Running Head: DECISION JUSTIFIABILITY AND ANTICIPATED REGRET Decision Justifiability and Anticipated Regret Jochen Reb Terry Connolly University of Arizona April 18, 2005 Please address correspondence to: Jochen Reb Eller College of Management University of Arizona P.O. Box 210108 Tucson, AZ 85721 (520) 621-1911 (520) 621-4171 (fax) jmreb@email.arizona.edu Acknowledgment: This work was supported in part by Grant # F496200031037 from the Air Force Office of Scientific Research. Decision Justifiability and Regret ABSTRACT We studied the role of decision justifiability in determining the intensity of anticipated regret (cf. Connolly & Zeelenberg, 2002). In three experiments we examined whether perceived justifiability can account for the effects of normality, a factor previously thought to affect anticipated regret through ease of counterfactual mutability (cf. Kahneman & Miller, 1986), and decision process quality, a previously unstudied factor. Study 1 found that perceived justifiability could account for the effects on anticipated regret of action (whether the decision was to act or not) and social normality (whether or not the decision matched those of friends and acquaintances). Study 2 showed that following a careful decision process reduced anticipated regret over a bad outcome and that perceived justifiability mediated this effect. Study 3 replicated the effect of decision process quality on anticipated regret through perceived justifiability in the presence of both action and social normality information. KEYWORDS: Decision Making; Decision Process Quality; Justifiability; Anticipated Regret 2 Decision Justifiability and Regret DECISION JUSTIFIABILITY AND ANTICIPATED REGRET Important general theories of human choice and behavior, such as utility theory or the theory of planned behavior, have typically conceptualized people’s decisions as the result of cognitions and calculations, such as probability and value estimates, at the expense of emotions. While philosophers have long speculated about the role of emotions in decision making -- and often come to the conclusion that emotions interfere with rational choice -- careful investigation of the effects of emotions on decision and of decisions on emotions is quite recent. A variety of emotions has been examined in this context, and decision-related regret has attracted particular attention (e.g., Savage, 1951; Bell, 1982; Landman, 1993). Numerous studies have shown that anticipated regret affects choice. Specifically, individuals often choose the option that reduces expected regret. Such regret avoidance has been found in numerous domains including health decisions (e.g., Connolly & Reb, 2003; Wroe, Turner, & Salkovskis, 2004), sexual behavior (Richard, van der Pligt, & de Vries, 1996), consumer behavior (Simonson, 1992), and negotiation (Larrick & Boles, 1995). For example, in a study conducted in New Zealand, Wroe et al. asked women in the third trimester of their pregnancy to predict (a) the regret they would experience if they did not immunize their child against six major diseases and the child experienced the disease; and (b) the regret they would experience if they did immunize their child and it experienced serious immunization side-effects. They found that these anticipated regret ratings strongly predicted both intention to vaccinate and actual vaccination at the time the babies were 8-10 weeks old. Given the role that anticipated regret plays in predicting choices we need to understand better why decision makers anticipate more regret for some options than for others. The present paper examines one potentially important determinant of the intensity of anticipated regret: the 3 Decision Justifiability and Regret justifiability of the decision. According to decision justification theory regret after a bad outcome is reduced if the decision maker considers the decision to have been justifiable (Connolly & Zeelenberg, 2002; see also Connolly & Reb, in press). The theory further predicts that decision makers will, at the predecisional stage, anticipate less regret for a decision to the extent that they consider the decision justifiable. While many past studies are consistent with this hypothesis (for a review see Connolly & Zeelenberg, 2002), hardly any research has explicitly been designed to examine the relation between anticipated regret and perceived justifiability. We examine here two important aspects of the role of decision justifiability in determining anticipated regret. First, we examine whether perceived justifiability can account for the previously established effect of normality on regret (Kahneman & Miller, 1986). Second, we predict that decision makers anticipate lower regret for a careful decision process and that is because they perceive such a process as more justifiable. Determinants of Anticipated Regret Intensity Previous research has identified three major factors that affect the intensity of experienced regret, anticipated regret, or both. We focus here on anticipated regret though the common finding (see Zeelenberg, 1996) is that anticipated and experienced regret match each other relatively closely and are affected by the same factors (though perhaps not with equal intensity, cf. Gilbert, Morewedge, Risen, & Wilson, 2004). Relative Outcome Severity First, the intensity of anticipated (and experienced) regret is thought to be influenced by relative outcome severity. Regret theory (Bell, 1982; Loomes & Sugden, 1982) argues that anticipated (and experienced) regret is a function of how bad (severe) the outcome of the option chosen is relative to some comparison standard, typically the outcome that would have been 4 Decision Justifiability and Regret received had one chosen a different option. The more severe the expected outcome for an option relative to a foregone outcome, the higher the anticipated regret (cf. Savage, 1951; Mellers, Schwartz, & Ritov, 1999). The idea makes immediate intuitive sense: Consider your anticipated regret for missing out on $100 versus $1 million. Clearly, the latter would be higher because of the higher relative outcome severity. Mutability Second, the intensity of experienced and, therefore, anticipated regret is thought to affected by mutability (Kahneman & Miller, 1986). In a landmark paper, Kahneman and Tversky (1982) showed that regret intensity depends on whether the option chosen involves action or inaction. Holding outcome severity constant, they found in a scenario study that people thought an investor who switched stocks (and lost money) would experience more regret than an investor who did not switch stocks (and lost the same amount of money), the so-called action effect. Kahneman and Tversky argued that it is easier to counterfactually imagine that one had not switched stocks than it is that one had switched stocks. Further, they argued that the ease of availability of such upward counterfactual thoughts leads to more intense regret. (For an introduction to the counterfactual thinking literature see, e.g., Roese, 1997; Roese & Olsen, 1995.) Findings such as this led to the development of norm theory (Kahneman & Miller, 1986), which argues that a bad decision outcome leads to more regret (more generally, emotional amplification) when the decision was abnormal, because abnormality stimulates counterfactual thoughts of what could have been. The counterfactual “I could have done the usual thing” comes immediately to mind. Consistent with the mutability account of regret intensity, regret has been found to be judged more intense after less normal behaviors such as actions, as compared to inactions 5 Decision Justifiability and Regret (Landman, 1987), and personally unusual behaviors as compared to personally normal behaviors (taking a different driving route to work than usual: Kahneman & Miller, 1986; making a decision inconsistent with one’s personality: Seta, McElroy, & Seta, 2001). However, some subsequent research showed results inconsistent with the mutability account. For example, N’gbala and Branscombe (1997) found an action effect only in a within-subjects design, not in a between-subjects design. They argued plausibly that norm theory (Kahneman & Miller, 1986) would have predicted just the opposite: a stronger effect in the between-subjects design. In the within-subjects case, the argument that counterfactuals are more easily available following abnormal decisions is moot because both action (abnormal) and inaction (normal) alternatives are explicitly given to the participants as part of the experimental materials. Decision Justifiability Findings such as these together with theoretical arguments (e.g., Janis & Mann, 1977; Sugden, 1985) have led to the identification of a third potential influence on the intensity of anticipated regret: the justifiability of the decision (Connolly & Zeelenberg, 2002; Connolly & Reb, in press). The presumed role of justifiability is central to decision justification theory (Connolly & Zeelenberg, 2002). According to this theory, there are two major components of regret: regret associated with the outcome being (comparatively) poor, and regret associated with the decision itself or the process that led up to it being poor. Self-blame is an essential ingredient of this second component of regret: the less justifiable the decision is perceived to be, the more intense will be regret after a bad outcome. Connolly and Zeelenberg (2002) have shown that differences in justifiability perceptions can – post hoc – account for a variety of past findings. For example, Zeelenberg, van den Bos, van Dijk, and Pieters (2001) showed that a soccer coach who acts and changes the team after 6 Decision Justifiability and Regret winning in the past is thought to experience more regret following a subsequent loss than a coach who does not act (does not change the team). However, the same choice is thought to lead to less intense regret when it takes place after a previous loss. The finding that a win-stay lose-switch strategy can protect from regret is clearly consistent with the argument that making a more justifiable decision leads to less regret (It may well, of course, be consistent also with a normality argument). Crawford, McConnell, Lewis, and Sherman (2002) found that experimental participants following the (bad) advice of an unknown stranger as to which of two football teams to bet on experienced more intense regret when their team lost than did those who ignored the advice. Apparently accepting advice from strangers, though plausible at the time, appeared unjustified (and thus blame-worthy) in retrospect. In a consumer preference study (Simonson, 1992), participants primed to think about regret chose the safer option (a SONY, a highly reputed, name-brand product) over the riskier option (a cheaper, no-name product) more often than did participants in a control condition. The SONY reputation, even if costly, appears to justify the choice and inoculate against self-blame. In a student-oriented version of the twoinvestors problem, Connolly, Ordóñez, & Coughlan (1997) showed that students displaced by computer reassignment from a good course section into a poorer one were expected to feel significant regret, though not as much as other students who brought this misfortune on themselves. The first group appears to suffer only outcome regret; the second group experiences self-blame regret as well. In addition to these post-hoc accounts of earlier findings in terms of decision justification theory at least one study explicitly tested if the intensity of regret depends on whether the decision makers made a choice based on good or bad reasons. In this study Inman and Zeelenberg (2002), following closely the win-stay lose-change idea (Zeelenberg et al., 2001), 7 Decision Justifiability and Regret presented participants with scenarios in which consumers either re-purchased a product or service or switched after previous positive or negative experience with the product or service. Consistent with decision justification theory and the earlier findings of Zeelenberg et al. (2001) respondents judged that a re-purchasing a product after past bad experience with it led to more regret than switching to another product. Similarly, switching to another product from a product after past good experience with it also led to more regret than re-purchasing the same product. In a study of related anticipated emotions such as guilt and sadness, Baron (1992) found a similar influence of reasons. Specifically, respondents who first rated their anticipated emotions in response to a scenario involving two options and were then presented with a good argument favoring one option over another tended to change their anticipated emotions in the direction favored by the argument. While these findings and post-hoc accounts are suggestive, more research is needed that explicitly tests the justifiability account and decision justification theory. Such research should (1) examine whether the effects of variables previously found to influence the intensity of anticipated regret can be accounted for by justifiability perceptions; and (2) identify new decision-related variables that could be expected to affect decision justifiability and test whether these variables also affect anticipated regret. The first study is designed to address the former issue. STUDY 1: NORMALITY, JUSTIFIABILITY, AND ANTICIPATED REGRET As we have shown past research found that the normality of a choice can affect regret: abnormal choices and actions appear to lead to more intense anticipated regret than do normal ones (Kahneman & Miller, 1986; Kahneman & Tversky, 1982). This has been explained in norm 8 Decision Justifiability and Regret theory terms (Kahneman & Miller, 1986) as due to the easier mutability of abnormal choices and behaviors leading to easier availability of counterfactuals and, thus, more intense regret. Study 1 examines an alternative explanation of the effect of normality on regret intensity. This explanation proposes that abnormal choices lead to more intense regret when they are perceived as less justifiable. In other words, we argue that justifiability perceptions mediate any effects on anticipated regret of factors that manipulate normality. In the present research we use a decision context in which anticipated regret has been found to predict real and important decisions and that has been the topic of past research: a parent’s decision whether or not to vaccinate her or his child. In the study of Wroe et al. (2004) described above, the authors compared different potential predictors of actual immunization decisions and found that “anticipated regret … was the strongest predictor of likelihood of immunizing the child” (p. 38), predicting 57% of the variance (demographic variables, in contrast, predicted only 1% of the variance). They also reported that most parents decided to vaccinate their children. The vaccination decision has also been the context of a number of studies examining a possible omission bias, a tendency to prefer inaction over action, in health-related decisions, a bias possibly resulting from increased anticipated regret for action (e.g., Ritov & Baron, 1990; Ritov & Baron, 1995). We are not concerned here with the debate about the existence of this bias (the interested reader can refer to the paper cited above as well as Connolly & Reb, 2003; Baron & Ritov, 2004). We use this context because anticipated regret has been shown to be a highly significant predictor of actual choices in this context and because the context allowed us to construct different (and, to us, plausible) versions of the scenario in which the parent behaves 9 Decision Justifiability and Regret either normally or abnormally, using either a careful or a careless decision process, and decides either to take action or not. We implemented two normality manipulations. First, we varied whether the decision maker decides to do what her friends and family do (social normality). Second, we manipulated whether the decision maker decides to vaccinate or not (action). Past research suggests that in this context the active option (i.e., vaccinating) is very common and strongly preferred, at least in the US population (Connolly & Reb, 2003). Thus, if anything, we expect a reversal of the action effect such that action will be regretted less than inaction if bad outcomes eventuate. As part of our research strategy, we manipulated social normality both within- and between-subjects. We expected that the respondents’ perceptions of the justifiability of making a given choice will be amplified when respondents are given the opportunity to contrast it with another decision. Whether a decision conforms to what one’s friends and family do (“socially normal”) may not be seen as more justifiable (and, therefore, leading to less anticipated regret) when evaluated in isolation. However, when explicitly contrasted with a socially abnormal decision leading to the same outcome, decision makers may perceive the socially normal choice as more justifiable (and, therefore, less regrettable). We manipulated action only betweensubjects because, based on previous findings showing the strong preference and general acceptance of vaccination as the normal choice in the population (Connolly & Reb, 2003; Wroe et al., 2004) we expected vaccinating (i.e., acting) to provide a strong enough justification to show in a between-subjects manipulation. Importantly, we predicted that the effects of action and social normality on anticipated regret would only occur when the manipulations also affect justifiability perceptions in a pattern consistent with the regret effects (i.e., lower justifiability associated with higher anticipated 10 Decision Justifiability and Regret regret). In the absence of experimental effects on justifiability perceptions, we did not expect any experimental effects on anticipated regret. Further, we expected that perceived justifiability would predict anticipated regret. Method Design and Procedure Participants read a scenario in which two protagonists each face the decision whether or not to vaccinate their small child. Both protagonists decide either to act or not. One chooses to do what most of her family and friends did when faced with a similar decision, the other chooses the opposite. The decision is always followed by the same bad outcome. Thus, the experiment manipulated two factors each with 2 levels: action (vaccinate vs. don’t vaccinate) and social normality (socially normal decision vs. socially abnormal decision). Action was manipulated between-subjects only, whereas social normality was manipulated both between-subjects and within-subjects, as described below. Participants read on the first page of the experimental materials a scenario involving two mothers who each had to decide whether or not to vaccinate her child against a flu. The scenario explained that the risk of an unvaccinated child getting the flu was about equal to the risk of a vaccinated child getting equally serious vaccine side-effects. On the next page, respondents read about the decision of the first mother, in which action and social normality information was manipulated. In all conditions, the outcome of this decision was equally bad: the child “was very sick and unhappy for almost three weeks”, as a result either of the flu or of vaccine side-effects. After reading about the decision and the outcome, participants rated how much regret they would feel if they were in the protagonist’s place. 11 Decision Justifiability and Regret On the next page, the decision of the second mother was described. She differed from the first only in that the social normality of her choice was opposite that of the first mother; action or inaction stayed the same. Thus, social normality was manipulated within-subjects at this point. Order was counterbalanced so that for about half the participants the first mother was described as having made the socially normal decision, while for the other participants she made the socially abnormal decision. The outcomes of both decisions were equally bad. Participants again rated the intensity of regret they would feel. On the next and final page, respondents rated several statements concerning the normality and justifiability of the decisions, as well as what they would have done in the protagonists’ situation. To summarize, action was manipulated between-subjects. The effect of social normality could be analyzed both between-subjects, using only the responses to the first decision and outcome (on the second page of the materials) and within-subjects, using the responses to the first and second decisions and outcomes (pages two and three of the materials). Participants Sixty-six undergraduate students at a large southwestern university participated for extra course credit. They took about ten minutes to complete the questionnaire. (Ten additional respondents were excluded for giving severely inconsistent responses, suggesting that they did not take the task seriously or had not understood the instructions). Materials and Measures Scenario. The first page contained the following scenario adapted from one used by Connolly and Reb (2003): In Arizona there have been several outbreaks of a certain kind of flu, which can cause severe illness in children under three. Most children just get normal flu symptoms 12 Decision Justifiability and Regret but, in a small number of cases, the children get very sick with high fevers, a lot of pain, and generally feel horrible for several weeks. A vaccine for this kind of flu has been developed and tested. The vaccine eliminates any possibility of the child getting the flu. The vaccine, however, can sometimes cause side-effects that are very similar to the severe flu symptoms: high fever, pain, feeling horrible for several weeks. Fortunately, these unpleasant effects are rare. In fact, the risk of a vaccinated child getting the unpleasant side-effects is about as low as the chance of a non-vaccinated child getting severe flu symptoms. Both Cindy and Linda are married and each of them has a one-year old child. Each of them has to decide whether or not to vaccinate the child against this flu. The second and third pages each started with a description of one of the mothers’ decision and its outcome, giving information on the experimental factors. It read (manipulations in parentheses): [Cindy decides [not] to vaccinate her child, [like most of the people she knows / although most of the people she knows decide [not] to vaccinate their children]. Unfortunately, her child [gets a severe case of the flu / experiences the severe side effects of the vaccine] and is very sick and unhappy for almost three weeks. Emotion ratings. After reading about the decision and its outcome, respondents were asked to imagine themselves in the protagonist’s situation and to indicate how they would feel. Regret was measured on an 11-point scale (0: “I wouldn’t experience this at all”; 10: “I would experience this a lot”). The regret measure was embedded in a list of eleven other decisionrelated emotions (taken from Reisenzein and Hofmann, 1993) in order to avoid demand effects. 13 Decision Justifiability and Regret After completing these scales, respondents turned the page, read about the second protagonist, and completed the second set of emotion measures. Decision ratings. After completing the emotion ratings for both scenarios, participants turned to the last page where they rated several items concerning the decisions of the two protagonists as well as their own vaccination preferences on 5-point Likert-scales (anchored at “strongly agree” and “strongly disagree”, coded as +2 and –2, respectively). Decision ratings were put on a separate page to reduce possible demand effects. A pair of items intended as manipulation checks asked about the social normality of the decision of the two protagonists (“[Linda / Cindy] chose the same alternative as most people she knows”). A second pair measured perceptions of decision justifiability (“[Linda/Cindy] made a good choice”). Results Manipulation Check The manipulation of social normality was successful. A between-subjects ANOVA on social normality ratings found the expected main effect of social normality (socially normal M = 1.45, socially abnormal M = -1.29, F(1, 62) = 75.14, p < .001). The same main effect was also revealed in a repeated-measures ANOVA (socially normal M = 1.41, socially abnormal M = 1.39, F(1, 62) = 163.19, p < .001). No other effects (action, order, and interactions) in the between-subjects and repeated-measures ANOVAs were significant, all ps > .1. Anticipated Regret To examine whether any of the experimental manipulations affected anticipated regret we first analyzed only the responses to the first decision with a between-subjects ANOVA including action and social normality as between-subjects factors. We found a significant main effect for action, F(1, 62) = 6.76, p < .05. Vaccination was considered less regrettable (M = 6.41, SD = 14 Decision Justifiability and Regret 3.43) than non-vaccination (M = 8.18, SD = 1.75). Whether the decision was socially normal (M = 7.42, SD = 2.41) or socially abnormal (M = 7.23, SD = 3.17) had no significant effect on anticipated regret intensity, F(1, 62) = .09, ns. The interaction was also non-significant, F(1, 62) = .19, ns. We next conducted a repeated-measures ANOVA on the full data set (i.e., responses to the decisions of both protagonists) with social normality as a within-, and action and order as a between-subjects factors. The main effect for action remained significant in the same direction, F(1, 61) = 7.97, p < .01 (action M = 6.19, inaction M = 8.15). Social normality now also affected regret intensity, F(1, 61) = 5.76, p < .05. A socially normal choice was considered less regrettable (M = 6.97) than a socially abnormal choice (M = 7.46). The effect of social normality became significant only when the manipulation was highlighted in a within-subjects design. The main effect for order and all interactions were non-significant, all ps > .1. Perceived Decision Justifiability We examined the relation between respondents’ judgments of the justifiability of the decision and their anticipated regret in several ways. First, analyzing only the responses to the first decision, we found in a linear regression analysis that perceived justifiability predicted anticipated regret, β = -.38, t(64) = 3.30, p < .01. The more a decision was perceived as justifiable, the less regrettable it was anticipated to be in the event of a bad outcome. Social normality perceptions, on the other hand, did not significantly predict anticipated regret, β = -.06, t(64) = .49, ns. The same significance test results were obtained in analyses of the whole data set (i.e., responses to both decisions). Next, we tested whether the experimental manipulations that affected anticipated regret also affected perceived justifiability. A between-subjects ANOVA with social normality and 15 Decision Justifiability and Regret action as between-subjects factors showed a significant main effect for action such that a decision to vaccinate was perceived as more justifiable (M = .47, SD = 1.16) than a decision not to vaccinate (M = -.21, SD = 1.15), F(1, 62) = 6.22, p < .05. In addition, ANOVA revealed a significant main effect for social normality, F(1, 62) = 6.29, p < .05. A decision to do what most of the people one knows do was considered more justifiable (M = .48, SD = 1.15) than a socially abnormal decision (M = -.20, SD = 1.16). The interaction with action was non-significant, p > .1. The same results were obtained in a repeated-measures ANOVA with social normality as within-subjects factor, and action and order as between-subjects factors: for action, F(1, 6) = 8.92, p < .01 (action M = .51, inaction M = -.25); for social normality, F(1, 62) = 4.63, p < .05 (socially normal M = .23, socially abnormal M = .02). The interaction between action and social normality was non-significant, p > .1. In addition, the main effect for order was marginally significant, F(1, 62) = 3.96, p = .09, such that ratings were somewhat higher when the socially normal decisoin was rated first (M = .35) than when the abnormal decision was rated first (M = .09). However, none of the interactions involving order were significant, all ps > .1. Because perceived justifiability predicted anticipated regret and was affected by the same experimental manipulations as anticipated regret it is possible that perceived justifiability acted as a mediator for the effects on regret. We tested whether the effect of action (independent variable) on anticipated regret (dependent variable) in the between-subjects analysis was mediated through perceived justifiability (presumed mediator). In addition to demonstrating a significant relation between the independent variable and the dependent variable, the independent variable and the presumed mediator, and the presumed mediator and the dependent variable as we have done already, one needs to test whether inclusion of the mediator reduces the impact of the independent variable on the dependent variable (cf. Baron & Kenny, 1986). When 16 Decision Justifiability and Regret we regressed anticipated regret on both action and perceived justifiability, the effect of action remained significant (β = .23, t(64) = 1.92, p < .05, one-tailed), and perceived justifiability remained a significant predictor (β = -.32, t(64) = 2.68, p < .01). A test for mediation according to Sobel (1982) was significant (z = 1.82, p < .05, one-tailed). Thus, decision justifiability perceptions partially mediated the effect of action on anticipated regret intensity. Discussion Study 1 was intended to examine the role of perceived justifiability in the effect of normality of choice on anticipated regret. We manipulated whether a mother decides to vaccinate her child or not (action, manipulated between-subjects) and whether she decides to do what most of the people she knows do (social normality, manipulated both between- and within-subjects). We measured both anticipated regret and perceived justifiability. We found that action affected anticipated regret in both between- and within-subjects analyses. Social normality, however, affected anticipated regret only when manipulated within-subjects. The results showed the hypothesized role of justifiability in explaining regret effects. First, perceived justifiability predicted anticipated regret. The more a decision was perceived as justifiable, the less regrettable it was considered in the event of a bad outcome. Second, a mediation analysis found that perceived justifiability mediated the effect of action on anticipated regret in the between-subject analysis. Perceived justifiability was rated at the end of the study after both decisions were presented, introducing a potential confound on the measure through a contrast effect of the within-subjects manipulation. However, action was held constant for each respondent so post hoc contrast effects are irrelevant. It is difficult to see how the within-subjects manipulation of social normality could have been confounded with the effect of action on 17 Decision Justifiability and Regret perceived justifiability. Thus, we are confident that the results of the mediation analysis were not affected in this case by the within-subjects manipulation of social normality. Third, highlighting the difference in social normality between the two protagonists through a within-subjects manipulation led to a significant effect on anticipated regret that was not obtained for the between-subjects manipulation. We argue that this is because withinsubjects, justifiability issues were made salient by direct comparison of normal and abnormal behavior. Without this additional salience the (between-subjects) normality manipulation may have been too weak to affect regret. As N’gbala & Branscombe (1997) argue, the mutability hypothesis predicts a stronger effect of normality in the between-subjects design because it rests on the argument that abnormal behaviors evoke counterfactuals more easily. However, in a within-subjects design, even the counterfactual for normal behavior is essentially obvious because both decision alternatives (normal and abnormal) are described to the respondent. This would imply that the normality effect would be found in the between-subjects rather than the within-subjects design, the opposite of our finding. Justifiability appears to have trumped mutability in determining regret in this context. Regression analysis also showed that social normality perceptions did not predict anticipated regret, further weakening the case that normality as such determines anticipated regret. Study 1 examined the effects of factors associated with the normality of a decision that have been previously shown to affect (anticipated) regret. While in the past effects of normality have been explained through the ease of counterfactual generation (Kahneman & Miller, 1986) we predicted that differences in perceived justifiability could account for the effects of action and social normality. The results of Study 1 support this interpretation. However, to further probe the importance of justifiability in the anticipation of regret it is important to identify new variables 18 Decision Justifiability and Regret that can be expected to affect perceived justifiability, and thus anticipated regret, in addition to reexamining previously studied variables such as normality. Study 2 does this by investigating the effect of decision process quality on anticipated regret and perceived justifiability. STUDY 2: DECISION PROCESS QUALITY AND REGRET Existing studies of justification and anticipated regret have examined justifications that are highly context-specific: previous experience with a particular product (Inman & Zeelenberg, 2002), the reputation enjoyed by a specific brand (Simonson, 1992), or an individual’s entrepreneurial personality (Seta et al., 2001). Study what examined the effect of another consideration, social conformity, that might serve as a regret-reducing justification in a variety of situations, though perhaps not a very compelling one. In the present experiment we examine a justification that is potentially powerful over a wide range of choices: the care and thoroughness of the decision process itself. Janis and Mann (1977) suggest that the anticipation of regret can motivate what they call a “vigilant decision process”. Our question here is whether the use of such a process does, in fact, lead to reduced expectations of decision-related regret. We study the effect of decision process quality on anticipated regret for the same vaccination scenario used before. The protagonist in the scenario was described either as following a careful decision process (collecting a lot of relevant information, surveying all available options and carefully considering the advantages and disadvantages of each) or a careless decision process (doing none of these). We also manipulated action such that one group read about a decision to vaccinate, the other group about a decision not to vaccinate. Although we were mainly interested in the decision process quality main effect, this additional manipulation allowed us to examine possible interactions between the two variables (that is, to 19 Decision Justifiability and Regret see whether the effect of decision process quality on anticipated regret depended on whether the decision was to vaccinate or not to vaccinate). Method Design and Procedure The design and procedure were identical to Study 1 except that decision process quality was manipulated instead of social normality. As with the manipulation of social normality in Study 1, decision process quality was manipulated both within-subjects and between-subjects. In contrast to Study 1, however, we expected decision process quality to be a strong enough manipulation of justifiability to affect anticipated regret even in both within- and betweensubjects designs. This prediction was borne out in the data and we will therefore focus largely on the between-subjects analyses and only briefly describe the parallel within-subjects results. These between-subjects analyses use only the responses to the first choice, which was either made using a careful or a careless decision process. As in Study 1, action was manipulated fully between-subjects, so that a respondent read either about two protagonists who both decided to vaccinate or two who decided not to vaccinate. Participants 148 students at a large southwestern university participated for extra-credit and took about 10 minutes to fill out the questionnaire. Materials and Measures The scenario was slightly changed from the previous one. Specifically, at the beginning of the scenario, second sentence, where it read “in a small number of cases” in Study 1, the scenario now read, less ambiguously, “in about 1% of cases”. The first page of the scenario also 20 Decision Justifiability and Regret contained the action manipulation and information about the decision outcome, information presented on the following page in Study 1. It ended as follows. … Both Cindy and Linda are married and each has a one-year old child. Both mothers [decide to / decide not to] vaccinate their child. Unfortunately, both children did [experience the severe side effects of the vaccine / get a severe case of the flu] and were very sick and unhappy for almost three weeks. Participants were then presented with two emotion rating sheets, one of which was headed by a description of a careful decision process, the other of a careless decision process.1 The careful decision process was described as: [Protagonist] talked to several doctors, read medical journals, consulted with family and friends, and thought seriously about what to do. The careless decision process stated: [Protagonist] did not collect any information, did not talk with friends or doctors before she made the decision, and didn’t think very seriously about the decision. Anticipated regret was measured on the same 11-point (0-10) scale as in Study 1. Perceived justifiability was measured through a rating of anticipated self-blame made on similar scale, reverse-coded such that higher values indicate higher perceived justifiability. Measures of anticipated regret and perceived justifiability of the first decision were taken immediately after respondents read the first part of the scenario, before they read about the second decision. The between-subjects analyses of perceived justifiability of Decision 1 are thus uncontaminated by contrast effects involving Decision 2. Results Anticipated Regret 21 Decision Justifiability and Regret We conducted an ANOVA on anticipated regret with decision process quality and action as between-subjects factors. This analysis revealed a significant main effect for decision process quality, F(1, 140) = 18.51, p < .001). As expected, anticipated regret was lower when the bad outcome followed a careful decision process (M = 5.64, SD = 3.01) than when it followed a careless decision process. (M = 7.67, SD = 2.57). This effect did not depend on whether the decision was to act or not (interaction F(1, 140) = .14, ns). Also, anticipated regret did not depend on whether the decision was to vaccinate or not, F(1, 140) = .05, ns. The same significance test results emerged from a repeated-measures ANOVA. Decision process quality, the within-subjects factor, again affected anticipated regret, F(1,139) = 62.44, p < .001). The effects of action, order, and the interactions were all non-significant, all ps > .1. Perceived Decision Justifiability Again, we examined the relation between perceived justifiability and anticipated regret in several ways. First, we correlated anticipated regret with perceived justifiability, analyzing only the responses to the first decision. As expected, perceived justifiability strongly predicted anticipated regret, β = -.66, t(146) = 10.64, p < .001. The same significance test result was obtained in an analysis of the full data set (i.e., responses to both decisions). Next, we examined whether the effect of decision process quality on anticipated regret was matched by a consistent effect on perceived justifiability. A between-subjects ANOVA on perceived justifiability showed a significant main effect for decision process quality, F(1, 140) = 14.15, p < .001), with perceived justifiability higher after a careful process (M = 4.08, SD = 2.94) than after a careless process (M = 2.33, SD = 2.60). The effect of action and the interaction effect were non-significant, both p > .1. The same main effect for decision process quality emerged from a repeated-measures ANOVA, F(1, 140) = 80.16, p < .01. In addition, decision process 22 Decision Justifiability and Regret quality interacted significantly with order, F(1, 140) = 19.75, p < .001. Analysis of means showed that the effect of decision process quality was stronger when the careless protagonist was presented first (M = 4.37 vs. M = 7.67) than when the careful protagonist was presented first (M = 5.92 vs. M = 7.07). No other main or interaction effects were significant, all ps > .1. Finally, we conducted a mediation analysis of the between-subjects effect of decision process quality on anticipated regret through perceived justifiability (cf. Baron & Kenny, 1986). We have already shown that decision process quality (independent variable) affected anticipated regret (dependent variable); that decision process quality affected perceived justifiability (presumed mediator); and that perceived justifiability predicted anticipated regret. A regression analysis with decision process quality and perceived justifiability as simultaneous predictors of anticipated regret showed that both decision process quality, β = .16, t(146) = 2.45, p < .05, and perceived justifiability, β = -.61, t(146) = 9.57, p < .001, remained significant. A Sobel (1986) test for mediation was significant, z = 3.56, p < .001. Thus, we find that perceptions of decision justifiability partially mediated the effect of decision process quality on anticipated regret. Discussion Study 2 was designed to test the prediction that decision process quality affects anticipated regret. We argued that if single good reasons for a decision, such as good past performance of a product (Inman & Zeelenberg, 2002) or a soccer team (Zeelenberg et al., 2001), can lead to increased justifiability and lower anticipated regret, a careful decision process should achieve the same result as well or better. As expected, we found that decision process quality affected anticipated regret intensity such that a bad outcome following a careful decision process was expected to lead to less intense regret than a bad outcome following a careless decision process. 23 Decision Justifiability and Regret As expected, perceived justifiability predicted anticipated regret. Moreover, a mediation analysis showed that perceived justifiability mediated the effect of decision process quality on anticipated regret. These results are consistent with decision justification theory and lend support to the idea that decision justifiability has a significant influence on the intensity of anticipated regret. In contrast to Study 1, action did not affect anticipated regret. While we cannot be sure about the cause of this difference in results, one explanation consistent with the justifiability idea is that different justifications are not simply additive in their effects. In the presence of a stronger justification, the influence of weaker justifications may be reduced or eliminated. As we argued earlier, the quality of the decision process is likely a very strong justification of a choice. When a person makes a choice after collecting a lot of information and deliberating carefully, either choice (i.e., vaccinating and not vaccinating) seems justified, and the action effect disappears. However, in the absence of this process information, vaccinating might appear more justified, as it reflects the majority choice. STUDY 3: DECISION PROCESS QUALITY, NORMALITY AND ANTICIPATED REGRET Study 3 combines the variables of Studies 1 and 2 and manipulates decision process quality, action and social normality within one experiment. In this study we wanted to further examine the idea that the effects of different justifications are not necessarily additive. It is possible that that a characteristic that served as a justification loses its influence on anticipated regret when another, stronger justification is added to the picture, as in our tentative explanation (above) for the disappearance of the action-regret link in Study 2. The present study will examine this possible non-additivity in the joint effect of three potential justifications: decision process 24 Decision Justifiability and Regret quality, action, and social normality. One can also imagine other forms of complex interactions and we will examine these on a more exploratory basis. In Study 3 we manipulated decision process quality between- and within-subjects as in Study 2. However, returning to the procedure of Study 1, we measured justifiability perceptions, together with several manipulation check variables, at the end of the experiment. This was done to rule out a potential influence of rating decision justifiability (as well as the manipulation checks) on the subsequent anticipated regret ratings, the primary focus of the study. The cost, in this case, was potential contamination of the justification measure with the contrast effect of a within-subject manipulation of decision process quality. Method Participants read about a protagonist who either vaccinated her child or not, did or did not do what most people she knows do, and engaged in a careful or careless decision process. Thus, we manipulated three factors each with 2 levels: action (vaccinate vs. don’t vaccinate), social normality, and decision process quality. Action and social normality were manipulated betweensubjects. Decision process quality was manipulated both between-subjects and within-subjects as in Study 2. One hundred and fifty-four undergraduate students at a large southwestern university participated for extra course credit. They took about ten minutes to complete the questionnaire. The materials and measures were identical to those for Study 1 except that the scenario contained three manipulations. The relevant paragraph of the scenario read as follows. [Cindy gives the matter a lot of thought, consults several doctors and medical journals, and talks to her family and friends. Finally, she / Linda doesn’t give the matter much thought, nor does she discuss it with her doctor, her family or her friends. She just] 25 Decision Justifiability and Regret decides [not] to vaccinate her child, [like most of the people she knows / although most of the people she knows decide [not] to vaccinate their children]. Unfortunately, her child [gets a severe case of the flu / experiences the severe side effects of the vaccine] and is very sick and unhappy for almost three weeks. The emotion ratings were the same as before and were followed by decision ratings. A pair of items measured decision justifiability: “[Linda / Cindy] made a justifiable decision”. The manipulation checks asked about the carefulness of the decision process (“[Linda / Cindy] followed a careful decision process”) and the social normality of the decision (“[Linda / Cindy] chose the same alternative as most people she knows”). All decision ratings were made on the same 5-point Likert-scale (coded -2 to +2) as in Study 1. Results Manipulation Checks The manipulations of decision process quality and social normality were successful. Between-subjects ANOVA on perceptions of the carefulness of the decision process showed the expected main effect for decision process quality, F(1, 146) = 224.25, p < .001 (careful M = 1.48, careless M = -1.32); no other main effect or interaction was significant, all p > .1. Betweensubjects ANOVA on perceived social normality showed the expected main effect of social normality, F(1, 146) = 116.81, p < .001 (socially normal M = .99, socially abnormal M = -1.24); no other main effect or interaction was significant, all p > .1. These effects were replicated in repeated-measures ANOVAs (using ratings of both protagonists): a main effect of decision process quality on perceived carefulness (careful M = 1.54, careless M = -1.42, F(1, 145) = 404.88, p < .001), and a main effect of social normality on perceived social normality (socially normal M = .99, socially abnormal M = -1.17, F(1, 146) = 26 Decision Justifiability and Regret 172.13, p < .001). In addition, within-subjects analyses showed a main effect of order on perceived carefulness, F(1, 145) = 4.42, p < .05, such that carefulness ratings were lower when the careful process was rated first (M = -.03) rather than second (M = .14). Importantly, order did not significantly interact with any of the other variables, all ps > .1. Also no other main effects and interactions significantly affected perceived decision process carefulness, all ps > .1. For perceived social normality, we found a main effect for order, F(1, 146) = 3.83, p = .05, such that normality ratings were lower when the careful process was rated first (M = -.25) rather than second (M = .07). However, order did not interact with any of the experimental variables, all ps > .1. In addition, there was a main effect for decision process quality, F(1, 145) = 7.27, p < .01, such that a careful decision process was perceived as more socially normal (M = .07) than a careless process (M = -.28). However, this effect was much weaker than the effect of social normality on the same variable. No other main effects or interactions significantly affected perceived social normality, all ps > .1. Anticipated Regret We first performed a between-subjects ANOVA on the first responses with decision process quality, social normality, and action as between-subjects factors. As expected, we found a main effect for decision process quality, F(1, 146) = 4.28, p < .05, such that anticipated regret was lower when a careful decision process was used (M = 6.43, SD = 3.43) than when a careless process was used (M = 7.43, SD = 2.88). The main effect for action was non-significant, F(1, 146) = 1.65, ns, (inaction M = 7.23, SD = 3.23, action M = 6.64, SD = 3.14). The main effect for social normality was also non-significant, F(1, 146) = .68, ns (socially normal M = 7.20, SD = 3.16, socially abnormal M = 6.69, SD = 3.21), as were all of the interaction terms, all ps > .1. 27 Decision Justifiability and Regret We next ran a repeated-measures ANOVA with decision process quality as within- and social normality, action, and order as between-subjects factors. Replicating the between-subjects results, the main effect of decision process quality was again significant, F(1, 146) = 21.48, p < .001 (careful M = 6.23, careless M = 7.22), but the other main effects were not, all ps > .1. This significant main effect was, however, qualified by a two-way interaction between decision process quality and social normality, F(1, 146) = 7.32, p < .01. The only significant simple effect was between a careless and a careful decision process with a socially normal choice. A careless decision process leading to a decision to do what most people one knows do was expected to be more regrettable (M = 7.63) than a careful decision process leading to the same socially normal choice (M = 6.04), F(1, 75) = 23.44, p < .01. Abnormal choices were expected to be equally regrettable whether the process that produced them was careless (M = 6.82) or careful (M = 6.41). While speculative interpretation is easy (e.g., a careless, socially conforming choice might be seen as parental abdication) we note that the effect (a) was not predicted, (b) is modest in size, (c) appeared only in within-subjects, not in between-subjects analysis, and (d) was not replicated in the analysis of perceived justification, reported below. In the absence of subsequent replication we therefore treat this finding with considerable caution. Perceived Decision Justifiability Again, we used several different analyses to examine the relation between perceived justifiability and anticipated regret. First, we found that perceived justifiability significantly predicted anticipated regret, analyzing only the responses to the first decision, β = -.30, t(152) = 3.89, p < .001. The more justifiable a decision was perceived, the less regrettable it was considered. Social normality perceptions did not significantly predict anticipated regret, β = .13, t(152) = 1.60, ns (note that the direction of the association was such that higher perceived 28 Decision Justifiability and Regret normality went along with higher anticipated regret, if anything). The same significance test results held when analyzing responses to both decisions. Next, we examined whether decision process quality affected perceived justifiability in a manner that matches its effect on anticipated regret. A between-subjects ANOVA with decision process quality, social normality, and action as between-subjects factors showed a significant main effect for decision process quality, F(1, 146) = 101.47, p < .001, such that a carefully made decision was perceived as more justifiable (M = 1.13, SD = 1.04) than a carelessly made decision (M = -.73, SD = 1.25). The main effect for action was not significant, F(1, 146) = .90, ns (Minaction = .13, Maction = .23). Also, a socially normal decision was not considered more justifiable (M = .14) than a socially abnormal decision (M = .21), F(1, 146) = .01, ns. None of the interactions were significant, all ps > .1. This pattern of results matches the pattern of results for anticipated regret. This result was replicated in a repeated-measures ANOVA with decision process quality as within- and social normality, action, and order as between-subjects factors. We found a main effect of decision process quality (careful M = 1.14, careless M = -.74, F(1, 145) = 194.38, p < .001). The interaction between decision process quality and social normality observed for anticipated regret was not significant for perceived justifiability, F(1, 145) = .54, ns. Thus, while the main effect of decision process quality on anticipated regret was mirrored by the justifiability perceptions, the interaction between process quality and social normality was not. No other main or interaction effects were significant, all ps > .1. Finally, we performed a mediation analysis to test whether perceived justifiability mediated the effect of decision process quality on anticipated regret found in the betweensubjects analysis. We already reported that decision process quality affected anticipated regret; 29 Decision Justifiability and Regret that decision process quality affected perceived justifiability; and that perceived justifiability predicted anticipated regret. When regressing anticipated regret on both the decision process quality and decision justifiability perceptions, decision process quality was not a significant predictor of regret, β = -.06, t(152) = .57, ns, but perceived justifiability remained significant, β = -.34, t(152) = 3.35, p < .01). A Sobel (1982) test for mediation was significant (z = 3.18, p < .01). We conclude that decision justifiability perceptions mediated the between-subjects effect of decision process quality on anticipated regret intensity. Discussion In Study 3 we manipulated decision process quality, action, and social normality. We found that a bad outcome following a careful, rather than careless, decision process was expected to be less regrettable even when information about action and social normality was present. Further, supporting a justifiability explanation of regret intensity, perceived justifiability was higher for a careful decision process and the effect of process quality on regret was fully mediated through justifiability perceptions. In the presence of process quality and social normality information, whether the decision was to act or not did not affect regret or justifiability perceptions. GENERAL DISCUSSION In this paper, we studied the effects of decision process quality, social normality, and action (i.e., whether the decision was to act or not) on anticipated regret. Our major concern has been with the role of perceived decision justifiability in explaining the intensity of anticipated regret. The three experiments reported yielded several important results. 30 Decision Justifiability and Regret First, past research and theorizing has suggested that the normality of a decision affects (anticipated) regret through the easier counterfactual mutability of abnormal choices (Kahneman & Tversky, 1982; Kahneman & Miller, 1986). Study 1 showed that the effects of action and social normality on anticipated regret can be to a substantial degree explained through perceived decision justifiability. We did not replicate the so-called “action effect” (e.g., Kahneman & Tversky, 1982). Our results suggest instead that whether a decision to act or not leads to more or less regret depends on the specific justifiability of the option rather than action or inaction per se (cf. Connolly & Reb, 2003; Inman & Zeelenberg, 2002). We chose a context in which “acting” is endorsed by the majority of the U.S. population: the decision whether to vaccinate one’s child against a serious disease. In this context, we found that the effect of action on anticipated regret was mediated through perceptions of decision justifiability. In addition, we found that social normality affected anticipated regret only when the manipulation was made salient in a withinsubjects manipulation. As predicted, in a within-subjects design, the differential justifiability of normal and abnormal behavior becomes more salient leading to a stronger effect on anticipated regret. The results are consistent with decision justification theory (Connolly & Zeelenberg, 2002). We now have two plausible explanations of these effects, one based on justifiability and the other based on mutability and counterfactual thinking (Kahneman & Miller, 1986). These explanations are not necessarily mutually exclusive. Future research should examine how justifiability and mutability relate to each other in explaining these effects, whether one explanation is more powerful than the other, and which explanation is more parsimonious. Second, we found that a careful decision process is expected to protect decision makers to some degree from regret following a bad outcome. The effect of decision process quality on 31 Decision Justifiability and Regret anticipated regret was significant in both Study 2 and Study 3, where social normality information was also given, in both between-subjects and within-subjects analyses, and independent of whether the decision was to vaccinate or not to vaccinate. Mediation analysis showed the effect of decision process quality on anticipated regret to be significantly mediated through perceived justifiability, supporting decision justification theory.2 All three studies showed the important role of decision justifiability in determining the intensity of anticipated regret. Table 1 summarizes the main effects of the experimental variables on anticipated regret and on perceived decision justifiability. With only one exception the experimental variables showed either significant main effects on both variables or on neither. The exception is Study 1, where the between-subjects analysis of social normality showed a significant effect on perceived justifiability but not on anticipated regret. It should be noted that, even when anticipated regret was reduced by strong justifiability, the mean score remained around the mid-point of the scale. Consistent with decision justification theory’s two-component model of regret, substantial outcome regret (over the child’s sickness) remains even if the selfblame component of regret is entirely eliminated. -----------------------------------Insert Table 1 around here -----------------------------------Two additional findings hint at the complexities of combining multiple sources of justifiability. First, we found no significant main effects on anticipated regret of either action or of social normality when decision process quality information was given (Study 3). These results suggest that the effects of weaker justifications, such as whether a decision is socially conforming, may be driven out by stronger justifications, such as the carefulness of the decision 32 Decision Justifiability and Regret process. Future research needs to examine in more detail the conditions under which different justifications crowd each other out. We also found a significant interaction between process quality and social normality on anticipated regret in Study 3, but place little confidence in this result absent of future replication. Limitations and Future Research Several limitations of our studies point to directions for future research. First, Janis and Mann (1977) predicted that regret aversion leads to “vigilant” decision making. Consistent with this prediction we have shown that people anticipate more regret when a poor outcome follows a careless decision process than a careful one. However, we did not demonstrate that decision makers will actually improve their decision processes to avoid this anticipated regret. Future research should examine whether regret aversion, either experimentally induced or measured as an individual difference variable, leads to more vigilant, careful decision making. Such a finding would have important implications for the debate about the functionality of regret (e.g., Zeelenberg, 1999) and would suggest that anticipated regret can have a beneficial effect on decision making. Further, we did not show that a careful decision process (or deciding to vaccinate, for that matter) actually reduces experienced regret after a bad decision outcome. Future research should examine the intensity of experienced regret as a function of the quality of the decision process. Decision justification theory (Connolly & Zeelenberg, 2002) assigns a key role to how justifications affect (anticipated) regret. Our results went a substantial way in examining and comparing different potential justifications. We found that the relation between different justifications can be complex. In our three studies different justifications acted independently on regret, dominated each other (driving each other out), and produced interactions with each other. 33 Decision Justifiability and Regret Clearly, the effects of multiple justifications need not be additive. Future research should examine in more detail the ways in which justifications combine and interact. A further limitation of our study was the use of a single context (in which anticipated regret has been shown to strongly predict actual choice, however; see Wroe et al., 2004). It is quite possible that justifications also interact with the decision context. In the context studied here, medical decisions for a child, a careful, comprehensive analytical decision process was seen as best justifying the choice the parent made. Such a process might not be seen as appropriate for a choice in which intuition and spontaneity is called for, as in the choice of a spouse. Similarly, the seriousness of the stakes involved might change the kind of justification called for. A modest flutter at a gaming table might be justified by “I simply felt like it”. A moderately expensive purchase of some new electronic gadget or a meal at a trendy restaurant might be adequately justified by noting that lots of other people were doing the same. Perhaps the “good decision process” justification used here is, in fact, seen as appropriate only for a subset of life’s big decisions. Finally, in all three studies, all decisions led to negative outcomes. One implication of decision justification theory’s distinction between self-blame regret and outcome regret is that regret might be experienced even in the absence of a bad outcome when the decision is perceived unjustifiable. Sugden (1985) suggested that one might experience extreme regret over a decision to drive home drunk from a party, even if one made the trip safely. Such self-blame regret in the absence of a bad outcome has not, to our knowledge, been demonstrated, and would in fact be somewhat surprising in light of the extensive literature (e.g. Pratto & John, 1991; Taylor, 1991) showing that negative events stimulate much more cognitive activity than do good ones. Future 34 Decision Justifiability and Regret research should examine whether or not a poor decision outcome is a prerequisite to the experience or anticipation of self-blame regret. Conclusion This paper examined the role of decision justifiability in determining the intensity of anticipated regret. We found support for the central prediction of decision justification theory (Connolly & Zeelenberg, 2002) that anticipated regret is reduced when a decision is perceived as justifiable. We also showed that engaging in a careful decision process is expected to protect the decision maker to some degree from regret following a bad decision outcome. Finally, when multiple sources of possible justifications are offered simultaneously, their combined effect is not, in general, simply the sum of the effects of each. Complex interactions are to be expected. Overall, these results support the ability of decision justification theory to provide an account of decision makers’ regret anticipations. They also suggest a positive view of the role of regret in decision making. Earlier research on the so-called action effect suggested that anticipated regret might be a biasing factor, leading to a preference for inaction even when the active option was objectively superior. The current research suggests, instead, that anticipated regret can have a beneficial effect on decision making, by stimulating a search for more justifiable decisions, and thus encouraging more careful decision processes. 35 Decision Justifiability and Regret FOOTNOTES 1 The header also included what was intended as a manipulation of “personal normality”, whether or not the protagonist made this choice as she normally made medical decisions for her child. In retrospect it became clear that the wording of this manipulation was unclear. Since the data showed no significant relationship between the manipulation and anticipated regret, we collapsed on this variable and excluded it from further analysis. 2 A reviewer points out that cognitive dissonance theory might provide an alternative account of the apparent ameliorating effect of good decision process on anticipated regret. Given that good decision process implies greater decision effort, the presumed dissonance would involve the elements “I made a large effort” and “I achieved (or expect to achieve) a poor (i.e. regrettable) result”. This dissonance could be reduced by reassessing downwards the regrettability of the outcome (the sick child), generating the negative correlation observed in Studies 2 and 3 between decision process quality and anticipated regret. This alternative account seems plausible to us (and, indeed, reminds us of the important similarities between decision justification and cognitive dissonance theories), and it is not obvious how we might distinguish the two accounts on the present data. On grounds of parsimony alone we prefer decision justification theory (which accounts for all three main effects via a justification-regret mechanism) over dissonance theory (which would account for the process quality findings of Studies 2 and 3 but does not offer an obvious account of the action and normality effects found in Study 1 or of their suppression in Studies 2 and 3). However, a serious effort to distinguish between the two accounts would require both a more complete development of decision justification theory and new data collection beyond the scope of the present report. 36 Decision Justifiability and Regret REFERENCES Baron, J. (1992). The effect of normative beliefs on anticipated emotions. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 63, 320-330. Baron, J., & Ritov, I. (2004). Omission bias, individual differences, and normality. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 94, 74-85. Baron, R. M., & Kenny, D. A. (1986). The moderator-mediator variable distinction in social psychological research: Conceptual, strategic and statistical considerations. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 51, 1173-1182. Bell, D. E. (1982). Regret in decision making under uncertainty. Operations Research, 30, 961981. Connolly, T., Ordóñez, L., & Coughlan, R. (1997). Regret and responsibility in the evaluation of decision outcomes. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 70, 73-85. Connolly, T., & Reb, J. (in press). Regret in cancer-related decisions. Health Psychology. Connolly, T., & Reb, J. (2003). Omission bias in vaccination decisions: Where’s the “omission”? Where’s the “bias”? Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 91, 186-202. Connolly, T. & Zeelenberg, M. (2002). Regret in decision making. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 11, 212-220. Crawford, M. T., McConnell, A. R., Lewis, A. C., & Sherman, S. J. (2002). Reactance, compliance, and anticipated regret. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 38, 56–63. Gilbert, D. T., Morewedge, C. K., Risen, J. L., & Wilson, T. D. (2004). Looking forward to look backward: The misprediction of regret. Psychological Science, 15, 346-350. Inman, J. J., & Zeelenberg, M. (2002). Regret in repeat purchase versus switching decisions: The attenuating role of decision justifiability. Journal of Consumer Research, 29, 116-128. 37 Decision Justifiability and Regret Janis, I. L., & Mann, L. (1977). Decision making. New York: Free Press. Kahneman, D., & Miller, D. T. (1986). Norm theory: Comparing reality to its alternatives. Psychological Review, 93, 136-153. Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1982). The psychology of preferences. Scientific American, 246, 160-173. Landman, J. (1987). Regret and elation following action and inaction: Affective responses to positive versus negative outcomes. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 13, 524-536. Landman, J. (1993). Regret: The persistence of the possible. New York: Oxford University Press. Larrick, R. P., & Boles, T. L. (1995). Avoiding regret in decisions with feedback: A negotiation example. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 63, 87-97. Loomes, G., & Sugden, R. (1982). Regret theory: an alternative theory of rational choice under uncertainty. Economic Journal, 92, 805-824. Mellers, B. A., Schwartz, A., & Ritov, I. (1999). Emotion-based choice. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 128, 332-245. N’gbala, A., & Branscombe, N. R. (1997). When does action elicit more regret than inaction and is the counterfactual mutation the mediator of this effect? Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 33, 324-343. Pratto, F., & John, O. P. (1991). Automatic vigilance: The attention-grabbing power of negative social information. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 61, 380-391. Reisenzein, R., & Hofmann, T. (1993). Discriminating emotions from appraisal-relevant situational information: Baseline data for structural models of cognitive appraisal. In N. H. 38 Decision Justifiability and Regret Frijda (Ed.), Appraisal and beyond: The issue of cognitive determinants of emotion (pp. 271293). Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Richard, R., van der Pligt, J., & de Vries, N. K. (1996). Anticipated regret and time perspective: Changing sexual risk-taking behavior. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 9, 185-199. Ritov, I., & Baron, J. (1990). Reluctance to vaccinate: Omission bias and ambiguity. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 3, 263-277. Ritov, R., & Baron, J. (1995). Outcome knowledge, regret, and omission bias. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 64, 119-127. Roese, N. J. (1997). Counterfactual thinking. Psychological Bulletin, 121, 133-148. Roese, N. J., & Olsen, J. M. (Eds.). (1995). What might have been: The social psychology of counterfactual thinking. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Savage, L. J. (1951). The theory of statistical decision. Journal of the American Statistical Association, 46, 55-67. Seta, J. J., McElroy, T., & Seta, C. E. (2001). To do or not to do: Desirability and consistency mediate judgments of regret. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 80, 861-870. Simonson, I. (1992). The influence of anticipating regret and responsibility on purchase decisions. Journal of Consumer Research, 19, 105-118. Sobel, M. E. (1982). Asymptotic confidence intervals for indirect effects in structural equation models. In S. Leinhardt (Ed.), Sociological Methodology 1982 (pp. 290-312). Washington DC: American Sociological Association. Sugden, R. (1985). Regret, recrimination and rationality. Theory and Decision, 19, 77-99. Taylor, S.E. (1991). Asymmetric effects of positive and negative events: The mobilizationminimization hypothesis. Psychological Bulletin, 110, 67-85. 39 Decision Justifiability and Regret Wroe, A. L., Turner, N., & Salkovskis, P. M. (2004) Understanding and predicting parental decisions about early childhood immunizations. Health Psychology, 23, 33-41. Zeelenberg, M. (1996). On the importance of what might have been: Psychological perspectives on regret and decision making. Doctoral dissertation: University of Amsterdam. Zeelenberg, M. (1999). The use of crying over spilled milk: A note on the rationality and functionality of regret. Philosophical Psychology, 12, 325-340. Zeelenberg, M., van den Bos, K., van Dijk, E., & Pieters, R. (2001). The inaction effect in the psychology of regret. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 82, 314-327. 40 Decision Justifiability and Regret Table 1: Summary of Significant Main Effects of Experimental Variables on Anticipated Regret and Perceived Decision Justifiability Dependent Variable* Study 1 Study 2 Study 3 Experimental Between-Subjects or Anticipated Decision Variable Within-Subjects Analysis Regret Justifiability Action Between Yes Yes Action Within Yes Yes Social normality Between No Yes Social normality Within Yes Yes Decision process quality Between Yes Yes Decision process quality Within Yes Yes Action Between No No Action Within No No Decision process quality Between Yes Yes Decision process quality Within Yes Yes Action Between No No Action Within No No Social normality Between No No Social normality Within No No * In all cases in which the experimental variable was shown to affect both dependent variables, greater decision justifiability is associated with lower levels of anticipated regret. 41