Linking the Gene Ontology with Social Ontology: A Prolegomena to the Ontology of Personhood David R. KOEPSELL1 SUNY Buffalo/Yale Center for Bioethics Abstract. The Gene Ontology captures information at a very small scale, namely: molecular function, biological process, and cellular components. At this level, the Gene Ontology project should be capable of developing a semantics for every relation of genomic data to protein synthesis to the biological processes that result. In essence, the Gene Ontology should be able to describe the complete biomechanical functioning of an organism. But what of the social ontological statuses of organisms, and the relations of individuals to their higher level functions? Can the Gene Ontology account for higher level activities of an organism (such as intentionality, rights, property relations, etc)? Without leaping to conclusions about whether higher level functions are in fact naturalistically based, we should develop a semantics to serve as a hypothetical bridge should genomics lead us in that direction. Keywords: genome, Gene Ontology, social ontology, bridge ontology, organism, legal ontology 1. Introduction Genomes carry the instructions for the complete functioning of organisms. The human genome, for instance, contains about 3 billion base pairs, which coordinate, through a variety of molecular, cellular and biological processes, the development, functioning and reproduction of individual humans. Describing the relations between the genome and its expression is 1 drkoepsell@gmail.com ; home page: http://www.davidkoepsell.com. Presently Research Assistant Professor at SUNY Buffalo Dept. of Philosophy -- coordinator of Graduate Research Ethics; Donaghue Visiting Scholar in Research Ethics at the Yale Center for Bioethics, 2006-2007. clearly a challenging ontological puzzle. The data architecture for the genome evolved, and is not necessarily plainly visible nor elegant. The genome itself carries apparently large chunks of junk that does not seem to play any practical role – at least not any more. Moreover, the useful data is not always coded in generally transparent ways, and useful units of information come in various sizes, places on the chromosomes, and not always contiguously. Thus, while the working definition of a gene (the largest of which is nearly 2.3 million base pairs long) is still the unit of information involved in making a particular protein, units of useful, or at least “effective,” information come in packets as small as a single base pair. Moreover, the old notion of “one gene, one polypeptide” has been challenged with the completion of the human genome project, which helped scientists conclude that individual genes may in fact code for as many as three proteins. To decipher the relation of the information contained in an individual’s genome, and the individual himself, clearly requires ontology. The Gene Ontology (GO) is aimed at attempting to gather data from gene discovery and correlate it in a useful ontology in order to fully describe an organism’s phenotype based on its genotype. Yet, lacking from this is any form of bridge to describe the individual beyond its phenotype. Because human persons appear to be more complex than the biomechanical processes that compose them, a complete Gene Ontology will only describe individuals at one level. Ontologies developed in fields such as law, sociology, psychology, and at the level of social institutions, all consider persons as complex, intentional, thinking beings imbued with features such as rights, duties, and relations to subjects and objects above the biomechanical level. Can a bridge ontology be developed that will tie the Gene Ontology together with ontologies of persons, and allow for semantic links among future ontologies in the biological, social, and especially legal domains? 2. The Gene Ontology: Overbroad and Insufficient The Gene Ontology does not describe persons, nor is it limited even to human beings. Rather, because genes often direct the same biochemical processes from one species to another, their ontologies capture relations among genes, proteins and biological processes across domains. As it turns out, for instance, the gene responsible for color vision exists in species as diverse as humans and drosophila melanogaster (the fruit fly). This information is tremendously helpful in identifying the evolutionary basis of inherited genetic traits among and within species, as well as diseases. The culmination of the Gene Ontology project, if there ever is one, will be a generic description of all genes and resulting proteins as well as biological processes, not restricted to any one species. Onto this, one could superimpose just the human genome, and acquire a general understanding of the functioning of a generic human organism, or a particular human’s genome, and understand fully the functioning of that individual at least on a biomechanical level. However, such an understanding, while perhaps biomechanically describing the functional basis of a person, fails to account for essential, higher order features of personhood. The Gene Ontology is thus both overbroad and insufficient on its own to incorporate or account for social ontologies that describe or involve persons as objects. At one level, then, the Gene Ontology describes a common set of phenotypes expressed by genes among all species, but also describes (ideally) some generic member of a species. Imagine then that we can sequence an individual’s genome, and have the complete Gene Ontology before us. That complete ontology will give us a snapshot of the biomechanical processes involved in that person, but will it describe the person per se? There are some heady philosophical issues tied up with a complete description of a person which we need not delve into for the moment, but a couple of criteria not already described by the GO are worth mentioning. Persons are complex continuants, whereas the most complex objects described by the Gene Ontology are simple chemical processes (occurrents). Even assuming a completely naturalistic basis for complex person-processes (like intending, bearing rights, reasoning, etc.) the sum of all the pysio-chemical processes described in the Gene Ontology still does not amount to a description of the continuant “person.” Intentionality is at most an emergent phenomenon, dependant on biomechanical processes, but in itself much more. It is at least a computationally highly complex neurochemical process, as yet uncontemplated by any of the categories or relations exiting in the current Gene Ontology. Another way to consider this is to ask: to what degree is an individual the sum of the entities expressed by his genomic data? Certainly, genomic data encodes something very important in describing a particular human, but it seems unlikely that it can fully describe an individual adult person. One reason is that the genomic data, while it codes for many, if not every, trait of an individual (including hair color, eye color, intelligence, and perhaps even preferences and tastes), fails to capture other historical factors that go into forming an adult person. On the other hand, infant persons are legally and socially relevant, and for a time, at least, little more than the sum of the entities expressed phenotypically by their genomic data. A complete ontology of personhood will necessarily include the human Gene Ontology and the other necessary and sufficient conditions of personhood. A complete ontology of personhood is necessary for other social ontologies. Since the Gene Ontology seeks to capture useful descriptions of much of what composes a human, and science shows that a good many features of personhood (e.g. behaviors, predilections, intelligence) are hereditable and many of them are genetically based. There is a dilemma: extend the Gene Ontology to capture relations and features of personhood, or develop a bridge ontology? As discussed below, one or the other is necessary for existing and future social ontologies. 3. The Necessity and Use of an Ontology of Personhood The necessity for linking the Gene Ontology with social ontologies is most apparent considering legal ontologies, in which nearly every legal category contemplates some right or duty owed among persons, rather than simply humans. Increasingly, new ethical and legal issues regarding the relations between persons and either a generic human genome or an individual’s particular genome (or some portion thereof) require ontological clarity regarding the statuses of those relations. The Gene Ontology describes the expression of the genome in the phenotype, and ultimately seeks to do so completely and comprehensively. Legal ontologies describe the relationships of persons to property and other persons. One glaring gap common to medical, biological, and social ontologies is a coherent description of the relations among individuals, their particular genomes, and the generic “map” of the human genome. The Gene Ontology does not presently have sufficient categories to deal with those sorts of relations, though it could conceivably at some level of complexity. Thus, while the Gene Ontology describes cellular components and biological functions, it does not yet encompass things like “mental states or processes” composed of the former, or the potentiality thereof, either of which is generally considered necessary for personhood in legal ontologies. Genes account for a number of persistent and legally relevant mental states that are considered to negate legal intentionality. A genetic link has been found between Aph-1b and mental illnesses such as schizophrenia. Genetic links seem likely with other mental illnesses and certain forms of mental retardation (such as defects on the FMR-1 gene), any of which may create the legally and socially relevant state of lacking capacity for sufficient intentionality for legal or social accountability. Genes seem also to be responsible for severe conditions such as microencephalia and Lissencephaly both of which may also diminish or negate the legal status of personhood. While cognitive defects may have a number of other possible causes, the potential for firm genetic links to persistent states that interfere with personhood suggests that other necessary “healthy” genetic bases exist for the presence in a human of the mental states considered to be relevant to personhood, or upon which personhood may necessarily depend. As a further example, the legal class “disabled” person” encompasses those who are congenitally disabled, as well as those who may acquire a disability. Defining a class of genomic disabilities, in other words -- finding genetic causes for a range of known disabilities, could have significant legal implications for those covered by such acts as the Americans with Disabilities Act (ADA). The benefits, and potential complications, of being able to determine with certainty the genomic existence of a particular individual’s disability are obvious. Linking legal and biomedical ontologies, and having access at some point to an individual’s genomic data, will clarify issues regarding the status of a particular “disabled person,” and potentially streamline processes under the ADA as well as insurance and medical schemes. Distinctions among racial “classes” or “races” have been used both legally and socially to broadly define ethnic classes, generally based on phenotype, and to legitimize and then later remunerate for disparate treatment of individuals and groups. Genomic research has cast doubt on the entire notion of “race” but has also shown some use for ethnic/geographic distinctions among groups in drug development. The nascent field of pharmacogenomics is aimed at targeting populations (which seem in some instances to fall along classical racial lines) with more appropriate drugs. It seems that certain ethnic groups respond in empirically different ways due to minor differences in genotype. [1] Genomic data, which can map these relevant genomic differences, will have significant legal and ethical repercussions. Remuneration or affirmative action schemes meant to provide relief to a historically oppressed class may be bolstered or hindered, depending upon how we treat discoveries regarding classical notions of race, and how we class individuals among various ethnic groups. What is clear is that as we refine the GO and other biomedical ontologies, some accommodation, either by new categories in those ontologies, or in bridge ontologies of persons and subclasses of persons, will add significant value to both legal and biomedical ontologies. Indeed, Barry Smith and others have done much to fix the errors and gaps in the GO and other biomedical ontologies through refinements in the GO and Open Biomedical Ontology (OBO) semantics and logic. [2], [3], and [4]. However, little has been done to link legal and biomedical ontologies, despite the obvious necessity and potential benefits. For instance, criminal liability attaches only to sane, adult persons. Only persons may be held criminally liable for wrongdoing. If biological and genetic conditions are responsible for certain forms of legal insanity or other incapacity, then it will be considerably helpful for those accessing legal ontologies to have all relevant evidence of biomedical or genetic determinants of various incapacities. As well, larger “philosophical” issues such as the ethics and legality of abortion or euthanasia depend on definitions of personhood that could be further clarified by access to a GO that accounts for all the necessary features of personhood and not mere human-ness. A rights-bearing person and a fresh human corpse are socially and legally distinct, although, at least momentarily, biologically and biomechanically (on the cellular level) indistinguishable. The law and culture, however, distinguish between the two by punishing, for instance, the fatal stabbing of one differently than the impalement of the other. The distinction is the same as the ontological distinction between mere humans and persons. The complete ontology of a person will include all relevant genomic features (i.e. those responsible for the requisite mental and physical states) and descriptions of whatever emergent features might be necessary to describe a person (e.g., a “soul” if naturalistic bases for personhood are ever deemed insufficient by the relevant empirical sciences). The legal class “person” already exists and is utilized in every legal ontology, whether explicitly or implicitly, but linkage with the GO and other biomedical ontologies requires further clarification and expansion, as well as incorporation of certain features of the GO. The gap noted is not necessarily a failure in the meta-ontology of the GO or other biological ontologies. It could conceivably be accommodated for by a comprehensive ontology of personhood, which belongs somewhere between biomedical and social ontologies. In fact, implicit in most existing social ontologies is a notion of personhood, to which rights, duties, obligations, etc. attach, but the relations and features of the entity “person” should be clarified and expanded to include relevant relations and features from the GO and other biomedical ontologies. Assuming, as empirical science does, a naturalistic basis for all relevant human behaviors (intentionality, rationality, etc.) then a bridge to legal and other social ontologies could be built into layers of the GO and other biomedical ontologies, or a bridge ontology of personhood could be developed. Either way, the GO and biomedical ontologies need to have a common entity at some level to facilitate interaction at the levels discussed in this paper. Even assuming that consciousness and other complex personhood-features are emergent or irreducible, they are nonetheless ontologically dependant upon genetic, molecular, biological processes which, when fully described, should encompass those emergent phenomena. Either approach should make clear that, given a certain set of preconditions, a genomic string plus X is a person, and thus has a certain legal and social status, and absent such, no person yet exists. 4. The Genome, Particular Gemones, Persons and Possessory Interests One important but tricky problem posed by the discovery of the sequence of the generic human genome, and the ability to sequence an individual’s particular genome, is the problem of defining the relationships among those entities. To what extent, for example, is your genome part of you, or is it in fact another expression of you? [5]. It turns out that answers to these and similar questions are both legally and socially significant as more aspects of the genome, and particular SNPs, haplotypes and alleles come to be “owned” through schemes such as patent and copyright. Ordinarily, expressions are productions of human intentionality. [6]. Humans, however, are “expressions” of particular genomes. Persons, finally, are a result of both genome and perhaps other factors (for instance, X + [occurrent] life of X). Whatever the ultimate ontological status of persons, there is currently no good account of the nature of the relations between humans, persons, the human genome, and particular genomes. Do persons stand in the relation of “owners” of their genome, given their arguably possessory interest in the data? Does the human species stand in the role of possessor of the generic human genome, as against, say, some alien species wishing to utilize the genome for evil (or profit). [7]. The human — person — genome relation, whether one of ownership, or otherwise, needs resolving to deal with a number of weighty and unresolved ethical and legal issues, such as: patenting of genes, cloning, stem cell research, etc. [8], [9]. The GO’s current ontology, because it does not extend to social ontological terms, cannot capture these relations. A bridge ontology of personhood, extending from the GO, can link this and other important biomedical concepts to legal and ethical concepts. 5. Conclusion The GO and other biomedical ontologies capture important data and relations within and among species and members of species. Missing from these ontologies is any ready manner to link these important concepts with legal and other social ontologies, specifically regarding the critical concept of personhood. Complex and timely ethical and legal issues are emerging from genomic and bioinformatics research, and central to most of these is the ontology of personhood which, if formally described, and linked to GO and OBO concepts, could do much to clarify emerging legal and ethical issues. Such a bridge ontology should be developed. References: [1] Van Delden, J., I. Bolt, et al. (2004). "Tailor-Made Pharmacotherapy: Future Developments and Ethical Challenges in the Field of Pharmacogenomics." Bioethics 18(4): 303-321. [2] Anand Kumar, B. S. "The Ontology of Processes and Functions: A Study of the Classification of Functioning, Disability and Health ". [3] Barry Smith, e. a. (2005). "Relations in biomedical ontologies." Genome Biology 6(46). [4] Olivier Bodenreider, A. B. (2005). Linking the Gene Ontology to other biological ontologies. Proceedings of the ISMB’2005 SIG meeting on Bio-ontologies 17-18. International [5] Guenin, L. M. (2003). "Dialogue Concerning Natural Appropriation." Synthese 136(3): 321-336. [6] Koepsell, D. (2000). The Ontology of Cyberspace. Chicago, Open Court. [7] Berry, R. M. (2003). "Genetic Information and Research: Emerging Legal Issues." HealthCare Ethics Committee Forum 15(1): 70-99. [8] Strydom, H. (2003). "The human rights side of the human genome. [Summ. in Afrikaans]." Tydskrif vir die Suid Afrikaanse Reg/Journal of South African Law; T35 2003:37 55. [9] Spinello, R. A. (2004). "Property Rights in Genetic Information." Ethics and Information Technology 6(1): 29-42.