Constitutional Rights and Private Law* by Aharon Barak (1) The Problem Presented; (2) The Four Models; (a) The Direct Application Model; (b) The Non- Application Model; (c) The Application through the Judiciary Model; (d) The Indirect Application Model; (3) The Indirect Application Models in Action; (a) Constitutional Rights as Objective Values; (b) First Channel of Application: Interpreting Private Law; (I) The Objective Aspects of Constitutional Rights and the Interpretation of Private Law; (II) The Interpretation of Valve Concepts; (i) Interpretation in Light of the Objective Aspects of Constitutional Rights; (ii) Public Policy; (iii) Good Faith; (III) Interpretation of Private Law and its Validity; (c) The Second Channel of Application: A Negative Arrangement and Lacunae; (I) The Silence of Private Law; (II) Negative Solution; (III) Lacunae; (d) Third Application Channel: Creating New Private Law; (I) New Legislation and Developing the Common Law; (II) New Legislation; (III) The Development of the Common Law; (IV) Proportionality of new legislation and the Development of the Common Law; (V) New Legislation and the Development of the Common Law – Discretion or Obligation; (i) Negative and Positive Rights; (ii) Fulfilling the Duty in Positive Rights; (4) The Indirect Application in Israel; (5) Conclusion * This paper is based on my past writing on this subject as well as an additional development of this train of thought. For previous publications see A Barak, 'Constitutional Human Rights and Private Law' in A M Rabello & P Sarcevic (eds), Freedom of Contract and Constitutional Law 105 (HUJI, 1998); A Barak, 'Constitutional Human Rights and Private Law' in D Freedman & D Barak-Erez (eds), Human Rights in Private Law 13 (Hart, 2001); A Barak, 'Constitutional Human Rights and Private Law' (1996) 3 Rev. Const. Stud. 218. 1 1. The Problem Presented All are in agreement that the individual’s constitutional rights1 are directed towards the state. The history of human rights is that of the recognition of individual rights vis-à-vis the state. The texts of the different constitutions have turned this history into a reality. Often, explicit provisions are found in the constitution, according to which the state must respect the rights of individuals determined therein.2 The question before us is: are constitutional rights directed at the state (vertical relationship) alone or are these constitutional rights directed at individuals as well (horizontal relationship)? Is an employee’s (just like any other individual’s) constitutional right to freedom of expression, directed at the state, also an employee’s constitutional right to freedom of expression vis-à-vis the employer? This question is recognized in comparative constitutional law as a one regarding third party’s effects (Drittwirkung). The first party is the individual. The state is the second party. The third party is made up of another individual. The question is: are constitutional rights, granted by the constitution to the first party (the individual) directed towards the second party (the state) alone or also visà-vis the third party (another individual)? The literature on this subject is vast.3 1 The term constitutional rights is used in the essay to describe rights expressly of impliedly guaranteed by the constitution. 2 See Section 11 to Israeli Basic Law: Human Dignity and Liberty 1391 LSI 150 (1992) (Isr.), available in English at: http://www.knesset.gov.il/laws/special/eng/basic3_eng.htm; Section 5 to Israeli Basic Law: Freedom of Occupation 1454 LSI 90 (1994) available in English at: http://www.knesset.gov.il/laws/special/eng/basic4_eng.htm; see also Section 1(3) of the Basic Law for the Federal Republic of Germany; Section 8(1) of the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa no. 108 of 1996. 3 In the last ten years there have been many articles published on this subject. The important books published during that period are - A M Rabello & P Sercevic (eds.), Freedom of Contracts and Constitutional Law (HUJI, 1998); R English & P Havers (eds.), An Introduction to Human Rights and the Common Law (Hart, 2000); D Friedmann & D Barak-Erez (eds.), Human Rights in Private Law (Hart, 2001); A Sajó & R Uitz (eds.), The Constitution in Private Relations: Expanding Constitutionalism (Eleven International Publishing, 2005); T Barkhuysen & S D Lindenbergh (eds.), Constitutionalisation of Private Law (Leiden, Martinus Neihoff Publishers, 2006); K S Ziegler (ed.), Human Rights and Private Law: Privacy as Autonomy (Hart, 2006); D Oliver and J. Fedtke (eds.), Human Rights and The Private Sphere: A 2 This dilemma appears to be resolved when the constitution states (expressively or impliedly) a clear stand. In some constitutions there is an express reference to the horizontal effect. Thus, for example, in the Constitution of South Africa there is an explicit provision, that reads as follows:4 A provision of the Bill of Rights binds a natural or a juristic person if, and to the extent that, it is applicable, taking into account the nature of the right and the nature of any duty imposed by the right. With this provision in mind, seemingly the question in South Africa is the scope of the provision and the circumstances where its conditions are met.5 This conclusion is not free from doubts,6 as the Constitutional Court’s rulings have determined that the application is indirect.7 In a small number of constitutions there are provisions regarding the horizontal application of special constitutional rights.8 The United States Bill of Rights is drafted in a manner that precludes the horizontal effect on most rights. Thus, for example, the first amendment states:9 Comparative Study (Routledge-Cavendish, 2007); C Mak, Fundamental Rights in European Contract Law: A Comparison of the Impact of Fundamental Rights on Contractual Relationships in Germany, the Netherlands, Italy and England (Alphen an den Rijn, Kluwer Law International, 2008); D Hoffman (ed.), The Impact of the UK Human Rights Act on Private Law (ed., 2011). 4 Section 8(2) of the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa (1996). 5 See S Woolman, 'Application' in S Woolman & M Bishop (eds.), Constitutional Law of South Africa, Chapter 31 ( 2nd. Ed., Pretoria, Juta Law, 2005). 6 See H H. Cheadle, 'Third Party Effect in the South African Constitution' in The Constitution in private relations, supra note 3, at 55. 7 Du Plessis v. De Klerk 1996 (3) SA 850 (CC); Bernstein v. Bester NO 1996 (4) BCLR 449 (CC); Carmichele v. Minister of Safety and Security 2001 (4) SA 938 (CC); Khumalo v. Holomisa 2002 (5) SA 401 (CC); Rail Commuters Action Group v. Transnet Ltd. 2005 (2) SA 539 (CC). 8 See U.S. Const., Amend. XIII, which bans slavery. This ban applies on interpersonal relationships. See also Article 9(d)THERE IS NO PART (d) IN ARTICLE 9 (IT HAS SECTIONS 9(1), 9(2), 9(3)) to the German Basic Law which bans agreements between individuals which limit the freedom of association. 9 U.S. Const., Amend. I. 3 Congress shall make no law respecting an establishment of religion, or prohibiting the free exercise thereof; or abridging the freedom of speech, or of the press; or the right of the people peaceably to assemble, and to petition the Government for a redress of grievances. This provision is directed at Congress, and burdens it with obligations. This provision has only a vertical effect. Under the assumption that a constitution is not expressly restricted to vertical effect, the question before us is if the constitutional rights apply onto horizontal relationships as well. The answer to this question is interpretive.10 What are the options available to the interpreter?11 In principle, one can think of four models: (1) Direct application model; (2) Non-Application model; (3) Application to the judiciary model; (4) Indirect application model. We will examine each of these four possibilities. 2. The Four Models a. The Direct Application Model The first model available to the interpreter is to interpret the constitution’s provisions regarding human rights as being directed at both the state and individuals.12 According to this approach, constitutional rights directly apply onto the relationships between individuals. Thus, for example, according to this option, the right to dignity and liberty found in Basic Law: Human Dignity and Liberty also applies onto the 10 See A Barak, Purposive Interpretation in Law 370 (Prunceton University Press, 2005) See Peter W. Hogg, Constitutional Law of Canada 102 (Vol 2, 5 th ed., 2007). 12 For this model see Barak, Purposive Interpretation, Supra note *. In German literature this approach is referred to as "unmittelbare Drittwirkung". For an analysis of this approach, see R Alexy, A Theory of Constitutional Rights 351 (translated by Julian Rivers, Oxford University Press, 2002); M Kumm & V Ferreres Comella, 'What Is So Special About Constitutional Rights in Private Litigation? A Comparative Analysis of the Function of State Action Requirement and Indirect Horizontal Effect', in The Constitution in Private Relations, supra note 3, at 241. 11 4 relationships between individuals. According to this approach, the Basic Law recognizes the employer’s constitutional duty not to limit the employee’s human dignity and the employee’s constitutional right not to limit the employer’s human dignity. Similarly, the freedom of expression anchored in the constitution is not just the freedom of the individual vis-à-vis the state but also vis-à-vis every other individual. considerations support this option: Two First, in the modern reality, the danger to constitutional rights is not only from the state but also from other individuals. At times, these have powers no less than those of the state. Constitutional Rights should therefore apply on horizontal relationships as well.13 Second, we are faced with an expansive privatization process.14 State powers, whose use by the governmental authority must respect the constitutional rights of the individual vis-à-vis the state, are transferred over to the private sector. If within this sector the constitutional rights do not continue to apply, the result will be that the privatization will release the state of its constitutional duties without replacing it by imposing such duties on the private sector. Despite the potency of these considerations, I believe that this model is not right.15 The reasons brought for its defense do not support it. Its methodology is wrong. Regarding the first consideration (the power of certain individuals as the state) – I believe that the individual’s protection vis-à-vis another individuals, no matter how powerful they may be, should be resolved in private law (stature or common law) itself. There is 13 See Barak, Purposive Interpretation, Supra note *, at 656. See Y Zamir, Administrative Authority 39 (2nd ed., vol. I, Nevo, 2010) (Hebrew); D Barak-Erez, Administrative Law 59 (vol. I, Tel Aviv, Israel Bar Association, 2010) (Hebrew); Y Dotan & B Medina, 'Legal Aspects of the Privatization of the Supply of Goods and Services' (2001) 37 Mishpatim 287 (Hebrew). 15 It is possible that it may be justified in special cases, when the legal system wishes to put up a red flag regarding a certain kind of inappropriate activity. Therefore (I?) justify the Indian Constitution which grasps as a duty not to discriminate against an obligation imposed not only vis-à-vis the state but also in interpersonal relationships: see Article 15 of the Constitution of India. See also afformentioned U.S. Const., Amend. XIII, which bans slavery. This ban applies on interpersonal relationships. 14 5 no justification in granting to a weaker individual a constitutional rights vis-à-vis a stronger individual, as this situation will also grant the stronger individual with a constitutional right vis-à-vis the weaker individual. The granting of constitutional status to a right is equal to the protection of said right from the state, a body that can legislate statutes or develop the common law and therefore limit the right. The granting of constitutional status to a right imposes limitations on the state to affect the right. This result is irrelevant to the protection of the weaker individual’s rights vis-à-vis the stronger individual. As to the relationship between the weaker and stronger individual, subconstitutional law is sufficient. The stronger individual has no legislative power and the limitation clause – which applies when the constitutional right is limited by a subconstitutional norm – does not apply. Of course, to the extent that said sub-constitutional law does not sufficiently consider the weakness of one side, particularly due to their chronic weakness, the road is open to consider its constitutionality.16 Indeed, disproportional protection by private law of the weak from the strong may make private law unconstitutional. As such, the weaker party’s constitutional right vis-à-vis the state is sufficient. There is no need to recognize this right as a constitutional right vis-à-vis the stronger side. The vertical effect is characterized by the constitutional right of the individual vis-à-vis the state. The state has no constitutional right vis-à-vis the individual. Acknowledging the horizontal effect will not strengthen the weaker party, for on the other side of the equation will stand a stronger individual with an identical constitutional right. 16 See F Raday, '"Privatization of Human Rights" and the Misuse of Force' (1994) 23 Mishpatim 21 PAGE# (Hebrew). 6 The second consideration (privatization which results in a release from constitutional obligations) may be a relevant when considering the constitutionality of the privatization.17 Thus, for example, the privatization of prisons was declared in Israel unconstitutional due to its disproportional limitation of the prisoner right vis-à-vis the state.18 When privatization is constitutional, the law that applies on the relationship between the individuals after the privatization should be the sub-constitutional law, which has been made suitable for privatization.19 It is not fitting that the vertical relationship which applied vis-à-vis the state before the privatization continue to apply, vis-à-vis other individuals after privatization. The direct application model is methodologically problematic. Its application is unsatisfactory. Methodologically when two principle-shaped constitutional rights conflict – whether it be the individual’s constitutional right vis-à-vis state or one individual’s constitutional right vis-à-vis another individual (according to the direct application model) – the conflict’s solution is not found at the constitutional level.20 The scope of the constitutional right does not change. The conflict’s solution is at the sub-constitutional level, such as at the legislative or common law level. On this level we determine if the law limiting a constitutional right to realize another constitutional right is constitutional. Therefore, even if direct application is recognized, the conflict’s solution regarding the 17 Relevant to this matter is the approach that the Parliament cannot release itself from its duty to determine primary arrangements (the non-delegable duty): HCJ 3267/97 Rubinstein v. Minister of Defense [1998] IsrSC 52(5) 481 PAGE#; HCJ 11163/03 Supreme Monitoring Committee for Arab Affairs in Israel v. Prime Minister [2006] (1) IsrLR 105 PAGE#. Gideon Sapir, Primary Arrangements, 32 Tel Aviv U.L.Rev. 5 PAGE# (2010) (Hebrew). 18 See HCJ 2605/05 Academic Center of Law and Business, Human Rights Division v. The Minister of Finance (not yet published, given on 19.11.2009). 19 See A Harel, Private Bodies in Administrative Law PAGE# (Tel Aviv, Israel Bar Association, 2008) (Hebrew); D Barak-Erez, 'Public Corporations' (1995) 19 Tel Aviv U. L. Rev. 273 PAGE# (Hebrew). 20 See A Barak, Proportionality: Constitutional Rights and Their Limitations 83 (Cambridge University Press, 2012). 7 scope of the rights will not be at the constitutional level but rather at the subconstitutional level, namely in providing the answer to the question of if the limiting law is constitutional. This level must of course fulfill the requirements of the limitation clause (proportionality). Therefore, the recognition of the direct application (horizontal) model is methodologically wrong. The logic at the foundation of the need to recognize the individual’s constitutional right vis-à-vis the state does not exist regarding the recognition of the constitutional right of one individual vis-à-vis another.21 Comparative law supports my opinion on this matter. b. The Non-Application Model The second model provides that constitutional rights apply only vis-à-vis the state (vertical relationship). A constitution is meant to protect the individual from the state and is not aimed in dealing with interpersonal relationships (horizontal), a relationship which has always been regulated by private law. According to this option, anything concerning interpersonal relationships should be regulated in private law, without any influence or penetration of the constitution’s provisions, all of which are part of the public sphere. Of course, the boundary between the public law and private law is not so clear nor is it impenetrable. There are reciprocal ties between public and private law. Therefore, when developing legal doctrines regarding private law, the judge will consider the public law. This consideration reflects the need to observe the entire structure of society, law and the legal system. However, according to the second model, this consideration by the judge is 21 Alexy, Supra note *, at 362: "[D]irect horizontal effect cannot mean that rights of the citizens against the state are also rights of the citizen against other citizens… direct horizontal effect cannot be achieved by exchanging the addressee of the right of a citizen against the state". 8 not based on the application – direct or indirect – of the constitution’s provisions regarding human rights on interpersonal relationships. Canadian law essentially takes22 the second option.23 The latter was determined in the Dolphin Delivery case.24 In that case the labor union organized a strike against the employer. The Dolphin Delivery Company was not the employer, but rather supplied products to the employer. Despite this, the labor union decided to picket against Dolphin Delivery. The latter applied to the court to request an injunction, which prevented the labor union from committing a civil wrong of inducing breach of contract. In court the labor union claimed that it should not handed down an injunction as it would limit its right to freedom of expression which is protected in the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms. The Supreme Court refuted this claim. It was ruled that the constitutional rights determined in the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms are directed towards the state and not other individuals. The non-application model is fitting to the extent that it rejects the direct application model. However, it creates too deep a rift between constitutional law and private law. There are closer ties between constitutional law and private law than those presented by the non-application model. At the core of these ties is the duties of private law – and the duty of the legislator and the judge who create and develop private law – to fulfill the constitutional values and principles.25 22 It is also possible to see weakened indirect application in it: See S Gardbaum, 'The 'Horizontal Effect' of Constitutional Rights' (2003) 102 Mich. L. Rev. 388 PAGE#. 23 See Hogg, supra note ___, at 101. See also Pepsi-Cola Canada Beverages v. R.W.D.U. [2002] 1 S.C.R. 156 PAGE#; Dagenais v. CBC [1994] 3 S.C.R. 835 PAGE#. 24 Retail, Wholesale and Department Store Union, Local 580 v. Dolphin Delivery Ltd [1986] 2 S.C.R. 573. 25 For this duty, see infra, at ___. 9 c. The Application through the Judiciary Model The third model is the application on the judiciary.26 The starting point is that constitutional rights are directed towards the state alone. However, the judge is a state organ, and therefore the constitutional right is directed towards him. According to this model when the judge speaks, the state speaks; when the judge acts the state acts. The judge is the state and human rights need to be protected vis-à-vis him as well. The meaning of the latter, from the judge’s point of view, is two-fold: Firstly, he must develop the common law in a fashion that conforms to his duty not to disproportionally limit constitutional rights. Secondly, he must act within the confines of the specific dispute in a fashion which conforms to the parties’ constitutional rights vis-à-vis the state. This model was developed in American constitutional law, wherein constitutional rights are directed towards the state. In the New York Times Co. v. Sullivan case27 it is triggered regarding the development of the rules of defamation in tort law. In this case, the discussion concerned a claim of defamation filed by Sullivan (a public figure) against the New York Times. It was decided that the court must develop the common law of defamation according to the first amendment. In the Shelley v. Kraemer case28 it was applied to prevent discriminatory remedies in individual disputes. Here, the Shelley family (an African-American family) had purchased a home. Kraemer lived in that same neighborhood. He applied to the court in order to prevent the Shelley family from gaining possession of the home as the latter would have contradicted a restrictive covenant applicable on the house, according to which a "Negro" cannot purchase the 26 For this model, see Gardbaum, supra note *. PAGE# New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254 (1964). 28 Shelley v. Kraemer, 334 U.S. 1 (1948). 27 10 home. The Supreme Court ruled that a judge cannot provide an injunction which would limit the principle of equality found in the Fourteenth Amendment. The third model – so long as it is regarding an individual dispute – is wrong.29 It is not accepted in comparative law, neither has it been developed in America. Despite this, the third model is correct when it concerns the common law. According to my point of view, the common law is subject to the general constitutional structure.30 A common law precedent may lawfully limit a constitutional right. To do so, it must fulfill the requirements of the limitation clause – it must be proportional.31 Therefore, I believe that New York Times Co. v. Sullivan case32 was rightly decided. This is not the case in Shelley v. Kraemer.33 When the time comes for the judge to grant an injunction, he must act according to the rules of the common law which is the legal framework where the rules of the restrictive covenant and its enforcement were developed. If these rules allow for the non-granting of a discriminatory injunction – he must act according to these rules. If these rules determine that there is room to grant an injunction order, even if it is discriminatory – he has the duty to lead to a change in these rules (only if he is authorized to do so according to the judicial hierarchy (for example if the matter is brought before the supreme court) or according to the rules of judicial power (in the federal law system)). The rules of the common law cannot limit constitutional rights, unless they fulfill the requirements imposed by the legislation limiting the constitutional rights. So long as the common law is not changed – he must act according to the rules of the common law. If not, the constitution’s provisions, which see the right to equality as a 29 See the word of Justice Mcintyre in the Dolphin Delivery case, supra note ___, at 443. See Barak, Proportionality, supra note *, at 118. See also infra note *. 31 Id., at 121. 32 See supra note ___. 33 See supra note ___. 30 11 right vis-à-vis the state alone and not vis-à-vis other individuals, becomes suddenly a right to equality vis-à-vis another individual. The judge is not empowered to do so. If a constitution’s provision regarding the right to equality applies vis-à-vis the state alone, and not on the relationship between individuals, there is no room for the conclusion that when a dispute between individuals comes to court, the judge must determine the dispute in an equal manner. This conclusion voids the constitutional provision according to which the right to equality applies on the relationships between the individual and the state only. Indeed, Shelley v. Kraemer’s ruling was not sustained. Instead, the courts developed the doctrine of State Action.34 The application of the constitutional rights included in the Bill of Rights vis-à-vis the judge are conditional that the individual, who according to the claim, limits the constitutional rights in his relationship with others, carries out functions which are traditionally the State’s. A significant amount of case law has been dedicated to this matter and has determined when the nexus between the State and the individual is sufficiently close, so close that it is possible to attribute the behavior to the State. This doctrine overrules, albeit not explicitly, the ruling in Shelley v. Kraemer. In light of the development of this doctrine, American law should no longer be seen as a system which adopts the model of the application through the judiciary. There are those who believe that the American approach adopts the indirect application.35 d. The Indirect Application Model 34 See E Chemerinsky, Constitutional Law: Principles and Policies 518 (3rd. Ed., Aspen Law & Business 2006). 35 See Gardbaum, supra note ___. PAGE# 12 The fourth model is that of indirect application.36 According to this model, the individual’s constitutional rights apply directly vis-à-vis the state and indirectly vis-à-vis an individual. The individual should not fill the shoes of the state, which possesses the duty concerning constitutional rights. An individual does not have constitutional rights vis-à-vis another individual. The rights between the individuals are at the subconstitutional level (statute or common law) and not at the constitutional level. Indeed, "the state's duties to uphold human rights are not the same content-wise as the individual’s duty to uphold human rights".37 "The duty of the state to act equally vis-àvis the individual is not the same content-wise as the individual’s duty to act equally visà-vis another individual".38 The individual’s freedom of occupation vis-à-vis the state is different in scope than the freedom of occupation of the individual vis-à-vis another individual. However, the individual’s constitutional rights vis-à-vis the state apply indirectly on the relationships between individuals. This indirect application is based on the assumption that each of the individual’s constitutional rights vis-à-vis the state have an objective value aspect which is projected itself onto all of the law’s branches. This means that the individual’s rights vis-à-vis the state to dignity, freedom, privacy and property express objective values (but not rights) which shape the relationships between individuals within private law. These values are used for the interpretation of the private law, to complete lacunae in it or develop it. To the extent that the existing private law limits "negative" constitutional right of the individual vis-à-vis the state, such law (statute or the common law) is constitutional only if it is proportional. To the extent that such This option is dubbed in German constitutional literature as “unmittelbare Drittwirkung”. For an analysis of this approach see Alexy, supra note ___, at 351; Kumm and Comella, supra note ___. PAGE# 37 Civ. App. 294/91, Hevrat Kadisha GAHSHA “Kehillat Yerusalayim” v. Kastenbaum, [1992] PD 46(2) 464 PAGE# (J. Barak). 38 HCJFH 4191/97 Recanat v. National Labour Court [2000] IsrSC 54(5) 330 PAGE# (P. Barak). 36 13 existing law does not protect proportionally the "positive" individual right vis-à-vis the state, the state must develop the private law to make it proportional.39 From the four models I discussed, this model is the proper one. It is accepted in most legal systems where this problem has arisen.40 It applies within the framework of the European Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms (1950).41 Amongst the legal systems which draw on the indirect application are Germany,42 Italy, 43 the Netherlands44 and New Zealand.45 The indirect application model recognizes the difference between the individual’s constitutional right directed towards the state and the individual’s sub-constitutional (statute or common law) right directed towards another individual. This difference is expressed in the normative status of the right and its scope. Regarding the normative status – while the individual’s right vis-à-vis the state is a right at the constitutional level, the individual’s rights vis-à-vis another individual is at the sub-constitutional level. It is mostly found in private law. As for the scope – the individual’s constitutional right vis-à-vis the state is more expansive than the individual’s right vis-à-vis another individual. There are two reasons for this: 39 Regarding this obligation see infra, at ___. See A Barak, 'Constitutional Human Rights and Private Law', in Human Rights in Private Law, supra note *. 41 See, C. Ovey & R C A White (eds.), Jacobs & White: European Convention on Human Rights 38 (4th ed., Oxford University Press, 2002); E A Alkema, 'The Third-Party Application of ‘Drittwirkung’ of the European Convention on Human Rights' in G J Wiarda, F Matscher & H Petzold (eds.), Protecting Human Rights: The European Dimension: Studies in Honour of Gerard J. Wiarda 33 PAGE# (Köln, C. Heymann Publishers, 1989); R S Kay, 'The European Convention on Human Rights and the Control of Private Law' (2005) 5 Eur. Hum. Rts. L. Rev. 466 PAGE#; A Clapman, 'The ‘Drittwirkung' of the Convention' in Macdonald, Matscher & Petzold (eds.), The European System for the Protection of Human Rights 163 (Springer, 1993). For the approach in International Law, see J H Knox, 'Horizontal Human Rights Law, (2008) 102 A .J. Int’l L. 1 PAGE#. 42 See Mak, Fundament Rights in European Contract Law, supra note ___, at 57. 43 See Id., at 104. 44 See Id., at 83. 45 See Hosking v. Runting (2004) 7 HRNZ 301. For an analysis of the case law, see A Geddis, 'The Horizontal Effects of the New Zealand Bill of Rights Act, as Applied in Hosking v. Runting 2004 N.Z. L. Rev. 681; P Rishworth, G Huscroft, S Optican & R. Mahoney, The New Zealand Bill of Rights 102 (Oxford University Press, 2003). 40 14 first, the objectives of the constitutional right are at full force vis-à-vis the state. Second, in determining the scope of the individual’s constitutional right vis-à-vis the state, one should consider the rational at the right’s basis. No balance should be made on the constitutional level between it and the considerations which justify the right’s limitation (i.e., the public interest or rights of others). Balances should be made only when determining the constitutionality of the limitation of the constitutional right by a subconstitutional law.46 With regards to the determination of the scope of the individual’s right vis-à-vis another individual, the scope of the right is determined by the subconstitutional law (such as a statute or common law) and is a product of the balancing between the rational at the rights basis and the rational at the basis of the constitutional rights of others or the public interest. The constitutionality of this balance is determined by the limitation clause i.e., this sub-constitutional law is constitutional only if it is proportional. The indirect application model does not blur the distinction between the individual’s constitutional right vis-à-vis the state and the individual’s right vis-à-vis another individual. According to this model, the rights which exist between individuals are not constitutional rights. They are not a part of the constitution, but rather, they are part of the sub-constitutional law. They are anchored in regular legislation or the common law (such as contract, tort, property and labor law). The rights and remedies for their breach have been shaped by private law over hundreds of years. In this shaping there is significant weight given to the fact that the constitutional law recognizes the existence of these rights vis-à-vis the state (vertical relationship). The existence of this relationship affects directly the constitutionality of this sub-constitutional law, and it 46 See, Barak, Proportionality, supra note *, at 80. 15 effects the rights of individuals vis-à-vis the state. Thus sub-constitutional law affects indirectly the rights between individuals (horizontal relationship). This influence is best expressed in the interpretation of the norms in private law, in the completion of the lacunae within it and the development of new and proportional private law. Hence the difference between this approach and the non-application model. The none application model creates a barrier between the constitutional rights and private law. This barrier is cracked only when the lack of non-application model determines that the development of the common law is affected by constitutional rights. The indirect application model takes a much stronger position. The influence of the constitutional rights on common law is extensive and much stronger in the indirect application model than in the non-application model. Private law, made by statute or common law,47 infringes on the constitutional right of each individual vis-à-vis the state, and therefore is subject to the limitation clause. The relationship between the indirect application model and the application through the judicial model are complex. On the one hand, both models provide that the constitutional rights apply only vertically. According to both models, the legislator and the judge must act to suit legislation and common law to constitutional rights. For this reason the decision in the New York Times Co. v. Sullivan48 case befits both models. On the other hand, the indirect model option sees the constitutional rights as an objective values working within private law and according to it. This is not true regarding the application on the judiciary. The State Action doctrine, as it has been developed in the United States, operates outside of private law. Its operation is within public law, and the 47 48 Id., at 118. Supra note *. 16 constitutional right is directed not only towards the state, but also vis-à-vis individuals carrying out the State’s functions. 3. The Indirect Application Models in Action a. Constitutional Rights as Objective Values The starting off point of the indirect application model is in the perception that constitutional rights have both a subjective and objective aspect.49 The subjective aspect is the duty that they impose on the state vis-à-vis the individual. Alongside the subjective aspect there is an objective aspect (Objective Wertordnung). Every subjective constitutional right reflects an objective value. These objective values operate on all of the law’s branches. Thus, for example, human dignity has two elements – subjective and objective. The subjective element is expressed in the constitutional right to human dignity granted to the individual vis-à-vis the state. The objective element is expressed by the fact that human dignity is an objective value of the legal system in general and of private law in particular. This differentiation between the two elements of constitutional rights has been expressed in the Luth case given by the German Constitutional Court.50 The case examined the legality of Luth’s behavior, who asked the public to boycott a film directed by a renowned Nazi. The movie’s producer applied to the civil court to prevent Luth from demanding the film’s boycott. The civil court ruled that Luth’s behavior is a civil wrong, as it falls within the boundaries of Section 826 of the B.G.B. which sets: The use of the terms “subjective” and “objective” in this context was taken from German constitutional theory. The subject aspect regards the individual’s right vis-à-vis the state. The objective aspect is regarding the constitutional value which applies on all relationships in the law. 50 BVerfGE 7, 198 (1958). 49 17 Whoever causes damage to another person intentionally and in a manner offensive to good morals is obliged to compensate the other person for the damage. Luth applied to the Constitutional Court. He claimed that the ruling limited his constitutional right to freedom of expression. The Constitutional Court ruled that Luth’s constitutional right to freedom of expression is an objective value of the legal system. The term “good morals” found in section 826 of the B.G.B. should be interpreted in a manner consistent with this objective value. Considering the case’s circumstances, Luth’s behavior should not be considered as offensive to “good morals.” Luth’s constitutional right to freedom of expression is directed towards the state alone. Luth has no constitutional right to freedom of expression vis-à-vis the film’s producer. However, in the relationship between Luth and the producer the objective value of freedom of expression does apply. This value influences the meaning of the private law’s provisions on "good morals" and other "valve concepts" of private law. We will now examine the different channels through which the objective aspects of the constitutional right affects private law (statute or the common law). I will discuss three main channels: (1) The interpretation of the private law; (2) referring to the gaps and the negative arrangement in private law; (3) developing private law. b. First Channel of Application: Interpreting Private Law I. The Objective Aspects of Constitutional Rights and the Interpretation of Private Law The indirect application model assumes that constitutional rights apply only on the relationship between the individual and the state. However, each of the individual’s 18 constitutional rights vis-à-vis the state expresses one of the legal system’s objective values. This objective value is not limited to the relationship between the individual and the state. It applies to all legal fields, and all legal relationships, including the relationship between individuals. It applies on private law.51 These objective value elements – derived from the individual’s constitutional rights vis-à-vis the state – have significant importance in private law. It is expressed in the interpretation of statutory private law. This interpretation in Israel is purposive interpretation.52 According to this interpretation, the statute text is given the interpretation which fulfills its purposes. This purpose, on a high level of abstraction includes the fundamental values of the legal system.53 These make up “a normative umbrella spread out above all legislation.”54 The latter expresses the fact that the law is “a living creature within its environment.”55 The law’s environment includes “not only the legislative context in proximity, but also extended circles of accepted principles, fundamental purposes and basic standards.”56 These fundamental principles include the objective values at the foundation of the constitutional rights. These values penetrate into private law through purposive interpretation. Therefore, the rules of contract, tort or property found within private law should be interpreted in a manner which fulfills human dignity, liberty, property and the other objective values derived from constitutional rights. 51 CA 6601/96 AES System Inc. v. Saar [2000] IsrSC 54(3) 850 PAGE#. See Barak, Purposive Interpretation, supra note *, at 370. 53 Ibid., 381. 54 See CA 165/82 Kibbutz Hatzor v Assessing Officer, [1985] 39(2) IsrSC 70, 75 (J. Barak). See also CA 2000/97 Lindorn v. Carnit – Road Accident Victims Fund [1999] IsrSC 55(1) 12, 29: “Alongside the specific purpose at the foundation of the defendant’s right is the general purpose. This is an objective purpose. It reflects the core values of the system … it is an expression of the understanding that legislation is not a one-off act of a passing legislator, but rather a link of legislative creation of a permanent legislator. It makes up a “normative umbrella” spread above all of the legislation…. This general purpose “trickles” into the purpose of all legislation. It is an expression of the structure of the system and its values”(P. Barak). 55 HCJ 58/68 Shalit v. Minister of the Interior, 23(2) [1970] P.D. 477, 513. 56 Kibbutz Hatzor case, supra note ___, at 75. 52 19 Like all fundamental principles which shape statutory's purposes, they are in constant conflict.57 The objective aspect of one constitutional right (freedom of expression) conflicts with the objective aspect of a different constitutional right (privacy). Sometimes the objective aspect of the constitutional right conflicts with objective principles like public interest, such as security, public order and health. This conflict is not solved by the “victory” of one objective aspect and the “loss” of another or that of the public interest. The solution to this conflict within the legislative purpose is through balancing between the conflicting values according to their importance at the decision point. This is an interpretive balancing.58 Interpretive analogy can be used for the needs of this balancing from the element of proportionality stricto sensu from the rules of constitutional proportionality.59 However, the limitation clause has no application. We are dealing here with a balancing for purposive interpretation and not for constitutional validity. II. The Interpretation of Valve Concepts i. Interpretation in Light of the Objective Aspects of Constitutional Rights A special case of the interpretation of the private law exists when private law uses valve concepts (ventilbegriffe; conceffi volvola). Examples of these are good faith, public policy or negligence. These are shaped as principles (to distinguish from rules).60 They reflect society’s values and its basic principles. They provide the legal system with the 57 See Barak, Purposive Interpretation, supra note *, at 153. Regarding the interpretive balancing, see Barak, Proportionality, supra note *, at 72. 59 Id., at 75. 60 Regarding the differentiation between principles and rules in this context, see Id., at 70. 58 20 appropriate flexibility. With their help, the legal system conforms to changing needs, yet still remains true to itself. Both legislation and the common law use these valve concepts to prevent stagnation within the law and to match up the law to changing conditions. The interpretation of the valve concepts which apply in private law is done on the background of the basic values of the legal system. These include the objective aspects of the constitutional rights to human dignity, freedom, property, privacy, freedom of movement and occupation. Indeed private law’s valve concepts take on a meaning which is influenced by the objective aspect of constitutional rights. This objective aspect has a “radiating effect” on the valve concepts.61 The valve concept’s content is determined through the interpretive balancing between all the values which express it, and, within them, the objective aspect of the subjective constitutional rights. I will demonstrate this through two of private law’s important valve concepts: public policy and good faith. ii. Public Policy One of the most important valve concepts is public policy. It operates in both public and private law alike. Through this concept “the legal system ensures the constant flow of fundamental values into the private law. This ensures harmony in the legal system. Through ‘public policy’ the legal system ensures the proper behavior in interpersonal relationships.”62 Main components of public policy are the values which make up the objective aspect of constitutional rights. Public policy is the fulfilling of values such as human dignity, freedom, privacy, property and freedom of occupation. 61 62 Regarding the “doctrine of radiation,” see Alexy, supra note *, at 352. Recanat case, supra note ___, at 363 (P. Barak). 21 Needless to say, alongside these values are additional values which reflect the public interest. These values are in conflict. “Often these basic principles conflict with one another…. One’s freedom of occupation limits another’s freedom of contract. expression limits another’s human dignity. One’s freedom of This is particularly obvious within the framework of “public policy” in contract law, as one of the basic principles of our legal system is the principles regarding freedom of contracts … and one of the fundamental rights of man that should be considered is that of the autonomy of the individual’s will. This is part of human dignity and freedom. Contractual relationships are an expression of this autonomy. Freedom of contracts is a constitutional right. When the contract’s content limits freedom of occupation, human dignity, freedom of movement, freedom of conscience and religion or freedom of expression – ‘public policy’ should not be shaped based on a simple use of these principles.”63 The solution to this conflict is found through proper balancing which reflects the relative importance of conflicting values. “In determining the scope of ‘public policy’ there must be an internal balance between conflicting interests and values.”64 Thus “only when the weight of the principles regarding freedom of contracts and the autonomy of the individual’s will is smaller than the weight of the opposing value – only then is there room to void a stipulation in a contract, or the entire contract, due to a conflict of public policy.”65 J. Procaccia was right to state that "determining the scope of public policy requires a delicate and complicated balance between conflicting values and interests".66 This balancing may learn, through CA 294/91, Hevrat Kadisha GAHSHA “Kehillat Yerusalayim” v. Kastenbaum, [1992] IsrSC 46(2) 464, 533 (J. Barak). 64 CA 5258/98 A. v. B., [2004] IsrSC. 48 (6) 209, 222 (P. Barak). See also CA 6601/96 AES System Inc. v. Saar [2000] IsrSC 43 (3) 850, 864. 65 Hevrat Kadisha GAHSHA “Kehillat Yerusalayim" case, supra note ___, at 533 (J. Barak). 66 CA 11081/02 Dolev v. Sigalit Kadosh (not yet published, given on 25.06.2007), at para. 18 (J. Procaccia). 63 22 interpretive analogy, from the rules of balancing set forth in the rules of constitutional proportionality.67 iii. Good Faith Good faith, for the purpose of this essay, is an objective standard. It expresses a standard of honesty, fairness and allegiance between adversaries.68 It is meant to determine that a person ensuring their matters, must do so in a manner which is fair and all the while considering the other party’s justifiable expectations. "Human being to human being, one cannot behave like a wolf, but one is not required to be an angel. Human being to human being, one must act like a human being.”69 The honesty and fairness between rivals are required by good faith and shaped by the values which make up the objective aspect of the constitutional rights. Good faith reflects the consideration of objective values regarding human dignity, privacy, property and liberty. Good faith is indeed a “pipeline”70 through which the objective values of the legal system flow through, and reflect the values of the constitutional right into private law. Additional values, related to the interpersonal behavior of those with opposite interests, also flow into it. These values are in constant conflict. Good faith reflects the proper balance between them. This balance expresses the relative social importance of 67 See Barak, Proportionality, supra note ___, at 101. FH 22/82 Beit Yules v. Raviv Moshe [1989] IsrSC 43(1) 441, 484; CA 1966/07 Amalia Ariel v. The Pension Fund of Eged Members Ltd. (not yet published, given on 9.08.2010). 69 LCA 6339/97 Roker v. Salomon [1999] IsrSC 55(1) 199, 279 (P. Barak). See also HCJ 59/80 Be'er Sheva Public Transport Services v. Beit Hadin Haartzi Leavoda [1980] IsrSC 35(1) 828, 834; Beit Yules, supra note *, at 484. 70 Roker case, supra, at 279. 68 23 the conflicting values.71 In determining this balance it is possible to learn, through analogy, from the rules of balancing that are part of constitutional proportionality. 72 III. Interpretation of Private Law and its Validity What is the case if the interpretation of private law – interpretation which takes into consideration the objective aspect of the constitutional rights – leads to a result which does not completely express this aspect? This occurs when private law determines arrangements which do not match up with the interpretive balance between the objective aspects of constitutional rights or between the other constitutionally protected objective values. What is effect of this private law? The answer is that the constitutionality of this private law will be tested. Indeed, this private law is an act of the state (whether legislation or common law). To the extent that this private law can limit the individual’s constitutional rights vis-à-vis the state, the limitation will lead to the unconstitutionality of the private law unless it fulfills the requirements of the limitation clause in general and the requirements of proportionality stricto sensu within it in particular. Thus, the radiation of the objective values at the foundation of constitutional rights onto private law does not ensure, in and of itself, that this private law is constitutional. It is possible that due to linguistic limitations, and the existence of additional and contradictory values, the means used by legislation and its interpretation, will lead the interpreter to conclude that private law limits individuals’ constitutional rights vis-à-vis the state, and that this limitation is not proportional. 71 72 See Barak, Proportionality, supra note ___, at 430. Id., at 101. 24 c. The Second Channel of Application: A Negative Arrangement and Lacunae I. The Silence of Private Law The interpretation of private law assumes the existence of relevant legal text. What happens if this text does not exist? If the absorption of the constitutional rights as objective values in private law is done through private law’s provisions – what happens if there is no relevant private law? Is this really the failure point of the indirect application? In order to answer this question we must list the different meanings of silence in private law.73 This silence has different voices. For this purpose, the two relevant meaning that can be given to such a silence are negative arrangement and lacuna. II. Negative Solution A negative solution is based on an interpretive conclusion, according to which the solution determined in the law contains an implicit negative solution regarding matters not regulated by law. At times the negative solution will reflect the objective aspects of constitutional rights. In this situation, the indirect application is resolved by the negative solution. But what is the case if a negative solution refuses the radiation stemming from the constitutional right’s objective values? What is the destiny of the indirect application is this situation? Does the latter mean that the indirect application of constitutional rights is not possible? My answer is that the non-expression of the objective aspects of constitutional rights may disproportionally limit the individual’s constitutional rights vis-à-vis the state who determined the negative solution. The result may be that the negative solution is 73 See Barak, Purposive Interpretation, supra note ___, at 67. 25 unconstitutional. Indeed, the destiny of a negative solution regarding constitutionality is the same as that of a positive solution regarding constitutionality. They both can disproportionally limit the individual’s constitutional right vis-à-vis the state. III. Lacunae We assume that the private law does not determine a text which should be interpreted with the constitutional right’s objective aspect in the background. We also assume that the lack of legislative text stems from a lacuna. Is the significance of the latter that there is no room for indirect application? In order to answer this question we must first examine the rules of lacunae and the reaction to the lacunae. If the court does not have the authority to complete the lacunae in the legislation – as is the case in most common law legal systems74 - then the lacunae remains as it. The solution to this legal problem will exhaust itself within the boundaries of the common law. The common law makes up a “security net” which is meant to solve, amongst others, most of the legislative lacunae. The only thing to examine is if this common law – similar to that of a negative solution – is constitutional. In most continental legal systems and in Israel, the court has the authority to complete a lacuna in the law.75 This complementary law is based on completion through analogy from a similar legislative norm from private law. Without a suitable analogy the judge looks to the general principles. Completion of lacunae is not merely an authority given to the judges. It is a duty imposed upon them. Once the lacuna in the legislation has been discovered, the judges 74 75 See Id., at 69. Id. 26 must complete it according to the rules used in their legal system to do so. Once the completion of the lacuna has been completed, new law has been added to private law. This complementary law was created by the judicial authority. This is sub-constitutional law. It adds a complementary norm to the legislation. Like the rules of the common law, this rule may also limit the individual’s constitutional right vis-à-vis the state. The constitutionality of this limitation will be determined according to its proportionality. d. Third Application Channel: Creating New Private Law I. New Legislation and Developing the Common Law The interpretation of private law – including its valve concepts – may lead to the conclusion, that these solutions cannot “absorb” the radiation of the objective aspect of the constitutional rights. In addition, this interpretation may lead to the conclusion, that the lack of solution in private law regarding the absorption of objective values is not a negative solution nor does it mean there is a lacuna. Has this situation led to the end of the road of the indirect application model? My answer is in the negative. If private law does not exist – it should be created. The legislator (in the framework of the legislation) and the judge (in the framework of the common law) cannot wash their hands of this. They should create new law (legislative or case law) which can express the objective values of the constitutional rights. II. New Legislation Much of private law is legislated. If there is no legislation which can “absorb” the objective aspects of constitutional rights, there is no escape from new legislation. The 27 legislator will legislate new laws to solve the problem not yet solved in private law. Through its content, the new legislation will express the objective aspect of the constitutional rights. This will be done through the legislative recognition of new individuals’ sub-constitutional rights vis-à-vis other individuals. III. The Development of the Common Law In the common law legal systems the judge’s power to create law is recognized. Contracts and Torts law in most common law legal systems are case law, where little legislation is involved. This development in the case law must take place here as well. When a judge encounters a legal problem regarding an interpersonal relationship whose basic values are derived from the objective aspect of the individual’s constitutional rights vis-à-vis the state, the judge should develop the common law in a manner that the basic constitutional values will be absorbed into private law. The development of the common law will translate the objective aspect of the constitutional rights into sub-constitutional law creating rights of individual vis-à-vis other individuals. This approach was adopted by the Constitution of South Africa that provides:76 (a)in order to give effect to a right in the Bill, must apply, or if necessary develop, the common law to the extent that legislation does not give effect to that right; and (b) may develop rules of the common law to limit the right, provided that the limitation is in accordance with section 36(1). 76 Section 8(3) of the Constitution of South Africa, Supra note 4. See also South African cases, supra note *. 28 From this provision it appears that the development of the common law is the duty of the judicial authority. It is needless to repeat that this development of the common law is possible only when the legislation does not determine a contradictory solution. The common law cannot change legislation. The judicial activity in the development of the common law, like in Holmes’ much quoted phrase, is "interstitially".77 The Supreme Court of Israel acted along these lines when it recognized compensation for a limitation of the individual’s will where surgery was carried out without the patient’s informed consent.78 Similarly the Supreme Court was asked to recognize procedural arrangements which would allow for the exposure of the identity of online commentators for slander. The request was denied by the majority.79 IV. Proportionality of new legislation and the Development of the Common Law New legislation and the development of common law must be proportional. Indeed, development of private law by the legislature or the judiciary is a state action. This action may limit a constitutional right of an individual. This limitation will be constitutional only if it's proportional.80 Therefore it must secure that the balance between the conflicting objective aspects will coincide with the balance between the individual's constitutional right vis-à-vis the state and the constitutional rights of others. This balance will be determined by proportionality stricto sensu. 77 See Southern Pacific Co. v. Jensen, 244 U.S. 205, 221. CA 2781/93 Daaka v. Carmel Hospital [1999] IsrSC 53(4) 526. 79 RCA 4447/07 Rami Mor v. Barak ESS [1995] The Company for International Telecommunications Ltd. (not yet published, given on 25/03/2010). 80 See Barak, Proportionality, supra note *, at 118. See also sec. 8(3)(b) to the Constitution of South Africa, Supra *. 78 29 V. New Legislation and the Development of the Common Law – Discretion or Obligation? i. Negative and Positive Rights The indirect application model is based on existing private law, including the completion of lacunae, which “absorbs” the objective aspect of the constitutional rights. Where such private law does not exist, the absorption of the objective aspect will be carried out by the new law anchored in legislation or common law, which develops private law. The question that arises in this matter is, is the development of this private law a discretionary activity by the legislator (in developing legislation) or the judge (in developing the common law) or a duty imposed upon them? If development of private law is not an obligation it raises the question of the efficiency of the indirect application model. The answer to this question leads us to an important issue of constitutional law, regarding the “positive” aspect of constitutional rights.81 The question is if the constitutional rights are but negative rights, meaning, rights which impose duties on the state (legislative, executive, judiciary) not to limit the right holder, or whether they are also positive right, meaning, those rights which impose a duty on the state to protect the right holder. When the approach is that the state duty is only a negative one, no duty to protect the individual’s constitutional right is imposed. This means the lack of duty to 81 Regarding this issue, see Barak, Proportionality, supra note *, at 422. See also Dieter Grimm, The Protective Function of the State in European and U.S. Constitutionalism 137 (George Nolte ed., 2005); Alastair Mowbray, The Development of Positive Obligations Under the European Convention on Human Rights by the European Court of Human Rights (2004); Sandra Freedman, Human Rights Transformed: Positive Rights and Positive Duties (2008); Henry Shue, Basic Rights: Subsistence, Affluence, and U.S. Foreign Policy 155 (2nd. Ed., 1996). 30 develop the private law in the spirit of the indirect application model. If, on the other hand, the duty of the state is also a positive duty, then the state must protect the individual’s constitutional rights vis-à-vis it from infringement by another individual. The state will have fulfilled its duties by developing the law according to the objective aspect of the constitutional right. The state will do so inter alia, if it recognizes the subconstitutional right of the right holder vis-à-vis other individuals. It will make up part of the private law. The answer to the question of the “positive aspect” of the constitutional rights changes from legal system to legal system. principle, the positive aspect.82 American law does not recognize, in The Bill of Rights is meant to prevent limiting constitutional rights by the state. They are not meant to impose upon it the duty to protect the individual. Other legal systems recognize the positive aspects of a number of rights, but not them all.83 German constitutional law recognizes the general positive aspect of all constitutional rights (the schutzplicht).84 This is the case in the Constitution of South Africa.85 The situation in the Israeli legal system is not free from doubt. It seems that the right to life, body and dignity has both a positive and negative aspect.86 The negative 82 See Jackson v. City of Joliet, 715 F. 2d 1200, 1203 (1982). For example the European Convention on Human Rights recognizes the positive aspect of a number of rights. See Mowbray, supra note ____. 84 See Dieter Grimm, The Protective Function of the State, in European and US Constitutionalism (Georg Nolte ed., 2005)ALREADY CITED IN FT. 81. 85 See Section 7(2) of the Constitution of South Africa (1996) ALREADY CITED IN FT. 4. 86 See HCJ 2557/05 Mate Harov v. Israeli Police [2006] 62(1) IsrSC 200, at para. 14 (P. Barak); CrimA 5121/98 Issacharov v. Head Military Prosecutor [2006] 61(1) IsrSC 461, at para. 62 THIS PARAGRAPH DOESN'T SEEM TO DIRECTLY DISCUSS THE POSITIVE AND THE NEGATIVE ASPECTS OF THE RIGHTS (J. Beinish); HCJ 6427/02 MGQ v. the Knesset [2006] 61(1) IsrSC 619, at para. 31 (P. Barak). 83 31 aspect (the state's duty not to limit a constitutional right) is expressed in section 2 of Basic Law: Human Dignity and Liberty: There shall be no limitation of the life, body or dignity of any person as such. The positive aspect (the state's duty to protect the constitutional right) is determined in section 4 Basic Law: Human Dignity and Liberty: All persons are entitled to protection of their life, body and dignity. Through this positive aspect the state in Israel is under a duty to protect the individual’s life, body and dignity from their infringement by other individual’s.87 The question which has not yet been resolved in Israel is if the positive aspect of the constitutional right applies only regarding the right to life, body and dignity included in Section 4 of the Basic Law or does it extend onto the entirety of the constitutional rights in this Basic Law (property, liberty, mobility, privacy) and in Basic Law: Freedom from Occupation (freedom of occupation). Recognizing the positive aspect of the constitutional right (all or some of them) raises two questions. First, do we find vis-à-vis the state's duty the individual’s right? Second, how can an individual realize the positive duty? ii. Fulfilling the Duty in Positive Rights Regarding the first question, I believe that if a duty is imposed onto the state to protect certain values, then opposite said duty stands the individual’s right.88 The state's duty is the individual’s right. Indeed, Basic Law: Human Dignity and Liberty, explicitly 87 HCJ 366/03 Commitment to Peace and Social Justice Society v. Minister of Finance [2005] 60(3) IsrLR 464, 479 (P. Barak). 88 See Grimm, supra note ___, at 153; Alexy supra note ___, at 301. 32 states that “all persons are entitled”89 to protection of their life, body and dignity. Human dignity is not only a "negative" right, but also a "positive" right. There is a constitutional obligation on the legislature, the executive and the judiciary to protect positive rights of individuals. It is not at their discretion – it is an obligation. Therefore, the judiciary is obliged to develop the common law in a manner that will guarantee protection of his rights vis-à-vis the state.90 How does the individual fulfill his positive right? My answer is that he will do so in one of the fashions available to him to realize his negative right. The German Constitutional Court has more than once ordered the legislature to use its legislative powers to fulfill the positive aspect of the constitutional rights. 91 In common law legal systems the right holder can ask the court to use its power to create common law.92 Needless to say, if this common law is not to the legislators liking, it has the power to void or change this case law. The positive aspect of the constitutional rights – similarly to the negative aspect – does not recognize an absolute positive right. This is a relative positive right. It can be limited by a proportional legal provision (statute or common law). Therefore, if not every positive aspect of the constitutional right is protected by the legal system, it is possible that this situation is constitutional as it is also proportional.93 New legislation that protects the positive right must be proportional. This is the case also for new 89 Section 4 of Israeli Basic Law: Human Dignity and Liberty, supra note ___. See Carmichele case, supra note *, in which the South African constitutional court imposed the courts to develop tort law so that it will recognize the duty of the police to take actions in order to protect individuals from the aggression of other individuals. See also, supra note 7. 91 See Grimm, supra note ___, at 153. See also Oliver and Fedtke, supra note ___, at 153. 92 See Rami Mor case, supra note * PAGE# (J. Rubinstien). 93 See Barak, Proportionality, supra note ___, at 429. 90 33 common law. Legislation which voids or changes the common law and fulfills the positive aspect is constitutional only if it is proportional. 4. The Indirect Application in Israel Basic Law: Human Dignity and Liberty and Basic Law: Freedom of Occupation determines a list of constitutional rights. The language of the Basic Laws does not determine who is the right holders. There is no explicit determination to the question if these rights are directed towards the state only or also towards other individuals. Both Basic Laws set forth that “all governmental authorities are bound to respect”94 the rights determined within them. It was not determined that this obligation is imposed only onto the state. The question of the application of the constitutional rights in interpersonal relationships (horizontal), is seemingly open and given to interpretive determination by the court. The issue arose for the first time during the Hevrat Kadisha GAHSHA “Kehillat Yerusalayim” v. Kastenbaum case.95 This case dealt with the question if relatives of the deceased are granted the right to add onto the tombstone, the deceased’s name in Latin letters as well as her date of birth and death in numbers. In my opinion I noted that this right can be based on the rules of private law. In this context I mentioned that the condition regarding having solely Hebrew letters which arises from the contract signed by the deceased’s husband, is contrary to public policy and is therefore void. This conclusion was based on the indirect application model, while noting that the question of 94 Section 11 to Israel's Basic Law: Human Dignity and Liberty, supra note ___; Section 5 to Israel's Basic Law: Freedom of Occupation, supra note ___. 95 supra note ___. 34 direct application remained open.96 The line of thinking through which the case was examined was that “the basic principles of the system in general and a person’s human rights in particular are not limited to public law. The differentiation between public and private law is not so severe. The legal system is not a confederation of legal fields. It makes up a unification of method and justice. Therefore, basic principles are principles of the entire system, and not solely of public law."97 The question I discussed in my opinion was “how do basic principles of public law flow into private law, and from there they are delivered into the individual’s behavior in his relationship with other individual’s.”98 In my answer I referred to the principles of interpretation.99 In addition, I mentioned that “private law includes a number of doctrines, which use tools through which the basic principles of the system in general and the person’s basic rights in particular flow into private law.”100 One of those doctrines is that of public policy. I noted that “this provision … channels into private law the basic principles of the law in general and basic human rights in particular.”101 I emphasized that “by transferring the basic principles of the system in general and the person’s human right in particular from public law into private, they were changed. The state's duty to fulfill human rights is different in content to the individual’s duty to fulfill human rights. It is clear the state's duty is more severe and that the protection of basic right vis-à-vis it is more expansive. However, every individual must also respect another individual’s basic rights. Indeed, the individual’s duty to fulfill the other’s basic rights is derived from the same source that 96 Ibid., at 530. Id. 98 Id. 99 Id. 100 Id. 101 Id., at 531. 97 35 the state's duty is derived from – these are the basic social understandings and the basic legal principles that the legal system is built upon.”102 The question of the indirect application arose again in the AES System Inc. v. Saar case.103 In this case an employee signed a non-compete agreement. The question was if this agreement was valid. Like in the Hevrat Kadisha GAHSHA “Kehillat Yerusalayim” case,104 it was decided that the agreement is void as it contradicts public policy. The indirect application model of constitutional rights has been recognized in all fields of private law.105 Thus, for example, it applies in contract law,106 tort law,107 property law108 and labor law.109 5. Conclusion With the recognition of the state’s duty to act – as well as the scope of this duty – the cycle is complete. The subjective constitutional right which operated in the relationship between the individual and the state on the constitutional level becomes the individual’s subjective sub-constitutional right vis-à-vis other individuals. metamorphosis takes place through three stages: This During the first stage objective constitutional values are drawn from subjective constitutional rights. During the second 102 Id. See also CA 3156/98 Ben Yishai v. Veingarten [1999] 55(1) IsrSC 939, 952 THE QUOTE DOESN'T SEEM TO APPEAR ON THIS PAGE. 103 Supra note ___. 104 Supra note ___. 105 See Hoffman, supra note *. 106 Elhannani case, supra note ___ NOT CITED ABOVE. Daphne Barak-Erez and Israel Gilad, Human Rights in Contract Law and Tort Law: The Quiet Revolution, 8 Kiryat Hamishpat 11 PAGE#(2009) (Hebrew). See also Deeksha Bhana & Marius Pieterse, Towards a Reconciliation of Contract Law and Constitutional Values: Brisley and Afrox Revisited, 122 S. Afr. L.J. 865 PAGE#(2005). 107 Id PAGE#. 108 See Hanoch Dagan, Property: Values and Institutions PAGE# (2011). 109 See Aharon Barak, Constitutional Rights and Private Law: Application in Labor Law in Elisheva (Elika) Barak Book PAGE#/CHAPTER#?(forthcoming, 2012). See also Labor Appeal No. 90/08 Isakov Inbar v. The Commissioner for Women Labor (not yet published, Feb. 8, 2011), at para. 8; Labor Appeal No. 3368-08-10 Dizingoff Club v. Zoili (not yet published, Nov. 16, 2011), at para. 11, 25 (P. Arad). 36 stage these objective values penetrate into private law – through interpretation and the completion of lacunae. During the third stage, the objective aspect of the constitutional right penetrates into private law through new legislation or new common law. If this legislation and development are the legislator’s and the judge’s duty – as there are if the legal system recognizes positive rights – then they have fulfilled their duty through the legislative or common law recognition of subjective rights at the legislative or common law level (at the sub-constitutional level) of the individual vis-à-vis the individual. This sub-constitutional law is constitutional only if it is proportional. It is important to note, that the indirect application model affects the interpersonal relationships. However, it does not turn these relationships into constitutional relationships. At the constitutional level is the relationship between the individual and the state. The relationship between individuals, whose content is affected by the indirect application, is not at the constitutional level. It is at the sub-constitutional level. It is planted into the private law (statute or common law). The constitutional level expresses the individual’s constitutional right vis-à-vis the state to its fullest extent. The constitutional possibility to limit this scope does not reduce it, but rather affects the constitutionality of the sub-constitutional law which limits it.110 This sub-constitutional norm – which reflects the private law as it was designed according to the effects of the indirect application – does not express the full scope of the constitutional right. Private law will express the constitutional right as it was limited by the other’s constitutional right and by the public interest. The individual’s right in the private law vis-à-vis another individual, will always be narrower in scope than the individual’s right vis-à-vis the 110 See Barak, Proportionality, supra note ___, at 32, 83. 37 state.111 The individual’s right vis-à-vis another individual, within private law, reflects the proportional limitations on the fulfillment of the constitutional right. It is an expression of the understanding that the individual’s constitutional right vis-à-vis the state is conveyed into the private law as an individual’s right vis-à-vis another individual. This right expresses the proportional limitations on the realization of the constitutional right vis-à-vis the state in private law. While the scope of the individual's constitutional right vis-à-vis the state is wider than the scope of the sub-constitutional right, the realization of the constitutional right vis-à-vis the state also happens within the sub-constitutional law. Hence the similarity between the two. Nonetheless, this similarity does not mean they are identical. This is due to the difference between the principles and values at the balance.112 In many cases, the result reached by indirect application model is not different from the one achieved by direct application model.113 A study of comparative law emphasizes that at times in the same legal system, two models of application are used, without the court having defined the difference between them.114 A legal system (such as German constitutional law) where all the stages occur – the transformation of a subjective constitutional right into an objective value, the penetration of objective values into private law through interpretation and the completion of lacunae, the duty to develop the private law by the legislator – will make up solutions according to both very similar methods of application. However, the difference between them should not be blurred. The results will not always be the same; the objective aspect of every constitutional right will not always be recognized; the purposive interpretation which grants an interpretive 111 Hevrat Kadisha case, supra note ___, at 531. See Medical Organization case, supra note * NOT CITED ABOVE At para. 20 (J. Naor); Ben Yishai case, supra note *, at 952. 113 See Kum & Comella, supra note ___. 114 See Oliver & Fedlke, supra note ___, at 520-557. 112 38 status to the objective purpose of every legal norm will not always apply; the legal system will not always agree to the penetration of objective values into its valve concepts; a duty will not always be imposed on the legislator and judiciary to develop the law in a fashion which fulfills the objective aspect of the constitutional rights. In any case where one of the stages is not activated in a complete fashion, the difference between the direct and indirect application models will be emphasized. Even if all stages are completely activated, there will still be a clear difference between the direct and indirect application models. This difference is expressed by the fact that in the direct application model the individual has a constitutional right vis-à-vis another individual. The indirect application model does not recognize a constitutional right between individuals. The indirect application model recognizes the individual’s sub-constitutional right (legislative or common law) vis-à-vis another individual. This difference may have little practical significance, because in both models the realization of the right, and the remedies for its limitation, are on a sub-constitutional level. There may be little difference between the content of a sub-constitutional law that realizes the right of an individual vis-à-vis the state and the content of a sub-constitutional law that realizes the right of an individual vis-à-vis another individual. Nonetheless, there is still a difference. The reason for this is that the interests and values taken into account in forming a subconstitutional law that deals with the right of an individual vis-à-vis the state differs greatly from the interests and values taken into account in forming a sub-constitutional law that deals with the right of an individual vis-à-vis another individual. :הערות מבניות 39 .1רווחים אחרי סוף משפט – במרבית המשפטים (הן בגוף הטקסט והן בהערות השוליים) אחרי הנקודה בסוף משפט מופיעים שני רווחים במקום רווח אחד [אפשר למחוק את הרווחים באמצעות פונקיית החיפוש/החלפה]. .2בטקסט מתורגם ,יש לציין את מקור התרגום (רשמי/עצמי). הערות כלליות: .1דחיית הנימוק הראשון לאימוץ מודל התחולה הישירה אחד הטעמים האפשריים לאימוץ מודל התחולה הישירה הוא שהכוח הנצבר בידי גופים פרטיים הופך גופים אלה לדומים בהיקף השפעתם למדינה .במאמר טעם זה נדחה בין השאר משום שתחולה ישירה לא תחזק את הצד החלש ,מאחר שגם הצד החזק יהנה מזכות חוקתית זהה (למשלAcknowledging the " : horizontal effect will not strengthen the weaker party, for on the other side of the .)"equation will stand a stronger individual with an identical constitutional right ואולם ,מן הטקסט לא לגמרי ברור ,האם העובדה ששני הצדדים מחזיקים בזכות בעלת היקף זהה משפיעה בהכרח גם על תוצאת האיזון בין שתי זכויות אלה .לכאורה ,גם אם האינטרס של הצד החזק מוגן על ידי זכות חוקתית ,מבחני המידתיות (למשל ,הנזק/תועלת שייגרמו לצד החלש מול הנזק/תועלת שייגרמו לצד החזק) אמורים להעניק לצד החלש הגנה טובה מספיק כדי לאיין את היעדר המאזן בין הצדדים. (ייתכן וחקיקה אכן מספיקה כדי לפתור מצבים אלה מבלי להידרש לשיח הזכויות ,אך נראה שנימוק יחסי הכוחות בין הצדדים מובא כנימוק נפרד שעומד בפני עצמו). הצעה :אולי יש מקום לפרט מדוע העובדה שגם הצד החזק יהנה מזכות חוקתית לא יוביל בכל זאת להגנה טובה יותר על הצד החלש לאחר האיזון בין הזכויות. .2ההבדל הפרקטי בין תחולה ישירה לתחולה עקיפה המאמר מפרט בפרק המסקנה (פרק )5את ההבדלים התיאורטיים בין מודל התחולה הישירה לבין מודל התחולה העקיפה ומוסיף שהם לא תמיד יובילו לאותה תוצאה. 40 ואולם ,בטקסט לא מובאות דומגאות ספציפיות (בפסיקה הקיימת או אף כדוגמה דמיונית) שיפרטו את הנסיבות בהן צפוי להיות הבדל בתוצאה אליה יובילו שני המודלים. הצעה :אולי יש מקום להציג בפרק ,5בקצרה ,דוגמה פרטנית שתבהיר את ההבדל בין המודלים גם במבחן התוצאה. 41