1 Taylor Ch. 1 Taylor shifts gears in this chapter. Having put in place his expressivist thesis in chapters 9 and 10, he now will explore expressivist concepts to examine the notion of what it is to be a “responsible human agent” or what is it to be a “person”. Taylor begins with Frankfurt’s claim that human agents are different from other agents in that human agents are able to form “second-order desires”, namely that human agents, unlike say infrahuman agents, are able to evaluate their desires; able, that is, to engage in self-reflection in rejecting some and accepting others of their desires. Thus, Frankfurt suggests that human agents’ capacity to evaluate their desires is bound up with selfreflection/evaluation, and Taylor agrees. However, Taylor suggests a further distinction with a view of clarifying this capacity we posses to evaluate our desires (by way of self-reflection). Taylor proposes that we distinguish between two broad kinds of evaluation. Taylor claims that what is missing in Frankfurt’s “second order desires” is the notion that evaluation is “qualitative”. That is, not only can we reject or accept some or other desire that is ours but we can also do so either (1) in terms of the outcome of our desires, or (2) in terms of the qualitative conditions of worth of our desires. These are two very different ways of evaluating our desires: weak and strong evaluation. Thus, in accepting or rejecting one or other of our desires, we make a choice in terms of their respective outcomes, but in evaluating our desires in terms of conditions of worth we make no choice at all, one desire is simply higher, more virtuous, more fulfilling, more refined, more profound, more noble than another desire, and hence it clearly is the preferred desire. Now Taylor warns us that “weak’ evaluation does not necessarily mean that the desires between which we must choose are “homogeneous” (that the two desires that can be characterized in the same manner as to their desirability) or that our evaluation of the two desires can be quantified (the rational aim of utilitarianism to be able to calculate the respective “desirability” of our desires). Utilitarianism in ethics has tried to do away with qualitative distinctions of worth on the grounds that such conditions of worth are an illusion hiding the real bases of our preferences which can be quantified. Thus, the utilitarian hopes that once we do away with strong evaluation (in terms of conditions of worth) we can calculate which desire is preferable (which results in the most pleasure or avoids the most pain). But as Taylor points out this is mythical quantification in terms of which the fulfillment of one desire is “more fun” or “less fun”. Utilitarianism is certainly right in rejecting evaluation in terms of conditions of worth at least if utilitarianism aspires to reduce practical reason in strongly evaluating desires to mere calculation. More importantly, weak evaluation is not just concerned with the outcomes of our desires either for we can choose between desires (as Frankfurt claims, we can have “second order” desires) but, as Taylor points out, these need not be strong evaluations or choices. Thus, one can desire not to have a desire, or one can desire a desire one does not yet have and still not engage in strong evaluation. Rather, Taylor’s distinction between two kind of evaluation, weak and strong, does not depend on the quantitative-qualitative evaluation 2 nor on the presence or absence of second order desires (as Frankfurt claims), rather the distinction between weak and strong desires depend on conditions of worth and this includes two interlocking criteria. (1) In weak evaluation a desire is good if it is desired, whereas in strong evaluation the desire must be evaluated in terms of conditions of worth. (2) Hence, in case of weak evaluation the choice between desires is simply their contingent incompatibility, but in case of strong evaluation the choice between desires is all about their worth (note the “moral” or normative implications). Now Taylor claims that this notion of worth turns on what I deem to be worthy as a mode of life, as the kind of person I am or aspire to be. Note that here the incompatibility of desires is no longer contingent (a matter of circumstances) rather it has to do with what I deem to be a worthy life. The reason is that in case of strong evaluation the language of the conditions of worth is deployed contrastively (this harks back to the notion of language as “web”). Thus, the characterization of my desires in strong evaluation is expressed in a contrastive language. This fact marks strong evaluation as very different from weak evaluation. [As Taylor notes in a footnote, it might be objected that the utilitarian also uses such qualitatively contrastive words such as “pleasure” and “pain” but in fact the utilitarian does not use these words contrastively holding that it is only pleasure that is desired. If in reply the utilitarian claims that the desire of pleasure is here contrasted with the desire to “avoid pain”, Taylor notes that it is precisely this contrast that utilitarianism has failed to make. Taylor also notes that “time” per se is not contrastive rather time is used circumstantially. In fact, there are many ways to describe my desire that are seemingly contrastive but in fact are not. What distinguishes weak from strong evaluation is the contrastive characterization of desire in case of strong evaluation, for in strong evaluation of our desires we employ the language of evaluative distinctions (and not merely circumstantially conflicting or contingently conflicting) wherein which the contrast between desires is “deeper”.] Strong evaluations (characterizing my desires, interests, attitudes, aspirations, etc. in a contrastive language of worth), leads inevitably to a conflict of interpretations. Which characterization of my desires I adopt will shape (realize and clarify) the meaning “things” have for us. Note here, not just the desires as “objects” themselves (subjective) but the desires of…something, meaning also the objects to which our desires are directed. Here we have Taylor using the notion of “expression” (of desires) to overcome the subject-object distinction. That is, the characterization of desires includes the characterization of the things/actions we desire. Taylor then immediately raises the question of which characterization (of desire) is more faithful, valid, to reality? But note here that in asking this question Taylor is in some sense backtracking for the characterization of desires in terms of conditions of worth also characterizes the object towards which the desires are directed in terms of the conditions 3 of worth. In other words, to ask about a “reality” outside of our strong evaluation returns us to a subject-object bifurcation which expressivism rejected. The strong evaluator in envisioning the alternatives in terms of conditions of worth possesses a richer language wherein to reflect on the alternatives. Thus, unlike the weak evaluator who merely weighs the alternatives and then calculates the consequences of each, the strong evaluator is able by way of his contrastive language to reflect on the alternatives terms of their worth (to life, his/her life) and the kind of person s/he is. Hence, the strong evaluator when confronted by alternative desires can articulate the alternative desires in terms of conditions of worth (and therefore as we have seen in Ch. 9 and 10 understands the “reality” of these desires very differently) and hence can reflect in choice in articulating a very different “reality”. Reflection is here not calculation of consequences of desires as “objectively” given, but reflection (and choice) on very different (deeper) experiences (realities) that are constituted in our articulations of conditions of worth. We are now, in strong evaluation, reflecting on the alternatives of desires in terms of the kind of person I am and the kind of life I live. The kind of articulacy and depth the strong evaluator possesses also raises the possibility of a plurality of visions that a weak evaluator lacks. That is, the kind of predicament (in a conflict of desires) the strong evaluator confronts results in a struggle of selfinterpretations (interpretations that profoundly affect the kind of self I am) as to which characterization (of desire and choice) is more authentic, illusion-free, genuine, authentic, and so resolves the apparently incommensurability of my desires through articulacy. Taylor makes the strong point that without this capacity to strongly evaluate our desires, we would lack the minimum degree of reflection (note reflection here depends on articulacy) that we associate with human agency and its capacity for choice (exercise of the will). Thus, freedom of will depends on reflection and reflection depends on articulacy (exactly the reverse of the weak evaluator – the designator!). Taylor then shifts perspective in his examination of the self by turning towards the question of responsibility within the context of evaluating desires, for the notion of responsibility is bound up with this capacity to evaluate desires. We might have anticipated this of course, given that freedom depends on articulacy and so responsibility insofar at it relies on freedom must also be tied to articulacy. There is one sense of responsibility that is already implicit in the notion of “will”. If we are capable of evaluating (weak or strong) our desires we may find that these are in conflict such that one presses more than another (or we will one against the other which presses more strongly: here the notion of “ought” emerges). That is, evaluation of desire already presupposes a sense of will and with it an elementary sense of responsibility (in willing/evaluating one over the other – as Frankfurt points out in case of second order desires). But this is not the sense of responsibility that Taylor wants. Not only are we agents because we can evaluate and be held responsible for choosing one, acting on one, over another desire, but we are responsible for the evaluations of the desires themselves. This 4 is a much stronger sense of evaluation, and hence of responsibility, for here evaluation is itself an activity we are engaged in [on the analogy of speech being activity we are engaged in when using language]. Thus, reflection on desires (evaluating them) already invokes our responsibility. Taylor asks how are we understands this stronger sense of responsibility? One way to understand it (a way that is characteristic of our modern era) is as “choice”. Thus, the notion of “value” suggests that we create values (“evaluation”). But Taylor objects that this way of understanding responsibility of evaluations as choice suggest that we merely choose (“radical choice”) without reason (since our values are our own creations). Or if we do base our evaluations on reasons, then these reasons are taken as simply valid (and not themselves chosen). This is the view that Taylor attributes to JeanPaul Sartre. The problem with this view (of radical choice or that we are radically free) is that if this is true then we can no longer see ourselves as strong evaluators, agents with depth. For as Taylor comments, while we can conceive of radical choice among strong evaluations, we cannot view our choice of evaluations as radical (on risk that otherwise our evaluations are not strong evaluations). The crux of the issue there is that Sartre sees responsibility as a matter of radical choice and radical choice is entirely a matter of the individual selfassertion. But of course this view runs counter to Taylor’s entire expressivist project (which, recall, was to overcome this bifurcation of individual and the world); the agent of radical choice is a simple “weigher”, a weak evaluator). But the theory of radical choice is even worse off than that for, as Taylor comments, it is incoherent (see pp. 31-32) for it wants to maintain both strong evaluation and radical choice (as Sartre seems to in his example). But strong evaluations, as we have seen, are “judgments” (not choices) in the sense that they involve contrastive articulations of desires-actions complexes and invoke our aspirations to a certain kind of life, being a certain kind of person and this may well, of course, involve a plurality of visions which can be very difficult to adjudicate (choose among). Now both in our articulations/judgments (strong evaluations) as well as in our efforts to adjudicate these we bear responsibility. Taylor then proceeds to examine this issue of responsibility from another angle. Strong evaluators, he writes, have depth because their articulations/evaluations are bound up with the kind of person they aspire to be/the kind of life they aspire to live; that is, these are bound up with our “personal identity”. Our identity is formed not only in our choices, but especially in our articulations/evaluations. Thus, in answer to the question “who am I as a person”? or “what is my identity?” we don’t point to our choices but to our evaluations which are inseparable from our being “agents”. Without our fundamental evaluations we cease being who we are. To ask of someone their identity as a person we are referred to their evaluations. Here Taylor writes of a horizon of evaluations (the traditions out of which we articulate our desires) without which we are lost as to our identity. This is also what is so puzzling about Sartre’s notion of radical freedom/choice for such freedom or choice is without the context/horizon of evaluations. This is the autonomy self-defining subjectivity of the 5 Enlightenment/modernity that is radically separated from context (social-cultural order of traditions) and it is what expressivism was intended to overcome. For this autonomy is really a fragmentation of identity, an alienation from the human historical world, from those strong evaluations which identify me as a person. The pressing question arises how do we come to our evaluations/articulations? Are these not a matter of radical choice? Are we not at all responsible for our evaluations? Taylor replies that evaluations are not so much chosen as they are an articulation of what is “higher/lower” and more integrated/fulfilling or not. Such articulation while not a matter of choice (in the usual sense) does invoke our responsibility and here is where Taylor resumes his expressivist thesis. That is, articulation (in this chapter, the articulation of desires, aspirations, etc.) is not of the simply “given”, rather it is our articulations/interpretations that give “them” (desires) “reality”, “shape” “embodiment”. That is, articulations are not simply descriptions of what is already objectively (out/in) there/here (not like the table which is then described by the word “table”, according to Taylor); on the contrary, articulation is a form-ulation which does not leave the “object” (desire, aspiration, etc.) unchanged but gives it “shape” in a way that we hold to be important/value. Thus, the manner in which we articulate/interpret our desires also (“in part”, here Taylor hesitates) constitutes those desires (our experience of our desires). If we change the articulation/interpretation of the desire, we also change (the shape) of the experience of desire. As Taylor notes, this is not a causal claim; rather, it is the claim that what we experience depends on, is given shape by, our articulations/interpretations (of our feeling, aspirations, etc.). Thus, the very nature of experience is formed (constituted) by our articulations/interpretations (and these are of course to be understood on the model of expression). How do we come to change our articulations of our desires/etc.? [Another way of asking this question is to ask “what makes change in personal identity possible?”] Taylor suggests in two ways. (1) We do in living with others; that is, as we are engaged in the world or as we find ourselves embedded in the world. (2) We do so because we find that our articulations clash with the articulations of others (either now in the present, or on reading with those in the past) or else we find ourselves unable to understand others or just unable to understand the way we live and so search for alternate articulations. Yet these articulation/interpretations are not totally arbitrary or relative to others’ articulations/interpretations; they are instead more or less adequate, truthful, insightful, distorting, delusional, etc. Thus, our evaluations strive to be faithful not to an independent object but rather to what inchoately and inarticulately makes “sense” (in the broad sense of “meaningful”) in living. At the same time, our articulations do not leave the object as it is. In “shaping” it, it makes the object more accessible; it places the object (desire) in the context of our lives. Precisely because these articulations are evaluations they also limit the nature of experience (and subsequent expression of experience). In this 6 sense our evaluations are a judgment on our person. That is, the limits of our experience (as well as expression) are also a judgment on us – that is, we are judged by our moral insight (articulation/interpretations as evaluations). This has nothing to do with radical choice/freedom; it has to do with the manner in which our articulations in fact shape our experience. Obviously our experience (our articulations and evaluations) are always open to challenge(is not all understanding): always open to elaboration, explication, analysis, and further interpretation. Indeed, I have a responsibility to continue the process of evaluation as long as I live/act and encounter the “world” in everything I do. This is especially so when it comes to what Taylor called our fundamental evaluations – the ones central (deepest) to our identity. For it is often our deepest evaluations that are least well articulated (these are often least clear) even to ourselves. But since this is so, if I do reevaluating my deepest evaluations it is not a matter of choice but of reformulation, reinterpretation, and re-understanding. Usually these fundamental evaluations are not articulated because we share (live) them with/in the community/tradition. Since they are “lived”, they need not be articulated. We have here then a tension between “living” and “saying/expressing”. Moreover, note that these deep evaluations cannot be evaluated/reinterpreted in some kind of meta-language (there is no such) nor is there an empirical inquiry (as designativist would claim) hat might help us to decide (obviously, since that inquiry, in turn, would also be articulated in the language of our evaluations). All we can do is converse and reflect on our deepest evaluations and try again and again to articulate them in a manner that would give us insight and understanding into ourselves and the world in which we live. Note that there is no yardstick, as Taylor comments, except to appreciate that any such reevaluation engages my very personal identity, an identity I have always in relationship to others who similarly engage in such re-evaluations. It is in this context Taylor writes about “radical evaluation” which the self reflecting on the self, on the self’s most fundamental issues (the “deepest” evaluations), and because this self-evaluation is something that we do we are also responsible (even if we fail to do so) for doing so and for the manner in which we do so. Radical evaluation we do in articulating (expressing) what we desire/feel/aspire to etc., always in the context of the world in which we live. Such expression reposes then on the contrastive web of language and hence is part of community and tradition. Taylor ends his paper with some brief comments on psychology. But these might easily apply to linguistics as well. Thus, any notion of “grammar” that is part of some theory of the brain, or some abstract mental mechanism, is misguided for these accounts/explanations cannot participate in the human agent as a self-interpreting subject – cannot account in principle for the expressivist conception of strong evaluation wherein articulacy is constitutive of, in this chapter, the inner self, our desires, aspirations, etc. This does not mean that linguistics cannot proceed in accord with a formal analysis of language; it does mean this abstractive endeavor must itself be seen as constituted communally in our speech practices, in the formulation and reformulation, in the 7 understanding/interpretation of the meaning (strong evaluations) of these speech practices which inevitably bear our responsibility because it is something we do. Finally, note here that Taylor relies in this chapter on chapters 9, 10. Thus, he does not explicitly mention the role of language and the question of meaning and the broader question of sense in this chapter. Moreover, he seems only concerned with the expression of “inner life” (desires, aspirations, interests, etc). But, of course, we recall that the expressivist thesis ties this inner life in expression to the world. LPM/March 2005