CONFERENCE ON DEMOCRATIC TRANSITION AND CONSOLIDATION Working Group1: Constitutional Design Coordinator: Richard Simeon Constitutional Design Alec Stone Sweet Although I emphasize rights and constitutional adjudication throughout this discussion paper, other aspects of constitutional architecture - executive/legislative relations, the legislative process and administrative oversight, the electoral systems, and so on - are as, or more, important in consolidating practices that may be crucial to stable democracy. Session One a. How do we strike the balance between the constitution as defender of rights, protecting minorities, and limiting government; and the constitution as an instrument of democratic governance and majority rule? Unfortunately, there is simply no easy or right answer to this question in any polity that seeks, through constitutional design, to establish, for the long term, (1) sufficient protection of basic human rights (and/or a viable federalism), and (2) responsible democratic government. The tension between values associated with fairness and justice (which are furthered through rules that limit government and protect minorities) and values associated with majority rule and decisionmaking efficiency (which are furthered through rules that enable those who are elected to enact their preferred policies) is both constant and inevitable. 1/10 CONFERENCE ON DEMOCRATIC TRANSITION AND CONSOLIDATION Alec Stone Sweet In Western Europe after World War II, in Southern Europe in the 1970s, and in Central and Eastern Europe in the 1990s, no major party involved in constitutional negotiations opposed (re)establishing a parliamentary system of government. The parliamentary model owes its popularity to its capacity to combine centralized government and representative democracy. At the same time, the disastrous experiences of Fascism, the Holocaust, and authoritarian state socialism fatally subverted the dogma that political majorities, or legislatures, could do no wrong, and placed the issue of human rights and limited government at the heart of the constitutional design agenda. Put very simply, the ideology of majority rule, and its corollary parliamentary sovereignty, was replaced by the ideology of higher law constitutionalism: every act of public authority must conform to the dictates of the constitution, including rights provisions, as interpreted and applied by some independent jurisdiction (e.g., a judge), or be considered unlawful. • Any polity that actually does protect human rights with minimal effectiveness, will limit majority rule in ways that will periodically be uncomfortable, sometimes unbearable, for political majorities. Rights provisions, after all, constitute substantive constraints on the exercise of all public authority. Yet with few exceptions, every successful new constitution that has appeared during the past fifty years contains extensive catalogues of rights - both negative and positive - as well as some form of judicial authority to enforce these provisions, especially against conflicting statutory authority. Across Europe, such constitutions were typically negotiated among representatives of the established political parties, who disagreed fundamentally about the nature and scope of rights to be enshrined. 2/10 CONFERENCE ON DEMOCRATIC TRANSITION AND CONSOLIDATION Alec Stone Sweet Conflicts over rights has actually turned out to be an advantage, where it leads the parties to agree to disagree, to the benefit of expanding rights protection, and orients the parties, and then citizens and groups, towards constitutional deliberation - argument, interpretation, and adjudication - as a proper and effective way to adapt the constitution, on an ongoing basis, to the polity's needs. In any case, it is never better for negotiating parties to set aside arguments about rights and their protection, simply because such arguments threaten to paralyze the rest of the constitution-making project. Last, the importance of constitutional adjudication to the protection of rights and minorities in any polity is heavily conditioned by how the constitution is designed in other ways. Where electoral systems chronically reproduce coalition governments, where legislative processes are laden with veto points, where competences are shared between national and subnational units of governments, radical reform legislation is less likely to be produced than in polities where policymaking powers are relatively centralized (i.e, veto free). A legislative reform is radical to the extent that it moves the situation away from the status quo (the initial situation governed by legislation then in place). By its very nature, reform provokes resistance because, its implementation will be costly to those who benefit from existing social relations and legal entitlements. Radical reforms strain or tear the web of existing legal regimes, administrative practices, and case law that has developed as reforms have been consolidated and institutionalized over time. Thus, we can expect that, other things being equal, the more a political system produces reform, the more it will produce a complex set of constitutional disputes that the courts will be asked to resolve. 3/10 CONFERENCE ON DEMOCRATIC TRANSITION AND CONSOLIDATION Alec Stone Sweet Session Two b. How can the constitution - including mechanisms for amendment and interpretation - be designed to ensure sufficient flexibility to meet changing needs, yet be rigid enough to withstand subversion by transient majorities? Assume that a central objective of constitutional design is to foster practices that will induce elected officials, administrators, and judges to engage in meaningful constitutional deliberation on their own, and in their interactions with other actors, and thus to participate in the continuous negotiation of the balance between the values of majority rule and efficiency, on the one hand, and those of fairness and justice, on the other. First, rights should be entrenched by giving them some kind of supraconstitutional status, through raising thresholds for their amendment (Spain), or insulating them from revision altogether (in effect, Germany). Rights texts, are, by their nature, flexible: they are typically open-textured, often vague; they may contain their own exceptions, or appear to be in contradiction with one another. Once entrenched, they become both flexible and rigid, in the strict sense that their revision can normally take place only through constitutional adjudication, that is, through processes of constitutional deliberation. Second, the diffusion and institutionalization of constitutional deliberation among important actors in the system can be provoked by establishing liberal rules of standing, that is, through permitting a wide range of people to challenge the constitutionality of public acts before a judge or court. Germany and Spain, for example, permit parliamentary minorities to attack legislation proposed by parliamentary majorities before the constitutional court; they permit parties to judicial disputes to raise constitutional questions 4/10 CONFERENCE ON DEMOCRATIC TRANSITION AND CONSOLIDATION Alec Stone Sweet in litigation before a judge; and they permit any individual to send a constitutional claim directly to the constitutional court. Third, the constitution ought to specify the rights and duties of judges. Provisions should guarantee judicial independence, at a minimum by fixing judges' terms of office and insulating them from removal or punishment by political officials (in all but the most extreme situations), and require that courts justify their decisions with reasons. Taken together, transient majorities, as well as state officials more generally, will be placed in the shadow of constitutional adjudication, and thus have an interest in taking seriously the requirements of that law in their day-to-day decisionmaking. c. Should the constitution attempt to resolve all outstanding issues and spell out detailed rules for governance; or is it preferable to leave some issues outstanding, with gaps, abeyances, and silences left for future resolution? Some provisions must be drafted with clarity in mind, including provisions that (1) guarantee regular, free elections, (2) constitute the various institutions of government and their jurisdictional attributes, and (3) determine how statutes and other legal acts are to be made. These are "rules of the game" which can only provide the benefits to all competing parties to the extent that they are consensually understood and accepted. For other provisions, significant gaps should be tolerated, even encouraged, including those spelling out rights and the precise boundaries governing jurisdictional relationships in federalism. These are areas in which flexible, on-going, case-by-case deliberation and adjudication are the appropriate methods of adapting the constitution over 5/10 CONFERENCE ON DEMOCRATIC TRANSITION AND CONSOLIDATION Alec Stone Sweet time, precisely because it is impossible at any ex ante moment to fix their terms in a determinant way. d. Can the gap between constitutional ideals and governmental performance erode the legitimacy of the constitutional order? Yes, if by "constitutional ideals" we mean provisions that are expected to be binding but are ignored by those in government. There can hardly be a worse situation than one in which elected officials choose to ignore or violate constitutional provisions with impunity. No, if by "governmental performance" we mean the failure of political majorities to enact good policy. The "legitimacy of the constitutional order" should be clearly distinguished from the support or lack of support for a given policy, or of that policy's apparent success or failure, so long as the policy in question has been produced through lawful, constitutional means. Of course, the degree to which this distinction is made is only an indicator, rather than an explanation, of a constitution's success. Session Four b. What are the strengths and weaknesses of alternative methods for constitutional adaptation: judicial interpretation, formal amendment, and evolving practices and conventions? Where constitutionalism is relatively robust, these three methods are rarely "alternatives" at all, but are often linked processes. Judicial interpretation can provoke amendment, either to ratify or consolidate what judges have done, or to reconstruct or undo it. Conventions, too, once developed, may serve as the basis for amendment, if the rules 6/10 CONFERENCE ON DEMOCRATIC TRANSITION AND CONSOLIDATION Alec Stone Sweet they contain have been shown to be useful to the major parties or other actors. And conventions may simply be best strategies adopted as a result of how the constitution has been interpreted by a judge. It is difficult to imagine a new constitution being silent on rights. Yet if a polity chooses to protect rights through constitutional provision, then it also has little choice but to establish a mechanism for the enforcement of the normative superiority of the constitution over statute and other norms. The same applies to the question of federalism. Constitutional judicial review, wherever it is effective, leads to the relative dominance of interpretation and adjudication over constitutional development. The statement does not imply a government of judges, since judges are only one set of actors who engage in the interpretation of the constitution, in interactions with other actors. The effective adaptation of the constitution through judicial interpretation is a powerful indicator of the success of a constitution. Going to judges to resolve constitutional disputes legitimizes the higher law and reinforces the centrality of constitutional judicial review, even when, in response, a constitutional decision is "overturned" through formal amendment. Again, this does not imply that judges "control" constitutional development in any definitive way, to the extent that: courts are activated by a wide range of non-judicial actors; they settle legal problems that are raised by a prexisting matrix of law and policy laid down, at least in part, by executives and legislators; and they take decisions that fall within the parameters established by the larger, ongoing policy debates. Judges are just one set of actors who engage constitutional issues; but where they do their jobs effectively, their work powerfully structure how non-judicial actors pursue their constitutional objectives. 7/10 CONFERENCE ON DEMOCRATIC TRANSITION AND CONSOLIDATION Alec Stone Sweet The rules governing formal amendment of the constitution should be more restrictive than the rules governing amendment of a statute, e.g., by requiring a supramajoritarian vote, and/or the consent of other institutions or of the citizenry through referendum. Where this is the case, state officials become players within arenas governed by relatively stable rules, rather than masters of the rules themselves. Where this is the case, judicial interpretations of the constitution and declarations of unconstitutionality can only be overruled when there is a relatively wide political consensus that the judges got it wrong. Put differently, it is appropriate that some controversial legislative reforms be adopted only through the revision of the constitution, to the extent that the procedures for amending the constitution provoke or require wide constitutional deliberation. c, d. What are the most appropriate fora and decision rules for constitutional discussion? How can the processes of constitution-making and constitutional change be structured so as to minimize self-interested behavior? "Self-interested behaviour" should not be "minimized," per se. Where constitutionalism is robust, self-interested behaviour is what animates processes of constitutional development, while not necessarily determining outcomes. To take an example, in Europe abstract review of legislation is initiated by opposition parliamentarians, for three reasons, each of which is self-interested. They hope to (1) block the majority's reforms, thus maintaining the status quo, (2) deal the government a defeat, to 8/10 CONFERENCE ON DEMOCRATIC TRANSITION AND CONSOLIDATION Alec Stone Sweet be registered in the press and public opinion, and (3) shape constitutional development in a direction that will best conform to the opposition's policy priorities. Of course, the majority will defend its projects as best it can, based on its own interests, and the argument will be transferred to the constitutional court for consideration and resolution. In places like France, where abstract review is the only mode of review available, the constitution would have little vitality or agency in the polity if political actors did not behave in a selfinterested manner. A similar analysis could be made about American-style judicial review (and European concrete review). Interests (social, political, economic) set judicial agendas and fix parameters for argumentation and decisionmaking. To be effectively pursued, interests have to be expressed in the language that a judge can hear and understand, typically a language that emphasizes judicial doctrine and precedent. A robust constitutionalism is one in which self-interest combines with principled discourse to produce outcomes. The trick is to channel self-interested behavior through processes established by the constitution (e.g., through liberal standing rules, rules establishing the independence of the judiciary). Underlying all of these points, of course, is the problem of uncertainty. Can those who negotiate constitutions be induced to pre-commit themselves to living under rules whose development they will not be able to directly control? It bears noting that are good reasons to be deeply critical of the expansion of judicial power and the attendant "juridification" of political life. In the view of some scholars, a polity is made worse off when it recasts most or all social problems as legal ones; juridification privileges lawyers and their way of doing politics, and stifles what some consider to be a more liberating, "deliberative," democracy. I disagree: to the extent 9/10 CONFERENCE ON DEMOCRATIC TRANSITION AND CONSOLIDATION Alec Stone Sweet that it is exercised with effectiveness, constitutional adjudication generates an expansive, relatively participatory deliberative mode of governance, one that would not have emerged in the absence of constitutional review. Session Five a. What is the contribution of a constitution to the processes of democratic transition? b. What is the contribution of a constitution to democratic consolidation? A "transition" that delays dealing with constitutional design issues is much more likely to be stillborn than one that works hard, even obsessively, to get the constitution "right." For reasons that are well known and can be expressed in a variety of theoretical languages, it is difficult to imagine a successful democratic transition and consolidation absent the prior elaboration of a sustainable constitution. By "constitution," I mean, at least, the authoritative higher-order rules that govern how all other authoritative, lowerorder rules shall be made, thus "validating" them juridicially (generically: Hart's secondary rules, Kelsen's grundnorm). c. By what criteria do we judge or evaluate success or failure in constitutional design? I would emphasize two: (1) the constitution's durability, measured in terms of the number of peaceful alternations in power of different political parties, following elections; (2) the constitution's capacity to draw the major actors in the polity into a discursive politics about the nature and meaning of the constitutional law. 10/10