PLATO ON FALSE PAINS AND MODERN COGNITIVE SCIENCE George Couvalis and Mathew Usher INTRODUCTION A common sense assumption about pains (and pleasures) is that they are mere sensations with a specific sensational character. Terms like ‘pain’ (‘pleasure’) are sometimes used metaphorically, but insofar as those terms are used literally, they designate items that have a common sensory component that is shared by all pains (all pleasures). Pains (and pleasures) may be contingently connected with other types of sensation or with beliefs. However, the defining character of pains (pleasures) is due to their specific sensational component. What makes pains painful (and pleasures pleasant) is this sensational component that all pains (all pleasures) have in common. Further, the badness of pains (and the goodness of pleasures) for the experiencing subject is an intrinsic property of their specific sensational character. Pains and pleasures differ in quantitative ways, for instance in their intensity or their duration, but they do not differ intrinsically in any other interesting respect. In Plato’s Philebus, Protarchus, a well meaning hedonist, defends this kind of view.1 In various places, Protarchus makes it clear that he considers pleasure to be a phenomenon that comes from different sources, but is always qualitatively identical (eg 12d-13c, 38a). On his account, when we get pleasure from watching a comedy by Aristophanes, our pleasure consists only of pleasant sensations caused by the comedy. If there is any thought component involved in our pleasure, it is completely separable from the sensations (the thought being the cause or the effect of the sensations). Regardless of what we think (true or false) about the comedy, such as that it reflects important aspects of real life, our pleasure seems to involve no possible misconceptions. Further, any other sensations caused by the comedy, such as the sensations induced by our jaws moving when we laugh, are only causally connected with the sensations of pleasure. In the Philebus, Plato puts into the mouth of Socrates the startling claim that pleasures and pains can be false. Plato means that pleasures and pains can be false in various ways, and some of his claims may be wrongheaded. 2 For instance, he sometimes seems to defend the bizarre thesis that false pleasures do not exist. We will focus on the claim that pleasures and pains can be false because they essentially involve judgements or beliefs. We take Plato to be saying that what makes pains painful and pleasures pleasant is that they essentially involve propositional attitudes with an intentional content which is about the external world and which is capable of being true or false. We will argue that Plato is right in this claim even though some of his other claims may be false. Plato wants to defend it in order to conclude that false pleasures are not really good. We will not consider the merits of this conclusion here. PLATO'S ACCOUNT 1 We have followed the normal convention of referring to passages in Plato which is to use the Stephanus numbers that are commonly used in scholarly references to the work of Plato. These numbers and letters indicate the corresponding section on the relevant volumes of the Greek text, in this case the Philebus except where stated. 2 Frede, D., Disintegration and Restoration : Pleasure and Pain in Plato’s Philebus., in Kraut, R., ed. Cambridge Companion to Plato, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1992, p. 443 At least four types of falsity are considered by Plato, (1) Pleasures and pains as propositional attitudes, (2) Falsity of overrated pleasures and pains, (3) Falsity in the identification of pleasure with freedom from pain, (4) Falsity of pleasures intrinsically mixed with pain. 1 Plato’s background justifications Plato partly justifies his view by means of contentious metaphysical claims about the limited (peiron) and the unlimited (apeiron), and about whether pleasures and pains really have being or substance (ousia). These claims are intended to connect a problematic metaphysics with his biological theory of the function of pain and pleasure. We will not be discussing his metaphysics in detail. However, we will be working within his metaphysical framework in some crucial respects. First, Plato is trying to come up with a definition of pleasure and pain as they really are. He wants to do this in part so that he can grasp what makes pains painful and pleasures pleasant. This is not, as he understands it, merely a conceptual task. It is a task in which we are engaged in grasping the real nature of items in the world. (By analogy, think of investigating the real nature of water and not merely its nominal essence in order to understand why it is a liquid at room temperature.) Like Plato, we are not merely doing conceptual analysis but trying to discover something about the nature of pain. A second, related, way in which we will be working within Plato's metaphysical framework is that like him, we think that understanding the physiology of pain is crucial to understanding the nature of pain. Modern commentators avoid detailed discussion of physiology, perhaps because they think he made a conceptual error in bringing a scientific model into a central part of his philosophical argument.3 However, some modern authors have argued that a physiological conceptualisation is necessary for understanding the ontology of pain.4 In the last half century, essentialism has revived in the philosophy of language, the philosophy of mind and the philosophy of science. What were once thought to be Plato's conceptual confusions might now be thought to be deep insights. In any case, Plato's line of argument in the dialogue make it clear that Plato thought that physiology would provide one of the important supports for his account. We will not be discussing Plato's physiology in detail in what follows, for although it may well have been advanced for its time, it has been replaced by more advanced work. Instead, we will focus on vindicating Plato's argument with some recent psychological and neurophysiological research on pain. Throughout the dialogue, Plato exploits the fact that pain and pleasure words in Greek (as in English) can be used to designate states which clearly involve complex emotions and belief-like states. He uses various root words to cover pleasure and pain which can be used to designate what are called mental pleasure and pain as well as what seem to be mere sensations. One root word he uses for pain is algos, which is a rather broad word covering all kinds of unpleasant states. Another is lipi, which covers both mental and what is commonly thought to be bodily distress. He also uses three root words for pleasure: one word, hedone, means delight or enjoyment; hairein means to rejoice; and terpsis means gladness or enjoyment. It might be thought that Plato merely exploits a metaphorical connection between some emotional states and 3 For non-physiologically based discussions of false pleasures of the propositional type see, Williams, B.A.O. Pleasure and Belief Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume (XXXIII) 1959 also reprinted in Hampshire, S., ed. Philosophy of Mind, London, Harper & Row, 1966, pp. 22542. Penner T. M., False Anticipatory Pleasures. Phronesis, 5, 1970, pp. 166-178. Frede, D., Rumplestilskins Pleasures : True and False Pleasures in Plato’s Philebus Phronesis, 30, 1985, pp. 151180 4 A good example is Grahek, N., Feeling Pain and Being in Pain, Hanse Institute for Advanced Study, 1, Oldenburg, University of Oldenburg, 2001. 2 pains (pleasures). However, Mary Hesse and others have pointed out that what might be thought to be merely metaphorical connections between items often turn out to be deep similarities between them. Such similarities can be indicated by the appearance of various items, as well as by similarities in their effects. Intellectual progress often consists in coming to grasp that what were thought to be merely analogical or metaphorical connections are really cases of deep similarity.5 We will see that although physical pains and unpleasant emotional states are importantly different, they nevertheless have deep and not merely shallow similarities. Plato’s arguments Plato initially claims that just because a group of items come under the rubric ‘pleasure’ (or the rubric ‘pain’) does not necessarily mean that they are alike in their goodness (badness). They may be opposed to one another just as the colours black and white can be said to be opposed to one another while still being colours. More importantly, they are not alike essentially because of a common sensational content (12d-13c). There may be a sensational component shared by pains, but it is not what unifies pains as painful (pleasures as pleasant). Further, he hints that once we realise what unifies them is that they are propositional attitudes of a certain kind, we realise that they can be not merely alike but importantly different because some can be true while others are false. To stun Protarchus, Socrates argues that memory is crucially involved in any enduring pleasures, as pleasures could not survive from one moment to the next without a background memory (21b-c).6 Plato hints that the process involved must be in some sense intelligent as it involves bringing together a memory of past sensational contents with present sensational contents and treating them as one continuous item. Further, Socrates argues that to enjoy ourselves we must be able to judge that we are enjoying ourselves, and this clearly involves an intelligent process. These arguments don’t establish that pleasures (and pains) are propositional attitudes, though they seem to show that some sort of cognition is essentially involved in the pleasantness of pleasures (and the painfulness of pains). To understand why, consider that when we perceive items in the external world, their existence is not dependent on our perceptions. In their case, the intelligent use of memory is only necessary in order to perceive them. However, when we perceive pains as painful (and pleasures as pleasant), the mode of our perception of them seems to be essential to their painfulness (pleasantness). This means that a cognitive state involving background memory seems to be not only necessary for perceiving them, but an essential part of them. At 35a-e Socrates follows up his earlier arguments by putting the claim that pleasures (and pains) must be understood to be intentional states directed towards objects of desire (or aversion). As he puts this point, they are states of the soul and not of the body. In his argument, he treats as types of pain thirst, hunger and other states that he takes to necessarily involve desire. His underlying claim is that for states to be pleasant or painful, there must be a perception that something makes up for a lack in us (and/or a perception that something is lacking in us). Such perceptions cannot be 5 A famous example is the apparently metaphorical description of light as a wave. See Hesse, M., Models and Analogies in Science, Notre Dame, Indiana, University of Notre Dame Press, 1966 ; Lamb, D., Discovery, Creativity and Problem-Solving, Aldershot, Avebury, 1991 6 See also Philebus, 33c, 34a, 35a-d, 36b, for more on the role of memory. 3 merely given in some pure sensory content. For us to be pleased or pained we must be aware of a lack in us and be aware that some object is the opposite of that lack in the sense that we must perceive it as the remedy for that lack. We are in touch with the objects in the world which we know will make up for a lack in us through memory. In modern terms, there is a specific kind of ‘this is good for me’ intentionality involved in pleasure (and ‘this is bad for me’ intentionality involved in pain). For Plato, infant thirst has a minimal intentional character for it is consciousness of a lack in the body and a desire for filling which is not intentionally directed towards a specific external object. It differs from the thirst of experienced individuals which has a more full blooded intentional character; for experienced thirst is a desire for things outside the body in which memories of what has previously been experienced to fill it are crucially involved. Such intentional states involve necessarily memories of past events and beliefs that certain things are beneficial or dangerous. In the Theaetetus (156b), Plato had put pleasures and pains in the same category as hearings, seeings, fears and other items. He called them perceptions (aistheses). To treat them in this way is already to treat them as judgements which are more than sensations. In the Philebus, which is written later, he treats some pleasures and pains as perceptions. For instance, he often treats pains as the perception of a deficit, and pleasures as the perception of the restoration of a deficit (31d-32b). However, Plato makes clear that he thinks a pleasurable perception is (typically) not only the perception of restoration, but a perception that a particular external object is restoring us. Further, in the Philebus, it is not essential to pleasures or pains that they be perceptions, for there are anticipatory pleasures in which the body is not involved, but only the soul (32c-33c, 35c-e). Plato treats such anticipatory pleasures, which obviously involve sophisticated cognitive states, as paradigmatic examples in order to argue that all pleasures and pains have a sophisticated cognitive component that is essential to them. At 36c Socrates directly introduces the idea the pleasures and pains can be true or false. Protarchus indicates that he cannot see how this is possible. Socrates draws an analogy with fears expectations and judgements, claiming that they can all be true or false. (Fears and expectations seem to necessarily involve anticipatory judgements). However, Protarchus denies that this is true except in the case of judgements. Socrates gets Protarchus to say that there is something a pleasure is about at 37a. Socrates then asks why pleasure 'admits only truth' whereas judgements admit of truth or falsity? What he is getting at seems to be that it is puzzling that when we are pleased we can be in no doubt that we are pleased, whereas when we judge, for instance, that something is round, we can be mistaken. He follows his question up later with the question: how is it that pleasures can be bad? He wants to say that we can only answer these questions if we treat pleasures as like perceptions in which it is as if there were a picture in the soul but also a judgement. I take it he means that if we understand pleasures in this way, we could be in no doubt that there is a judgement and we can understand how the judgement could be bad - the badness would be a kind of falsity. He also says that the proper way to understand the nature of fear and anger is similar. We will not discuss the later parts of the dialogue. It is important to note that at many points we are shown through Protarchus' behaviour that while Plato can make 4 his position plausible, he is unable to provide a very strong case for it. Protarchus often agrees with Socrates, but then withdraws his agreement or shows his discomfort with it. This is not because Protarchus is shown to be debauched like Philebus. On the contrary, he is portrayed as a genuine seeker after truth who can vaguely grasp that Socrates' line of argument is subject to a general objection. The general objection is that Socrates is constantly mixing up items that are contingently connected with pleasure (pain) with pleasure (pain). Had Plato not been so biased in favour of his own view, he might have shown this more clearly in the dialogue. For instance, in response to Socrates' view about anticipatory pleasures, he might have had Protarchus attempt to distinguish the pleasures from the sophisticated judgements which produce them. In following this line of thought, Protarchus would have consistently denied that pleasures and pains have an intentional object, something he foolishly admits in the dialogue. If he were to argue in this way, Protarchus would not be producing an ad hoc hypothesis to defend his view, for when we are pained, we always seem to be in the grip of very obvious sensations which have a specific character. These might be thought to be constitutive of the painfulness of pain. Thus, it is not unreasonable for Protarchus to think that it is solely sensational content that makes pain unpleasant and that judgement is only contingently connected with the unpleasantness of pain. Protarchus might have become a thorough Benthamite by following this line of argument. He might have claimed that the pleasure the axe murderer gets in killing is in itself good, even if the axe murderer's actions are bad all things considered. We have argued that Plato's argument for his view is inadequate. Modern defenders of his view have relied on conceptual analysis or intuition. Arguments from conceptual analysis or intuition are subject to the general objection that pains might be quite different from the ways in which we conceive them. After all, science has shown that the folk concepts of a vacuum and of heat are quite inadequate. Remember, however, that we have emphasised that Plato relies in important part on an antiquated biology and psychology of pain. This makes us realise that an up to date biology and psychology of pain might bear out his view. Three kinds of evidence might be discovered: A) Evidence that there are two biological systems which can be dissociated, one producing the sensory component of pain and one producing the propositional attitude component which makes pain unpleasant. (We are speaking here of what cognitive scientists call a double dissociation.) B) Evidence that the propositional attitude component of pain is crucial to making non-central cases of pain unpleasant. C) Evidence that in typical cases of pain, the sensational component is not essential. As we will see, modern research has brought to light evidence of kinds A and B, but has rendered Plato's attempted unification of unpleasant states solely via their propositional attitude content problematic.7 MODERN RESEARCH Researchers have turned up three types of cases that are particularly relevant to Plato's account. All three types of cases usually result from lesion damage or surgery 7 The reader should note that there is another line of argument Plato could take, which is to argue by using modern research that the sensational content itself is representational. As far as we can tell, this is true, but the representational content has nothing to do with the painfulness of pain. On the contrary, it is emotionally inert. This means that while pointing out that the sensory content of pain is representational would undermine Protarchus, it would not support Plato. 5 to very specific parts of the brain, although they can be the result of other conditions. People who have the conditions we will describe can be otherwise normal and certainly quite rational. In cases of type 1, which are called cases of 'pain asymbolia', people report that they feel pain and can describe it in considerable detail while saying that it does not bother them. Such people commonly laugh in surprise at the fact that they are in pain and sometimes even describe the pain as 'agonising', despite the fact that the pain does not bother them. In type 2 cases, people are not bothered by what would normally be dull chronic pains unless they are brought to their attention and they focus on them. They then dislike them. When their attention goes elsewhere, they are not bothered by pain at all. In type 3 cases, patients report unpleasantness, but, apart from locating it only in the vaguest manner, cannot specify its sensory characteristics. In the best described case, the patient could not characterise the feeling he had in terms of the well known characteristics of pains. For instance, he did not have a feeling that he would characterise as burning, prickling, cold or hot. He could not describe the feeling as slight pain or intense pain. He had a feeling somewhere between fingertips and shoulder that he could only characterise as unpleasant and wanted to avoid. Although the feeling was actually produced by the researchers by stimulating pain fibres, the subject did not perceive the unpleasantness as pain. 8 What explains such bizarre behaviour in otherwise largely normal people? The repeated results of various studies, including brain scans, have led researchers to consider the pain system to be two interactive yet distinct subsystems. 9 We have what is called a ‘sensory discriminative’ system and this gives us the location, intensity, duration, and nature (stabbing, burning, prickling) component of the stimulus.10 We also have the affective motivational system that consists of several structures and it is the activity of these structures that make pain experiences phenomenologically unpleasant.11 The activities of the two systems can be dissociated. When we realise this, we can produce a simple explanation of why people who have pain asymbolia laugh in surprise at the fact that they can have intense pain that does not bother them. The explanation is that the folk concept of pain mistakenly includes in it the belief that the characteristic sensations of pain can only occur if unpleasant pain affect occurs. 8 Ploner, M., Freund, H.-J., and Schnitzler, A., Pain affect without pain sensation in a patient with a postcentral lesion Pain, 81,1999, pp. 211- 214. Also, Fentanyl causes painfulness yet severely inhibits our discriminatory sensitivity. Sufferers of Parkinson’s disease and Huntington’s chorea often report that they feel pains but are unable to localise them. See Hardcastle, V.G., The Myth of Pain, Cambridge Massachusetts, MIT Press, 1999, p 104 9 Aydede, M., An Analysis of Pleasure Vis-aVis Pain, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 61, 3, Nov 2000, p. 544-545 10 ibid, p. 545 This system is served by the ventrobasal thalamus at which noxious stimuli arrive through the spinothalamic and neospinothalamic projection systems and go directly to the somatosensory cortex. 11 ibid, p. 549 6 The Sensory and Affective Systems The sensory system, gives discriminative information about the location, intensity, duration, and nature of noxious stimuli. It is served by networks of nerve fibres found in most of our tissue. Nerve endings in our tissues called receptors, come in many different types and their receptive fields often overlap.12 Damage at any point in our tissue will activate at least two or more of these networks and send nerve impulses along sensory nerve fibres that run into the spinal cord.13 The sensory pain fibres come in two types A-delta (Ad) and C fibres. Nerve impulses produced by injury are conducted rapidly to the central nervous system by Ad fibres which are very sensitive to the specific injurious agent’s pressure, thermal, or chemical characteristics. C fibres are also sensitive to characteristics of injurious stimuli but are much slower in transmission than Ad fibres. 14 The C fibres have an important function based on their release of chemicals into nerve endings. 15 This chemical signalling system is the basis for the increased excitability, sensitivity changes and long lasting effects like tenderness of the area, that follow injury.16 The firing of Ad fibres is an important causal agent in causing immediate acute pain. The firing of C fibres is important in causing chronic pain.17 Indifference to these noxious signals from nerve fibres can occur as a result of disease (congenital, and psychosis), but also in quite normal and healthy people whose attention is engaged elsewhere, as in sports people and soldiers.18 It is important to note here that indifference to noxious stimuli is not the same as pain asymbolia. In these cases people are indifferent to noxious stimuli that normally, but are not in this case, accompanied by unpleasant feelings, that is, they are not conscious of injury or pain, whereas in asymbolia cases people are indifferent to pain which is present at the forefront of consciousness.19 The limbic system is a collection of structures that surround the thalamus on each side of the brain and includes parts called the hypothalamus, hippocampus, amygdala, septum and cingulum. 20 It is often referred to by researchers as the, ‘emotional HQ’ of the mind.21 Surrounding these is the cerebral cortex (which is of course larger and more developed in more highly cognitive animals).22 The limbic system interacts with sections of the frontal cortex (cognitive HQ) that are accordingly, functionally 12 Melzack, R., and Wall, P., The Challenge of Pain, London, Penguin, Third edition, 1988, pp. 82-84 It is postulated that a gating mechanism exists in the spinal cord that plays a significant role in modulating the impulses from nerves. We will not be discussing the gate theory here. See Melzack, R., and Wall, P., 1988, opcit Chapter 9, pp. 165- 193. 14 ibid pp. 86-88, 101. Fibers do not respond to all stimuli, some are very sensitive to specific stimuli like hair movement, skin or tissue indentation, crushing, stretching, warming, cooling, or chemicals. 15 ibid pp. 99-100 16 ibid, pp.99-100 17 Chronic pain is the term for a number of different pathological conditions including ; pain in the absence of any stimulus, pains that last longer than what they should under normal conditions and sometimes never cease, pain in response to what should be non-painful stimuli, pains of greater intensity than normal, pain spreading to uninjured tissue, pains for which the cause may or may not be known but treatment is ineffective. ibid pp. 288-289 18 Correlation between the firing of nerves and the perception of pain is very weak, see Hardcastle, 1999, opcit p. 106, 122. Melzack, R., and Wall, P., 1988, opcit Chapter 1, pp. 3-15 19 Grahek, N., 2001, opcit pp. 105-106 20 Melzack, R., and Wall, P., 1988, opcit p. 124 21 Hardcastle, V, G., 1999, opcit p. 116 22 Melzack, R., and Wall, P., 1988, opcit p. 124 13 7 designated as parts of the limbic system.23 Evidence indicates that the limbic structures are particularly important as the basis for the aversive drive and affect (painfulness) of pain and the attraction / attention (pleasantness) of our pleasure as well as other kinds of behaviour.24 The highest concentration of opiate receptors in the brain is in the limbic system.25 The role of the limbic structures becomes more complex and subtle when we consider that they are strongly interconnected with the somatosensory cortex and cognitive processing areas like the frontal cortex.26 Lobotomies and surgical section of limbic structures results in loss of painfulness in pain sensations, particularly in chronic pain. This procedure is performed on people whose long term, chronic and intractable pain, fails to respond to all other treatment methods. Some of them involve the removal of certain parts of the brain located in the frontal lobes, or the whole lobes themselves often severing the projections between the thalamus, hypothlamus and cingulate cortex.27 These people (type 2 cases) no longer feel the painfulness of, or aversion to chronic pain. Like complete asymbolia patients (type 1 cases) they perceive pain, it just doesn’t bother them unless they focus on it. They still feel sensory / discriminative sensations of pain, (location, intensity, type), particularly in the case of new or different acute pains, identify them as pains, but are only briefly or not at all upset by them and show only transient pain behaviour (wincing, moaning, complaining) if any. These sections and lobotomies do not interfere so much with the perception of pain, or normal immediate reactions to pain, particularly new pains, but reduce the long lasting, persistent emotional substrate of chronic pains.28 The patients lose their fear of pain. 29 A similar dissociation effect is reported by people on morphine for pain, and people who undergo hypnosis and are told that their pains will not hurt anymore.30 In particular evidence indicates that the anterior cingulate cortex, an area primarily involved with emotion and attention and strongly interconnected with the limbic system, needs to be active for someone to feel aversion to a painful stimulus.31 PET scans done on patients under hypnotic suggestion that their pains would not hurt, showed that activity in the cingulate cortex decreased while in the somatosensory cortex (primarily involved in the discriminative processing) activity remained unchanged.32 Cingulotomies, (removal of the cingulum) do not have the global 23 ibid p. 134 ibid p. 132-137, “The amygdala seems to provide an ‘affective bias’ as a result of matching incoming information against past experience so that animals and people can respond adaptively to familiar or unfamiliar stimuli. … After ablation of the amygdala, monkeys unhesitatingly ingest hot, sharp or otherwise injurious objects that normally, on the basis of past experience, elicit caution or avoidance.” p. 135. 25 Aydede, M., 2000, opcit p. 555. Several descending control systems use endorphins and enkephalins the bodies own opiates, see Melzack, R., Wall, P., opcit p. 137-144 26 Melzack, R. and Wall, P., opcit pp. 134-135 27 Hardcastle, V, G., 1999, opcit p. 117 28 Grahek, N., 2001, opcit p. 121. 29 Freeman, W., and Watts, J.W., Psychosurgery in the Treatment of Mental Disorders and Intractable Pain, Oxford, Blackwell, 1950, p. 353 30 See Damasio, A. R., The Feeling of What Happens : Body and Emotion in the Making of Consciousness, New York, Harcourt Brace, 1999, p. 75. Hardcastle, V.G., 1999, opcit, p. 104. Carter, R., consultant ed, Christopher, F., Mapping the Mind, London, Weidenfeld and Nicolson, 1998, p. 114 31 Carter, R., 1998, opcit p. 114 32 Rainville, P., Duncan, G. H., Price, D. D., Carrier, and Bushnell, M.C., Pain Affect Encoded in Human Anterior Cingulate But Not Somatosensory Cortex, Science, 277, 1997, pp. 968-971 24 8 personality effects of lobotomies, however patients do show attentional and executive deficits.33 Evidence suggests that damage to the anterior cingulate is typically involved in cases where what seems to be lacking is some kind of active background memory.34 The anterior cingulate, also seems to coordinate perceptions of bodily threat with frontal areas in the cortex involved in plans and response priorities.35 In the case of pain asymbolia, (type 1 cases) the sensory character of pain has been totally dissociated from its normal affective character apparently because of damage in the rough area called the posterior insula which either cuts the connection between somatosensory information and the limbic system or destroys the ability to perceive a variety of kinds of information as threatening. 36What seems to be lacking in both type 1 & 2 cases is high level cognitive evaluations of painful stimuli which have to do with the long term implications of bodily damage. Suffering anxiety, dread or fear concerning pain is essential to the painfulness of chronic pain. We have mentioned type 3 cases. Consider the only well studied example of a type 3 case in the literature. The patient's state was produced by stimulating C fibres. However, what he experienced was not pain, even though it was unpleasant. The reason is that the patient was not aware of the sensory reports normally produced by C fibres, which would give a unifying painful character to his experience. As Nikola Grahek has correctly said, this patient suffers from painfulness without pain.37 It is important to stress, however, that he does not experience it specifically as painfulness, but merely as an unpleasant state which cannot be characterised in any detail. By contrast, in the type 1 and 2 cases we have described above, the patients are not in doubt that they are in pain because the sensory unity in their experience is intact. They are feeling pain which they can characterise either as burning or pricking etc. However, what they experience lacks painfulness. It is, to their amazement, in no way unpleasant. We see from all this that the sensory character which unifies the experience of pain has nothing to do with painfulness. These facts seem to fit Plato's account beautifully and seem to refute Protarchus's account. Cognitive Content It has long been argued that memories, present perceptions and associations, cultural factors, beliefs, goals, fears, and expectations influence pain perception. Modern research on the brain shows that areas of the brain functionally responsible for emotion and cognition have a significant role in our normal, paradigmatic pain experiences. Paradigmatic pains (like cutting yourself with a knife) are complex constructions with many dimensions that involve our current experience of sensory discriminative information combined with past understandings of similar experiences and our beliefs about the world.38 Even before noxious stimuli arrive at brain areas involved in pain experience, they have been modulated by higher brain mechanisms. Contentful mental states like memories, and propositional attitudes like fears, goals 33 Grahek, N., 2001, opcit p. 129 ibid pp. 127-129 35 Price, D. D., Psychological and Neural Mechanisms of the Affective Dimension of Pain, Science, 288, 2000, p. 1771 36 Grahek, N., 2001, opcit p. 54. See also Price, D.D., 2000, opcit p. 1771 37 ibid p. 8 38 Hardcastle, V.G., 1999, opcit pp. 118-119 34 9 and expectations, singularly and in combination, play the essential role in painfulness.39 Consider these two experiments that demonstrate that propositional attitudes (expectations and fears) make the character of our sensory experience. One experiment was done on patients undergoing a procedure that involved inflating a balloon in their bowels.40 The inflation of the balloon is reported as painful by patients. In this experiment patients who had just had the balloon inflated and then deflated were told that the balloon was being inflated again, but in fact it was not. The patients reported that they could feel the (rectal) pain from the balloon being inflated even thought it was not. A PET scan was done during this experiment, and the reports of pain from the (false) inflation of the balloon showed activations in the prefrontal cortex. 41 Another simple experiment demonstrates the involvement of expectations in pleasant and painful affect.42 Participants were asked to agree to experience either a painful, pleasant or neutral sensation. All participants placed their fingers in a machine that (unbeknownst to them) simply had a vibrating emery board. Those participants that signed on for the painful (but harmless) sensation were expecting a painful sensation, and reported that indeed the sensation was painful, while those who signed on for the pleasurable sensation expected pleasure, and reported a pleasurable sensation. Those who signed on for the neutral sensation agreed that the sensations they felt were neither pleasant nor painful. The experiment provides good evidence that the awfulness (affective motivational aspect) of pain is not caused by the sensation or noxious stimulus but is already part of how we perceive the stimulus or sensation. Beliefs about the consequences, the “meaning” of your injury, and thoughts about how your body has perhaps been fatally damaged make pain sensations significant. The opposite can also occur, where beliefs and expectations of “good” things can change what we feel. The classic example of this is the placebo. Research shows that placebos relieve pain at half the rate of the supposed drug, whatever the supposed strength of the drug is.43 Beliefs informed by memories of past experiences can form sophisticated schemas; that is, patterns of concepts, response patterns and associations drawing from memories, present experiences and expectations.44 Belief structures about injury, its consequences, and lethalness can be ingrained and conditioned.45 Fear and anxiety, expectations and memories connected with our sensory perception makes the aversive affective dimension, the unpleasantness, a contentful and meaningful state that engages our attention. It makes good evolutionary sense that our 39 ibid pp. 170-171 Silverman, D. H. S., Munakata, J.A., Ennes, H., Mandelkern, A., Hoh, C.K., Mayer, E.A., Regional Cerebral Activity in Normal and Pathological Perception of Visceral Pain, Gastroenterology, 12, 1997, pp. 64-72 41 ibid, pp. 65-68 42 Anderson, D., and Pennebaker, J., Pain and pleasure. Alternative interpretations of the identical stimulations. European Journal of Social Psychology 10, 1980, pp. 207-210 43 Hardcastle, V.G., 1999 opcit p. 106 44 Melzack, R., and Wall, P., 1988, opcit p. 136. Hardcastle, V.G., 1999, opcit p. 119., Study and schema theory by Chapman, R.C., and Nakamura, Y., Hypnotic Analgesia : A Constructivist Framework, The International Journal of Clinical and Experimental Hypnosis, XLVI, 1, 1998, pp. 626 45 Hardcastle, V. G. 1999 opcit p. 114 40 10 beliefs about the nature of our bodies and the dangers posed by injury are involved in the affective aspects of pain. Childhood Pain There is evidence that the suffering of pain, remembered or not, effects later experiences of pain. 46 This would seem to occur because of developments in both the sensory discriminative, and the affective pain systems of the brain. It is well documented that injurious stimuli increase the size of the somatic fields for neurones sensitive to pain and aids in maintaining neural connections that might otherwise have atrophied away.47 Hence pain behaviour and experience can be influenced by earlier sensory inputs as a result of the traces they have etched into neural connections.48 It has been plausibly postulated that chronic pain and hyper- sensitivity may be the result of early acute painful experiences.49 A study showed that neonatal circumcision effected pain response with higher behavioral pain scores for months after the operation. 50 Given the immaturity of infant and child brains we might expect that their pain experiences are significantly different to those of adults. Not only might we expect their sensory system to be less developed and attuned, but also the affective motivational system, descending control systems and beliefs about the world will be immature compared to those of adults and older children. 51 A handful of studies done on infant and child pain do suggest that infant and child pain experiences are different to those of adults. Studies have shown that infants have simple, diffuse, and less modulated reactions (poor localisation and reflex withdrawal) to painful stimuli than adults and older children.52 More focussed responses (defensive reflexive movements, greater localisation) to painful stimuli do not emerge until after 12 months. 53 It has been observed that pain thresholds decrease with age, while the ability to localise pain increases.54 But while the sensory component might take some time to mature, infants do nevertheless exhibit enhanced acute pain responses and the typical stress responses to tissue damage like sweating, increased heart and respiratory rates, and hormone level changes.55 Furthermore infants cry when given inoculations, but can be soothed by comforting or the administration of analgesics.56 This would suggest that infants are experiencing something painful despite the immaturity of their sensory system. As children grow and experience more they will attach meanings and emotions to their life experiences and begin to have more sophisticated hopes and fears. Researchers have shown that anticipatory fear is evident in infants as young as 6 46 ibid p. 199 ibid p. 199 48 Melzack, R., and Wall, P., opcit p. 124 49 Hardcastle, V. G., 1999, opcit p. 199 50 Taddio, A., Goldbach, M., Ipp, M., Stevens, B., and Koren, G., Effect of neonatal circumcision on pain responses during vaccination in boys, 1995, Lancet, 345, pp. 291-299 51 Hardcastle V.G., 1999, opcit pp. 194 –200. Neurophysioloical evidence supports this. Thalamocortical fibres do not reach the cortex until 26 weeks gestation. The neural activity of somatosensory cortex, prefrontal cortex and anterior cingulate increases substantially from birth to eighteen months, but does not reach mature form until after a year. 52 ibid pp. 194, 197 53 ibid p. 194 54 ibid p. 194. 55 ibid p. 197 56 ibid p. 197 47 11 months and that as they grow older the pain reaction in young infants and children is replaced by anger.57 This suggests that beliefs and attitudes about the causes, desirability, and understanding of pain are developing and changing as children grow. Also as we mature we develop skills for coping with pain and make use of these skills. Infants and very young children, by contrast lack the coping skills that adults and older children have, and may well feel more painfulness than an adult would in some circumstances.58 Children’s pain behaviour may not look like pain behaviour to an adult. Apparently children with chronic pain report that they are in pain, but show no typical pain behaviour, while repeated acute pain in children often resembles chronic pain in adults.59 PLATO'S ACCOUNT AND MODERN RESEARCH What can we conclude from all this concerning Plato's account? Plato's view that the painfulness of pain does not consist of some sensory character all pains have seems to be borne out. The characteristic sensations we typically get when we are in pain can be dissociated from the painfulness of pain, and vice versa. Further, Plato seems to be correct in thinking that it is an integral part of the painfulness of pain that we have memories and/or other cognitively sophisticated states which are in part to be understood to be propositional attitudes capable of being true or false. We have seen that this is particularly clear in the case of chronic pains. Finally, Plato seems to be importantly correct in thinking that infant pain is importantly different from the pain of adults or older children. Protarchus might still try to respond to Plato's central claim by arguing that although we have shown that much of the sensational content of pain is irrelevant to its affective character, we have not shown that there is no aversive felt content left which is purely sensational. To reply to this response, let us consider the above mentioned case of a patient who experienced an ill localised pain which he could characterise in no other way but by its unpleasantness. The puzzled patient, who is a normal rational person, could not perceive his pain as either intense or not intense, either burning or pinprick like, or in any other way researchers suggested. Discussion with the patient and brain scans showed that this patient is not experiencing any of the normal somatosensory characteristics of pain, but found what was happening to him intensely unpleasant and wanted to avoid it.60 To say that this patient was having a mysterious kind of pain sensation seems to us merely an ad hoc manoeuvre. The simplest explanation is that the patient merely is aware of his propositional attitude that he would like to escape from an unspecific causal agent. The experimenters and the subject are inclined to call it a feeling because the subject is aware of his negative propositional attitude to a causal agent acting in a very ill localised area, not because his experience has any other painful sensory character. Of course, it would be possible for Protarchus to say that the subject was having a special kind of aversive sensation which cannot be characterised any further. However, for him to respond in this way in the absence of any other sensory characterisation of the experience would be for him to indulge in an untestable ad hoc manoeuvre. 57 ibid p. 194 ibid p. 195 59 ibid pp. 194- 195 60 Grahek, N., 2001, opcit. pp. 100-103 58 12 We should note, however, that some important parts of Plato's account are not correct. The reader will remember that Plato proceeds by talking as if thirst, hunger and other unpleasant states are pains in essentially the same way as paradigmatic cases of pain. Research which has been done on various unpleasant states shows that Plato may be partly correct. Part of what unites various unpleasant states is emotional states. The same parts of the limbic system are activated in many emotional pains as in physical pains. This is probably why they are called emotional 'pains' in various languages.61 But matters are not as simple as this, for while there are two dissociable systems in the brain, they normally work together as parallel distributed systems which strongly interact. We cannot explain the workings of parallel distributed systems here, or discuss the detailed workings of the pain system. However, it is sufficient to point out that the merger of the activity of the two pain systems in the brain is often not like the mixture of the activity of two atoms which do their work separately, but like the merger of two waves in a new wave, in which the two previous waves have no separate existence. This is probably why the emotional attitudes and the sensational contents of pain fuse in the everyday phenomenology of pain.62 A related problem with Plato's account is that the different phenomenology of paradigmatic pains reflects something crucially different from other unpleasant states and which has to do with the underlying physiological states that are involved. The function of Ad and C fibres has nothing to do with lack. Ad fibres are finely tuned to warn of potential mechanical, thermal or chemical damage and to cause rapid reactions to the threat of such damage. C fibres have more than one function. Some of them function to give fine grained reports of the locality of pain.63 All of this suggests that paradigmatic pains are fundamentally different from other states that are called pains in a looser sense. In paradigmatic pains, fine grained content is present which warns of highly specific kinds of actual or potential harm and provides information about the precise site in which the threatening cause is active. The informational content is very rich in paradigmatic pains, and very different from that in other unpleasant states. Thus while Plato is correct to stress that a crucial aspect of typical pains is that they are propositional attitudes, he is mistaken in treating the sensory aspect of pain as of minor interest. George Couvalis, Matthew Usher E-mail Address : george.couvalis@flinders.edu.au. matteusone@primus.com.au The Flinders University of South Australia. We thank the members of the Philosophy Department of the University of Valencia, Spain for their helpful comments, particularly Josep Corbi and Jordi Valor. Bibliography 61 Carter, R., 1998, opcit. p.114 Hardcastle, 1999, opcit, pp. 106-108, 120. Aydede, M., 2000, opcit pp. 550-552 63 Melzack, R., and Wall, P., opcit, pp. 86-88, 99-100 62 13 Anderson, D., and Pennebaker, J., Pain and pleasure, Alternative interpretations of the identical stimulations, European Journal of Social Psychology, 10, 1980, pp. 207210 Aydede, M., An Analysis of Pleasure Vis-à-vis Pain, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 6, Nov 2000, pp. 537-569 Carter, R., consultant ed, Christopher F., Mapping the Mind, London, Weidenfeld and Nicolson, 1998 Chapman, R.C., and Nakamura, Y., Hypnotic Analgesia : A Constructivist Framework, The International Journal of Clinical and Experimental Hypnosis, XLVI, 1998 Damasio, A. R., The Feeling of What Happens : Body and Emotion in the Making of Consciousness, New York, Harcourt and Brace, 1999 Frede, D., Rumplestilskins Pleasures : True and False Pleasures in Plato’s Philebus, Phronesis, 30, 1985, pp. 151-180 Freeman, W., and Watts, J.W., Psychosurgery in the Treatment of Mental Disorders and Intractable Pain, Oxford, Blackwell, 1950 Grahek, N., Feeling Pain and Being in Pain, Hanse Institute for Advanced Study, Oldenburg, University of Oldenburg, 1, 2001. Hardcastle, V.G., The Myth of Pain, Cambridge Massachusetts, MIT Press, 1999 Hesse, M., Models and Analogies in Science, Notre Dame, Indiana, University of Notre Dame Press, 1966 Frede, D., Disintegration and Restoration : Pleasure and Pain in Plato’s Philebus, in Kraut, R., ed. Cambridge Companion to Plato, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1992, pp.425-463 Lamb, D., Discovery, Creativity and Problem-Solving, Aldershot, Avebury, 1991 Melzack, R., and Wall, P., The Challenge of Pain, London, Penguin, Third edition, 1988 Penner T. M., False Anticipatory Pleasures, Phronesis, 5, 1970, pp.166-178 Plato, Philebus, Trans, Introduced, and notes by, Frede, D., Indianapolis / Cambridge, Hackett Publishing Company, 1993 Ploner, M., Freund, H.-J., and Schnitzler, A., Pain affect without pain sensation in a patient with a postcentral lesion, Pain, 81,1999, pp. 211-214 Price. D.D., Psychological and Neural Mechanisms of the Affective Dimension of Pain, Science, 288, 2000, pp.1769-1772 14 Rainville, P., Duncan, G. H., Price, D.D., Carrier, and Bushnell, M.C., Pain Affect Encoded in Human Anterior Cingulate But Not Somatosensory Cortex, Science, 277, 1997, pp. 968-971 Silverman, D. H. S., Munakata, J.A., Ennes, H., Mandelkern, A., Hoh, C.K., Mayer, E.A., Regional Cerebral Activity in Normal and Pathological Perception of Visceral Pain, Gastroenterology, 12, 1997, pp. 64-72 Taddio, A., Goldbach, M., Ipp, M., Stevens, B., and Koren, G., Effect of neonatal circumcision on pain responses during vaccination in boys, Lancet, 345, 1995, pp. 291-299 Williams, B.A.O. Pleasure and Belief, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary (XXXIII), 1959, also reprinted in Hampshire, S., ed. Philosophy of Mind, London, Harper & Row, pp. 225-42 15