writers, painters, sculptors, artists and musicians. Members with scientific and technical skill are expected to introduce and 29 oversee new public works and other projects to increase France’s wealth and make the life of its citizens healthier and more enjoyable.101 Later in the century, the industrial revolution was the catalyst for a series of utopias that reveal even sharper disagreements about the benefits of technology and economic development. Almost all of their authors recognize the impracticality of small, isolated communities and most are deeply influenced by socialism.102 A little known but interesting example is Ignatius Donnelly’s Caesar’s Column. Published in 1890, it attributes all social and economic evils to borrowing with interest. Donnelly insists that usury benefits only the lender and a small number of borrowers, reducing all others to debt and bankruptcy. His future America outlaws borrowing and introduces other laws to prevent the concentration of wealth. There are still rich men, and the desire for honor is mobilized to encourage them to dispose of excess wealth in a socially productive way. Under the guidance of the government, they donate their money, to schools, hospitals, libraries, parks and amusement centers for the benefit the people. A statue of each donor is placed in a great national gallery to honor them in perpetuity. Donnelly’s understanding of economics is flawed, to say the least, but his insight that honor can induce charitable giving in a capitalist society is right on the money. The backlash against industrialism found expression in art, architecture and other forms of literature. William Morris’ News from Nowhere, published in 1890, self-consciously explores these connections. Morris was a publisher, specializing in handcrafted editions, drawn to PreRaphaelite Brotherhood and later influenced by socialism. He used his wealth to support the newspaper of the Social Democratic Federation. He was fascinated by the pre-modern era, in which he convinced himself life was more purposeful and less corrupt. Two of his historical 30 romances are about fifth century German tribes and full of praise for the fellowship and community of tribal democracy.103 News from Nowhere transforms London into a quasi-rural, pre-modern economy run along socialist lines where everyone has access to food, education, culture and the material possessions essential for a fulfilling life. There is no money or credit, but a collective joy in producing goods of high artistic quality and providing them to people who need and appreciate them. Young people receive a fundamental education, but little emphasis is put on “book learning.” Instead, people are taught agriculture and crafts. As people are happy, and there is only limited foreign exchange and intercourse, and there is no war and thus nor need for armies or fleets. Following the lead of the Pre-Raphaelites, Morris regards the Middle Ages as a kind of golden age. He idealizes it as a time when craftsmanship, the simple pleasures of life and tightknit social relations flourished. His future Londoners dress in variants of medieval garb and live in houses with thatched roofs. Morris' utopia is modern in the sense that there is no class system, no differences among people in their standard of living, and remarkably for a Victorian, equal opportunity and treatment of women. He is ahead of his time in recognizing the horrendous effects of industrialization on the environment. His hero, who awakens in London in the distant future, is amazed to discover a clean Thames, teeming with wildlife, in which he can safely swim. There is a more general commitment by the society to minimize pollution and maintain green swards throughout the metropolis. Some British and American authors wrote utopias that envisage positive benefits to technology and economic development, suitably regulated by radically reformed institutions. Looking Backward, 2000-1887 is arguably the most famous example of this genre. It became an instant best-seller and inspiration for numerous societies dedicated to political and economic 31 reform. Its principal character, Julian West, is a young American who awakens after a century of hypnosis-induced sleep. His native Boston has been transformed into a quasi-suburban socialist utopia. Doctor Leete, his guide, explains how the quality of life has been significantly improved by drastically reducing the length of the working week. Nobody works before the age of twentyone and everyone retires at forty-five with a reasonable pension and other impressive benefits. America’s industry is commonly owned and its products are distributed more or less equally to its citizens. Technology has not only facilitated production but has enhanced social and cultural life. People are able to listen to live concert performances in their homes through tubes that carry the sounds of music across town. Much free time is devoted to socializing in a manner that has not changed since the Victorian era. The “vacuum left in the minds of men and women by the absence of care for one's livelihood has been taken up by love.”104 Like Morris, Bellamy is sensitive to environmental issues. His Boston is unrecognizable to the recently awakened American because it is green, clean, well-laid out and populous but uncrowded. Bellamy perpetuates female subjugation. His women are brought up to be virginal, pious, domestic and deferential. They work in their own industrial army where they perform tasks “suitable” to their gender. They must be married and mothers to attain positions of authority, presumably because this makes them more acceptable to men. Looking Backward nevertheless appealed to women, even suffragists, and there were many female members of Bellamy clubs.105 Bellamy’s world is a dystopia for African-Americans, who are segregated and forced to perform menial labor. Looking Backward looks forward in other ways. It invents readily available lines of personal credit, gigantic retail stores like Wal-Mart and the ability of distribution centers to deliver goods promptly to people’s homes. Following the program advocated by consumer 32 cooperatives of Bellamy’s day, the cost of goods is reduced by cutting out “the middleman.” Bellamy was a committed socialist and wanted his book to show how the future he described was prefigured in contemporary developments.106 His socialist society has been brought about without acute class conflict, let alone revolution, making it utopian in the negative sense understood by Marx and Engels. Bellamy tells us nothing about how socialism was achieved or how it functions at the macro level. It is implicitly a command economy, with decisions about production, employment and distribution of goods made by bureaucracies. This economy functions smoothly in the novel, which seems unrealistic given our knowledge of the Soviet Union. The “industrial army” makes it evident that production is the core of the economy, which is anachronistic from the vantage point of a post-industrial world. Most troubling of all, Bellamy’s America is authoritarian. Labor is organized and disciplined like an army, propaganda is delivered directly into the home by the telephone and no organized opposition appears to be sanctioned.107 The most influential nineteenth century utopia was the set of scholarly discourses in which Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels elaborated their version of socialism: historical materialism. They sought to distance themselves from so-called utopians whose works, in their view, were mental exercises in which “Reason became the measure of everything” and inspired societies in which social leveling occurs “in its crudest form.”`108 In contrast to many utopian authors, Marx and Engels claim scientific justification for historical materialism, insisting that it was based on universal laws of historical development. Like so many utopians, they fail grapple with the question of how you get there from here. They insist on the need for revolution, but their extensive corpus of writings contains few thoughts about how socialism would be 33 constructed and organized, how the state would wither away and, most importantly, how human consciousness would be transformed to make a communist world possible.109 Karl Mannheim suggests that ideologies and utopias fulfill different functions, although both have ideal origins. They are “incongruous with” prevailing life situations.110 Marx’s vision of socialism is much closer to anti-industrial utopias than either Marx or Engels were willing to recognize. It is well-ordered, and prosperous, without factories or war, yet humans have the kind of leisure and choices that allow them to develop their potential. Engel's language is positively utopian. “With the seizing of the means of production by society," he writes, "production of commodities is done away with, and simultaneously, the mastery of the product over the producer. Anarchy in social production is replaced by systematic, definite organization. The struggle for individual existence disappears. Then for the first time, man, in a certain sense, is finally marked off from the rest of the animal kingdom, and emerges from mere animal conditions of existence into really human ones.”111 Utopias spawned numerous critiques. Some emphasize the literary limitations of the genre. From More’s Utopia to Huxley’s Island, utopias tend to be didactic works with long instructional speeches or dialogues and turgid descriptions of institutions. Pedagogy is given primacy over plot. Utopias are invariably static; their social, economic and political institutions, practices and values are frozen on the grounds of perfection.112 There is no conflict or dissension, only near-universal satisfaction, and uncertainty of all kinds is replaced by personal and collective security. This thoroughly unrealistic tranquility is based on the belief, common to utopias, that human needs and aspirations are fully compatible and can be satisfied or harmoniously channeled by appropriate institutions. Utopias also rest on the all-important corollary that human beings have the insight and political skill to design, bring into being, 34 manage and fine tune the array of institutions and practices that produce social harmony and human fulfillment. Ortega y Gasset and Karl Popper accuse utopian thinking of laying the intellectual foundations for totalitarianism.113 Utopias can hardly be held responsible for the socialeconomic conditions that enabled psychopathic leaders like Lenin, Mussolini and Hitler to gain and consolidate power. They have nevertheless been consistently authoritarian. They put extraordinary trust in intellectuals – whether guardians, scientists or philosophers -- and severely restrict personal freedom as it is considered a threat to order and stability. Even post-World War II utopias, whose authors should have known better, reveal this kind of naïveté. In B. F. Skinner’s, Walden Two, published in 1948, the chief utopian planner Frazier rather smugly explains: “When a science of behavior has once been achieved, there's no alternative to a planned society. . . . We can't leave the control of behavior to the unskilled.”114 Judith Skhlar aptly observes that in utopias “Truth is single and only error is multiple.”115 DYSTOPIAS If golden ages enabled utopias, utopias inspired dystopias. Dystopias depict dysfunctional societies that exaggerate features of the present, like bureaucracy, capitalism, socialism, advertising and technology, to show their truly dreadful consequences when used for perverse ends. Evgeny Zamyatin’s, We, Aldous Huxley’s Brave New World, George Orwell’s 1984 and William Golding’s Lord of the Flies are classic representatives of this genre. A few dystopias are counterfactuals set in the present, as are the spate of novels premised on a German victory in World War II.116 In the second half of the twentieth century, dystopias far outsold utopias, and several of them (e.g., 1984, A Clockwork Orange) became box office hits when 35 turned into films. Utopias and dystopias are a good barometer of the mood and expectations of intellectuals and sometimes of the population more generally. Dystopias were unknown in the ancient world, although utopias were a source of parody in classical Athens. Aristophanes’ Ecclesiazusae, Thesmophoriazusae and Birds ridicule them as politically and socially naive. In modern times, this tradition finds expression in Gulliver's Travels, which can be read as a parody of Bacon’s New Atlantis. Mary Shelley’s Frankenstein can also be interpreted as a critique of utopian thinking. Her monster is a prescient warning of how scientific knowledge, ostensibly intended to benefit humankind, can give rise to unintended horrors. Dystopia came into its own at the end of the nineteenth century in response to industrialization, bureaucratization, materialism and mass politics. H. G. Wells, an early master of the genre, published six utopias and two dystopias. When the Sleeper Wakes, which first appeared in 1899, describes the world encountered by its hero Graham, who regains consciousness after being in a coma for two hundred years.117 In the interim, he has inherited sizeable wealth, which has been managed astutely by a trust -- the “White Council” -- established in his name. They have used the income to establish a globe-spanning economic and political order. Graham’s revival comes as a shock to the Council, which puts him under house arrest and tries as far as possible to keep him ignorant of their society and the turmoil that his awakening has provoked. He manages to discover that he is the legal owner and master of the world and that a revolutionary movement, led by a man named Ostrog, is trying to overthrow the established order. Graham is liberated by Ostrog's agent and survives a harrowing flight across the roofs of London’s skyscrapers while pursued by armed monoplanes. He arrives at a massive hall where the workers and underprivileged classes have gathered to launch an uprising and, led by Ostrog’s 36 brother, chant the Song of the Revolution. In an ensuing mêlée with the police, Graham escapes and wanders around a London engulfed by fighting. He eventually encounters Ostrog, leader of the now triumphant revolution, who provides him with comfortable quarters and, at his request, flying lessons. Through his friendship with a young woman, he learns that the people are suffering as grievously under Ostrog as they did under the previous regime. In a subsequent confrontation with the new leader, Graham realizes that he has no real commitment to economic and social reforms but is interested only in power. To suppress a growing insurrection in Paris, Ostrog uses African shock troops to get the workers back in line. Graham demands that he keep the Africans out of London. Ostrog agrees, but promptly breaks his promise. With the help of the workers, Graham escapes captivity a third time and makes a beeline for his aircraft. Ostrog’s forces hold a few landing areas to which the air armada bringing troops in from Africa heads. To delay the air fleet and give the workers time to capture the landing sites, Graham uses his airplane as a battering ram and knocks several transport airplanes out of the air. He also brings down Ostrog's machine, seemingly at the cost of his own life. Wells’ novel is remarkably prescient. Coming of age in a world where the popular press and mass electoral politics made their debuts, he recognized how easily they could be exploited by ambitious politicians to advance parochial ends. He envisaged politics as becoming a struggle for power divorced from any principles or rules of the democratic game. To make successful appeals, politicians would nevertheless have to associate themselves with symbols venerated by the masses, even create them. “The Sleeper” was the most potent symbol in the society, and the White Council and Ostrog struggle to control the now very much awake Sleeper while Graham attempts to assert his identity and use it for benign ends. In contrast to Marxism, Wells understood that politics could dominate economics because the drive for power would 37 eclipse that for wealth, as it does for the villains in the Sleeper novels. Wells projects the racism of his day into the future, making it another political weapon that the elite can exploit. The masses are enraged but cowed by widespread rumors of atrocities – which the author is careful never to confirm – allegedly committed by African troops in the course of their occupation of Paris. The novel can nevertheless be read as a critique of colonialism and socialism. The “White Council,” an unambiguous reference to a consortium of colonial powers, manages the world in its own interest, using capital extracted from the labor of the masses. Ostrog is a socialist revolutionary whose real goals turn out to be no different from the exploiters he so vocally opposes. In the twentieth century, influential dystopias explore the malign consequences of bureaucracy, materialism and socialism. Evgenii Zamyatim’s We, published in 1924, was the first fictional exposé of the Soviet experiment. He lived through the 1906 and 1917 Russian Revolutions but spent much of the First World War in Newcastle, where he worked in the Tyne shipyards. We combines the authoritarian socialism of the Soviet Union with the rationalization of Tyneside’s labor, and carries both to deliberately absurd lengths. His “One State,” led by the Benefactor and his Guardians, has existed for 1,000 years and came into being after a Hundred Years War that all but annihilated European civilization. Citizens have numbers instead of names: odd numbers preceded by consonants for males, and even numbers preceded by vowels for females. They are confined within the green walls of their cities and march four abreast to work every morning in matching uniforms. Privacy is verboten, but sex is sanctioned as a form of release and recreation. It is entirely heterosexual and must be preceded by the filing of a requisition form. Liaisons with appropriate partners are scheduled by the “Sexual Department” after an extensive study of candidates’ hormonal levels. Space engineer D-503 rebels, stimulated 38 by his love for E-330, a member of a dissident group. Their plot to takeover the space station fails. D-503 is captured and “fantasiectomized,” a surgical procedure that removes his imagination. Now reconciled to “One State,” he betrays the other conspirators, who are tortured and executed. Huxley’s Brave New World, published in 1932, is an industrial dystopia superficially portrayed as a utopia. People appear to live secure, healthy and hedonistic lives in a technologically advanced society where poverty and war have been eliminated. So, too, have art, literature, science, religion and family – everything that makes people who they are. The government maintains social stability through a rigid social order and the free distribution of hallucinatory drugs. Brave New World shares much with Zamyatin’s We, which Huxley claimed never to have read. He acknowledges the influence of H. G. Wells’ Men Like Gods and The Sleeper Awakes.118 Huxley was impressed by the soft-sell, totalitarian bent of American mass advertising and assembly line production introduced by Henry Ford. In Brave New World, Ford is made the Lord and the symbol “T,” derived from the Model T, replaces the cross and becomes the dominant icon of the society. Ford's famous dismissal of history as “bunk” is the official line of the World State. Isaiah Berlin describes Brave New World as “the most influential modern expression of disillusionment with purely technological progress.”119 George Orwell’s 1984 is an unambiguous dystopia. The novel is set in in 1984 London, a city that has become a provincial capital of the totalitarian state of Oceania, one of three world superpowers. Ubiquitous billboards feature photographs of “Big Brother,” the party leader, and the slogan “BIG BROTHER IS WATCHING YOU.” Citizens are barraged by propaganda beamed at them from televisions and loudspeakers in public places. They endlessly hear that “War is Peace, Freedom is Slavery and Ignorance is Strength.” Like contemporary CCTV, 39 television cameras monitor the population to detect social and political deviants. The principal protagonist, Winston Smith, works for the powerful Ministry of Truth, where he rewrites history, destroying and adding evidence to the records of people, making some of them “unpersons” as the need arises. The past is made totally subservient to contemporary domestic and foreign policy goals. War is continuous, as allegedly are the victories won by Oceana’s forces. Both justify economic hardship and the authoritarian political regime. In Brave New World, for which the United States was the model, people are pacified through access to pleasure. In 1984, modeled on the Soviet Union, they are kept in line through fear and punishment. Neil Postman observes that Orwell and Huxley were responding to different concerns: What Orwell feared were those who would ban books. What Huxley feared was that there would be no reason to ban a book, for there would be no one who wanted to read one. Orwell feared those who would deprive us of information. Huxley feared those who would give us so much that we would be reduced to passivity and egoism. Orwell feared that the truth would be concealed from us. Huxley feared the truth would be drowned in a sea of irrelevance. Orwell feared we would become a captive culture. Huxley feared we would become a trivial culture, preoccupied with some equivalent of the Feelies, the Orgy Porgy, and the Centrifugal Bumble-puppy. As Huxley remarked in Brave New World Revisited, the civil libertarians and rationalists who are ever on the alert to oppose tyranny ‘failed to take into account man's almost infinite appetite for distractions.’120 Orwell’s 1984 is closer to Zamyatin’s We in its plot and politics. The society is hierarchical, with Big Brother at the apex, the Party in the middle and the all but nameless 40 “proles” at the bottom. Winston Smith lives in a drab one-room apartment and survives on a near subsistence diet of black bread and synthetic food supplemented by rotgut gin. He is discontented, and keeps a secret journal which he fills with negative thoughts about the Party. He has an illicit romance, which serves as a catalyst for his alienation from Big Brother and attempt to join the Brotherhood underground. The Brotherhood appears to be set up and run by the Party as a clever means of identifying dissidents. Winston is betrayed, imprisoned, interrogated, tortured and brainwashed. He emerges, disgusted by his former affair and with renewed love for Big Brother. These novels indicate that dystopias are not the work of traditional conservatives. Their authors do not defend capitalism, religion or Victorian values. They are not opposed to modernity, but to the dangerous political and economic directions in which they believe it is heading. Wells was a socialist, but broke with the Fabian Society because he considered it insufficiently radical. He ran unsuccessfully for Parliament in 1922 and 1923 as a Labour Party candidate. Huxley was not directly involved in politics but was attracted to social experimentation, drugs and the counter-culture that emerged in California and the American southwest, where he lived after 1937. George Orwell, born Eric Arthur Blair, chose to experience colonialism in Burma and live in poverty in Paris and London. He fought in the Spanish Civil War and throughout his adult life maintained a deep commitment to social injustice and intense opposition to authoritarianism. Bacon, More, Hegel and Marx were optimistic about the future and wrote utopian tracts or novels. Rousseau and Nietzsche broke with this tradition and envisaged a bleak, culturally desolate future. For many intellectuals, two World Wars and the Holocaust appeared to confirm Nietzsche’s pessimistic view of history. Post-structuralists like Foucault and Derrida not only 41 reject the Enlightenment “project” but condemn progressive narratives of history as dangerous falsehoods.121 Dystopia more or less triumphed over utopia in the course of the twentieth century as intellectuals became increasingly disillusioned with the allegedly liberating power of reason. The failure to achieve a classless society, by peaceful or revolutionary means also hastened the demise of utopia.122 Many of us respond negatively to utopias because of their authoritarian political structure and oppressive regulation of private life.123 In the Second World War’s immediate aftermath, Scottish poet and socialist Alexander Gray exclaimed that “no Utopia has ever been described in which any sane man would on any conditions consent to live, if he could possibly escape.”124 Utopias flourished in the immediate post-war years and garnered wide audiences. B. F. Skinner's Walden Two (1948), Robert Graves, Seven Days in New Crete (1949) and Aldous Huxley’s Island (1962) follow the time-worn formula of distant island or future worlds that reject industrialism in favor of a simple, agricultural life. From the perspective of the twentyfirst century, such idylls seem impractical and unattainable, if not undesirable. As history’s course is never linear, it is not impossible that optimism will return at some future date. If so, we can expect it to give new life to utopias. To be compelling, they will have to take a new form, and as we will see, contemporary science fiction is already experimenting with possible outlines. REFERENCES 1 Wilde, Soul of Man Under Socialism, p. 24. 2 Kermode, Sense of an Ending, pp. 35-36. 3 Montesquieu, Spirit of the Laws, Book 19.12 and 14, 4 Weber, Economy and Society, I, 24-43, 212-16 and 319-325; Durkheim, Rules of Sociological Method, pp. 51-55, argues that habits, custom and tradition account for most behavior most of 42 the time. They prevail because of our cognitive need for simplification. Dewey, Human Nature and Conduct; James, Principles of Psychology; Simon, Administrative Behavior; Turner, Brains, Practices, Relativism; Bourdieu, The Logic of Practice; Steinmetz, State/Culture; Hopf, "Logic of Habit in International Relations." 5 Taylor, “To Follow a Rule.” 6 Goffman, Behavior in Public Places, Interaction Ritual, Presentation of Self in Everyday Life and Stigma. 7 Greenblatt, Renaissance Self-Fashioning, p. 95. 8 Derrida, Of Grammatology. 9 Hume, Inquiry Concerning Human Understanding, section iii, and “On the Study of History.” 10 Dilthey, “Understanding of Other Person and Their Life Expressions.” 11 Somers, “Narrative Constitution of Identity.” 12 Bruner, "Life as Narrative," Acts of Meaning and "Narrative Construction of Reality"; Schank and Abelson, Scripts, Plans, Goals, and Understanding; White, "Value of Narrativity"; Brooks, Reading for the Plot. Ricoeur, "Narrative Time” and Time and Narrative. 12 Geertz, Local Knowledge; White, When Words Lose Their Meaning; Dworkin, Politics of Interpretation; Hales, “Inadvertent Rediscovery of Self in Social Psychology”;Bruner, "Life as Narrative”; Sarbin, Narrative Psychology; Gergen, and Gergen, "Narrative Form and the Construction of Psychological Science”; Williams, "Genesis of Chronic Illness”; Kleinman, Illness Narratives; Spence, Narrative Truth and Historical Truth; Schafer, Analytic Attitude; Valentine, Fluid Signs; Turner and Bruner, Anthropology of Experience. 43 13 White, "Value of Narrativity in the Representation of Reality," On Narrative; and Content of the Form; Mink, "Autonomy of Historical Understanding" and "Narrative Form as a Cognitive Instrument"; Danto, Narration and Knowledge. 14 Ricoeur, “Narrative Identity,” p. 198. 15 Heider and Simmel, "Experimental Study of Apparent Behavior"; Michotte, Perception of Causality. 16 Bertaux, Biography and Society; Bertaux and Kohli, "Life Story Approach"; Freeman, "History, Narrative, and Life-Span Developmental Knowledge"; Linde, "Privates Stories in Public Discourse." 17 Becker, Outsiders; Memmi, Colonizer and the Colonized; Goffman, Presentation of Self in Everyday Life and Stigma; Lebow, White Britain and Black Ireland; Brodkin, How Jews Became White Folks; Jacobson, Whiteness of a Different Color; Nicholson, Identity Before Politics. 18 Beck, “The Reinvention of Politics”; Lash, “Reflexivity and its Doubles.” 19 Price and Tanenwald, “Norms and Deterrence”; Reus-Smit, Moral Purpose of the State; Klotz, Norms in International Regimes; Lebow, Cultural Theory of International Relations. 20 Augustine, Confessions. 21 Bakhtin, Problems of Dostoevsky’s Poetics. 22 Rousseau, Émile; Goethe, Werther. 23 Malinowski, “The Role of Myth in Life”; Basso, “Stalking with Stories"; Herdt, Guardians of the Flutes; Gross and Barnes, eds., Talk That Talk. 24 Hayes, Essays on Nationalism; Kohn, Prophets and Peoples; Deutsch, Nationalism and Social Communication. 25 Deutsch, Nationalism and Social Communication, p. 81. 44 26 Herodotus, Histories; Freud, Moses and Monotheism; Anderson, Imagined Communities. 27 Williams, Life of Goethe, pp. 215-16. 28 See especially, Seigel, Idea of Self. For a more widely cited but more partisan reading, Taylor, Sources of the Self. 29 Hopf, Social Construction of International Politics; Also, Clunan, Social Construction of Russia's Resurgence, who identifies five distinct post-communist identities. 30 Guzzini, Geopolitics Redux, esp. ch. 1. 31 Lebow, Cultural Theory of International Relations. 32 Wolin, Politics and Visions, p. 19. 33 Khanna, “Text as Tactic”; Williams, “Utopia and Science Fiction.” 34 Lebow, Forbidden Fruit. 35 Hobbes, Leviathan; Riley, General Will Before Rousseau. 36 Nozick, Anarchy, State and Utopia; Rawls, Theory of Justice, esp. ch. 3. For critiques, Dworkin, “Original Position”; Sandel, Liberalism and the Limits of Justice, ch. 3; Kilcullen, Rawls. 37 Hegel, Philosophy of History, Part III, 3(b). Benhabib, Critique, Norm and Utopia, pp. 42- 43, maintains that Hegel’s model of “transparent ethical life” is a “retrospective utopia.” See also Wenning, "Hegel, Utopia, and the Philosophy of History." 38 Benhabib, “Toward and Deliberative Model of Democratic Legitimacy.” 39 Huxley, Island. 40 Skinner, Walden Two. 41 For documentation of prehistoric warfare, Keeley, War Before Civilization. 42 Lovejoy and Boas, Primitivism and Related Ideas in Antiquity, pp. 1-7. 45 43 Frye, “Varieties of Literary Utopias.” 44 Finley, “Utopias Ancient and Modern.” 45 Seneca, Epis, 90.46. 46 Homer, Iliad, 13.3-9. 47 Pliny, Natural History, 4.88-89; Plutarch, Life of Serorius,.8.2-3. 48 Bremmer, “Paradise”; Noort, “Gan-Eden in the Context of the Mythology of the Hebrew .” 49 Tablet 1, 103-221. 50 Benjamin, “Paradisiacal Life." 51 For modern readings, Barr, Garden of Eden and the Hope of Immortality; Wallace, Eden Narrative. 52 Augustine, City of God. Book XIV, 24, pp. 472-73. 53 Ibid., XXII, 1-9, XIII, 12-15 and XIV, 12-14, who defined curiosity as man’s desire to transform his perfect human knowledge into perfect divine knowledge and thus become like a god. 54 Nietzsche, Birth of Tragedy, pp. 73-75; Vidal-Nacquet, Black Hunter, p. 252, offers the same judgment about the last century of Hellenic studies. 55 Wilde, quoted in Kermode, Romantic Image, p. 56. 56 Fish, Self-Consuming Artifacts, ch. 1, and Is There a Text in the Class, pp. 323-24, 347-48; White, When Words Lose Their Meaning, pp. 18-20, 286-91; Iser, Implied Reader. 57 Heinberg, Memories and Visions of Paradise; Goodwin and Taylor, Politics of Utopia, on the conservatism of golden ages. 58 Leibniz, Theodicy. 46 59 Clarke, City and the Stars. 60 Smith, Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of Wealth of Nations, II.ii, p. 362. 61 Kateb, Utopia and Its Enemies, pp. 68-112. 62 Hesiod, Theogony, lines 42-47, 560-612, Works and Days, lines 42-105; Aeschylus, Prometheus Bound. 63 Hesiod, Theogony, lines 560-612. 64 Hesiod, Works and Days, lines 91-92. 65 Lebow, Tragic Vision of Politics, chs. 4, 9. 66 Homer, Iliad, 1.260-28 and 5.302-4, refer to a golden age 67 Pindar, Odae Pythiae, III, 1-6. 68 Hesiod, Works and Days, lines 109-21. 69 The nineteenth century British classicist George Grote observed that Hesiod’s story of the five ages represents a fusion of two distinct and incompatible myths. The first, which predates Hesiod, is the myth of the Four Ages, all bearing names of metals, and succeeding each other in declining order of value. The second is the age of heroes, which Hesiod or a precursor, inserted between the third and fourth age. Berlin, Crooked Timber of Humanity, p. 25. 70 Plutarch, Tiberius, 2.3.63-64; Ovid, Metamorphoses, 1.95, 101-02, 123-24. 71 Virgil, Georgics, 1.125-26; Plutarch, Tiberius. 2.3.35-50; Ovid, Metamorphoses, 1.113-62; Seneca, Octavia, 120-30; Evans, Utopia Antiqua, pp. 83-87. 72 Shakespeare, King Lear, 5.3.325-26. 73 Shakespeare, The Merchant of Venice, 5.1.64. 74 Finley, “Utopianism Ancient and Modern.” 75 Evans, Utopia Antiqua, p. 3. 47 76 Bloch, Principle of Hope. 77 Manuel, “Toward a Psychological History of Utopias.” 78 Dawson, Cities of the Gods, for communist utopias in ancient Greece. 79 Logan, Meaning of More’s “Utopia,” pp. 7-8. 80 Homer, Odyssey, Books IX-XII. 81 Plato, Republic, 9.592b. 82 Ibid., 414b-e. 83 Ibid., 373d-e. 84 Ibid, 506c and Statesman, 309c6-10. 85 Hexter, More’s Utopia, pp. 70-71. 86 Iambulus, Heliopolis. 87 Mumford, “Utopia.” 88 Finley, “Utopianism Ancient and Modern.” 89 Vergil, Ecologues, IV, 37-45, for a possible exception. 90 Logan, The Meaning of More’s “Utopia,” p. 3, contends that More is aware of this double meaning. “Meter IV Verses in the Utopian Tongues,” which appears as an appendix to Utopia, reads in the sixteenth century English translation: “Wherefore not Utopie, but rather rightely/ My name is Eutopie: a place of felicitie.” 91 More, Utopia, p. 107. 92 Ibid., pp. 15-16. 93 Skinner, “Review Article,” and Foundations of Modern Political Thought, vo. 1., p. 256; Bouwsma, “Two Faces of Humanism.” 94 Greenblatt, Renaissance Self-Fashioning, ch. 1. 48 95 Machiavelli, Prince, ch. 19. 96 Ibid., pp. 45-46. 97 Ibid., pp. 54-55. 98 Plato, Critias, 120d6-121c4 and Timaeus, 19b-d, 22a, 25a-b6. See also his Phaedrus, 278d7, Laws, 676 99 Weinberger, “Introduction.” 100 Bacon, Advancement of Learning, II.47, p. 286. 101 Saint-Simon, “Sketch of a New Political System”. 102 Frye, “Varieties of Literary Utopias.” 103 Morris, House of the Wolfings and Roots of the Mountains. 104 Bellamy, Looking Backward, p. 261. 105 Strauss, “Gender, Class, and Race in Utopia.” 106 Bowman, Year 2000, p. 74. 107 Frye, “Varieties of Literary Utopias.” 108 Engels, “Socialism: Utopian and Scientific”; Marx and Engels, “Manifesto of the Communist Party.” 109 Marx, “After the Revolution” and Engels, “On Morality” are the principal sources and both are very short essays. 110 Mannheim, Ideology and Utopia. 111 Engels, “Socialism: Utopian and Scientific.” 112 Manuel, “Toward a Psychological History of Utopias”; Evans, Utopia Antiqua 113 Ortega y Gassett, xx; Popper, Open Society and Its Enemies; Ulam, “Socialism and Utopia.” Mumford, Story of Utopias, offers a more benign judgment. 49 114 Skinner, Walden Two, p. 226. 115 Skhlar, “Political Theory of Utopia.” On Skinner, see Kateb, Utopia and Its Enemies, pp. 141-47. 116 117 Rosenfeld, World Hitler Never Made, for a review of this literature. Wells, When the Sleeper Wakes. This is a substantially revised version of The Sleeper Awakes, published in 1910. 118 Find cite XX 119 Huxley and Huxley, Aldous Huxley, p. 150. 120 Postman, Amusing Ourselves to Death, foreword. 121 Foucault, Language, pp. 153-54. 122 Shklar, After Utopia. 123 Bowman, Year 2000, p. 121. 124 Gray, Socialist Tradition, p. 62. 50