Manuscript (revised) submitted to Annual Review of Public Health, Vol. 25 (2004) Implications of the precautionary principle for primary prevention and research Philippe Grandjean Institute of Public Health, University of Southern Denmark, Odense, Denmark; and Department of Environmental Health, Harvard School of Public Health, Boston, MA, USA (e-mail: pgrand@hsph.harvard.edu) Running title: Implications of precaution Key words: Decision making Environmental pollution Research design Risk assessment Toxicity Address for correspondence: Philippe Grandjean, Winslowparken 17, 5000 Odense, Denmark (phone: +45-6550.3769, fax: +45-6591.1458) Implications of precaution (Grandjean) 2 Contents Abstract 3 Introduction 4 History of precaution 5 Environmental disease causation 6 Complexities and shortcomings of risk assessment 8 Types of incertitude 10 Defining the Precautionary Principle 11 Critiques of the Precautionary Principle 13 Differences between the United States and Europe 16 The systemic approach to decision-making 17 A precautionary research paradigm 20 Statistical issues of precaution 23 The future of precaution 25 Acknowledgments 27 Literature cited 27 Figure legends Tables Figures Implications of precaution (Grandjean) Abstract The Precautionary Principle (PP) is an extension of the public-health presage that prevention is better than cure. The PP has recently achieved new relevance in regard to serious, but uncertain threats to human health and the environment, and has now entered national and international legislation. However, frameworks for its unambiguous application in practice are yet to be designed. They will depend on legal and cultural circumstances and are likely to involve pluralities of perspectives and stakeholder participation. The rules for causal reasoning and dosedependence need to be addressed and may be conveniently expressed in accordance with probability theory. Although the PP will allow action before convincing evidence is secured, it is not science averse. However, it provides an occasion to review environmental health research strategies, methodologies, and research reporting traditions. From this perspective, current research is afflicted by important biases and insufficient focus on major environmental health problems. 3 Implications of precaution (Grandjean) 4 Introduction Policy decisions in public health must address some amount of uncertainty when balancing likely benefits and estimated costs. Although new insight will allow better appreciation of difficult issues, such as those occurring in environmental and occupational health, an expanded perspective may also enlarge the list of problems that need to be managed. Ignoring the problems carries its own costs (as deferring a decision is a decision in itself). With environmental and other public health problems becoming increasingly complex and international in scope, scientific documentation alone rarely justifies simple solutions. Unfortunately, important environmental and occupational hazards often become entangled in legalistic and regulatory combats that block preventive measures. As a counter-measure and partial solution to this impasse, the so-called precautionary principle (PP) has been introduced. It supplements the traditional risk assessment that requires extensive scientific evidence, because it applies to situations with important threats to human health or the environment where the evidence is still only suggestive. Additionally, the PP provides a procedure to obtain a better balance in public-health policy decisions and to circumvent unrealistic demands for full scientific proof before preventive action is deemed to be justified. The aim is to be more anticipatory in terms of health and dealing with unknowns. The PP is now a mandatory consideration according to some national and international legislation. While precaution is not new in public health, the formal application of the PP offers new procedural opportunities that affect the ways in which policy decisions are arrived at and carried out. This growing body of experience in interpreting and applying the PP, especially in legal settings, is steadily adding to the operational definitions of the PP. As an important and partially overlooked consequence, application of the PP will also have an impact on the types of scientific knowledge and documentation that is needed for decision-making. These issues, therefore, deserve attention by the public health community. Implications of precaution (Grandjean) 5 History of precaution Precaution is common sense and is crucial in all public health decisions. In general, prudence would suggest that the benefits of any doubt should befall the patient. While firmly embedded in common sense and ancient sayings (“in dubio, pro salus”), the most frequently mentioned and perhaps overrated example from medical history is the removal of the handle on the Broad Street water pump in London by John Snow (24). The intervention was clearly precautionary: it was based on incomplete, yet credible evidence, and it prescribed a cost-effective preventive measure, the success of which could then be monitored. Yet, other examples may be at least as important. Gockel discovered in the late 17th century that the endemic colic in a wine-producing district was due to the addition of lead to sweeten the taste of sour wine (22). Based on Gockel’s recommendation, the Duke of Württemberg then prohibited this practice under the penalty of death. However, as Gockel had not convincingly ruled out supposed competing causes, and because lead compounds were thought to be useful as therapeutics, disbelieving scholars rejected his conclusions. In extending Gockel’s work, George Baker carried out a series of experiments that provided further evidence; in this case, examining the Devonshire colic in a district of England where lead-adulterated apple cider was produced (5). Baker recommended precaution in dealing with this toxic metal, because ‘abundans cautela non nocet’ (excess safety precautions do not harm). However, despite Gockel’s and Baker’s efforts, discussions on lead toxicity continued, and clinical lead poisoning remained prevalent. Numerous other environmental hazards were identified at a time when prevention would have been precautionary, but the options were missed (24). Prominent examples were recently reviewed in a monograph published by the European Environment Agency: asbestos, benzene, bovine spongiform encephalopathy, diethylstilbestrol, growth promoting antimicrobials, halocarbons that damage the ozone layer, methyl-tert-butyl ester (MTBE), polychlorinated biphenyls, sulfur dioxide, and tributyltin (24). Vinyl chloride and alkyllead compounds are also Implications of precaution (Grandjean) 6 considered important examples (48). Thus, the history of prevention clearly documents numerous credible warnings that were not heeded. Table 1 shows the most important messages gained from examining early warnings that were missed (24). In contrast, only few examples come to mind where exaggerated prevention appears to have greatly exceeded the need (24). Among possible examples are saccharin and acrylamide, but in both cases, corrective action was later introduced. The modern PP has emerged from the German Vorsorgeprinzip that was introduced in a social context during the 1930s and formally extended to environmental policy about 1970 as a planning instrument (9). The ‘foresight’ was considered necessary to protect against hazards at an early time before serious adverse effects occurred. Although not a literal translation, the so-called precautionary principle was born and included in the first convention on the protection of the North Sea, held in 1984. This was later to be followed by many other international agreements (56, 62). Environmental disease causation A substantial part of the total burden of disease in industrialized countries has been attributed to environmental factors, with the bulk of this amount affecting children and vulnerable groups, such as the poor and women in reproductive age (65). A recent report from the U.S. National Research Council estimated that a large portion of developmental disorders in children are caused by environmental factors (53). Lead poisoning appears to be the most important environmental risk factor in regard to children’s health (47). However, all estimates of this kind are approximate and based on expert judgment from information on individual hazards, such as lead, that represent only a small portion of the total exposure burden. Apart from our dependence upon a healthy global ecology, environmental disease causation is therefore highly important from a public health standpoint, but its true impact is bound to be seriously underestimated due to the lack of documentation. Implications of precaution (Grandjean) 7 Scientific information on the health effects of most industrial chemicals has been shown to be either limited or nonexistent (59): Nearly three out of four (71%) of the sampled highpriority chemicals did not meet the minimum data requirements for health hazard screening set by the Organisation for Economic Cooperation and Development (OECD) Chemicals Program. Of the nearly 3,000 high production volume (HPV) chemicals, which are made or imported to the U.S. at more than 1 million lbs/yr, only seven percent possessed a complete set of publicly available screening data on their toxicity (71). This review also found that 43% of HPV chemicals had no testing data on basic toxicity. Among 491 chemicals used by children and families in consumer products, only 25% had full screening data (71). Furthermore, not all potential adverse effects are included in the tests required by the authorities. For example, neurotoxicity tests (in chicken) are normally required only for cholinesterase-inhibiting pesticides (2). Thus, even for those chemicals that have been tested, limited information exists on how those substances can influence human health at environmental levels of exposure. A major reason for this unfortunate situation is the inappropriate allocation of responsibilities, where regulatory authorities are usually in charge of the assessment instead of the enterprises which produce, import, or use the substances; information on the use of substances and exposure potentials is also difficult to access (14). Important insight also derives from changes in exposure limits. For example, a critical review of the toxicology data led the Center for Disease Control, in 1960, to decide on an action level for the blood-lead concentration in children at 600 µg/liter (2.9 µmol/liter). As evidence on lead toxicity accumulated, the limit was lowered; 30 years later, the action level had been decreased to 100 µg/liter (0.5 µmol/liter) (13). In hindsight at least, enough information seemed available much earlier to trigger the stricter actions. On the other hand, had new evidence not emerged, the high levels acceptable in 1960 might have prevailed. This example suggests that even exposure limits of today should be regarded as temporary approximations based on currently available documentation. Implications of precaution (Grandjean) 8 New information is scheduled to be forthcoming more rapidly than in the past. OECD has coordinated an international effort to screen the HPV chemicals. Among ‘existing’ substances (i.e., those that were marketed in Europe by September, 1981), about 30,000 are marketed in volumes above 1 ton per year. The European Commission has now presented draft principles for obtaining basic toxicological information on those of the chemicals about which little is known (16). However, US authorities have protested against the proposal and threaten to contest this requirement within the World Trade Organization (8, 32). Whatever the outcome of this dispute, additional data will emerge, though only slowly and mainly focusing on limited aspects of socalled priority chemicals. Still, many uncertainties will prevail. At the same time, anthropogenic changes in the environment are occurring at a greater pace. Our improved understanding of the world is therefore lagging behind in determining the risks to human health and the environment, and new knowledge will not eliminate uncertainty as a permanent concern. If changes in decision-making are not instituted, remaining gaps in critical knowledge will continue to block or may be used to block the efforts to reduce or eliminate diseases that might be preventable by better management of environmental hazards. Complexities and short-comings of risk assessment During the last 25 years or so, risk assessment has been a successful, evidence-based approach to management of environmental pollution (52). However, risk assessment, at least as currently practiced, is most useful when scientific information is virtually complete. Human exposures are modeled and the dose-response relationship is then used to calculate the risk associated with the exposure (Fig. 1). Because of high ambitions for systematic priority-setting, with its frequent links to cost-benefit analyses, risk assessment has become increasingly complicated. Scientific desires of a full understanding the biology of environmental health have become a stumbling block, because toxicological mechanisms of action were demanded as a prerequisite for risk assessment (especially for carcinogens). One recent example is di(2-ethylhexyl)phthalate, where Implications of precaution (Grandjean) 9 intense research has focused on identifying a reason why carcinogenicity in rodents should not apply to humans (50). In response to this pressure, the International Agency for Research on Cancer chose to downgrade the classification of this rodent carcinogen from possibly carcinogenic to not classifiable (39). Certain default settings have long been used in risk assessment for extrapolation from laboratory animal studies and high-dose exposure to low doses and vulnerable human populations. These procedures are now criticized for not being scientific, and have been said to be ‘hallowed’ only by long use and acceptance by a regulatory agency (6). Likewise, the monotone dose-response curve has come under attack, e.g., because some observations suggested the possible existence of so-called hormesis at low doses (11). Pragmatic application of linearized dose-response relationships was challenged, because other models led to widely differing risk assessments (20). Mathematical modeling, long employed as a useful tool, also appeared to be an obstacle when the default conditions applied were realized to be of unknown validity (52). These revelations were then followed by belligerent demands for objectivity in science (31). While the validity of extrapolation from animal experiments was cast in doubt (10), epidemiology received the harshest critique (67). Observational studies will always have weaknesses, since exposures are not determined as a matter of experimental design. However, sophisticated critiques by recognized experts have been used with the aim of disproving evidence on environmental hazards, such as man-made mineral fibers (51). An international call for guidelines on 'Good Epidemiological Practice' was thought by many to serve a useful educational purpose. However, this ‘sound science’ movement was not an indigenous effort from within the profession to improve the quality of scientific discourse. It turned out to be part of a sophisticated public relations strategy controlled by industry executives and lawyers whose aim was to manipulate the standards of scientific proof to serve the corporate interests of their clients (55). Thus, strict interpretation of epidemiological rules had the purpose of dismissing epidemiological findings that, for some reason, were unwelcome. This effort first targeted Implications of precaution (Grandjean) 10 evidence on environmental tobacco smoke, but also dealt with other environmental contaminants. As a result, the Chemical Manufacturers Association (later renamed American Chemical Council) co-funded these efforts along with the Philip Morris Company (55). In this atmosphere, scientific rigor became misunderstood as the unrealistic need to conduct controlled experiments with statistically robust conclusions. Inconclusive studies were labeled “negative” and were thought to represent “no risk” rather than “no information”. Risk assessment also became a battling ground in regard to access to information. Because evidence is the basis upon which the evaluation of risks must rely, suppression of information occurred, as did withholding of evidence, lambasting of whistle-blowers, and releasing of half-truths or untruths (45). For example, in determining occupational exposure limits, and often maintaining them at inappropriately high levels, corporate representatives acted as expert consultants to committees thought to be neutral (12). The ongoing contentious scientific debates on minute scientific details, the incomplete access to toxicology information, the associated challenges in the legal system, and the resulting defensive reaction from regulatory authorities has led to “paralysis by analysis” (24, 66). Risk assessment has therefore become part of the problem and not part of the solution. Types of incertitude The major problem in the standard risk assessment approach is uncertainty (37). “Incertitude”, as a general term for all types of uncertainty, is a given in public health, as well as a key characteristic of environmental health problems. Examples from past experiences show that incertitude was not appropriately interpreted, with the result of unnecessary human suffering and environmental degradation (24). Lack of scientific data is of course not the same as proof of harm or the opposite, but this ignorance means that any conclusion about safety is unfounded. One could question why 70% of chemicals marketed after 1981 (and about which adequate toxicology Implications of precaution (Grandjean) 11 information is required before marketing) are considered hazardous, while only a few percent of previously marketed chemicals are similarly labeled from available toxicity data. Different heuristic taxonomies have been used to categorize the types of incertitude involved. The simplest dimension of incertitude is so-called “risk”, which encompasses variability due to factors such as imprecision and sampling error in the data base. Uncertainty (in the narrow sense of the word) involves incomplete knowledge on the type of adverse effect, the particular aspect of the exposure that may be harmful, the dose-response model, the impact of combined exposures, and similar considerations that cannot be settled from current information. Ignorance is considered when even less information is available, but may still be potentially remedied by further research. The final aspect is indeterminacy, where the problem shows dependence on multiple variables or chaotic properties that defy attempts to predict the outcome (66). Some forms of incertitude may be dealt with in risk assessment by including so-called “uncertainty factors” (formerly called “safety factors”) (40). While a greater incertitude also leads to the use of larger uncertainty factors, the incertitude in regard to the uncertainty factors also increases. Therefore, this approach has important practical limitations and the PP appears like a useful approach when knowledge is lacking (e.g., on the type of outcomes and also their probabilities) (66). Defining the precautionary principle Given this complex background, it is hardly to be expected that a simple statement of a logical principle will provide a key to resolving the conundrums of decision-making in environmental health. Nonetheless, to counterbalance the imperfect solutions provided by traditional risk assessment, statements have been phrased that indicate how precaution should be exerted. Probably the most widely known definition is the one provided in the Rio declaration: “Where there are threats of serious or irreversible damage, scientific uncertainty shall not be used Implications of precaution (Grandjean) 12 to postpone cost-effective measures to prevent environmental degradation” (70). Other definitions include stronger wordings, e.g., by leaving out that actions must be cost-effective, or by including a reverse burden of proof. Thus, a group of experts formulated the Wingspread definition (73): “When an activity raises threats of harm to the environment or human health, precautionary measures should be taken even if some cause and effect relationships are not fully established scientifically.” Also, in regard to the onus of proof, the statement reads: “In this context the proponent of an activity, rather than the public, should bear the burden of proof.” In the European Union, the PP is considered “a general rule of public policy action to be used in situations of potentially serious or irreversible threats to health or to the environment, where there is a need to act to reduce potential hazards before there is strong proof of harm, taking into account the likely costs and benefits of action and inaction” (24). Table 2 summarizes the most important aspects of the PP as used in Europe (i.e., that the application must be proportional, non-discriminatory, comparable, cost-efficient, and subject to revision) (17). As many as 19 different definitions have been put forward on various occasions (62). They generally include four dimensions (3, 62): 1) the existence of a threat, 2) uncertainty about its implications, 3) anticipatory action, and 4) a command to act. Fig. 2 shows how the PP may lead to action against serious threats where uncertainty would not justify proper risk assessment. Given that the PP is a culturally framed concept, the words “sometimes”, “if necessary”, and “may” suggest space for negotiation for which procedural rules need to be established. In regard to causal associations, similar distinctions are also important (e.g., between “beyond reasonable doubt”, “preponderance of evidence”, “weight of the evidence”, “more likely than not”, and “a definite possibility”). Still, differences between the definitions have been taken as an alleged weakness of the PP and a sign of disagreement on the interpretation of the PP (61). An exact definition of the PP must depend on the legal and cultural circumstances (25). From a legal viewpoint, the PP is considered a guide to utilizing scientific evidence in decisionmaking contexts (19). Although such guides need specification and refinement before they can be Implications of precaution (Grandjean) 13 used in a predictable way, the PP does not differ in this regard from other approaches to using factual information such as in the law (19). Employing the PP may involve, for example, alternatives assessment, full-cost assessment, and a participatory decision process. It may be coupled with the right-to-know aspect, empowering the citizen to take action, and these aspects of information access are probably most consequential in regard to legal ramifications (61). The wording of the PP must also carefully consider the serious problem of state authority in the face of scientific incertitude. The PP should be considered a policy tool to deal with scientific uncertainty and ignorance, with the aim of deciding upon actions involving more research, a preventive intervention, or both. The PP can also be looked upon as an extension of risk assessment and, in accordance with, for example, the “de minimis” approach used in regard to the so-called threshold of toxicological concern (44). It represents a “negligible” cut-off point below which a hazard is ignored (also a matter that is open to interpretation). As a precautionary decision, an Executive Order from the US President required special emphasis on children’s environmental health, and the subsequent Food Quality Protection Act allows the use of a 10-fold factor to secure that children are not exposed to toxic amounts of pesticides and other pollutants (21). A similar blanket approach has been used in the EU, where water contaminant concentrations must be below a limit of 0.1µg/liter (the detection limit at the time) (1). Critiques of the precautionary principle It has been claimed that the PP results in huge expenses invested into risks that don’t exist, because “...it is plainly irrational to fear risks the existence of which is conjectural...” (31). The assertion is that the PP will result in unjustified costs that would be far better deployed improving social welfare elsewhere. On the same note, the concern is that the grandmotherly maxim of' “better safe than sorry” will stop all innovation in society. The consequences of such exaggerated concerns with Implications of precaution (Grandjean) 14 risks were examined in a “survey of 40 scientists”. Had the precautionary principle been allowed to prevail in the past, the response was reportedly: no heart surgery or antibiotics, and hardly any drugs at all; no airplanes, bicycles or high-voltage power grids; no pasteurization, pesticides or biotechnology; no quantum mechanics; no wheel; no discovery of America. In short, their message was: no risk, no gain (69). However, as indicated above, the lack of information currently offers automatic rewards to the producers who do not provide toxicological data. Furthermore, the PP may be a “speed bump” in some cases, but is not an inevitable prediction that leads to an obstruction or a ban of new technology or human enterprises in general. While science-based conjecture is not flawless, at least the application of the PP aims at offering a better balance. The risk to human health and the environment may otherwise be too great. One only has to think of the US chemist Thomas Midgley, who first invented tetraethyllead as an octane-boosting gasoline additive and later on invented chlorofluorocarbons. Midgley has been said to have had a greater impact on the atmosphere than any other single organism in Earth history (49, p.111). The harsh criticism of the EC communication claims that it is ill-defined, lacks checks and balances, and omits evidentiary criteria for precaution (32). Given the dependence upon legal circumstances and tradition, the weak or vague points must deserve careful scrutiny. While the PP clearly prescribes a value judgment (which may be subjective), the same is true for risk assessment (18, 52). It therefore seems that the PP is no more ambiguous than other decision rules (62). Open and transparent procedures are necessary to prevent biased decisions, with regard to the perceived level of evidence required for proof of causality. The specific procedures for applying the PP must then be carefully worked out as appropriate for the legal and cultural setting (19). Thus, the weaknesses in instrumental aspects should be considered temporary in regard to a newly introduced legal principle. EC Court rulings are already providing assistance in this development. Implications of precaution (Grandjean) 15 A related but more general issue is whether the precautionary principle is at all legitimate in a democratic society. Because the PP prescribes action in the face of incertitude, it may lead to exercising arbitrary power unchecked by democratic processes; thereby, potentially leading to capricious discrimination and/or trade protectionism. Again, this concern is relevant and must be confronted (62), but current disagreements between the US and the EU seem to have kindled controversies on this issue beyond proportion. In fact, the participatory aspects of PP-based decision-making seem more legitimate in a modern democracy than technocratic solutions based on traditional risk assessment. Application of the PP should not lead to piecemeal solutions, like those sometimes attributed to misdirected risk management. Countervailing risks must be kept in mind (32). Thus, the risk balance was not considered when providing clean drinking-water from wells that leached toxic substances from soil minerals. In Bangladesh, arsenic contamination is now causing severe health effects (29), while parallel problems in India are mainly due to fluoride. Similarly, octaneboosting gasoline additives like MTBE were not sufficiently evaluated before introduced as substitutes (24, 29). Therefore, application of the PP will lead to problems of comparisons between risks that are exchangeable and, at the same time, subject to precautionary reduction (Table 1). Finally, the PP has also been criticized for being hostile to science. Accordingly, if a decision may be reached on the basis of incomplete information, then the incentive for further research could be less (30). However, application of the PP may itself require new research and monitoring. Goldstein (30) proposed that the public agency that made the initial hazard claim should also invest in independent research to establish the validity of it. Likewise, as discussed below, the use of the PP is likely to change the way that scientific information is applied and probably also the way it is planned and reported. Implications of precaution (Grandjean) 16 Differences between the United States and Europe In discussing potentials for trade wars and clashes between legal systems, the differences between US and EU approaches become highly apparent (e.g., in regard to genetically-modified foods and hormone-treated beef) (72). While the precautionary principle is now part of the treaty that forms the legal basis of the European Union, U.S. legislation, in various ways, also reflects precautionary approaches, although in a diluted or compromised form (3). The now rescinded Delaney Clause was a prime example of this concept, but the superceding Food Quality Protection Act allows consideration of uncertainty by mandating the use of uncertainty factors. Another US approach has been to impose maximal allowable control technology to regulate air pollution. Although such requirement may be advantageous in current perspective, it may not necessarily provide sufficient protection in the longer term as new insight into health risks emerge. In addition, it may freeze pollution abatement at the level that is achievable now (3, 29). However, the current overzealous practice of evidence-based risk assessment and the “hard look” reviews by the courts have diminished precautionary approaches (3). In an important decision in 1980, the US Supreme Court held that OSHA cannot regulate benzene exposure on the basis of mere conjecture about uncertain risk and that OSHA must demonstrate ‘significant risk’ before regulating. This decision constituted a significant motivation for adoption of risk assessment as a basis for risk regulation in the US (72). In the so-called Daubert Decision, the US Supreme Court instructed federal judges to allow only expert testimony that was both reliable and relevant. The court also stated that evidence should be based on a testable peer-reviewed theory with a known error rate and be widely accepted by the scientific community. The implications of this decision could make PPbased decisions difficult to defend in these courts. Generic regulation has been accepted in the US based on extrapolations from detailed knowledge on single chemicals, but only in restricted situations, such as benzidine-related dyes. Because occupational exposures are often mixed, the IARC (International Agency for Research Implications of precaution (Grandjean) 17 on Cancer) has grouped these exposures together, and this classification has been heeded. However, in other circumstances, no such extrapolation is accepted (19), and court decisions have reversed some agency decisions to apply generic regulations (3). In Europe, generic regulation is used (e.g., in regard to the above mentioned drinking-water contaminants) (1). In some regards, the EU therefore may be more precautionary than the US; while the opposite appears to be the case in others. Blood donations provide an interesting example, where the FDA requires rejection of blood from a donor who has spent three months or more in the UK, or five years or more in Europe, since 1980. This decision is meant to decrease the risk of transfer of the BSE agent via blood. Clearly, this decision is precautionary, but of course it can in no way be matched by the EU. Meanwhile, the EU’s strong stand on GMO (genetically modified) corn and hormone residues in meat is being challenged by the US in the World Trade Organization (72). The systemic approach to decision-making Current risk assessment in regard to human health and the environment suffers from reductionism (24, 38). The requirement that decisions must be based on solid evidence and scientific proof results in a reification of environmental health and piecemeal solutions. Although important achievements have been made, the problems of complex chemical exposures and ecological intricacies require a different approach. Instead, what is needed is a decision that is approximately right and timely, rather than one that is precisely correct but too late. Because of the failure of risk assessment to appropriately address incertitude and to provide guidance in large-scale and complex environmental health problems, it needs to be supplemented by a systemic paradigm that includes shared decisions within a broader context. For purposes, such as this, de Rosnay (60) has recommended the use of a systemic approach that he calls the macroscope (Table 3). The PP is relevant in this regard, because it is not a rule that is only to be applied when faced with a concrete threat. The PP is also an overarching principle that is applicable throughout Implications of precaution (Grandjean) 18 the whole process of policy formulation. Tickner (68) proposes a framework that he calls precautionary assessment. It starts with problem scoping, stakeholder identification, and allocation of responsibilities. Then, it follows the environment and health impact analysis that includes an uncertainty analysis. Analysis of alternatives is included before the final precautionary action analysis. Such systemic perspectives provide a necessary alternative to technology-based environmental management. Fig. 3 shows, graphically, how precautionary actions lead to better insight that may eventually allow formal risk assessment. Costs and benefits include non-economic considerations (17). For this reason, the European Commission has affirmed that requirements linked to protection of public health should ‘undoubtedly’ be given a greater weight than economic considerations. Thereby the singularity of strictly financial cost-benefit analysis is challenged as a decision-making tool. The role of science in PP-based decision-making must therefore be to allow pluralities of perspectives instead of hiding a single view under the veil of scientific truth. Because of the substantial degrees of incertitude, decisions in environmental health are no more a matter of applied science or even professional consultancy based on extrapolation and inference. They become “post-normal science” (27); where, in plain words, we need to promote gardening rather than botany. This need then calls for a passage from a substantive rationality to a procedural rationality, where the quality of the process becomes paramount (27). In designing consistent and accountable procedures, a major problem is to establish the detailed rules of evidence, including the hierarchy of knowledge, evidence, documentation, individual results, and permissible extrapolations. Although when to act is not a new question, the challenge is to define the threshold under more complex circumstances, while applying consistent criteria (32, 57). Different levels of proof may be needed for different purposes, depending on the severity of the problem (Fig. 2). False positives and unfounded vetos must be avoided, because the blocking of useful innovations could unreasonably hamper social and economic development, while, at the same time, cast doubt upon the validity of the process (57). Additional attributes are Implications of precaution (Grandjean) 19 goal-setting for the long term; for instance, establishing desirable futures rather than crisis management and aiming at clean production coupled with monitoring to secure high quality (24). The PP-based decision process must address public concerns, which may be more directed at ensuring that a potential problem is not ignored, in contrast to scientists who are often reluctant to give credibility to unproven possibilities. The decision-making framework should provide a process where different positions can be reconciled. It must become more participatory, substituting technocratic or authoritarian leadership styles with widening acceptance of qualitative criteria for judging the environment (e.g., human rights, ethical values, animal welfare, quality of life issues, socioeconomic considerations, and sustainability) (15). The European Commission requires that minority views be considered in this process, provided that the credibility and reputation are recognized (17). In this participatory process, the consumer will be empowered to take informed precautionary action so as to exercise choices of risks (61). Although polarized opinions will undoubtedly remain, this process allows consideration of all aspects and, therefore, also a better chance of resolution of opposing views. A variety of methodological approaches have been proposed, including trade-off analysis (4) and multicriteria mapping (66). Using maximin criteria, one gives priority to actions aimed at improving the condition of those who are worst-off, thereby avoiding the policy with the worst possible consequences. Implications of the maximin approach are likely to agree with decisions based on the PP; although potentially in conflict with a utilitarian strategy (54). Quantitative Bayesian evaluation is possible and attractive (54), but these methods also possess some inherent difficulties (58). The California Department of Health Services has sponsored an admirable program to explore the possible health effects of electric and magnetic fields (EMF) from power lines (54). Using transparent democratic foresight strategies, it examined the advantages and disadvantages of different actions. The lessons learned from this experience will be highly appropriate for the procedures used for future decision-making on similar environmental health Implications of precaution (Grandjean) 20 problems. Indeed, EMF serves as a useful example of the significance of incertitude in regard to a potentially serious hazard (28, 74). The PP-based decision may be a request for further research to allow an improved basis for future decisions, but all decisions should be considered provisional and dynamic. Measures based on the PP may assign responsibility for providing the supplementary information required (17). At present, the principle of prior approval (‘positive list’) has shifted the responsibility for producing scientific evidence for drugs, pesticides, food additives. Likewise, monitoring may be needed to track environmental health factors to allow linkage of increased prevalence ranging from chronic diseases to causative pollution factors (23). In such cases, the decision process will involve a dynamic relationship with research, where new information is taken into account while reconsidering the previous decision. A precautionary research paradigm Due to the fact that decisions under the PP may be taken on the basis of incomplete evidence, precautionary science is likely to emphasize association rather than proof (i.e., at a lower scientific validity) (43). The PP has been interpreted as research averse, since no new research would be needed once a decision has been made. However, all decisions are provisional, and some decisions may mandate additional research and monitoring, perhaps as the only action until new information allows reconsideration. As expressed by the European Commission, uncertainties should stimulate research (17). Indeed, targeted toxicology and intervention studies would likely serve both scientific purposes and policy means. Several authors have discussed whether there is such term as “precautionary science” (7, 30, 43, 68). Although some general ideas have been presented, it is clear that science should not change drastically due to the application of the PP. However, PP-based thinking has elucidated some weaknesses in the current approaches in environmental health research. Several important Implications of precaution (Grandjean) 21 aspects are indicated in Table 4. Mending these problems and redirecting research efforts could constitute an important shift in paradigm. First of all, the PP may provide a welcome occasion to critically consider the overall strategies for environmental health research (43). Although replication is necessary in science where a single observation may represent an accident or an exception, replication can also be carried too far. A review of major environmental health journals will reveal that the vast majority of published papers deal with a few hundred well-studied environmental toxicants. Some of this information may still be useful for paradigms of PP-based decisions on, say, groups of persistent or bioaccumulative chemicals (including compounds not yet studied). However, the failure of environmental health research to target unstudied or understudied pollutants is a major embarrassment. The PP suggests that attention be shifted to new issues, instead of narrow and narrowing research topics that elicit repetition to reduce already limited uncertainties. New research should focus more on larger-scale patterns, trends, early indicators, and other ‘red flag’ parameters that may be of more general importance. Rather than attempting to provide complete documentation for the purpose of sophisticated risk assessment, research should be directed toward expanding perspectives and covering new ground. This shift does not mean that efforts to support evidencebased risk assessment should be halted, but they do need to be complemented. PP-based decisions are also likely to mandate follow-up monitoring; this type of effort then effectively becomes an intervention study, where changes are documented as a result of a ban or other action. Far too much scientific literature is descriptive rather than analytic, and thus provides even more limited guidance for primary prevention. Some authors (7) have recommended a shift from “mechanistic” science to precautionary science. This change is parallel to the shifts from analytic to systemic approaches in Table 1 and is thought to affect the design of research, the scale of the issues confronted, and how error, validity, and uncertainty are addressed. Clearly, the hubristic language and thinking about Implications of precaution (Grandjean) 22 uncertainties in regard to risk assessment should be discarded (66). Instead of systematically neglecting unknowns and poorly understood issues, these problems should now become an object of research. They should become the center of attention rather than an annoying interference with good science. Related statistical issues are considered separately below. Among priority issues to tackle are interactions between different toxic exposures (43, 64) and the significance of individual vulnerability within groups at risk (33, 46). For example, subtle adverse effects may decrease the physiological reserve capacity and thereby the susceptibility toward some other exposure or adverse incident (35). This issue deserves to be further explored, as it could have wider implications for our understanding of low-dose toxicity and the long-term effects as well as interactions. On the whole, much research is based on biochemical effects on a molecular scale, but effects on populations and ecosystems need to be incorporated, as do the potential effects on future generations. This may appear like a tall order. However, large numbers of physicists are capable of collaborating on huge projects to seek new complex knowledge. Environmental health research should also become a joint enterprise that tackles some of the above scientific problems that have already been apparent for too long. One final issue that deserves to be mentioned is openness, which relates to research as much as to decision-making. Transparency and accountability are crucial for research to provide credible guidance for PP-based decisions as described above. Just as laboratory accreditation requires traceability of all procedures, researchers should retain records to document the methods as well as the choices that inevitably must be made. Stakeholder participation should be considered both in the planning phases of the study and in communicating progress and outcomes. Research publication may now benefit from rapid publication on the internet, and some scientific journals allow or even solicit publicly accessible storage of data materials and protocols. Implications of precaution (Grandjean) 23 Statistical issues of precaution Conceptually, scientists will normally support a positive association (i.e., the risk is real) if the probability that the observed risk has arisen by chance is below 5%. A type I error means that an innocuous factor is mistakenly identified as a risk, but this should then happen only in one out of 20 studies. Scientists are often willing to ‘miss’ a real association (i.e., conclude the risk does not exist, when it actually does) with a probability of 20%. This is referred to as a type II error, which is then bound to happen in one out of five studies. However, there is an implicit bias in being more cautious about falsely detecting something than about failing to detect something (43). Table 4 lists this imbalance along with other tendencies that cause a bias in evaluating potential environmental causes of disease. The caveats expressed by Hill (36) in regard to the aspects of causal thinking are often overlooked: “All scientific work is incomplete. (...) All scientific work is liable to be upset or modified by advancing knowledge. That does not confer upon us the freedom to ignore the knowledge we already have, or to postpone the action that it appears to demand at a given time.” Because the exigencies of public health problems demand action, causal inferences must be made despite imperfect knowledge. In addition, the public is more concerned that any potential risk is not overlooked, irrespective of statistics. Public policy, as well as the application of the PP, must then avoid anti-precautionary tendencies. The potential biases (Table 4) need to be considered when evaluating causal evidence and dose-response relationships, and one needs to take into account what can be known, given the methods and study opportunities available. Nonetheless, Pharisaic efforts to discount evidence of causal associations prevail, as already indicated in regard to the “good science” strategy. Sometimes, review documents mistake the validity of the conclusions for meticulousness in identifying presumed violations of causal criteria. Uncertainty of information is then confused with the quality of the information (43). For example, in evaluating the possible decline in semen quality as an effect of exposure to endocrine disrupting chemicals, an expert committee used Implications of precaution (Grandjean) 24 Hill’s criteria in reaching the following conclusion (41): “For outcome, the evidence is judged to be weak. A global trend for declining semen quality is not supported by current data. (...) There is no evidence relating to the strength of the hypothesis because of the lack of exposure data. There are no human data to support an EDC-related mechanism. However, the biological plausibility of the hypothesis remains strong, based on information from clinical experience and experimental systems.” A similar conclusion was reached in regard to breast cancer and endocrine disruptors, although the experts at the same time admitted that few studies had provided exposure assessments that related to the time of greatest relevance. While in accordance with good science, these conclusions do not reflect PP-based conjectures. Although a normal reporting practice, standard probability values are of little interest in regard to PP-based thinking, because they only indicate the likelihood of the data, or some that are more extreme, given that the null hypothesis is true. However, a frequent issue is that the null hypothesis is not true and these p values are therefore not helpful. Given the PP-related concerns with potentially large threats, confidence limits (e.g., with a 95% coverage) would be much more appropriate to ascertain the possible upper range of a hazard. In standard analyses of epidemiological data, the exposure as independent variable is considered to be without error, which is almost always wrong. A non-differential imprecision, which would be typical of biomarker analyses, generally causes a bias toward the null hypothesis, thereby resulting in an underestimation of the true effect of the exposure. Epidemiological studies rarely take into regard the error function of the exposure estimate or consider only the laboratory imprecision. The full extent of the misclassification, which includes biological and other preanalytical sources of variation, may be considerable larger than the laboratory error alone. Accordingly, the underestimation of the toxic potential of the exposure may be far greater than normally assumed (34). Although exposure imprecision can be modeled in sensitivity analyses, they require that the degree of imprecision be known (which is rarely the case). From a precautionary viewpoint, Implications of precaution (Grandjean) 25 sensitivity analyses should include appropriate magnitudes of exposure errors to explore the reasonable extent of possible underestimation of the dose-effect relationship. One approach to estimation of safe exposure levels is the benchmark dose, which takes into account some aspects of statistical power, so that smaller studies will result in a lower benchmark dose. However, when applied to epidemiological data, where exposure misclassification is a common problem, benchmark doses have now been found to be overestimated due to imprecision of the exposure parameter (42). These impacts of exposure misclassification show that a critique of risk assessment for being overly conservative (6) should acknowledge that some aspects, such as benchmark dose calculations, may not be conservative after all. Moreover, unadjusted benchmark dose levels are often misconstrued by regulatory agencies to represent approximate thresholds, even when adverse effects are documented below this level. Such interpretations of statistical data may indeed be non-conservative and antiprecautionary (42). In addition to errors of type I and type II mentioned above, researchers sometimes refer to type III errors (i.e., when the research has answered the wrong question) (63). As indicated by some commentators on precautionary science (7), good science may well commit type III errors when judged from a precautionary viewpoint. The highest scientific quality may be a poor publichealth effort. The future of precaution Threats to human health and the environment must be identified and managed to every extent possible, but the links between research and public health action are insufficient. The precautionary principle offers a possible solution to escape from the impasse created by reductionist approaches to risk assessment and piecemeal prevention. The idea expressed by the PP is not new, but perhaps the time has now come for this worthy approach to be applied in larger-scale environmental health issues. Implications of precaution (Grandjean) 26 At this point, the PP, as it is expressed in primary legislation and case law, does not yet provide the necessary framework to link uncertain facts to causation and the dose-dependency of effects (19). The primary legislation needs to include more detailed guidance on handling large uncertainties for the sake of agency-based rule-making. If possible, a threshold of scientific evidence needs to be defined that, when crossed, commands a branch of government to provide protection against a hazard deemed potentially serious (32). This threshold must aim at reducing legal ambiguity. Unless the PP is formalized and operationally defined, it will remain susceptible to the critique that it is haphazard and uncertain itself. A first step could be to identify the threshold that justifies a shift of the onus of scientific proof. For example, countries like Denmark and Sweden have used objective criteria to draw up lists of “undesirable” chemicals that are persistent or bioaccumulative. Where new restrictions apply, unless countered by new test data, a chemical will be taken off the list. The European Commission has already expressed that decision-making should incorporate issues such as inequity and injustice, psychological stress and discomfort, and animal welfare (15). Such aspects are not encompassed by the current framework of risk assessment, but would seem to be appropriate for risk management and for the types of decisions that may follow PP-based considerations. These prospects highlight the need for new procedural rules to achieve the necessary multidisciplinary collaboration, stakeholder participation, and transparency. In decision theory, aspects of causal conjectures may be defined in accordance with the calculus of probability theory. Thus, the uncertain elements that form the basis of a PP-based decision may be expressed as a matter of probabilities that can be updated by new empirical information. Several techniques are available and need to be critically evaluated. A constructive framework should aim at utilizing modern statistical methods of causal analysis that will allow choices that are both reproducible and efficient (58). Although erroneously criticized for being science averse, the PP is an important impetus to review current research strategies, methodologies, and research reporting traditions. Traditional Implications of precaution (Grandjean) 27 risk assessment must continue to be supported by research, but it should be supplemented by research that more directly targets the perspectives that require application of the PP. In this regard, the research must facilitate PP-based decisions by exploring the potential extent of uncertain threats to human health and the environment. By addressing these important issues, environmental health research can help reestablish the link between science and public health. Acknowledgments The author’s research is supported by the US National Institute of Environmental Health Sciences (ES09797 and ES11681), and the Danish Medical Research Council. The contents of this paper are solely the responsibility of the author and do not represent the official views of the NIEHS, NIH, or any other funding agency. Literature cited 1. Altenburger R. 1995. Drinking water: for human consumption only? The amendment of directive 80/778/EEC parameter 55 in the light of aquatic toxicology. Chemosphere 30: 307—12 2. Andersen HR, Nielsen JB, Grandjean P. 2000. Toxicologic evidence of developmental neurotoxicity of environmental chemicals. Toxicology 144: 121—7 3. Applegate JS. 2000. The precautionary preference: An American perspective on the precautionary principle. Hum. Ecol. Risk Assessm. 6: 413—43 4. Ashford NA. 1999. A conceptual framework for the use of the precautionary principle in law. In Protecting public health and the environment: Implementing the precautionary principle, ed. C Raffensperger, J Tickner, pp. 198--206. Washington: Island Press 5. Baker G. 1772. An inquiry concerning the cause of the endemial colic of Devonshire. Med. Trans. R. Coll. Phys. 1: 175—256 Implications of precaution (Grandjean) 6. 28 Barnard RC. 1995. Risk assessment: The default conservatism controversy. Regul. Toxicol. Pharmacol. 21: 431—438 7. Barrett K, Raffensperger C. 1999. Precautionary science. In Protecting public health and the environment: Implementing the precautionary principle, ed. C Raffensperger, J Tickner, pp.106–22. Washington, DC: Island Press 8. Becker E, Lee JB. 2003. Europe plan on chemicals seen as threat to U.S. exports. The New York Times, May 8 9. Boehmner-Christiansen S. 1994. The precautionary principle in Germany. In Interpreting the precautionary principle, ed T O’Riordan, J Cameron, pp. 31–60. London: Cameron May 10. Brown SL, Brett SM, Gough M, Rodricks JV, Tardiff RG, Turnbull D. 1988. Review of interspecies risk comparisons. Regul. Toxicol. Pharmacol. 8: 191—206 11. Calabrese EJ, Baldwin LA. 2003. Hormesis: The dose-response revolution. Annu. Rev. Pharmacol. Toxicol. 43: 175--97 12. Castleman BI, Ziem GE. 1988. Corporate influence on threshold limit values. Am. J. Ind. Med. 13: 531--59 13. Centers for Disease Control. 1991. Preventing lead poisoning in young children: a statement by the Centers for Disease Control--October 1991. Atlanta, GA: Centers for Disease Control 14. Commission of the European Communities. 2001. White paper, Strategy for a future chemicals policy (COM(2001) 88 final). Brussels. URL: http://europa.eu.int/eur-lex/en/com/wpr/2001/com2001_0088en01.pdf (accessed 10 June, 2003) 15. Commission of the European Communities. 2003. Final Report on Setting the Scientific Frame for the Inclusion of New Quality of Life Concerns in the Risk Assessment Process. Implications of precaution (Grandjean) 29 Health & Consumer Protection Directorate-General. URL: http://europa.eu.int/comm/food/fs/sc/ssc/out362_en.pdf (accessed 10 June, 2003) 16. Commission of the European Communities. 2003. The new chemicals legislation REACH. URL: http://europa.eu.int/comm/enterprise/chemicals/chempol/whitepaper/reach.htm (accessed, 10 June, 2003) 17. Communication from the Commission on the precautionary principle (COM(2000) 1). Brussels: European commission, 2000. URL: http://europa.eu.int/comm/dgs/health_consumer/library/pub/pub07_en.pdf (accessed, 10 June, 2003) 18. Covello VT, Merkhofer MW. 1993. Risk assessment methods, approaches for assessing health and environmental risks. New York: Plenum 19. Cranor CF. 2001. Learning from the law to address uncertainty in the precautionary principle. Sci. Engin. Ethics 7: 313--26 20. Crump KS. 1996. The linearized multistage model and the future of quantitative risk assessment. Hum. Exp. Toxicol. 15: 787--98 21. Dourson M, Charnley G, Scheuplein R. 2002. Differential sensitivity of children and adults to chemical toxicity. II. Risk and regulation. Regul. Toxicol. Pharmacol. 35: 448-67 22. Eisinger J. 1982. Lead and wine. Eberhard Gockel and the colica Pictonum. Med. Hist. 26: 279--302 23. Environmental Health Tracking Project Team. 2000. America's Environmental Health Gap: Why the Country Needs a Nationwide Health Tracking Network. Johns Hopkins School of Hygiene and Public Health, Department of Health Policy and Management, URL: http://healthyamericans.org/resources/files/healthgap.pdf (accessed 10 June, 2003) Implications of precaution (Grandjean) 24. 30 European Environmental Agency. 2001. Late lessons from early warnings: the precautionary principle 1896-2000. Environmental Issue Report No. 22. Luxembourg: Office for Official Publications of the European Communities 25. Fisher E. 2002. Precaution, precaution everywhere: Developing a ‘common understanding’ of the precautionary principle in the European Community. Maastricht J. Eur. Comp. Law 9: 7--25 26. Foster KR, Vecchia P, Repacholi MH. 2000. Science and the precautionary principle. Science 288: 979--81 27. Gallopin GC, Funtowicz S, O'Connor M, Ravetz J. 2001. Science for the twenty-first century: from social contract to the scientific core. Int. Soc. Sci. J. 53: 219--37 28. Gee D. 2003. Strengths of the precautionary principles: Late lessons from early warnings. Paper presented at the Conference on Application of the Precautionary Principle to Electromagnetic Fields (EMF), Luxembourg, 24-26 February 2003. URL: http://europa.eu.int/comm/health/ph_determinants/environment/EMF/Conf24_26feb2003/ gee.pdf (accessed, 3 July, 2003) 29. Goldstein BD. 2001. The precautionary principle also applies to public health actions. Am. J. Public Health 91: 1358--61 30. Goldstein BD. 1999. The precautionary principle and scientific research are not antithetical. Environ. Health Perspect. 107: A594--5 31. Gori GB. 1996. Science, imaginable risks, and public policy: anatomy of a mirage. Regul. Toxicol. Pharmacol. 23: 304--11 32. Graham JD, Hsia S. 2002. Europe’s precautionary principle: promise and pitfalls. J. Risk Res. 5: 371--390 33. Grandjean P. 1992. Individual susceptibility to toxicity. Toxicol. Lett. 64/65: 43--51 34. Grandjean P, Budtz-Jørgensen E, Keiding N, Weihe P. 2003. Underestimation of risk due to exposure misclassification. Eur J Oncol (in press) Implications of precaution (Grandjean) 35. 31 Grandjean P, Jensen BM, Sandø SH, Jørgensen PJ, Antonsen S. 1989. Delayed blood regeneration in lead exposure: An effect on reserve capacity. Am. J. Public Health 79: 1385--8 36. Hill AB. 1965. The environment and disease: Association or causation? Proc. R. Soc. Med. 58: 295--300 37. Hoffmann-Riem H, Wynne B. 2002. In risk assessment, one has to admit ignorance. Nature 416: 123 38. Holling CS. 1998. Two cultures of ecology. Conservation Ecology (online). 2: 4 39. International Agency for Research on Cancer. 2000. Some Industrial Chemicals. IARC Monographs on the Evaluation of Carcinogenic Risks to Humans, Vol 77. Lyon 40. International Programme on Chemical Safety. 1994. Assessing human health risks of chemicals: Derivation of guidance values for health-based exposure limits (Environmental Health Criteria 170). Geneva: World Health Organization 41. International Programme on Chemical Safety. 2002. Global assessment of the state-of-the-science of endocrine disruptors (WHO/PCS/EDC/02.2). Geneva: World Health Organization, URL: http://www.who.int/pcs/emerg_site/edc/global_edc_TOC.htm (accessed, 3 July, 2003) 42. Keiding N, Budtz-Jørgensen E. 2003. Statistical issues in precaution. Eur J Oncol (in press) 43. Kriebel D, Tickner J, Epstein P, Lemons J, Levins R, et al. 2001. The precautionary principle in environmental science. Environ. Health Perspect. 109: 871—6 44. Kroes R, Kozianowski G. 2002. Threshold of toxicological concern (TTC) in food safety assessment. Toxicol. Lett. 127: 43—6 45. Kurland J. 2002. The heart of the precautionary principle in democracy. Public Health Rep. 117: 498—500 Implications of precaution (Grandjean) 46. 32 Landrigan PJ. 1999. Risk assessment for children and other sensitive populations. Ann. N. Y. Acad. Sci. 895: 1—9 47. Landrigan PJ, Schechter CB, Lipton JM, Fahs MC, Schwartz J. 2002. Environmental pollutants and disease in American children: estimates of morbidity, mortality, and costs for lead poisoning, asthma, cancer, and developmental disabilities. Environ. Health Perspect. 110: 721—8 48. Markowitz G, Rosner G. 2002. Deceit and denial. The deadly politics of industrial pollution. Berkeley: University of California Press 49. McNeill JR. 2000. Something new under the sun. An environmental history of the twentieth century. New York: Norton 50. Melnick RL. 2001. Is peroxisome proliferation an obligatory precursor step in the carcinogenicity of di(2-ethylhexyl)phthalate (DEHP)? Environ. Health Perspect. 109: 437-42 51. Miettinen OS, Rossiter CE. 1990. Man-made mineral fibers and lung cancer. Epidemiologic evidence regarding the causal hypothesis. Scand. J. Work Environ. Health 16: 221—31 52. National Research Council. 1994. Science and judgment in risk assessment. Washington, DC: National Academy Press 53. National Research Council. 2000. Scientific frontiers in developmental toxicology and risk assessment. Washington, DC: National Academy Press 54. Neutra RR, Delpizzo V. 2002. Transparent Democratic Foresight Strategies in the California EMF Program. Public Health Rep. 117: 553—63 55. Ong EK, Glantz SA. 2001. Constructing "sound science" and "good epidemiology": tobacco, lawyers, and public relations firms. Am. J. Public Health 91: 1749—57 56. O’Riordan T, Cameron J. 1994. Interpreting the precautionary principle. London: Cameron May Implications of precaution (Grandjean) 57. 33 Ozonoff D. 1999. The Precautionary Principle as a Screening Device. In:Protecting public health and the environment: Implementing the precautionary principle, ed C Raffensperger, J Tickner, pp. 100–5. Washington: Island Press 58. Ricci PF, Rice D, Ziagos J, Cox LA Jr. 2003. Precaution, uncertainty and causation in environmental decisions. Environ. Int. 29: 1—19 59. Roe D, Pease W, Florini K, Silbergeld E. 1997. Toxic Ignorance: The Continuing Absence of Basic Health Testing for Top-Selling Chemicals in the United States. New York, NY: Environmental Defense Fund. URL: www.environmentaldefense.org/documents/243_toxicignorance.pdf (accessed 10 June, 2003) 60. de Rosnay J. 1979. The macroscope. A new world scientific system. New York: Harper & Row 61. Sand PH. 2000. The precautionary principle: A European perspective. Hum. Ecol. Risk Assessm. 6: 445—58 62. Sandin P. 1999. Dimensions of the precautionary principle. Hum. Ecol. Risk Assessm. 5: 889—907 63. Schwartz S, Carpenter KM. 1999. The right answer for the wrong question: consequences of type III error for public health research. Am. J. Public Health 89: 1175—80 64. Sexton K, Beck BD, Bingham E, Brain JD, DeMarini DM, et al. 1995. Chemical mixtures from a public health perspective: the importance of research for informed decision making. Toxicology 105: 429—41 65. Smith KR, Corvalan CF, Kjellstrom T. 1999. How much global ill health is attributable to environmental factors? Epidemiology 10: 573—84 66. Stirling A, Gee D. 2002. Science, precaution, and practice. Public Health Rep. 117: 521— 33 67. Taubes G. 1995. Epidemiology faces its limits. Science 269: 164—9 Implications of precaution (Grandjean) 68. 34 Tickner J. 2003. Precautionary assessment: A framework for integrating science, uncertainty, and preventive public policy. In Precaution, environmental science, and preventive public policy, ed J Tickner, pp. 106–22. Washington, DC: Island Press 69. Tudge C. 2003. Where to draw the line. New Scientist 178: 23 70. United Nations Conference on Environment and Development. 1992. Rio declaration on environment and development. Rio de Janeiro, URL: http://www.unep.org/Documents/Default.asp?DocumentID=78&ArticleID=1163 (accessed, 27 June, 2003) 71. U.S. Environmental Protection Agency. 1998. Chemical Hazard Data Availability Study, April 1998. Office of Pollution Prevention and Toxics. URL: http://www.epa.gov/opptintr/chemtest/hazchem.pdf (accessed, 27 June, 2003) 72. Wiener JB, Rogers MD. 2002. Comparing precaution in the United States and Europe. J. Risk Res. 5: 317—349 73. Wingspread statement on the precautionary principle. 1999. In Protecting public health and the environment: Implementing the precautionary principle, ed C Raffensperger, J Tickner, pp. 353–5. Washington, DC: Island Press 74. World Health Organization. 2002. Precautionary policies and health protection: principles and applications. Report on a WHO Workshop, Rome, Italy, 28–29 May 2001 (EUR/02/5027100). Copenhagen: WHO regional Office for Europe. URL: http://www.euro.who.int/document/e75313.pdf (accessed, 3 July 2003) Implications of precaution (Grandjean) 35 Figure legends Fig. 1. Risk assessment is based on exposure assessment and dose-response relationships. Each parameter and model is associated with some uncertainty, but can be included in statistical models. In this way, risk assessment can approach the types of analysis that would be appropriate for precautionary analysis. Redrawn from Covello & Merkhofer (18). Fig. 2. While risk assessment may address hazards at all levels of severity, when sufficient evidence is available, the precautionary principle fills in the empty space where uncertainty prevails, although the hazard may be serious. Fig. 3. When an environmental health issue is poorly known, it may first become the object of precautionary analysis, and the information will gradually increase as stakeholders become involved and precautionary actions are instigated, including subsequent monitoring and research. These efforts may eventually provide the basis for a formal risk assessment. Implications of precaution (Grandjean) 36 Table 1. Lessons learned from early warnings about environmental hazards and the delayed responses. From European Environment Agency (24). 1. Acknowledge and respond to ignorance, as well as uncertainty and risk, in technology appraisal and public policymaking. 2. Provide adequate long-term environmental and health monitoring and research into early warnings. 3. Identify and work to reduce “blind spots” and gaps in scientific knowledge. 4. Identify and reduce interdisciplinary obstacles to learning. 5. Ensure that real world conditions are adequately accounted for in regulatory appraisal. 6. Systematically scrutinize the claimed justifications and benefits alongside the potential risks. 7. Evaluate a range of alternative options for meeting needs alongside the option under appraisal, and promote more robust, diverse and adaptable technologies so as to minimize the costs of surprises and maximize the benefits of innovation. 8. Ensure use of “lay” and local knowledge, as well as relevant specialist expertise in the appraisal. 9. Take full account of the assumptions and values of different social groups. 10. Maintain the regulatory independence of interested parties while retaining an inclusive approach to information and opinion gathering. 11. Identify and reduce institutional obstacles to learning and action. 12. Avoid “paralysis by analysis” by acting to reduce potential harm when there are reasonable grounds for concern. Implications of precaution (Grandjean) 37 Table 2. Elements of the precautionary principle, according to the European Commission (17,26). Proportionality "Measures...must not be disproportionate to the desired level of protection and must not aim at zero risk" Nondiscrimination "comparable situations should not be treated differently and... different situations should not be treated in the same way, unless there are objective grounds for doing so." Consistency "measures...should be comparable in nature and scope with measures already taken in equivalent areas in which all the scientific data are available." Examination of the "This examination should include an economic cost/benefit analysis benefits and costs of when this is appropriate and feasible. However, other analysis action or lack of action methods...may also be relevant" Examination of scientific "The measures must be of a provisional nature pending the developments availability of more reliable scientific data"... "scientific research shall be continued with a view to obtaining more complete data." Implications of precaution (Grandjean) 38 Table 3. Two approaches to environmental health represented by the reductionist view of traditional risk assessment and the systemic approach associated with the precautionary principle. Revised from de Rosnay (60) and Holling (38). Attribute Philosophy Causation Analytic Systemic Risk assessment Precautionary principle Narrow and targeted Broad and exploratory Disproof by experiment Multiple lines of converging evidence Parsimony the rule Requisite simplicity the goal Single and separable Multiple, interactions, only partially separable Hypotheses Incertitude Single and null hypotheses Multiple, competing hypotheses Rejection of false Separation among competingq hypotheses hypotheses Eliminate uncertainty Incorporate and learn from incertitude and aim at high precision Models Discipline-oriented Multidisciplinary Precise and validated, used to Imprecise and tentative, developed account for observations in response to observations Statistics Concern with Type I error Concern with Type II error Evaluation goal Peer assessment to reach Peer assessment and judgment to ultimate unanimous agreement facilitate consensus-building The danger Exactly right answer for Exactly right question but useless the wrong question answer Implications of precaution (Grandjean) 39 Table 4. Potential bias in environmental research using standard methodological approaches.* Type of scientific study Experimental study Observational studies Both Methodological feature Main direction of error: High doses Limited range of doses Low genetic variability Exposure to single substances only Chronic rather than fetal-lifetime exposure Standard effect measures Social confounders Concomitant exposures Inappropriate controls Exposure misclassification Inadequate follow-up Lost cases Ignoring complexity in data analysis Publication bias toward positive findings Post hoc hypothesis Scientific and social pressure to avoid false alarm Low statistical power (e.g., small studies) Use of 5 % probability level to minimize chances of false positives Use of 20% probability level to minimize chances of false negatives False positive False negatives False negative False negative False negative False negative False positive False positive False positive/negative False negative False negative False negative False positive/negative False positive False positive False negative False negative False negative False negative *Based on discussions at the Collegium Ramazzini Conference on The Precautionary Principle: Implications for Research and Prevention, Bologna, 23-24 October, 2002; revised from Gee (28).