Wang Shaoguang State Effectiveness and Democracy State Effectiveness and Democracy Wang Shaoguang “In framing a government which is to be administered by men over men, the great difficult lies in this: you must first enable the government to control the governed; and in the next place oblige it to control itself.” Madison: The Federalist, No. 51 Introduction In the late 1980s and early 1990s, when the “third wave” of democratization (Huntington 1991) began to spread from South Europe and Latin America to East Asia, Eastern Europe, the Soviet Union, sub-Saharan Africa, and elsewhere, many were very optimistic about the future of the unfolding “worldwide democratic revolution." Now, a decade later, the optimism has somehow faded away. Although the U.S. Government continues to claim, "At long last, democracy is triumphant,"1 those who have made efforts to assess the progress of the third wave find that the reality is not as rosy as people once tended to believe. Among nearly 100 countries that appeared to be moving away from authoritarian rule in the early 1990s, at present, only fewer than 20 are “clearly en route to becoming successful, well-functioning democracies” (Carothers 2002). In addition to over a dozen countries that have suffered “democratic breakdown” or “democratic reversals” (e.g., Pakistan, Kenya, Lebanon, Lesotho, Niger, Peru, Sierra Leone, Zambia, and several post-Soviet states), most transition states seem to have stuck in what Larry Diamond terms "twilight zone" (Diamond 1999b) or what Thomas Carothers calls “gray zone” (Carothers 2002). Falling in between outright dictatorship and well-established democracy, those political systems have recently earned new labels, such as “semi-democracy,” “formal democracy,” “electoral democracy,” “façade democracy,” “pseudodemocracy,” “weak democracy,” “partial democracy,” “virtual democracy” (Collier & Levitsky 1997), “illiberal democracy,” (Zakaria 1997) and “broken-back democracy” (Rose & Shin 2001). However, ever adding qualified adjectives to characterize those systems is still misleading, because most of them are not democratic at all. Why are so many third wave transition countries in trouble? Or more generally, what are the conditions under which democracies can survive and function? The standard answer to this question normally points to three key variables as the preconditions for a successful venture into stable democracy, namely, a relative high level of economic development (which is associated with such intervening variables as a high standard of living, a high level of literacy, a sizable and strong middle class) (Lipset 1959; Fukuyama 1993, Barro 1999; Przeworski et. Al 2000), a vibrant civil 1 On June 26-27, 2000, at a two-day conference to celebrate the spread of democracy held in Warsaw, the U.S. State Department, one of the conference sponsors, claimed, "At long last, democracy is triumphant." Over the last quarter-century, the department says, the world has witnessed "a profound democratic revolution." Electoral democracies now represent 120 of the 192 existing countries and 58 percent of the world's population. 1 Wang Shaoguang State Effectiveness and Democracy society (Putnam 1993; Linz & Stepan 1996),2 and a strong civic culture (Almond & Verba 1963; Inglehart 1997; Diamond 1999). There is no doubt that these are in fact attributes which characterize the old and stable democracies, nor that they are generally lacking in most of the transition countries. However, they are by no means the only things that are absent in the majority of third-wave countries. Another things those countries are commonly wanting seems to be coherent, functioning states. In most countries that once belonged to the former Soviet Union and former Yugoslavia, no national state institutions had existed before they began transition. Thus they had to struggle with difficulties of building states from scratch when they became independent. They are still struggling. Throughout much of sub-Saharan Africa, states exist but are largely incoherent, nonfunctional, and instable. Latin American countries fare not much better. They mostly entered their attempted democratic transitions with “a deep legacy of persistently poor performance of state institutions” (Carothers 2002). Elsewhere in the third world, transition away from authoritarian rule often unfolded in the context of extremely weak state structures, which are unable to cope with most of the major problems facing these societies, from crime and corruption control to the provision of basic public services, such as health, education, and social security. Almost all of countries with non-performing states are stuck in the “gray zone”, suffering the syndrome of either “feckless pluralism” or “dominant power politics” (Carothers 2002). Interestingly, it is in those third wave countries where state building did not appear to be a major challenge that democratic progress seems to have made much headway. They are primarily countries in Southern and Central Europe as well as the Baltic region, though there are also a few in South America and East Asia. Examples include Spain, Portugal, Greece, Poland, Hungary, the Czech Republic, Estonia, Slovenia, Uruguay, Chile, Taiwan and South Korea (Linz & Stepan 1996; Carothers 2002). This observation sharply contrasts with a misconception about democratic transition that was prevailing all over the world in the late 1980s and early 1990s. At that time, people normally thought that democracy was associated with minimal government, and that democracy and state therefore were antitheses against each other. Since the state was viewed as an obstacle to political opening, then democratization entailed “destatization.” To increase the survival probability of democracy, it was widely believed, state capacity should be weakened rather than strengthened. As a result, democratizing initiatives in many parts of the world, driven by both domestic reformers and international advocates, often focused primary attention on dismantling the structures of control and reducing the extent of state involvement in the economy and society. Only after a decade of experimentation with “shrinking the state” did a growing number of reformers come to realize the critical importance of having a capable state, not just a minimal one, if democracy were to perform effectively and to be consolidated (Grindle 1997) Similarly, transitology has also taken a detour before rediscovering the state. Initially, studies of third wave democratization largely ignored the role of the state. The focus then was on such questions as what could be done to foster a strong civil society, how to institutionalize competitive election, what form of legislativeexecutive relative was more desirable, etc. The existence of an effective state was either taken for granted or considered inconsequential. As time goes by, however, students of democratization become increasingly aware that in many third wave According to Linz and Stepan (1996), in addition to civil society, other four “interconnected and mutually reinforcing conditions must exist or to be crafted for a democracy to be consolidated,” which include political society, a rule of law, a state bureaucracy, and a economic society. 2 2 Wang Shaoguang State Effectiveness and Democracy countries, something is missing. What is it? “The short answer is: basic institutions of the modern state” (丁学良 2000; Rose & Shin 2001). O’Donnell’s (1992) was among the first to remind us that the progress of democratization is contingent on the institutional viability and the effectiveness of state institutions. Then in the mid-1990s, Przeworski (1995) as well as Linz & Stepan (1996) arrived at the same conclusion that, without an effective state, there can be no democracy. Now more and more scholars agree that the presence of an effective state is a prerequisite for democracy (Rose & Shin 2001; Carothers 2002). That is true especially among those who study Africa (du Toit 1995; Mengisterab & Daddieh 1999) and the states of the former Soviet Union (Holmes 1997; Kuzio, Kravchuk, & D’Anieri 1999; Sperling 2000; Kopecky & Mudde 2000). Although a new consensus has begun to emerge about the imperative of effective state institutions for successful democratic transition and consolidation, the exact linkages between the two has not yet been systematically explored; and therefore many crucial questions remain unanswered. This research is designed to fill out this vacuum. The paper is organized as follows. The Section I tries to reconceptualize democracy. Whiles most define democracy as a type of political regime, the section emphasizes that it is also a form of public authority. As such, it needs to acquire what Michael Mann calls “infrastructural power” (Mann 1993: 59-61). The Section II deals with the concept of state effectiveness. In addition to offer a definition of the state, it attempts to identify the nuts and bolts of an effective modern state. By doing so, the section is intended to provide a framework for comparing state effectiveness across countries. The Section III endeavors to answer the central question of the paper: why democracy can work and last without an effective state. Based upon the insight that an effective state is a prerequisite of a high-quality and sustainable democracy, the Section IV derives six hypotheses concerning conducive or adverse circumstances for democratic transition and consolidation. The final section is a brief summary. The upshot of the arguments presented in this paper is that democracy is unlikely to flourish where it is not based upon a solid infrastructure of state institutions.3 I. Democracy Democracy as a Type of Regime Democracy is one type of political regimes. What distinguishes democracy from various types of non-democratic regimes lies in that democracy enables people to manage power relations and thus control rulers, while others do not (Shapiro 2001).4 The most influential twentieth century approach to the democratic management of power relations is one pioneered by Schumpeter (1942). According to Schumpeter, democracy is an “institutional arrangement for arriving at political decisions in which individuals acquire the power to decide by means of a competitive struggle for the people’s vote” (1942: 269). In such a political system, rulers are held accountable for their actions in the public realm by citizens, not by directly involving in decision-making process, but indirectly through the competition and cooperation of their elected representatives (Schmitter & Karl 1993). 3 The purpose of this study is very modest. Focusing on the relationship between state effectiveness and democracy, it attempts neither to explain why state building is more successful in certain countries than others nor to examine how state capacity can be strengthened. 4 For typology of non-democratic regimes, see Linz & Stepan (1996) and Brooker (2000) 3 Wang Shaoguang State Effectiveness and Democracy As a device for managing power relations, democracy in a minimum must meet two criteria at once, namely, what Dahl calls “inclusiveness” and “public contestation.” The former refers to participation, or more precisely, the right for virtually all adults to vote and contest for office. The latter refers to opposition rights, or creating institutionalized channels for meaningful opposition by those who are adversely affected by government policies. A political system cannot be called democratic unless both inclusive participation and political competition are present. By the end of the eighteenth century, for instance, Britain has already had a highly developed system of public contestation, but only a very small proportion of its population were permitted to take part in political competition. Thus, despite the existence of competitive pluralism, one cannot call the Britain of the nineteenth century a democracy, because one-person-one-vote, which is widely seen as a nonnegotiable requirement of democracy, was absent. Britain did not become a modern political democracy until the early twentieth century when all adult citizens were franchised and “entitled to participated on a more or less equal plane in controlling and contesting the conduct of the government” (Dahl 1971: 4). Almost all the Western democracies have followed this public-contestation-first-and-popular- participationlater path to democracy. Conversely, in some political systems, people are allowed and sometimes required to participate in politics, but are stripped the right to oppose government policies. Such systems are not democratic either, for without meaningful opposition, it is not possible for people to control and contest government behavior. Only when contestation and participation are combined, it is realistic for people to curtail domination. Then the system is qualified to be called democratic. Democracy as a Form of Governance Most scholars define democracy only as a type of regime. We think it is necessary to emphasize that democracy is also a form of governance of a state. Democracy differs from other forms of regimes in its distinctive way of governance, but, as Bagehot (1949:3-4) pointed out, every political system must gain authority and then use authority. In other words, “authority has to exist before it can be limited” (Huntington 1968: 8). If a government cannot perform basic state functions, no matter how democratic its form is, the people of the country would not be able to benefit from it. In this sense, “the issues pertaining to the state are logically prior to those concerning the political regime” (Przeworski 1995: 13). Without an effective state, no democracy is meaningful. (Linz & Stepan 1996: 17). The separation between regime type and state allows us to conceptualize democracy as a compound of democratic institutions and state institutions (Rose & Shin 2001). The former refers to institutions that revolve around four stages of democratic representation: pre-voting, voting, post-voting and inter-election period (Shapiro 2001). More specifically, democratic institutions include bundles of rights and obligations associated with citizenship, methods of organizing interests, electoral system, arrangements of dividing and supervising powers, and so on. The central distinctive task of democratic institutions is to limit power (Przeworski 1995). As for state institutions, we will deal with them in the following section. Suffice it to say here that the main purpose of state institutions is to furnish the government with authority and thereby enable it to govern. In the literature, democratization has often been defined as the process of regime change, which involves the emergence of institutionalized contestation and the expansion of participation in the contestation to groups that have been excluded from political life. The conceptualization of democracy as both a type of regime and a form 4 Wang Shaoguang State Effectiveness and Democracy of governance sheds new light on the real meaning of democratization. From this perspective, democratization consists of two separate processes: a process of transition from a non-democratic regime to a more or less democratic one as well as a process of state building or re-building (Rose, 333). Similarly, the concept of consolidation of democracy needs to be reconsidered. In addition to “routinizing” democratic practice and internalizing democratic values (Linz & Stepan 1996: 5), a consolidated democracy must also be able to effectively govern the full territory over which it claims sovereignty. Thus, state-(re)building should be an indispensable undertaking throughout democratization and consolidation. It is ill advised for third wave countries to damage or weaken essential state capacities during their transition. Wherever and whenever the efficacy of the state is in doubt, a crisis of governance is likely to emerge; if unsettled in due course, the crisis of governance may eventually give rise to the crisis of democracy. II. State Effectiveness Because state effectiveness is so vital to democratic transition and consolidation, we devote the section to examining this topic. What is the state? The state may be defined, in the Weberian sense, as a set of institutions that monopolize the legitimate use of force and rule-making within a given territory. The monopolization of physical force is the very foundation the state’s existence rests, which endows the state with power to make authoritative binding decisions and to perform its other functions.5 Without power, a state cannot be effective. Power, of course, has many faces. Following Mann (1993), we believe it useful to distinguish two types of state power: despotic and infrastructural powers. The former refers to the power state elites can exercise “without routine negotiation with civil society groups” (Mann 1993: 59). State despotic power is measured by its intrusiveness or extensiveness. While such power is broad and sometimes unlimited in non-democratic settings, it is more constrained, albeit in varying degrees, in democratic systems. Infrastructural power, on the other hand, is measured by its effectiveness. According to Mann’s definition, “infrastructural power refers to the capacity of the state actually to penetrate civil society, and to implement logistically political decisions throughout the realm.” (Mann 1986: 114). Infrastructurally most powerful states are found in today’s Western democracies, where the state’s capacity to penetrate everyday life surpass that of any historical or contemporary third world state. States in other times and other places may be intrusive and ruthless, but they often encounter enormous difficulties in penetrating people’s social and economic life. State infrastructural power in Western democracies, however, is so pervasive that their citizens cannot even find “hiding place from the infrastructural reach of the modern state” (Mann 1986: 114). Despotic power and infrastructural power are analytically two independent dimensions of state power. While the former defines the nature of the state (or regime type), the latter conditions state capacity and effectiveness. Democratization by definition will weaken state despotic power, but it would be unwise to bring collateral damage to the infrastructural power of the state in the process. A less intrusive state does not entail a less effective state. One can even argue that democracy probably 5 The monopolization of physical force is of course an ideal assumption. In no country does the state has complete monopoly of the use of force in practice. However, all but a few states have a legitimate monopoly in the sense that most people believe that the state should have a monopoly. 5 Wang Shaoguang State Effectiveness and Democracy needs more infrastructural power to function effectively, efficiently and sustainably than other forms of government. Where state infrastructural power is deficient, efforts must be made to build essential state institutions and capabilities. In the literature about the state, “statebuilding” is often vaguely defined as a process in which the state accumulates power. In our understanding, state building involves accumulating only infrastructural power, not despotic power. The above discussion leads to two fundamental questions of this paper: What specific infrastructural power does a state have to possess to be effective? Why is an effective state a prerequisite of sustainable democracy? Despite growing evidence that state effectiveness underpins democracy, to our knowledge, these questions have not been systematically examined. The rest of this section tries to answer the first question and leaves the second to the next section. Given the broad and growing scope of state activities, state effectiveness obviously is a complex and multidimensional phenomenon. No single index seems able to capture all aspects of state effectiveness. Thus, we need to identity some key state functions and use the state’s capability to perform them to gauge the effectiveness of various states. There are six most critical functions we believe effective states should have capacities to perform (Pye 1966; Binder et al 1971; Grew 1978): 1. To monopolize the legitimate use of violence 2. To extract resources 3. To shape national identity and mobilize consent 4. To regulate the society and economy 5. To maintain internal coherence of state institutions 6. To redistribute resources The first two sets of functions are those that define any state, including premodern states. According to Weber, as long as there were people or groups that used or threatened to use physical force to pursue their interests, political power existed. But the state did not emerge until there was a political organization that was able to monopolize the legitimate use of physical force in the enforcement of its order in a given territory Even pre-modern states were characterized by the creation of regular armies and a taxation system (Weber 1978 I: 54-6). The other four functions are the features of modern nation-state, which add “routine, formalized, rationalized institutions” of wider scope not only over its citizens but also to a very large extent over all actions taking place in the areas of its jurisdiction (Mann 1993: 56). If a state is capable of performing all of those functions well, we call it an effective state. If a state is only capable of performing some of the functions, we call it less effective. When a state is unable to perform any of those functions, it can legitimately be called a failed state. By contrast the distinctive attributes of effective states with those of less effective or totally failed ones, we should be able to identify the essential infrastructural power an effective state must possess. While the particular manifestations of effective states may vary from country to country, they all may share certain basic ingredients. Let’s examine those six state capacities one by one in little detail. The capacity to monopolize the legitimate use of violence By Weber’s definition, the basic test of the existence of a state is whether or not its national government can lay claim to a monopoly of force in the territory under 6 Wang Shaoguang State Effectiveness and Democracy its jurisdiction. Obviously, the monopoly of force is a “means” rather than an “end” for the state. Its end is to encounter external threat to the sovereignty and internal threat to social order. To achieve this goal, all states must build up and deploy armed forces and police forces, with the former primarily to defend against possible foreign invasion and the latter to prevent and punish deviant conduct and repress social unrest. Such institutions are vital to state power. Here we want to emphasize the importance of developing a professional, resourceful, dedicated, disciplined, and uniformed police. Repressive regimes are often called “police states”. This is actually a wrong label. In fact, the ratio of policemen to population is highly correlated with the degree of freedom. Put differently, the ratio tends to be low in so-called “police states,” while it is much high in so-called “free countries” (史天健 2001). Clearly, if the territory of a country is carved up by foreign forces, its government cannot claim to be an effective state (e.g., Palestine). Similarly, if several internal rival groups coexist in a country and all of them possess organized violence, none would be in a position to establish permanent control of the contested territory. Wherever such a situation is present, we may call it “statelessness” (e.g., Afghanistan, and many African countries such as Angola). The capacity to extract resources State monopoly of physical force did not come cheap. In order to do so, states needed to “extract from the population a share of the yearly product of its economic activities” (Poggi 1990: 66). Thus, as early as in the sixteenth century, when the modern nation-state just began to emerge, Jean Bodin already realized, "Financial means are the nerves of the state" (Cited from Kugler & Domke 1986: 45). Not long after, Esmund Burke came to the same conclusion: “The revenue of the state is the state. In effect all depends upon it…” (Cited from Levi 1988: 122). Indeed, just like a human being cannot be alive without blood, a state cannot function without revenue. It is the availability of resources that permits the state to carry out its other tasks. In this sense, an effective government has to be fiscally viable. More specifically, a state that is unable to generate sufficient resources for realizing its policy goals cannot be effective. In contrast, a political system must be effective if it can extract sufficient resources from the society, aggregate those resources into a national pool, and use them for national purposes. In the last century or so, the scope of state operation has expanded considerably. To finance bigger governments, states need to explore more productive extractive devices. In the past, states raised revenue mainly through such mechanisms as military or colonial ventures, the sale of offices, tax farming, monopolies, donations, and even drawing on state elites’ private wealth (Poggi 1978, 97). Now, “the regular, unobtrusive levying of taxes on various phases and aspects of the modernized economic process” has largely replaced those less efficient instruments (Poggi 1990, 66). As a result, in Western democracies, government spending typically increased by three- to five-fold, if not more, in the twentieth century (Poggi 1990: 109-110). At present, it commonly accounts for one-third to a half of the gross domestic products (GDP) in those countries. And people in the West have become more or less used to a strong extractive state. Elsewhere, state extractive capacity varies greatly from country to country and generally is much weaker. In the 1950s, after conducting several case studies in the third world, Nicholas Kaldor, a British economist, came to the conclusion that there were no inherent obstacles to raising the rate of government financial extraction. For a 7 Wang Shaoguang State Effectiveness and Democracy variety of reasons, however, few developing countries followed his prescriptions (Waldner 1999: 45). What started in the West centuries ago thus has barely been underway in much of the third world. The capacity to shape national identity and mobilize consent Backed by extractive capacity, coercive capacity is the most basic aspect of state power. But it would be extremely costly to maintain domestic peace by coercion alone. For any political system to operate effectively, there must exist some shared identities and shared values. This is especially true in diverse societies. Let’s first deal with the necessity of national identity. In the early phases of state development in the West, and in the third world today, the state is one among many autonomous power centers (families, villages, localities, ethnic groups, religious organizations, and governments) that compete for people’s loyalty. Thus, the construction of state coercive and extractive capacities must be followed by rationalization of authority and nation building. The former refers to the centralization of political power, involving the replacement of traditional familial, local, religious, and ethnic authorities by a single, secular, national authority (Huntington 1966). The latter means “internal homogenization” (Tilly 1975: 661), involving the transformation of “peoples’ commitment and loyalty from smaller tribes, villages, or petty principalities to the larger central political system, creating a common national culture of loyalty and commitment” (Almond & Powell 1966: 36). The formation of national identity is very important. The breakup of the Soviet Union, Yugoslavia, and Czechoslovakia and ethnic conflicts in Indonesia, Sri Lanka, and many African countries vividly demonstrate that the absence of national identity could be a powerful centrifugal force. When a significant proportion of the population perceive themselves distinct ethnically, culturally, linguistically, or religiously from other people who live within the same boundaries, they may be motivated to create their independent states or join other states. It is true that multiethnic and multicultural states normally have greater difficulties in winning and maintaining the allegiance of diverse population. But this observation should not lead us to the conclusion that ethnic, cultural, religious or linguistic identity is primordially given and thereby any effort to shape a national identity in such diverse societies is doomed to failure. In fact, almost all nations started out as very diverse culturally, linguistically, religiously or ethnically. The presence of a strong national identity in some but not all countries implies that identity is amendable. All states have a tendency to assimilate populations within a given territory into a single nation through education and other socialization channels.6 Thus the formation of national identity is best understood as an outcome of purposeful state efforts to overcome heterogeneity in the society, although some exogenous historical accidents may also affect the outcome. If a society is fragmented where opportunistic politicians can use the strategy of exacerbating minuscule differences to pursue their personal interests, “it is more likely a consequence of institutional failure rather than a cause of it” (Przeworski et al 1995: 21). In addition to shaping national identity, the state also endeavors to shape its citizens’ values and beliefs. By doing this, it hopes to further reduce the costs of ruling. Emile Durkheim put a great deal of emphasis on the existence of a common set of values and beliefs in any society. He contends that only when most members of a 6 For the example of France, see Weber (1976). 8 Wang Shaoguang State Effectiveness and Democracy society share such a set of core values, moral unity could be retained. Without moral unity, any system would degenerate sooner or later (Durkheim 1951). (Ritzen) This goal of anchoring people in a common set of core values can be achieved through a range of strategies. Where people’s values and beliefs happen to be congruent or consonant with the state’s preferences, the state is inclined to reinforce societal convergence, deference, and indifference to forestall the emergence of values and attitudes that diverge from the state’s. Where state and societal preferences do diverge, the state may use various tactics to change societal values and beliefs to make them congruent or consonant with its own (Nordlinger 1981: 74-117). Moreover, every state strives to inculcate certain values and beliefs upon children so as to make these future citizens more obedient and more disciplined (Creveld 1999: 210-17) Once state instilled values and symbols become widely shared, largely unquestioned values and symbols in a society, it is easy for the state to wrap up authoritative actions with these values and symbols. Then citizens may feel obligated to comply with state policies (Poggi 1978: 101). Wherever states are unable to mold national identity and to implant in the masses official value systems, they are unlikely to be effective, because a great deal more resources and energy would have to be diverted to fighting against centrifugal forces, subduing nonconforming ideas, and cracking down defiant behaviors. The capacity to regulate the society and economy The regulative capacity is defined as the ability of the state to change and subordinate behavior of individuals and groups away from their own inclination and in favor of the behavior prescribed by the state. While the capacity to mobilize consent concerns people’s internal convictions, the regulative capacity deals with people’s external behavior. Regulations are necessary because modern societies are full of hazards engendered from industrialization, commercialization, urbanization, and asymmetrical distribution of power and information. To protect people and the nature, the state needs to regulate not only such clearly deviant social activities as murder and assault, but also many aspects of economic and social life, including, among other things, weights and measures, contract, industrial R&D, road construction, public utility services, food and drug quality, garbage collection, mail delivery, labor-management relations, working conditions, safety standards, the relief of destitution, consumer protection, the protection of the environment and natural resources, health, education, sports, marriage, the promotion of the arts, and even parental responsibility. It is by no means easy for the state to regulate the society and economy. To facilitate effective regulation, for instance, the state must collect and store a massive amount of information about everyone living and working in the country.7 In developed countries, this is not a problem. Birth, schooling, marriage, divorce, occupation, income, ownership of house and automobile, honor, misconduct, exit from and entry into the country, and death are all constantly under state watch. Nothing seems to be able to escape state screening. In the developing world, however, even statistics on such basic items as population size and distribution are often deficient, not to mention information about mobile tax bases or practices of food handling. For countries that are not capable of monitoring the whereabouts and Emerged just before 1800 in English and all European languages, the word “statistics” means data pertaining to the state (Mann 1993: 361). 7 9 Wang Shaoguang State Effectiveness and Democracy behaviors of their populations, it is unrealistic to expect their states to possess much regulative capacity. Since the rise of “regulatory state” in the West in the first half of the twentieth century, there have been complaints about the growing power of the state. The complaint is mainly leveled against the state’s regulatory encroachment into “a much expanded and differentiated range of social [and economic] activities” (Poggi 1990: 109). However, no one can deny a simple fact that, in today’s world, all those wellordered societies, whether democratic (e.g., Norway) or not (e.g., Singapore), are highly regulated. Where governments lack adequate regulative capacity, again whether democratic (e.g., India) or not (e.g., Egypt), people there typically have to put up with frequent industrial accidents and environmental disasters, untreated water, broken draining system, chaotic traffic, appalling work conditions, tense labormanagement relations, shoddy consumer products, horrendous medical services, and the like. The contrast between the two types of countries clearly points to the significance of regulative capacity for any modern state. The capacity to maintain internal coherence of state institutions To modernize and broaden the collection of taxes, to shape national identity, to inculcate official ideology into citizens, to control for negative externalities of the market, to coordinate economic actors’ behavior, to improve people’s quality of life, to structure social conflicts, and to maintain order and a rule of law, the state must be backed up by a an effective bureaucracy. “The vast bureaucratic structure of modern states with their tens of thousands of officials make them the core of modern government” (Friedrich 1963: 464). As an instrument of execution of the authoritative decisions of the government, the bureaucracy must be professionalized and meritocratic so that its recruits have technical talent and requisite training to be competent for tasks assigned to them. But, just as important from the perspective of the state is an ability for it to maintain internal coherence of bureaucratic institutions. The modern bureaucracy is a complex and sophisticated organization made up of multiple, minute organs. Though all the activities of the bureaucracy are supposed to be ultimately sanctioned by and directed from a single center, there is a danger of the coherence of the system being undercut by the inertia and departmentism of bureaucratic agencies and the particularism and corruption of individual bureaucrats. It is often the case that political executives’ policy-making efforts are thwarted by the bureaucracy not so much because it intends deliberately to sabotage those political leaders as because large organizations tend to proceed from inertia and to persist in their routine unless stopped. In addition, bureaucrats and their organizations tend to believe that they understand the policy area in question better than the political executives (Peters 1987). A more acute problem with bureaucracy, however, is that each agency “seeks to maximize the state resources it commands, and to assign priority to its own concerns over all others” (Poggi 1990: 30-1). This kind of desire may motivate bureaucratic agencies intentionally to hinder or block the collection of vital information for centralized decision making and to involve in pointless competition against each other. As a result, the ultimate authority of the state may find it difficult, if not impossible, to enforce its policy agenda and to prevent its agents from deserting their strictly implementary role. The corporate coherence of the state then becomes the casualty of “bureaucratic free enterprise” (Tullock 1965) 10 Wang Shaoguang State Effectiveness and Democracy The most detrimental problem with the bureaucracy, especially among third world countries, is particularism and corruption, namely, officials using their offices to favors their relatives and friends or to maximize their personal wealth, power, and status. Rather than dehumanize administrative process as expected by Max Weber (1946: 215-16), officials who practice particularism allow love, hatred, and other personal elements to affect their decisions made in the name of the state. Corrupt officials also give preferentiality to people related to them in the execution of state directives, but not out of emotion, but out of careful calculation of potential gains and risks (Ackerman 1999). Despite the difference in motive, both particularism and corruption impair the impartiality of public administration, breed a distrust of public authorities, set off political alienation, and, in extreme case, may even lead to system breakdowns (Klitgaard 1988). An well-functioning state is supposed to operate as a machine in which the wheels and gears are precisely adjusted to one another, a machine “propelled by energy and directed by information flowing from a single center in the service of a plurality of coordinated tasks”(Poggi 1978: 98). In large part, the ability of a state to accomplish its goals is a function of the coherence of its political institutions. Where government institutions do not mesh with each other and particularism and corruption are rampant, intrastate and state-society conflicts are bound to increase, thus undercutting the ability of the whole system to control the flow of tax resources and to achieve other policy goals. The capacity to distribute resources The distributive capacity refers to the authoritative redistribution of scarce resources between difference social groups. This is a relative new measure of state effectiveness that did not take form until the advent of the welfare state in the West in the late nineteenth century and early twentieth century. The purpose of redistribution is to provide the least fortunate members of the society with economic security as well as to reduce inequality in income and wealth distribution. Urbanization, higher literacy levels, the demonstration effect of the Western welfare states have all increased the volume and intensity of pressures for the state to use its coercive power to redistribute income, wealth and opportunity worldwide. Even in many developing countries, people now expect their governments to mitigate social risks and narrow the gaps between the “haves” and “have not” through some forms of redistribution. Some contends that since the welfare state is primarily a Western luxury that only rich countries can afford, the effectiveness of a state should not be measured by its distributive capacity (Gros 1996). To the extent that inequality often increases the probability of political instability (Alesina, Ozler, Roubini & Swagel 1996; Alesina & Perotti 1996), the distributive capacity in effect is one that helps to maintain domestic public order and enhance its legitimacy. Given the importance of public order and legitimacy for any regime, the instrumental value of redistribution should not be underestimated. In summary, an effective state is defined by its ability to defend its sovereignty and territory, to exert coercive control over the population, to tax compulsorily, to inculcate a sense of common identity, to regulate human activities in economic and social realms, and last but not least, to centrally coordinate its agencies and agents so as to interlock them into a unitary whole. Clearly, these state capacities are 11 Wang Shaoguang State Effectiveness and Democracy interdependent to each other. Developing and integrating these capacities is essential for any state to become effective. 8 Why is an Effective State a Prerequisite of Sustainable Democracy? Having defined both “democracy” and “state effectiveness,” we now turn to the relationship between the two. There may be a wide range of necessary conditions for democracy to work and last. We argue that the existence of an effective state is one of those necessary conditions, and probably the most important one. Without an effective state, there can be no democracy. This point, of course, is by no means novel. Several scholars have called attention to the role of the state in recent years (O’Donnell 1992; Przeworski 1995; Linz & Stepan 1996, Rose & Shin 2001). What we would like to add to the literature is to provide theoretic explanations about how the operation of democracy is contingent on the viability and the effectiveness of state institutions. For a democracy to work and last, there must exist an effective state that is capable of performing the following tasks. To define the political community within which democracy operates Democracy can be simply defined as rule by the people. But, who are the people? Obviously, the concept of the people does not mean everyone in the world. No country, no matter how democratic it is, allows foreigners, including those who obtain legal residence, to vote. Rather, only adult citizens have the right to do so. Then, who are citizens? Webster’s Encyclopedic Unabridged Dictionary defines “citizen” as “a native or naturalized member of a state or nation who owns allegiance to its government and is entitled to its protection.” Thus, “without a state, there can be no citizenship; without citizenship, there can be no democracy” (Linz & Stepan 1996: 28). Indeed, a democracy presupposes a well-defined territorial-social unit, for, as pointed out by Robert Dahl, democratic methods “cannot solve the problem of the proper scope and domain of democratic units” (Dahl 1989: 207). The majority principle, for instance, would not work unless we know exactly the boundary of the whole political community. We call such community a “territorial-social unit,” because it is not purely territorial; its rightfulness has to be accepted by the people. Perhaps, the word “accepted” is not strong enough. Dankwart Rustow is more to the point when he argues that what is actually required is a “prior sense of community, preferably a sense of community quietly taken for granted that is above mere opinion and mere agreement” (1970: 350). Only when the vast majority of citizens “have no doubt or mental reservations as to which political community they belong to” (Rustow 1970: 351) then it is possible for them to organize their life in a democratic fashion. Conversely, if large segments of the population in a territorial-social unit refuse to accept the unit as an appropriate entity to make legitimate decisions, and desire to create their independent states or to merge with other states, then unit faces a serious “stateness” problem (Linz and Stepan 1996). Under such a circumstance, democratic procedure can neither work nor solve the problem of identity. Here the key challenge is to cultivate a strong identification with the territorial-social unit. In 8 There are many reasons why in many territories of the world no such state exists. But it is an issue that we cannot cover in this short essay. The focus of this paper, as stated before, is on the relationship between state effectiveness and democracy. 12 Wang Shaoguang State Effectiveness and Democracy Western Europe, the process of nation building was generally guided by coercive governments, which used a wide range of instruments to repress and eliminate multilingualism and multiculturalism in their territories. Those methods are not acceptable by today’s moral standards. Nevertheless the resultant nation-states had defined the political communities within which democratization could take place later (Linz & Stepan 1996: 33-33). The lesson from the first wave of democratization is that state and nation building should precede democratization and that the existence of a viable nation-state is a prerequisite for a modern democracy. To protect citizens’ basic rights For democracy to exist, all full citizens must enjoy such basic civil rights as freedom to form and join organizations, freedom of expression, right to vote, the right to a fair trial, etc. But, “the conditions necessary to exercise them are not automatically generated by the mere existence of democratic institutions; a viable state is necessary to make their exercise possible” (Przeworski 1995: 12). During the Cold War era and soon after, when all political evils seemed to stem from "too much government," the state was often regarded as the biggest threat to civil liberty. Political rights then were primarily understood as “negative rights,” as "walls" erected against state power, or as shields used to protect vulnerable individuals from abusive governments. It was widely believed that only by limiting the power of the state could personal liberties be secured. By now, however, the inadequacy of this notion of rights has become evident, because people in Russia and many other transition countries still cannot enjoy much real liberties even after dictatorship ended, official indoctrination disappeared, new political parties sprung up like mushrooms, dissidents were released from jails, and censorship was removed. The governments in those countries were simply too disorganized and too week to enforce their own laws. What happen in those countries makes excruciatingly clear that liberties could be threatened just as thoroughly by state incapacity as by repressive state apparatus. This observation leads Stephen Holmes (1997) to conclude, “liberal rights depend essentially on the competent exercise of a certain kind of legitimate public power.” Why individual liberty depends on some sort of state power? The reason behind this is that only in a society composed of angels where power resources were equally distributed could its member enjoy liberties without the presence of public authorities. The problem is that this kind of society exists only in our dream. In the real world, “individuals are partial to themselves and, left to their own devices, the strong and the deceitful have an irresistible proclivity to exempt themselves from generally valid laws.” Therefore, “without a well-functioning public power of a certain kind there will be no prevention of mutual harm, no personal security…” (Holmes 1997). In this sense, the distinction between “negative” and “positive” rights is a false dichotomy. No right is simply a right to be left alone by public authorities. Defined by law, all rights amount to entitlements that require governmental authorities to deliver rather than merely to forbear (Holmes 1999). State power is needed to guard property rights, to prevent harm, to repress force, to contain fraud, and above all, to extend its protection to the vulnerable. Viewed from this angle, rather than a threat to personal freedoms, a liberal state is “the largest and most reliable human rights organization” (Holmes 1997). A liberal state, of course, must be limited in many ways, but to enforce and protect citizens’ rights, a liberal state must be able to exercise effectively its claim to the monopoly of the legitimate use of force 13 Wang Shaoguang State Effectiveness and Democracy in the territory and to mobilize sufficient resources (Holmes 1999). “For this reason, a non-performing state cannot be a liberal state” (Holmes 1997). To create and maintain a rule-based polity “Rule of law” means the predominance of law over discretionary authority. A state based on the rule of law is not necessarily democratic (e.g., Singapore), but a high-quality democracy must be ruled by law rather than by arbitrary decisions of a ruler or his agents (Rose & Shin 2001). In a democracy, laws constitute not only a tool to control the masses but also an instrument to constrain officials and bureaucrats. In essence, laws are rules governing human behavior in a given society. Democracy is a rule intensive polity. In addition to the legal provision of civil rights, there must be rules with regard to citizenship, election, distribution of power, relationship between different branches of government, etc. The guidance provided by those rules enables political actors to coordinate their behavior, thus helping reduce uncertainty and create order in human interactions. Without rules, it is hard to imagine how democracy can function. For rules to be effective in guiding actors' future courses of action, they must have the following three characteristics. (1) Rules should clear so that proper interpretation is possible, general so that like case are treated alike, inclusive so that no one may avail herself of loopholes, and non-contingent so that nothing can excuse rule-breakers. (2) Rules are ex ante restrictions that bind the ex post behavior of all parties. The purpose of rules is to define the way the game is played. Therefore, no one in the game should be allowed unilaterally to change these rules after the fact. Political actors' incentives are often not time-consistent. They may have incentive to accept certain rules in principle; but when the situation changes, it may become tempting for them to revise the rules. For rules to be effective, they have to be able to restrain the ex post behavior of all parties. (3) Rules must be enforced in such ways that ensure compliance. Although rules can be self-enforcing when it is in everybody's interests to live up to these rules, another method to ensure compliance seems to be more important in most cases: the threat of external sanction. Only with enforcement of sanction against offenders can rules be sustainable (Wang forthcoming). When rules meet the above criteria in a political system, we may call it highly institutionalized. Only when a state is highly institutionalized can democratic procedures be constraining. In contrast, if rules (particularly those defining the scope and limits of power) are vague, unbinding, and not supported by a credible enforcement mechanism, they work at best as a soft source of constraint on political actors' options. There would be a considerable gap between the formal rules of the game and widely accepted informal practices, and ex-ante procedures would not matter that much. In such a context, democracy cannot operate properly because those in power have too much discretion, while others lack effective means to restrain them. When those in power retain widespread discretion in interpreting and applying rules (laws), they could effectively turn the rules into a controlling mechanism against the general public. Consequently, the accountability of the state would be low. In this sense, a polity lacking the rule of law is not compatible with democracy. To vitalize civil society The last two decades of the twentieth century witness the revival of the concept of civil society. Many believed that civil society played a crucial role, if not the leading role, in fostering, deepening, and consolidating democracy. How does civil society promote democratic transition and consolidation? Citing from 14 Wang Shaoguang State Effectiveness and Democracy Huntington, Larry Diamond’s explanation is brief yet to the point (Diamond 1999: 239): “The first and most basic democratic function of civil society is to provide ‘the basis for the limitation of state power, hence for the control of the state by society, and hence for democratic political institutions as the most effective means of exercising that control.’ After the transition, this involves checking, monitoring, and restraining the exercise of power by formally democratic states and holding them accountable to the law and public expectations of responsible government.” If the 1980s and early 1990s was a decade of romantic adoration of civil society, more recent years have become a time of reflection (Diamond 1994b; Foley & Edward; Berman 1997; Verba, Schlozman & Brady 1997; Rieff 1999; Carothers 1999). While still treasuring the potential positive value of civil society for democracy, people now come to realize that, on the one hand, civil society is by no means a paradise epitomized by harmony, 9 and on the other hand, the state-society relationship is far more intricate than unrefined civil society theorists tend to believe. For the purpose of this paper, we focus on the latter reflection. Today, even some of those most convinced of the indispensable role of civil society agree that the relationship between the state and civil society is one of "mutual empowerment" or "synergy," rather than a zero-sum one (Evans 1997). The two are interrelated in many ways: 1. At best, civil society can act as a counter weight to the leviathan of state power. But it can never provide a substitute for the organized public institutions of the state. 2. When civil society acts as a counter weight to state power, it should check and limit the despotic but not infrastructural power of the state. 3. It makes sense for civil society to aim the state as an object of its efforts only when the state is an effective one. If the state is incapable of solving any economic and social problems, there is no point of dealing with it. 4. Only robust state institutions can provide an arena in which civil society can operate (Motyl 1993). A growing body of recent works suggests that an effective state is a prerequisite to civil society. Crisis of the state more often than not leads to a degeneration of civil society rather than its revival. Conversely, when the state is relatively strong and resilient, civil society is more likely to thrive (O’Donnell 1993; Chazan 1994; Shue 1994). This is so because “just as modern markets depend on economic decisions being nested in a predictable institutional framework, likewise ‘civic engagement’ flourishes more easily among private citizens and organized groups when they have a competent public sector as an interlocutor” (Evans 1997). 5. Civil society can improve the ability of the state to govern. When civil society and the state both are relative strong, the vibrancy of the former itself may make citizens more respectful and hence obedient to the latter (Diamond 1994b). In Putnam’s words, "civic associations are powerfully 9 Civil society consists good as well as bad actors. Some may work at high-minded aims, but most are simply single-issue groups that are preoccupied with the pursuit of parochial self-interests. The proliferation of the latter “could choke the workings of representative institutions and systematically distort policy outcomes in favor of the rich and well-connected or, more simply, the better organized” (Carothers 1999). Moreover, when institutional environments are unfavorable, a strong civil society cannot even save existing democracies, not to mention bringing about or helping consolidate new democracies (Berman 1997). 15 Wang Shaoguang State Effectiveness and Democracy associated with effective public institutions…strong society, strong state" (1993: 176). If the above remarks are right, one may conclude as Evans does, “a sustained efflorescence of civil society may well depend on the simultaneous construction of robust, competent organizational counterparts within the state…[A] move toward less capable and involved states will make it more difficult for civic associations to achieve their goals, thereby diminishing incentives for civic engagement. (Evans 1997) To meet peoples’ basic demands For three reasons, democracy, especially a premature one, has to deliver some basic public goods and services in order to survive. First, many people embrace democracy not for the sake of democracy but as a solution for the crisis their country faces, including political as well as social and economic crises. Second, democratization is likely to heighten political and social citizenship, which may give rise to the pressure for uniformity of treatment, the reduction of social risks, higher living standards, better quality of life, and greater degree of equality. Third, democracy itself offers people more freedoms, opportunities, and power to push for policy changes. To make the society a humane one, for instance, a democratic system must be able to regulate the market so as to eliminate, or at least limit, the damage the market may bring about. As Robert Dahl notes, “Democracy would almost certainly lead to the destruction of certain economic orders… [including] a strictly free market economy” (1993). Otherwise, unregulated markets will unavoidably generate unfairness and chaos, which in turn may weaken the political support of the regime. Moreover, in societies characterized by severe inequality, a democratic government needs make efforts to more or less narrow the gap between the “haves” and the “have nots” via some sorts of redistribution. As a matter of fact, all matured democracies have established elaborate systems of social welfare to make their societies more coherent. When a democracy fails to ensure basic economic security for large segments of the population, it will become politically very fragile. Regulation and redistribution are just two examples. More generally, if a democratic system proves unable to provide such essential public goods and services as external security, domestic order, justice, basic education, prevention of epidemic diseases, some compensations for those hurt by market swings, and some alleviation of gross inequality, its poor performance will make people increasingly more frustrated, thus eventually leading to legitimacy crisis and probably the breakdown of democracy (Linz & Stepan 1996: 12-13).10 This danger tends to increase as a brief “honeymoon period” of democratization passes and “the memories of authoritarian failure fade” (Huntington 1993: 10)11 Only a state with strong capacities is able to perform well in generating social well being. Coupled with democratic institutions, it should also be willing to satisfy people’s demands. That is why both Linz & Stepan (1996) and Pzeworski (1995) consider the efficacy and effectiveness of the state is the key to democratic legitimacy and stability. 10 Weil (1989), however, argues that poor state performance may lead to a crisis of confidence, but it is unlikely to lead to a legitimation crisis or a rejection of democracy. 11 Pierre Du Toit (2001) noted, “At the end of South Africa's ‘miracle transition’ in 1994, carried along by the momentum of positive thinking, we tended to be optimistic about the prospects of democratic consolidation. Since then, however, much appears to have gone wrong, and a lot of this has to do with the performance of state institutions, especially those engaged in delivering public safety.” 16 Wang Shaoguang State Effectiveness and Democracy In summary, if a democracy is to work and last, the state must be able to define the community in which it operates, to protect citizens’ basic rights, to create and maintain a rule-based polity, to vitalize civil society, and to meet peoples’ basic demands. Only an effective state can perform those tasks. Without these capacities, there can be no democratic governance. How Does State Effectiveness Affect Democratic Consolidation? Based upon the insight that an effective state is a prerequisite of sustainable democracy, we intend in this section to derive some propositions concerning conducive or adverse circumstances for democratic consolidation.12 Most of them have been put forward by others before, but their underlying assumptions and logics are not necessarily identical with mine. For us, the key intervening variable that affects the outcome of democratic consolidation is the degree of state effectiveness measured by the six capacities discussed in the Section II. The higher the degree of state effectiveness is, the less difficult the democratic consolidation becomes. Conversely, for whatever reason, where state infrastuctural power is deficient, democracy is less likely to function well and survive. Of course, state effectiveness is merely one of necessary conditions for democratic consolidation, not a sufficient condition, for an effective state may or may not be a democratic one. Proposition 1: There may not be any specific preconditions for democratization, but an effective state is a prerequisite to democratic consolidation. The third wave demonstrates that democratization can occur anywhere, including such “the most unlikely and unexpected places” as Mongolia, Albania, and Mauritania, but consolidated and stable democracies are much harder to find because many of third wave countries do not have effective governments (Carothers 2002). Proposition 2: Democratic consolidation is more likely to be successful where state and regime was distinguished from one another under the old regime. This is so because the previous regime types may define the characters of state institutions. Under certain types of regimes (e.g., the sultanistic regime, the regime ruled by a strongman or a hegemonic party), there are in effect no distinction between the regime and state. Consequently, when democratization begins, the state apparatus are likely to collapse along with the old regime. The statelessness gives rise to a large number of difficult challenges that newly democratizing country has to face, which in turn makes democratic consolidation extremely difficult, if not entirely impossible. The regime under the Shah’s rule in Iran was an example (Fishman 1990; Shain & Linz 1995). Proposition 3: The more disruptive the transition process is, the more difficult it is to consolidate democracy. The type of transition that hurts state capacity least is more likely to produce consolidated democracy. Transition may be initiated by reformist incumbents of the old regime or by opposition forces. The form of transition may be gradual and peaceful or radical and violent. As far as democratic consolidation is concerned, incumbent-initiated transition (Spain, Korea, and Taiwan) are preferable to an 12 Limited by space, we are unable to test these propositions even in the most rudimentary way. 17 Wang Shaoguang State Effectiveness and Democracy opposition-led transitions (the Philippines); orderly and peaceful transitions are preferable (the former Czechoslovak) to ones preceded by revolutionary wars, ethnic wars, or widespread riots (Indonesia). Put differently, where a state remains intact during the process of regime transition, it may help the new regime to consolidate; where transition undermines state cohesion and institutional hierarchy, it is more difficult for the new regime to consolidate (Di Palma 1990; Fishman 1990; Shain & Linz 1995). Proposition 4: The more heterogeneous a society is, the more difficult it is to consolidate democracy. It is far more difficult to consolidate democracy in multiethnic and multicultural societies than in homogeneous societies. As Huntington points out, “the more complex and heterogeneous the society, the more the achievement and maintenance of political community become dependent upon the working of political institutions” (Huntington 1968: 9). Thus, state-building challenges tend to be more acute in a multiethnic and multicultural society than in a society where all people consider themselves as members of the same community. When state building is not very successful, what J.S. Mill calls “fellow-feeling” (1958: 230) would be absent among the people. When a large proportion of the population do not want to be part of the community upon which the state is founded, the issue of crafting democratic norms, practices, and institutions becomes secondary to what Linz & Stepan call “the problem of stateness” (1996). The presence of the stateness problem may damage the prospects of democratic consolidation in two ways. First, to solve the stateness problem, the new democratizing regime would have to make great effort in nurturing national identity, which will inevitably divert tremendous amounts of scarce resources and precious energy from its effort to consolidate democracy (Kuzio et al. 1999, 6-7). Second, “some ways of dealing with the problems of stateness are inherently incompatible with democracy” (1996: 29).13 Proposition 5: The larger state size is, the more difficult it is to consolidate democracy. This proposition is partially related with the last. A large population is statistically more heterogeneous: The larger a society, the more likely it encompasses many religious, racial, ethnic, and linguistic groupings, which increases the difficulty of governance. In addition to the heterogeneity problem, larger countries are also likely to encounter considerable problems of vertical integration and horizontal coordination, which further lowers the effectiveness of the state. Indeed, there is empirical evidence suggesting that the quality of governance is correlated with the size of the country (Treisman 2000). As a result, it is much harder for larger democracies to consolidate.14 13 Dahl’s 1971 study confirmed that the higher degree of subcultural pluralism, the less likely a political system is to be democratic or nearly so. Among the 114 polities he studied, 58% with a low degree of subcultural pluralism, 36% with moderate pluralism, and only 15% with market pluralism were polyarchies, or near-polyarchies (1971: 110-111). 14 Dahl & Tufte (1973) and Diamond (1999: 117-160) find significantly greater incidence [of stable democracy] in very small countries. Another study discovers that the predicated probability of being democratic is much higher in small than large countries. Interestingly, if a country is both small and an island, the predicated probability for it to be a democracy is even higher (Ott 1995). This makes sense because it is relatively easy to govern a small island that is protected by a nature from foreign invasion. Perhaps, we should put forward a related proposition: In those countries that face less challenges to their governance capabilities, it is easier to develop and consolidate democratic regime. 18 Wang Shaoguang State Effectiveness and Democracy Proposition 6: Stable democracy is more likely to appear in old than in new states. The longer time a country has existed, the more likely it has been successful in crafting state loyalty. On the contrary, new states are very likely to run into the challenges of nation building, unless only one nation with nearly cultural uniformity exists in each of them. Such perfect congruence between the nation and the state is rare among newly independent countries, especially those in Africa. It would be logically and empirically impossible for a new state to consolidate democracy before it solves the problem of national identity. If the priority were given to nation-building, however, at least for the time being, either democracy would not emerge at all, or it emerges but would not be stable (Linz & Stepan 1996). Even if the new state chooses to pursue democratization and nation-state at once, its chance to consolidate democracy would be smaller than its older counterpart, because the former confronts simultaneously the problems that the latter may enjoy the luxury of solving sequentially over fairly long historical periods (Huntington 1968: 397-397). This explains why the most stable democracies in today’s world are still those that emerged from the first wave of democratization. Implications The central argument of this essay is that, without an effective state, there can be no stable democracy. If our basic points are right, then it would be suicidal for democratic reformers intentionally or unintentionally to undermine or weaken state institutions in the process of democratization, especially in those countries where states are nonexistent or extremely weak to begin with. Of course, during the democratic transition, the ways state power being exercised must change, but state power itself should not be enfeebled Rather than single-mindedly trying to restrain state power, democratic reformers should make more efforts to build national state institutions where none existed before, and to strengthen state capacities where they are weak. There are three additional reasons for democratic reformers to pay more attention to the issue of state building when studying democratic transition and consolidation. First, where state effectiveness—a precondition of stable democracy— is lacking, it cannot be supplied through the practice of democracy itself (Emerson 1966: 7). Specific efforts must be made to strengthen state capacities. Second, the democratic regime probably needs a more effective state as its foundation than other types of regime, because it allows more social forces to take part in political competition. While non-democratic regimes may be able to survive with low levels of state building, a functioning and stable democracy is possible only in the presence of a set of effective state institutions. Otherwise it cannot meet the new challenges set off by liberalization and democratization. Finally, democratization may unleash forces that are likely to put enormous pressures on the system. For instance, the breakdown of authoritarianism may trigger territorial disintegration; popular respect for government may plummet in a new political environment; rising expectations may overload the government, exceeding its capacity to respond; the demise of the previously dominant party may leave both the state and society disorganized, thus creating institutional vacuum; and pressures for greater uniformity (a result of expended citizenship) may expose regional, ethnic, class, and religious differences previously obscured and to stimulate resistance (Przeworski 1995). 19 Wang Shaoguang State Effectiveness and Democracy Bibliography 丁学良. 2000. “转型社会的法与秩序:俄罗斯现象”《清华社会学评论》第二 期。 史天健. 2001. “国家建设与民主化: 对于一些基本理论问题的探讨” 未刊稿。 Ackerman, Susan Rose. 1999. Corruption and Government. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Alesina, Alberto, Sule Ozler, Nouriel Roubini, and Philip Swagel. 1996. "Political Instability and Economic Growth." Journal of Economic Growth, Vol. 1 (June). Alesina, Alberto and Roberto Perotti. 1996. “Income Distribution, Political Instability, and Investment.” European Economic Review 40: 1203-28. Anderson, Benedict R. O'G. 1983. Imagined communities: reflections on the origin and spread of nationalism. London: Verso. Almond, Gabriel and G. Bingham Powell, Jr. 1966. Comparative Politics: A Developmental Approach. Boston: Little, Brown and Company. Almond, Gabriel and Sidney Verba. 1963. The Civic Culture: Political Attitudes and Democracy in Five Nations. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Bagehot, Walter. 1949. The English Constitution. London: Oxford-World’s Classics. Barro, Robert. 1999. “Determinants of Democracy.” The Journal of Political Economy, Vol. 107, No. 6: 158-183. Berman, MicSheri. 1997. "Civil Society and the Collapse of the Weimar Republic." World Politics, (April). Binder, Leonard, James S. Coleman, Joseph LaPalombara, Lucian W. Pye, Sidney Verba, and Myron Weiner. 1971. Crisis and Sequences in Political Development. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Brooker, Paul. 2000. Non-Democratic Regimes: Theory, Government & Politics. New York: St. Martin Press. Burkhart, Ross E. and Michael S. Lewis-Beck. 1994. "Comparative Democracy: The Economic Development Thesis." American Political Science Review 88 (1994):903-10. Carothers, Thomas. 1999. “Think Again: Civil Society.” Foreign Policy (Winter). -----. 2002. “The End of the Transition Paradigm.” Journal of Democracy 13.1: 5-21. Chazan, Naomi. 1994. "Engaging the State: Associational Life in Sub-saharan Africa." In Joel Migdal, Atul Kohli and Vivienne Shue (eds.), State Power and Social Forces: Domination and Transformation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 255-289. Collier, David and Steven Levitsky. 1997. "Democracy with Adjectives: Conceptual Innovation in Comparative Research," World Politics 49 (April 1997): 430-51. Creveld, Martin van. 1999. The Rise and Decline of the State. Cambridge; Cambridge University Press. Dahl, Robert A. 1989. Democracy and Its Critics. New Haven, CT.: Yale University Press. -----. 1993. “Why All Democratic Countries Have Mixed Economies?” In John Chapman and Ian Shapiro, eds., Democratic Community. New York: New York University Press, pp. 259-82. Dahl, Robert A and Edward R. Tufte. 1973. Size and Democracy. Stanford: Stanford University Press. Deutsch, Karl W. 1961. "Social Mobilization and Political Development." American Political Science Review 55 (1961):493-514. 20 Wang Shaoguang State Effectiveness and Democracy Di Palma, Giuseppe. 1990. To Craft Democracies: An Essay on Democratic Transitions. Berkeley: University of California Press. Diamond, Larry. 1990. "Three Paradoxes of Democracy." Journal of Democracy (1990). -----. 1992. Economic Development and Democracy Reconsidered. In Reexaming Democracy: Essays in Honor of Seymour Martin Lipset. Ed. Marks, Gary and Larry Diamond. Newbury Park, Calif: Sage Publications. ------. 1994a. Political Culture and Democracy in Developing Countries. Boulder, Colo.: Lynne Rienner. -----. 1994b. “Rethinking Civil Society: Toward Democratic Consolidation,” Journal of Democracy, Vol. 5, No. 3 (July). -----. 1996. "Is the Third Wave Over?" Journal of Democracy 7 (July 1996): 20-37. Diamond, Larry and Marc F. Platter. 1998. Democracy in East Asia. Baltimore: the Johns Hopkins University Press. Diamond, Larry, Marc Plattner, Yun-han Chu, and Hung-mao Tien. 1997. Consolidating the Third Wave Democracies. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University press. Diamond, Larry Jay. 1999a. Democracy in developing countries. Boulder: Lynne Rienner Publishers. Diamond, Larry Jay. 1999b. Developing democracy toward consolidation. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. Domínguez, Jorge I and Abraham F Lowenthal. 1996. Constructing democratic governance Latin America and the Caribbean in the 1990s. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press. Du Toit, Pierre. 1995. State Building and Democracy in Southern Africa: Botswana, Zimbabwe, and South Africa. Washington, D.C.: United States Institute of Peace Press, 1995. -----. 2001. “Gelding: A New Approach to Rebuilding the State.” An unpublished paper, Department of Political Science, University of Stellenbosch. Durkeim, Emile. 1951. Suicide: A Study in Sociology. New York: Free Press. Emerson, Rupert. 1966. The Erosion of Democracy. Journal of Asian Studies, Vol. 20, No. 1, pp. 1-8. Evans, Peter. 1997. “The Eclipse of the State? Reflections on Stateness in an Era of Globalization.” World Politics, No. 50 (October): 62-87. Evans, Peter B, Dietrich Rueschemeyer, and Theda Skocpol. 1985. Bringing the state back in. Cambridge Cambridgeshire, New York: Cambridge University Press. Fishman, Robert M. 1990. “Rethinking State and Regime: Southern Europe’s Transition to Democracy.” World Politics, Vol. 42, No. 3 (April): 422-440. Foley, Michael and Bob Edward. 1996 "The Paradox of Civil Society," Journal of Democracy, (July) Friedrich, Carl. 1963. Man and His Government. New York: McGraw-Hill Inc. Fukuyama, Francis. 1993. "Capitalism and Democracy: The Missing Link." Dialogue 2 (1993):2-7. Gallo, Carmenza. 1997. “The autonomy of weak states: States and classes in primary export.” Sociological Perspectives, 1997, Vol. 40 Issue 4, p639, 22p, 1 graph Gerth, H. H. and Wright C Mill. 1946. From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology. New York: Oxford University Press. Grew, Raymond, ed. 1978. Crises of Political Development in Europe and the United States. Princeton: Princeton University Press. 21 Wang Shaoguang State Effectiveness and Democracy Grindle, Merilee S. 1997. “The Good Government Imperative: Human Resources, Organizations, and Institutions.” In Merilee S. Grindle, ed., Getting Good Government: Capacity Building in the Public Sectors of Developing Countries. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Gros, Jean-Germain. 1996. Towards a taxonomy of failed states in the New World Order: Decaying Somalia, Liberia, Rwanda and... Third World Quarterly, Sep96, Vol. 17 Issue 3, p455, 17p Haggard, Stephan. 1990. Pathways from the periphery the politics of growth in the newly industrializing countries. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Hagopian, Frances. 2000. “Political Development, Revisited.” Comparative Political Studies. Vol. 33, No. 6/7: 880-911. Holmes, Stephen. 1997. “What Russia Teaches Us Now: How Weak States Threaten Freedom.” American Prospect, Vol. 8, No. 33. Holmes, Stephen and Cass R. Sunstein. 1999. The Cost of Rights: Why Liberty Depends on Taxes. New York: W.W. Norton & Co. Huntington, Samuel P. 1993. “Democracy’s Third Wave.” In Larry Diamond and Marc F. Plattner, eds., The Global Resurgence of Democracy. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, pp. 3-25. -----. 1997. Democracy for the Long Hall. In Consolidating the Third Wave Democracies. Ed. Diamond, Larry, Marc Plattner, Yun-han Chu, and Hungmao Tien. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University press. Huntington, Samuel P and Joan M. Nelson. 1976. No Easy Choice: Political Participation in Developing Countries. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. Inglehart, Ronald. 1997. Modernization and Postmodernization: Culture, Economic, and Political Change in 43 Societies. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Inkeles, Alex and David H. Smith. 1974. Becoming Modern. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press. Johnson, Chalmers A. 1972. Conspiracy at Matsukawa. Berkeley: University of California Press. Johnson, Chalmers A. 1982. MITI and the Japanese miracle the growth of industrial policy, 1925-1975. Stanford: Stanford University Press. Johnson, Chalmers A. 2000. Blowback the costs and consequences of American empire. New York: Metropolitan Books. Kitschelt, Herbert. 2000. "Linkages Between Citizens and Politicians in Democratic Polities." Comparative Political Studies 33 (2000): 845-79. Klitgaard, Robert. 1988. Controlling Corruption. Berkeley: University of California Press. Knight, Jack. 1992. Institutions and Social Conflict. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Kopecky, Peter & Cas Mudde. 2000. “What has Eastern Europe taught us about the democratization literature (and vice versa)?” European Journal of Political Research, Vol. 37: 517-539. Kugler, Jacek and William Domke. 1986. "Comparing the Strength of Nations." Comparative Political Studies, Vol. 19, No. 1. Kuzio, Taras, Robert S. Kravchuk, and Paul D’Anieri, eds. 1999. State and Institution Building in Ukraine. New York: St. Martin Press. Kuzio, Taras. 2001. “Nationalizing States or Nation-building? A Critical Review of the Theoretical Literature and Empirical Evidence.” Unpublished manuscript, Yale University. 22 Wang Shaoguang State Effectiveness and Democracy Levi, Margaret. 1988. Of Rule and Revenue. Berkeley: University of California Press. Linz, Juan J. and Alfred Stepan. 1978. Latin America, The Breakdown of Democratic Regimes. Baltimore and London: The Johns Hopkins University Press. Linz, Juan J and Alfred C Stepan. 1996. Problems of democratic transition and consolidation southern Europe, South America, and post-communist Europe. Baltimore, Md: Johns Hopkins University Press. Lipset, Seymour Martin. 1959. "Some Social Requisites of Democracy: Economic Development and Political Legitimacy." American Political Science Review 53 (1959):69-105. Mann, Michael. 1986. “The Autonomous Power of the State: Its Origins, Mechanisms and Results.” In John A. Hall, ed., States in History. London: Basic Blackwell, pp. 109-136. -----1993. The Sources of Social Power: The Rise of Classes and Nation-States, 17601914. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Mengisteab, Kidane and Cyril Daddieh. 1999. State Building and Democratization in Africa: Faith, Hope, and Realities. Westport, CT: Praeger. Migdal, Joel S., Atul Kohli, and Vivienne Shue. 1994. State Power and Social Forces: Demination and Transformation in the Third World. New York: Cambridge University Press. Mill, John Stuart. 1958. Considerations on Representative Government. New York: Liberal Arts Press. Motyl, Alexander J. 1993. Dilemmas of Independence: Ukraine after Totalitarianism. New York: Council on Foreign Relations. -----. 1995. “The Conceptual President: Leonid Kravchuk and the Politics of Surrealism.” In Patterns in post-Soviet leadership. Ed. Colton, Timothy J and Robert C Tucker. Boulder: Westview Press. Murrell, Peter. 1991. "Can Neoclassical Economics Underpin the Reform of Centrally Planned Economies?" Journal of Economic Perspectives 5 (1991):59-76. Nader, Lauder. 1974. Up the Anthropologist: Perspectives Gained from Studying Up. In Reinventing anthropology. Ed. Hymes, Dell H. New York: Vintage Books. Nettl, J. P. 1968. “The State as a Conceptual Variable.” World Politics, Vol. 20, No. 4 (July): 559-592 Nordlinger, Eric A. 1981. On the Autonomy of the Democratic State. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. O'Donnell, Guillermo. 1992. “Delegative Democracy?” East-South Systems Transformation, University of Chicago, Working Paper No. 21. -----. 1993. "On the state, democratization and some conceptual problems: A Latin American view with glances at some post-communist countries." World Development, Vol. 21, No. 8. O'Donnell, Guillermo, Philippe Schmitter, and Lawrence Whitehead. 1986. Transitions from Authoritarian Rule. Baltimore: Johns Hoptins University Press. Ott, Dana. 1995. Political Democracy, Political Protest and State Size: Some Empirical Findings. www.microstate.net/reports/ott1.htm. Pei, Minxin. 1998. The Fall and Rise of Democracy in East Asia. In Democracy in East Asia. Ed. Diamond, Larry and Marc F. Platter. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. 23 Wang Shaoguang State Effectiveness and Democracy Peters, B. Guy. 1987. “Politicians and Bureaucrats in the Politics of Policy-Making.” In Jan-Erik Lane, ed., Bureaucracy and Public Choice. London: Sage Publications. Poggi, Gianfranco. 1978. The Development of the Modern State: A Sociological Introduction. Stanford: Stanford University Press. -----. 1990. The State: Its Nature, Development and Prospects. Cambridge: Polity Press. Przeworski, Adam. 1986. “Some Problems in the Study of the Transition to Democracy.” In Transitions from Authoritarian Rule: Comparative Perspectives. Ed. O'Donnell, Guillermo, Philippe C. Schmitter, and Lawrence Whitehead. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. Przeworski, Adam and Group on East-South Systems Transformations. 1995. Sustainable democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Przeworski, Adam and Fernando Limongi. 1997. "Modernization: Theories and Facts." World Politics 49 (1997):155-83. Przeworski, Adam, Michael Alvarez, Jose Cheibub, and Fernando Limongi. 2000. Democracy and Development: Political Institutions and Well-Being in the World, 1950-1990 Cambridge, Eng.: Cambridge University Press. Putnam, Robert D. 1993. Making Democracy Work: Civic Traditions in Modern Italy. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Pye, Lucian W. 1966. Aspects of Political Development. Boston: Little, Brown and Company. Rieff, David. 1999. "The False Dawn of Civil Society." The Nation, (February 22). Rustow, Dankwart. 1970. “Transitions to Democracy: Towards a Dynamic Model.” Comparative Politics, Vol. 2, No. 3 (April). Rose, Richard and Doh Chull Shin. 2001. “Democratization Backward: The Problem of Third Wave Democracies.” British Journal of Political Science, Vol. 31: 331-354. Schmidt, Steffen W., Laura Guasti, Carl H. Lande, and James Scott. 1977. Friends, Followers, and factions: A reader in Political Clientelism. Berkeley: University of California Press. Schmitter, Philippe C. and Terry Lynn Karl. 1993. “What democracy is…and is not.” In Larry Diamond and Marc F. Plattner, eds., The Global Resurgence of Democracy. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, pp. 39-52. Schumpeter, Joseph. 1942. Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy. New York: Harper. Shain, Yossi, and Juan J. Linz. 1995. Between States: Interim Governments and Democratic Transitions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Shapiro, Ian. 2001. “The State of Democratic Theory.” In Ira Katznelson and Helen Milner, eds., Political Science: The State of the Discipline. Washington, D.C.: American Political Science Association. Shleifer, Andrei and Robert W Vishny. 1998. The grabbing hand government pathologies and their cures. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press. Shue, Vivienne. 1994. “State Power and Social Organization.” In Joel Migdal, Atul Kohli and Vivienne Shue (eds.), State Power and Social Forces: Domination and Transformation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 65-88. Smith, Adam. 1910. The wealth of nations. London, New York: Dent. Dutton. Sperling, Valerie, ed. 2000. Building the Russian state: institutional crisis and the quest for democratic governance. Boulder, Colo.: Westview Press. 24 Wang Shaoguang State Effectiveness and Democracy Stepan, Alfred. 1986. Paths Toward Redemocratization: Theoretical and Comparative Considerations. In Transitions from Authoritarian Rule: Comparative Perspectives. Ed. O'Donnell, Gullermo, Philippe C. Schmitter, and Laurence Whitehead. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. Stepan, Alfred C. 1978. The state and society Peru in comparative perspective. Princeton, N.J: Princeton University Press. Thomas, George M. and John W. Meyer. 1984. “The Expansion of the State.” Annual Review of Sociology, Vol. 10: 461-482 Tilly, Charles. 1975. “Reflections on the History of European State-Making.” In Charles Tilly and Gabriel Ardant, eds., The Formation of national States in Western Europe. Princeton, N.J: Princeton University Press. Treisman, Daniel. 1999. “Decentralization and Corruption: Why are Federal State Perceived to be More Corrupt?” Paper prepared for presentation at the Annual Meeting of the American Political Science Association, Atlanta, September. -----. 2000. “Decentralization and the Quality of Government.” Unpublished paper, University of California, Los Angeles. Triska, Jan F. and Paul M. Cocks. 1977. Political Development in Eastern Europe. New York: Praeger. Tullock, Gordon. 1965. The Politics of Public Bureaucracy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Verba, Sidney Kay Lehman Schlozman, and Henry E. Brady. 1997. "The Big Tilt: Participatory Inequality in America." The American Prospect, No. 32 (MayJune): 74-80, <http://epn.org/prospect/32/32verbfs.html>. Wade, Robert. 1990. Governing the market economic theory and the role of government in East Asian industrialization. Princeton, N.J: Princeton University Press. Waldner, David. 1999. State Building and Late Development. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Wang, Shaoguang. Forthcoming. “Defective Institution and Its Consequences: Lesson from China, 1980-1993.” Communist and Post-Communist Studies. Weber, Eugene. 1976. Peasants into Frenchmen: The Modernization of Rural France, 1870-1914. Stanford: Stanford University Press. Weber, Max. 1946. From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology, ed. and trans. H. H. Gerth and C. Wright Mills. New York: Oxford University Press. Weber, Max and Max Rheinstein. 1954. Max Weber on law in economy and society. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Weber, Max. 1978. Economy and Society, 2 vols. Berkeley: University of California Press. Weil, Frederick D. 1989. “The Sources and Structure of Legitimation in Western Democracies: A Consolidated Model Tested with Time Series Data in Six Countries Since World War II.” American Sociological Review, Vol. 54, No. 5 pp. 682-706. Weiner, Myron and Ergun Özbudun. 1987. Competitive elections in developing countries. Durham, NC: Duke University Press. Zakaria, Fareed. 1997. “The rise of illiberal democracy.” Foreign Affairs, Vol. 76, No. 6: 22-43. 25