Economic Actors and Criminal Liability / William A. Schabas War Economies, Economic Actors and International Criminal Law William A. Schabas The newly-elected Chief Prosecutor of the International Criminal Court (ICC), in one of his first public declarations dealing with prosecutorial strategies and orientations, on 16 July 2003, focused on the role of economic actors in armed conflict. After indicating that the crisis in the Ituri region of the Democratic Republic of Congo would be the likely target of his initial investigations, he turned to what were described as ‘[m]oney-laundering and other crimes committed outside the Democratic Republic of Congo which may be connected with the atrocities’. According to Chief Prosecutor Luis Moreno Ocampo, Various reports have pointed to links between the activities of some African, European and Middle Eastern companies and the atrocities taking place in the Democratic Republic of Congo. The alleged involvement of organized crime groups from Eastern Europe has also been mentioned. Their activities allegedly include gold mining, the illegal exploitation of oil, and the arms trade. There is general concern that the atrocities allegedly committed in the country may be fuelled by the exploitation of natural resources there and the arms trade, which are enabled through the international banking system. Although the specific findings of these reports have not been confirmed, the Prosecutor believes that investigation of the financial aspects of the alleged atrocities will be crucial to prevent future crimes and for the prosecution of crimes already committed. If the alleged business practices continue to fuel atrocities, these would not be stopped even if current perpetrators were arrested and prosecuted. The Office of the Prosecutor is establishing whether investigations and prosecutions on the financial side of the alleged atrocities are being carried out in the relevant countries.1 1 Professor, Director of Irish Centre for human rights ‘Communications Received by the Office of the Prosecutor of the ICC’, Press Release No.: pids.009.2003-EN, 16 July 2003, pp. 3-4. 1 Economic Actors and Criminal Liability / William A. Schabas The Prosecutor’s declaration had been anxiously awaited by those who follow the unfolding work of the new institution, because the Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court gives the Prosecutor an enormous amount of individual discretion in deciding to launch cases. That economic factors would figure so prominently on his agenda was quite astonishing and utterly unexpected, especially because the Court’s jurisdictional framework seems to leave it very few, if any, tools with which to address economic dimensions of armed conflict including money-laundering, illicit natural resource exploitation and the illicit arms trade. Indeed, to date, private sector actors, such as transnational corporations, have been highly invisible in armed conflict, fueling war and atrocity, yet operating deep within the shadows and often from remote and privileged environments. At best, they are conceptualized as secondary participants in international crimes, in a world where impunity, amnesty and immunity ensure that even the central architects of systematic human rights violations are still about as likely to be held accountable as they are to be struck by lightening. Chief Prosecutor Ocampo is surely aware of the obstacles in his way, because of the shortcomings of current legal norms and mechanisms capable of snaring the economic actors who contribute to conflict. Two paths lie open: strengthening the inadequate norms and mechanisms that currently exist, and beginning to contemplate the creation of a new legal regime better adapted to tackle these problems. Economic agendas may contribute significantly to the outbreak and the perpetuation of war. It seems that in our post-Cold War context, civil wars are often little more than campaigns to acquire access to natural resources and markets, although somewhere in the distant past it may be possible to identify a role for ideological factors and political objectives.2 Prosecutor Ocampo’s laconic statement nevertheless highlighted some of the complexities, because economic actors in armed conflict correspond to a variety of profiles. His reference to the ‘international banking system’, the exploitation of natural resources, the arms trade, and to companies from various parts of the world seems to point to classic white collar criminals ensconced within wood-paneled boardrooms in major capitals and financial centers. These forces are cloaked in legality and legitimacy, largely beyond the reach of existing law. But note was also made of ‘organized crime groups’, whose usually more clandestine activities situate them in a different legal paradigm and one that is probably more within the grasp of existing international regulation. For this latter category, the problem may be more a question of implementation and enforcement. Finally – and here the law is perhaps most robust – are 2 Mats Berdal and David M. Malone (eds.): Greed and Grievance: Economic Agendas in Civil Wars, Boulder and London: Lynne Rienner, and Ottawa: International Development Research Centre, 2000. 2 Economic Actors and Criminal Liability / William A. Schabas the economic dimensions of war crimes themselves, the well-recognized international offences of pillage and plunder, condemned by customary law for centuries and expressly prohibited in one of the first great humanitarian law treaties, the Hague Convention of 1907.3 Catching the Accomplices Only days after the adoption of the Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court at the conclusion of the Rome Conference in July 1998, the prestigious British business daily the Financial Times published an article warning ‘commercial lawyers’ that the treaty’s accomplice liability provision ‘could create international criminal liability for employees, officers and directors of corporations.’ Writer Maurice Nyberg referred to condemnation of violations of human rights involving multinational corporations by non-government organizations like Human Rights Watch, adding that ‘[i]t takes little imagination to jump from complicity with human rights violations to complicity with crimes covered under the ICC Treaty.’4 Certainly, to the extent that economic actors including international businesses are involved in war crimes and crimes against humanity, there is much potential and the law is, as the analysis below demonstrates, quite adequate. The participation will almost invariably be indirect, as financiers, or as merchants of weapons and other war paraphernalia, or traders in the spoils of war. International criminal law may apply to the extent that illegal means or methods of war are being employed, or that civilian non-combatants are being victimized. Note that the liability of economic actors would not be for economic crimes, as these are essentially absent from the Rome Statute, save for the war crime of “pillage and plunder.” Rather, economic actors would be held responsible as accomplices in the “classic” international crimes: torture, disappearance, apartheid and so on. There are a variety of definitions of complicity in international criminal law, of which the most widely accepted, and arguably the broadest, is that found in article 25 of the Rome 3 4 Prosecutor v. Kunarac et al. (Case No. IT-96-23-T and IT-96-23/1-T), Decision on Motion for Acquittal, 3 July 2000. Prohibitions of pillage and plunder can be found in: Convention (IV) Respecting the Laws and Customs of War by Land, [1910] U.K.T.S. 9, annex, arts. 28, 47; Agreement for the Prosecution and Punishment of Major War Criminals of the European Axis, and Establishing the Charter of the International Military Tribunal (I.M.T.), annex, (1951) 82 U.N.T.S. 279, art. VI(b); Convention (IV) Relative to the Protection of Civilian Persons in Time of War, (1950) 75 U.N.T.S. 287, art. 33; Statute of the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia, UN Doc. S/RES/827 (1993), annex, art 2(d); Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court, UN Doc. A/CONF.183/9, arts. 8(2)(a)(iv). Maurice NYBERG, ‘At Risk from Complicity with Crime,’ Financial Times, 27 July 1998. 3 Economic Actors and Criminal Liability / William A. Schabas Statute.5 An individual can be prosecuted for war crimes or crimes against humanity if he or she (c) For the purpose of facilitating the commission of such a crime, aids, abets or otherwise assists in its commission or its attempted commission, including providing the means for its commission; (d) In any other way contributes to the commission or attempted commission of such a crime by a group of persons acting with a common purpose. Such contribution shall be intentional and shall either: (i) Be made with the aim of furthering the criminal activity or criminal purpose of the group, where such activity or purpose involves the commission of a crime within the jurisdiction of the Court; or (ii) Be made in the knowledge of the intention of the group to commit the crime… It should be relatively easy to understand how an economic actor might fall within the reach of these provisions.6 Although the subject has received little or no attention from the ad hoc international criminal tribunals for the former Yugoslavia (ICTY) or Rwanda (ICTR), there are precedents in the post-Second World War prosecutions. In concentration camp prosecutions, personnel at Belsen were found ‘in violation of the laws and usages of war [and to be] together concerned as parties to the ill-treatment of certain persons...’7 The Judge Advocate who successfully prosecuted the case conceded that ‘mere presence on the staff was not of itself enough to justify a conviction,’ but insisted that ‘if a number of people took a part, however small in an offence, they were parties to the whole.’8 Nuremberg prosecutors also succeeded in obtaining a conviction 5 6 7 8 Complicity is also included in other instruments, such as: Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of the Crime of Genocide, (1951) 78 U.N.T.S. 277, art. III(e); Convention Against Torture and Other Cruel, Inhuman or Degrading Treatment or Punishment, (1987) 1465 U.N.T.S. 85, art. 4(1); Statute of the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia, supra note 3, arts. 4(3)(e), 7(1); Statute of the International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda, UN Doc. S/RES/955, annex, arts. 2(3)(e), 6(1); Statute of the Special Court for Sierra Leone, art. 6(1). See: William A. Schabas, ‘Enforcing International Humanitarian Law: Catching the Accomplices,’ (2001) 83 International Review of the Red Cross 439; Tom Farer, ‘Shaping Agendas in Civil Wars: Can International Criminal Law Help?,’ in Mats Berdal and David M. Malone, supra note 2, pp. 205-232. United Kingdom v. Kramer et al. (‘Belsen trial’), (1947) 2 LAW REPORTS OF THE TRIALS OF THE WAR CRIMINALS 1 (British Military Court), p. 4. Ibid., pp. 109, 120. 4 Economic Actors and Criminal Liability / William A. Schabas of three I.G. Farben executives who were involved in the construction of the slave-labor factory at Auschwitz.9 Two of them, Friedrich Flick and Otto Steinbrinck, were found guilty of complicity because of their financial support of SS leader Heinrich Himmler’s activities and, more generally, those of the SS.10 The ruling did not, however, extend to the corporation itself. For several years now, judges at the ICTY in The Hague have been fine-tuning a brand of complicity known as ‘joint criminal enterprise’, by which even relatively remote accomplices to an atrocity can be found guilty of crimes committed by others to the extent that the acts themselves were an objectively foreseeable outcome of the conspiracy.11 Now applied to war crimes and crimes against humanity, the concept has proven most effective in recent years in the prosecution of organized crime. Even the terminology itself – ‘enterprise’ – suggests an economic context. The Prosecutor of the Special Court for Sierra Leone is promising to explore this territory more thoroughly. For example, the indictments, issued in March 2003 against, among others, the late rebel leader Foday Sankoh and his ally, former Liberian president Charles Taylor, allege a ‘joint criminal enterprise’ whose objective was ‘to gain and exercise political power and control over the territory of Sierra Leone, in particular the diamond mining areas. The natural resources of Sierra Leone were to be provided to persons outside Sierra Leone in return for assistance in carrying out the joint criminal enterprise.’12 Although criminal prosecution of economic participants in armed conflict for their role in assisting grave violations of international criminal law has much potential, it is not without its problems. First, if the objective is to choke off the conflict by depriving combatants of funds, or in some other way to stymie the economic agendas that are at work, the alleged wrongs that are committed rarely fall within the scope of international criminal law. For example, although the Rome Statute prohibits use of certain weapons, such as poison, asphyxiating gas and hollow-tip bullets, it does not at present challenge 9 10 11 12 United States of America v. Carl Krauch et al. (‘The I.G. Farben Case), (1948) 8 TRIALS OF THE WAR CRIMINALS 1169, p. 1180. United States of America v. Friedrich Flick et al. (‘The Flick Case), (1948) 6 TRIALS OF THE WAR CRIMINALS 1217-1221. Prosecutor v. Tadic (Case No. IT-94-1-A), Judgment, 15 July 1999, 15 July 1999. Also: Prosecutor v. Krnojelac (Case No. IT-97-25-PT), Decision on Form of Second Amended Indictment, 11 May 2000; Prosecutor v. Brdjanin & Talic (Case No. IT-99-36-PT), Decision on Form of Further Amended Indictment and Prosecution Application to Amend, 26 June 2001; Prosecutor v. Krnojelac (Case No. IT-97-25-T), Judgment, 15 March 2002 E.g., Prosecutor v. Sankoh (Case No. SCSL 2003-02-I), Indictment, 7 March 2003, para. 27; Prosecutor v. Sesay (Case No. SCSL 2003-5-I), Indictment, 7 March 2003, para. 23; Prosecutor v. Koroma (Case No. SCSL 2003-3-I), Indictment, 7 March 2003, para. 24; Prosecutor v. Brima (Case No. SCSL 2003-6-I), Indictment, 7 March 2003, para. 23; Prosecutor v. Taylor(Case No. SCSL 2003-03-I), Indictment, 7 March 2003, paras. 20, 23. 5 Economic Actors and Criminal Liability / William A. Schabas the use of those arms that are most common, especially in civil wars: automatic rifles and other forms of small arms, machetes, anti-personnel mines and cluster bombs. Anti-personnel mines were widely used in the conflict in the former Yugoslavia, yet there have been no prosecutions alleging that this was contrary to the laws or customs of war, and therefore prohibited by article 3 of the Statute. In other words, while it may be possible to convict an arms manufacturer or trafficker who knowingly contributes to the use of prohibited weapons – an analogy here would be the conviction of those who supplied Zyklon-B gas to Nazi extermination camps13 – most of the lethal weapons are not prohibited by international law. When they exist, the prohibitions, such as the Ottawa Convention on anti-personnel mines, are neither comprehensive nor universal. While the principles of complicity liability seem straightforward enough, most of the existing experiments in international criminal law have limited them in one way or another. The case law of the ad hoc tribunals for the former Yugoslavia and Rwanda has required that participation in a crime be ‘substantial.’14 This may discourage prosecution of economic actors, whose involvement in crimes, though undisputed, may seem to be too remote. The Prosecutors of the ICTY and ICTR have shown little interest in pursuing economic actors, although there is an outstanding indictment for the Rwandan businessman Felicien Kabuga for his role in financing the Rwandan génocidiaires.15 Similarly, the jurisdiction of the Special Court for Sierra Leone is confined to ‘persons who bear the greatest responsibility’ for serious violations of international humanitarian law. 16 Determining who bears the greatest responsibility would appear to belong essentially to the realm of the discretion of the Prosecutor. Theoretically, he might determine that transnational diamond merchants, such as De Beers, fall within this category,17 but this is not the direction that prosecutions have taken, and the initial indictments have been directed to military and political leaders. 13 14 15 16 17 United Kingdom v. Tesch et al. (‘Zyklon B Case’), (1947) 1 LAW REPORTS OF THE TRIALS OF THE WAR CRIMINALS 93 (British Military Court), pp. 93-101. Prosecutor v. Tadic (Case no. IT-94-1-T), Opinion and Judgment, 7 May 1997, paras. 691, 692. Also: Prosecutor v. Delalic et al. (Case no. IT-96-21-T), Judgment, 16 November 1998, para. 326; Prosecutor v. Furundzija (Case no. IT-95-17/1-T), Judgment, 10 December 1998, paras. 223, 234; Prosecutor v. Aleksovski (Case no. IT-95-14/1-T), Judgment, 25 June 1999, para. 61. Prosecutor v. Bizimana et al. (Case no. ICTR-98-44-I), Prosecutor’s Amended Indictment Pursuant to the Decision of Trial Chamber II on the Defence Motion…, 21 November 2001, paras. 4.24-4.25. Statute of the Special Court for Sierra Leone, art. 1. L. Sanders, ‘Rich and Rare Are the Gems they War: Holding De Beers Accountable for Trading Conflict Diamonds,’ (2001) 24 Fordham International Law Journal 1402. 6 Economic Actors and Criminal Liability / William A. Schabas Finally, while it may be of considerable interest to pursue private businesses for their complicity in war crimes, and not just the individuals who work within them as managers and directors, this is not always possible. For example, the jurisdiction of the International Criminal Court is confined to ‘natural persons.’18 Corporate bodies and legal persons were excluded from the Rome Statute for essentially practical reasons. Many domestic justice systems do not provided for criminal prosecution of corporate bodies or legal persons. For the complementary regime of the ICC to operate fairly, it was believed necessary to find a common denominator of all major criminal justice systems, and this made it unrealistic to include a provision on corporations.19 Shortcomings of Existing Law International law endeavors to regulate armed conflict in a number of ways. First, and foremost, it prohibits the use of force except in two extraordinary circumstances, enforcement action pursuant to Chapter VII of the Charter of the United Nations and ‘the inherent right of self-defense. Its success in this area is debatable, and prevention of conflicts may well have more to do with the political and the diplomatic than it does with any legal prohibition. Nobody has been prosecuted for ‘crimes against peace’ since the 1940s. Attempts to make aggression an international criminal offense punishable by the International Criminal Court are proceeding, but at a leisurely pace, and there is no assurance that they will succeed. Two issues make progress difficult in this area: there is no agreement among States about how to define aggression; and there are possible conflicts with the United Nations Security Council should the ICC attempt to determine issues of aggression, because article 39 of the Charter of the United Nations says this is the prerogative of the Council. The law is considerably more developed and sophisticated in the area of jus in bello, the legal regime governing the conduct of armed conflict, irrespective of whether the war itself is unlawful. In addition to a weighty repertoire of treaties, with the 1949 Geneva Conventions as the centerpiece, international law also brings a rich body of customary 18 19 Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court, supra note 3, art. 25(1). For discussion of the debates leading to the exclusion of corporate bodies, see: Per Saland, ‘International Criminal Law Principles’, in Roy Lee, ed., The International Criminal Court: The Making of the Rome Statute, Issues, Negotiations, Results, The Hague: Kluwer Law International, 1999, pp. 189-216, at p. 199; Kai Ambos, ‘General Principles of Law in the Rome Statute’, (1999) 10 Criminal Law Forum 1, at p. 7; Andrew Clapham, "The Question of Jurisdiction under International Criminal law over Legal Persons: Lessons from the Rome Conference on an International Criminal Court’, in: Menno T. Kamminga and Saman Zia-Zarifi (eds), Liability of Multinational Corporations under International Law, The Hague: Kluwer Law International, 2000, pp.139-195. 7 Economic Actors and Criminal Liability / William A. Schabas norms to bear in this area. As recently as 1996, the world’s supreme judicial body, the International Court of Justice, declared that the ‘cardinal principles’ of international humanitarian law are the obligation to distinguish between combatants and non-combatants, never to make civilians the object of attack, and to eschew the use of weapons that cause unnecessary suffering to combatants.20 International humanitarian law provides a relatively sophisticated body of legal rules and principles to govern international armed conflict, many of them customary in nature and developed virtually from antiquity, but it has rather less to say with respect to intra-state armed conflict. This is explained partly by historical reasons and partly by the reluctance of States to allow international law to pry into an area of great sensitivity to them, their conduct in putting down armed challenges to their own authority. To the extent that rules exist to govern the conduct of internal armed conflict, their applicability is conditional on certain threshold definitions. These exclude many low-level conflicts of great seriousness, as well as riots, disturbances and terrorist acts. Although there are important exceptions, such as the recent interventions in Kosovo, Afghanistan, and Iraq, most contemporary armed conflicts are internal in nature. In parallel with international humanitarian law is the more modern regime of international human rights law. It is said to apply without exception in both peacetime and wartime, and without any interest in whether or not a conflict is international or internal in scope. Nevertheless, certain principles of human rights law, such as the right to a fair trial and freedom of express, can be suspended or derogated from in time of war.21 Moreover, courts continue to debate whether or not human rights law and humanitarian law operate together, reinforcing each other, or whether one supersedes the other. The International Court of Justice seems to consider that humanitarian law displaces human rights law because it is a specialized body of principles intended to govern situations of armed conflict (lex specialis).22 Finally, there is an ongoing debate among scholars and practitioners to what extent international human rights law does apply to ‘non-state actors’, like transnational corporations and other economic actors. But aside from what may seem highly technical issues of the application of these two bodies of law, the real problems reside with the substance of the norms, which do not 20 21 22 Legality of the Threat or Use of Nuclear Weapons (Advisory Opinion), [1996] I.C.J. Reports 226, para. 78. For example, International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, (1976) 999 U.N.T.S. 171, art. 4. On this subject, see the recent ‘General Comment No. 29’ of the United Nations Human Rights Committee, UN Doc. HRI/GEN/1/Rev.6, p. 186. Legality of the Threat or Use of Nuclear Weapons (Advisory Opinion), [1996] I.C.J. Reports 226, para. 26. 8 Economic Actors and Criminal Liability / William A. Schabas generally deal with economic matters. They are targeted at the core issues of threats to bodily integrity, such as killings, mutilations, summary executions, sexual assaults and pillage. Of course, economic actors who are directly involved in such violations and abuses fall within its ambit as much as traditional combatants. Generally, though, the role of economic actors is more indirect. For example, while it is widely agreed that trade in diamonds helped to fuel conflict in places like Sierra Leone, 23 unless it can be established that diamond traders were actual accomplices in the atrocities committed against civilians, there is little that existing law can contribute. If it were actually an unlawful act to buy and sell diamonds, even while knowing that somewhere along the chain of possession they had been bartered for small arms or anti-personnel mines that were then turned on the innocent, most jewelers in the developed world would have to close their doors. Finally, if the purpose of the exercise is to prevent conflict rather than to regulate it, ensuring that wars do not happen instead of seeing that they are conducted with respect for rules of chivalry, international law is woefully inadequate. The prohibition of the use of force within the Charter of the United Nations, coupled with the punishability of crimes against peace or aggression for those individuals who actually participate in a breach of the peace, relates only to international armed conflict. By and large, international law has nothing to say about the jus ad bellum of internal wars. There is even acknowledgement of the legitimacy of resort to the use of force in some circumstances. The preamble to the Universal Declaration of Human Rights accepts ‘recourse, as a last resort, to rebellion against tyranny and oppression,’ 24 while the humanitarian law instruments nod benignly at ‘armed conflicts in which peoples are fighting against colonial domination and alien occupation and against racist regimes in the exercise of their right of self-determination.’25 Illegal use of force may provoke political intervention by bodies like the Security Council of the United Nations, but it continues to elude such fora as the international criminal tribunals. For example, the ICTY is powerless to prosecute those who actually started the wars in Croatia, Bosnia and Herzegovina, and Kosovo; its subject-matter jurisdiction is confined to violations committed after the wars had begun. Although the Security Council imposed an arms embargo on the region, the Tribunal cannot prosecute those 23 24 25 John L. Hirsch, Sierra Leone, Diamonds and the Struggle for Democracy, New York: International Peace Academy, 2001. Universal Declaration of Human Rights, G.A. Res. 217 A (III), U.N. Doc. A/810, preamble. Protocol Additional to the 1949 Geneva Conventions of 12 August 1949, and Relating to The Protection of Victims of International Armed Conflicts (Protocol I), (1979) 1125 U.N.T.S. 3, art. 1. 9 Economic Actors and Criminal Liability / William A. Schabas who defied the prohibition because this is not an offence within its jurisdiction. In what was a last-minute and inadequate drafting compromise, the Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court has jurisdiction over the crime of aggression, but only to the extent that the offence is subsequently defined and that the tension with article 39 of the Charter of the United Nations, which appears to reserve determination of cases of aggression to the Security Council, is resolved.26 Unless States parties to the Statute can agree on a legal formula, prosecutions for aggression cannot take place. At present, they seem far indeed from any agreement.27 It is, perhaps, a commonplace, but one that deserves repeating. Wars, especially civil wars, are often rooted in social tensions and dislocations that result from violations of economic and social rights. The ‘rebel war’ in Sierra Leone (1991-2002) may have been launched by individuals who were trained in Libya and funded by Liberia, but it drew its initial support from a stratum of the country’s youth that was quite understandably dissatisfied with endemic corruption, poverty and underdevelopment. This portrait of the conflict, already noted by some observers, is becoming increasingly evident as the hearings of Sierra Leone’s Truth and Reconciliation Commission unfold. Economic actors, including corrupt officials and greedy transnational corporations in mining and other areas of commercial activity, contributed to the overall misery and wretchedness of the country in the three decades since independence, in 1961. Weak notions of social responsibility among local elites as well as transnational commercial operators must be strengthened if what may now be little more than a ceasefire is to be transformed into lasting peace. Blaming the war on meddling by Muammar Qadhafi and Charles Taylor is to some extent a distraction from the underlying economic causes of the war, something to which both national and transnational businesses contributed. Corporate Responsibility and Civil Liability Economic agendas are pursued through organizations in one form or another, generally rebel groups of commercial corporations. The corporation dates to the early stages of capitalist economies, and facilitates business activities in a number of ways, not the least of which is the protection of the personal assets of the individuals who direct them and profit from them. One means of regulating economic agendas in armed conflict may well 26 27 Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court, supra note 3, art. 5(2). See Theodor Meron, ‘Defining Aggression for the International Criminal Court,’ (2001) 15 Suffolk Transnational Law Review 1. Sylvia A. de Gurmundi Fernandez, ‘The Working Group on Aggression at the Preparatory Commission for the International Criminal Court,’ (2002) 25 Fordham International Law Journal 589. 10 Economic Actors and Criminal Liability / William A. Schabas be through standards of corporate responsibility. This is an area receiving an increasing amount of attention, mainly with regard to human rights abuses suffered by persons in the South at the hands of commercial corporations directed from the North. Labor standards and environmental protection are at the core of contemporary concerns, but there is no reason why the approaches undertaken in these areas cannot and should not be extended to the context of armed conflict. Most efforts in the area of corporate responsibility belong to the realm of ‘soft law’ initiatives or ‘corporate social responsibility’ (CSR). These are codes of conduct and best practice, adhered to voluntarily by businesses, sometimes in exchange for public relations and marketing advantages in one form or another. The prospect of consumer boycott may often be a realistic encouragement to compliance. It seems likely that negative publicity about the international diamond market and its contribution to conflict in Angola, Sierra Leone, and elsewhere may well have influenced the behavior of the international diamond industry. Labeling requirements whose objective is to unleash the forces of consumers have had a nod of acceptance from the World Trade Organization dispute resolution system.28 Yet, one needs to distinguish between different types of corporations with operations in the area of armed conflict. Large, transnational companies in the extractive industries, who through their operations may become complicit in violations of international law, are typically legitimate entities and relatively amenable to CSR initiatives. Where the corporations involved are arms dealers and shadowy commodity traders, however, benevolent corporate culture is unlikely to be at its highest. Most of the relevant operators are not particularly vulnerable to ‘naming and shaming.’ Their activities are more analogous to those of organized crime than to that of innocent merchants and traders whose products and services, inadvertently, are put to evil use. One of the justifications for persuasion rather than coercion when transnational corporations are involved revolves around the legal difficulties associated with regulation. International norms of human rights and humanitarian law are addressed to States, not individuals or corporations, it is argued. In response, a growing body of law holding States responsible for ‘horizontal violations’ of human rights is invoked. Although non-State actors may not be directly liable under international law, States are responsible for ensuring that corporations under their jurisdiction behave in accordance with certain minimum standards. 28 WTO Appellate Body, United States-Import Prohibition of Certain Shrimp and Shrim Products (12 October 1998), (1999) 38 International Legal Materials 11. 11 Economic Actors and Criminal Liability / William A. Schabas This argument helps to a point, but then confronts the additional obstacle of extraterritoriality. States argue that to the extent that they are obliged to ensure their corporate citizens behave responsibly, this duty is confined to their own territory. Anything further might be taken as a violation of the sovereignty of other States. Wealthy countries that attempt to regulate the conduct of their own nationals, corporate and other, in poorer countries may even find themselves charged with neo-colonialism. Here too, though, there is a potent answer. States are increasingly prepared to enact legislation governing conduct of their nationals abroad when this involves serious violations of human rights. Examples include the statutes adopted by many developed countries aimed at sexual tourism by their own nationals in countries where the justice system is overwhelmed, or simply corrupt, and therefore unwilling or unable to address the exploitation of children. Similarly, many States have anti-trust and anti-bribery legislation with extraterritorial effect. In other words, there are significant exceptions to the general rule discouraging legislation with extraterritorial effect. Consequently, robust national legislation in those countries that are home to transnational corporations, that is aimed at commercial activity by corporations that contributes to armed conflict abroad, could well have a meaningful impact. There has already been at least one attempt to legislate in this area. In 1996, the State of Massachusetts adopted what was known as its ‘Burma law,’ which attempted to regulate state contracts with companies doing business with or in Burma.29 The statute was struck down as unconstitutional by the United States Supreme Court, but only because the field was deemed to be one of federal jurisdiction, and not because such initiatives were impermissible per se. The real problem, of course, is defining the line beyond which commercial activity is no longer legitimate and acceptable. In many ways, this is the same problem faced in the criminal sphere, with respect to complicity in war crimes and crimes against humanity. In that context, the diamond merchant who trades with armed groups engaged in notorious atrocities may be considered close enough to the offence for criminal complicity to be engaged. However, the jeweler in a foreign city who only suspects the products he or she is dealing with are ‘blood diamonds’ may be deemed to be rather too remote. 29 An Act Regulating State Contracts with Companies Doing Business with, or in Burma (Myanmar), 1996 Mass. Acts 239, ch. 130 (codified as Mass. Gen. Laws §§7: 22G-7: 22M, 40 F½ (1997). 12 Economic Actors and Criminal Liability / William A. Schabas When corporate responsibility is being addressed, within the context of civil liability however, the rigorous standards that apply to criminal prosecution need not be observed. Justice systems balk at punishing a foreign jeweler who is merely suspicious as to the origin of diamonds, but have rather less difficulty imposing various civil consequences, such as fine or confiscation, in such circumstances. The burden of proof is one of preponderance of evidence, and not the daunting reasonable doubt standard of criminal trials. In so many respects, then, a legal regime focused upon corporate accountability and responsibility, with civil or administrative but not criminal consequences, has much to recommend itself. Model legislation might be devised indicating how such a system could operate. Commercial corporations with their head office in a given country, or perhaps substantial assets or activities, or some other significant nexus, would be required by law to abstain from acts that might facilitate a conflict. These could be defined in a general sense, or applicability might be triggered by some determination by a national or perhaps an international body concerning a state of armed conflict. Upon proof that the norms of conduct were breached, a variety of sanctions could be contemplated, including fines, confiscation of assets, personal liability for directors and, ultimately, company closure. ‘Economic’ Truth Commissions Political compromises associated with conflict resolution have often involved some form of pardon or amnesty. The premier legal instrument governing non-international armed conflict, Protocol Additional II to the Geneva Conventions of 1949, actually says that ‘[a]t the end of hostilities, the authorities in power shall endeavor to grant the broadest possible amnesty to persons who have participated in the armed conflict…’30 But to ensure that amnesty does not equal amnesia, and out of concerns that enforced silence about perpetration of atrocities leaves post-conflict societies with festering sores that are fundamentally destabilizing, many countries have convened truth and reconciliation commissions. The most well-known, of course, is that of post-apartheid South Africa. But more than twenty-five others have been cataloged over the last couple of decades.31 By and large, truth commissions focus on violent breaches of civil and political rights or of international humanitarian law. They attempt to bring together victims and perpetrators, and thereby promote reconciliation, but with frank and candid recognition of 30 31 Protocol Additional to the 1949 Geneva Conventions and Relating to The Protection of Victims of Non-International Armed Conflicts, (1979) 1125 U.N.T.S. 609. Priscilla B. Hayner, Unspeaking Truths, Facing the Challenge of Truth Commissions, Routledge: New York & London, 2002. 13 Economic Actors and Criminal Liability / William A. Schabas the truth as a prerequisite. Generally, they try to assess responsibilities for the conflict, and to make recommendations aimed at preventing a recurrence. There is no reason why truth commissions cannot also address the economic causes of conflict, the role of economic agendas during the conflict, and the possible ways to deal with them in post-conflict setting. The South African Truth and Reconciliation Commission has done this, but very much as an afterthought. Its initial report, in 1998, did not delve into the economic and social issues. Five years later, in its final report, the Commission laid a share of the blame for apartheid upon the role of business, including transnational corporations, and called for companies to finance programs of compensation out of existing assets and future profits. Citing ‘decades of profits [that] were based on systematic violations of human rights,’ the 2003 report proposed a levy of 3 billion rand on South African companies, including Anglo-American Mining Corporation (which is itself a shareholder in the De Beers diamond business), and criticized an 800 million rand trust fund established by business as ‘paltry’. The Commission pointed to a wealth tax levied in West Germany in order to rebuild East Germany following reunification as a model. The Sierra Leone Truth and Reconciliation Commission, which began work in July 2002, has a broad mandate enabling it to explore the role of economic actors, including those involved in the diamond trade which did so much to fuel the ten-year civil war. Its enabling statute charges it with creating ‘an impartial historical record of violations and abuses of human rights and international humanitarian law related to the armed conflict in Sierra Leone.’32 This allows it to examine violations and abuses of economic and social rights, as well as civil and commercial rights. Moreover, it is also to determine whether the ‘violations and abuses were the result of deliberate planning, policy or authorization by any government, group or individual, and the role of both internal and external factors in the conflict.’33 Therefore, the Commission has wide authority to examine the role of economic agendas, notably the contribution of ‘respectable’ transnational corporations as well as that of quasi-criminal commercial operations. The Truth and Reconciliation Commission Act states that the government is required to implement the Commission’s recommendations. The Commission’s work is incomplete at this point, and it is, therefore, too early to say whether it will rise to this challenge. But its legislative framework provides an open door for such inquiry. The Commission conducted detailed research into diamond mining, and held public hearings on the subject. Its final report, due to be released in May 2004, is likely to make 32 33 Truth and Reconciliation Commission Act 2000, No. 4 (2000), s. 6. Ibid., s. 7. 14 Economic Actors and Criminal Liability / William A. Schabas recommendations concerning the regulation of diamond mining, changes to the tax structure, and similar measures. There have been suggestions that truth commissions might also provide an appropriate framework to address property disputes of various types resulting from armed conflict. They do not seem to be particularly appropriate for this arena, however. Truth commissions are best at speaking to phenomena of human rights abuse committed on a large scale, by States or rebel groups, and often in contexts where it is difficult to identify the specific perpetrator. It might trivialize their significance were they to be reduced to arbitration of individual claims, rather like ordinary civil courts. Initial assessments of the information gathered by the Sierra Leone Truth and Reconciliation Commission indicate that victims are not so interested in achieving individual justice, in terms of restitution or compensation, as they are in seeing a new political regime that ensures to them basic economic and social rights, such as housing, work, education, and health care. Generally, one of the great advantages of truth commissions is their flexibility. They do not establish guilt and they do not impose punishment or other sanction. They are, nevertheless, fact-finding bodies that can attribute responsibilities. By and large, their rules of evidence are extremely liberal. The sorts of jurisdictional issues that plague judicial solutions rarely arise with truth commissions. Of course, they are usually powerless to implement their findings and recommendations; this is left to political bodies. But overall, it would seem desirable that in future truth commissions, the possible role of business in the conflict be flagged openly in the enabling instruments, and that truth commissions be persuaded that no analysis will be complete if this dimension is not studied and considered. Conclusion International law has proven itself to be modestly successful at regulating the conditions under which the use of force is acceptable as well as the means and methods of warfare. It has not been particularly good at controlling the phenomenon of weapons that cause unnecessary suffering or that are indiscriminate, subject to a few rather archaic exceptions, such as dum-dum bullets and poisonous gas. As a result, the most significant economic actors in armed conflict – arms producers and traders– largely escape legal sanction. Sometimes there are efforts to choke a conflict by means of arms embargo, of course, but these efforts have been notoriously unsuccessful, as the cases of the former Yugoslavia and Rwanda bear out. 15 Economic Actors and Criminal Liability / William A. Schabas As for other economic activities, such as trade in mineral and other resources, there can be no doubt that such ventures fuel armed conflict. This is probably as old as armed conflict itself. Traditionally, armies live off the land. Where there is nothing left to plunder, they wither and die, as Napoleon discovered at the gates of Moscow. The Nazi armies were finally reversed when they could not quite extend their front lines enough to include the rich oil fields of the north Caucasus, necessary to fuel the war literally as well as figuratively. How different are these historical examples from the case of Sierra Leone’s Revolutionary United Front occupying the country’s fabulous alluvial diamond fields? Pressure from civil society is already leading to the development of legal instruments, most of them ‘soft’ rather than ‘hard,’ aimed at improving corporate social responsibility. To date, the focus has been mainly labor and environmental standards. There is no reason why this should not extend to the specific concerns of armed conflict. In Canada, pressure from non-governmental organizations and industrial unions induced the petroleum company Talisman to abandon its interests in Sudan, where its activities had allegedly been associated with war crimes or crimes against humanity in the context of one of the world’s most long-lived civil wars. Commercial corporations that are involved in armed conflicts, to one extent or another, may find themselves – or their directors and managers – exposed to criminal prosecution as accomplices in international crimes. This is an area that deserves to be explored much further. In 1997, when women’s organizations felt the International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda was neglecting gender crimes, an intense lobbying campaign essentially changed the prosecutorial agenda, and resulted in the first significant international judgments on the role of rape in armed conflict.34 A serious concerted effort to encourage prosecution of the economic accomplices to conflict-related crimes might also be undertaken, to similar effect. International prosecutors have a great deal of discretion in the targets that they choose. At Nuremberg, there were efforts to establish the role that the German business community played in the rise of Nazism. These met with varying degrees of success. Walther Funk was found guilty of war crimes and crimes against humanity principally for his role in the German financial establishment, where he was President of the Reichsbank. He was found guilty and sentenced to life imprisonment. But in the recent crop of international prosecutions – Yugoslavia, Rwanda – there has been little interest in developing cases that highlight the economic dimensions of the conflicts. This is probably not because of 34 Prosecutor v. Akayesu (Case no. ICTR-96-4-T), Judgment, 2 September 1998. 16 Economic Actors and Criminal Liability / William A. Schabas the inherent difficulty in preparing cases as it is with prosecutorial strategy. The efforts of the Prosecutor of the Special Court for Sierra Leone, who has referred to economic issues in several of his indictments, may signal a change in this respect. The Chief Prosecutor of the International Criminal Court has also manifested an interest in economic matters. Perhaps the best way forward, in terms of bringing international law to bear on economic agendas in armed conflict, would be to assist the Chief Prosecutor of the new International Criminal Court in focusing on this area. One or two convictions of those involved in the business of war, rather than in the war itself, will surely make headlines in the Financial Times or the Wall Street Journal. The deterrent effect may be worth more than a score of Security Council resolutions. 17