João Constâncio and Maria João Mayer Branco (eds.), Nietzsche on Instinct and Language (proceedings of a conference held in 2009 at Universidade Nova de Lisboa). ). Berlin and Boston: Walter de Gruyter, 2011. xxiv + 295 pp. ISBN 978-3-11-024656-8. Cloth, $140. Nietzsche’s critique of the will to truth, and, more specifically, the metaphysical tradition, is inextricable from both his philosophy of language and his turn to physiology. Though the way in which Nietzsche conceived of the intertwinement of language, reason and the body developed through the course of his philosophical maturation, it is nonetheless an interconnection that spans the breadth of his oeuvre (compare e.g. the early Nietzsche’s unpublished essay ‘Uber Wahrheit und Lüge im außermoralischen Sinn’ [1873] and the late work, ‘Book V’ of Die fröhliche Wissenschaft [1887]). To be sure, Nietzsche on Instinct and Language seems principally concerned with comprehensively mapping out this complex interrelation across its various formulations. The modern, occidental habit of preaching the authority and higher worth of reason over and against the compulsions of the body undoubtedly finds precedence in Plato’s schema of the tripartite soul; however, more immediately, as Nietzsche points out, the diremption and hierarchicisation of these “antipodes” ought to be imputed to Descartes’ dualism (JGB 191). As is well known, Nietzsche took it upon himself to subvert this opposition, and hence the topographical aspect of Nietzsche on Instinct and Language is directed at illustrating the precise way in which reason and the body are more properly conceived of as existing on a single continuum. Language becomes of prime importance since, as it is both bodily function and the medium of dialectical thought, it represents the connective tissue bridging mind and body. In addition to the above, the editors’ introduction delineates another, corollary objective of the volume – namely, to interrogate the self-reflexive issues raised by Nietzsche’s linguistics. Certainly, one must ask, if Nietzsche accepts language as instinctual, and as incapable of expressing a purely rational or transcendent form of truth, then where does this leave the truth value of his own texts? Or, more to the point, how is Nietzsche’s own use of language alive to, and indeed, how does it embrace, the linguistic limitations of which it speaks? This is described in terms of his struggle to forge a new, critical-philosophical ‘language’. Though this is a recurrent theme throughout the eleven articles comprising the volume, it is most prominent in the latter half the book, and one therefore finds the first two chapters laying foundations toward this end. The essays which constitute the first chapter, entitled ‘Nietzschean Beginnings and Developments’, therefore focus on Nietzsche’s early thoughts concerning language. Andrea Bertino, for example, does so through a series of comparative ‘notes’ on Nietzsche and Herder; subsequently, Chapter Two, ‘Dissolving an Opposition’, tries to explicate the way in which Nietzsche contests the traditional opposition between language and instinct. Thus, Chiara Piazzesi’s paper from this cluster give a close reading of FW 14 to show how Nietzsche breaks down the opposition between love and greed and thereby illustrates the more general point that such bipolar oppositions originate as linguistic phenomena that are then projected onto the experienced world; it is then in Chapter Three, ‘Instinct, Language and Philosophy’, that, in their respective essays, Werner Stegmaier and Scarlett Marton examine in greater depth the broader philosophical consequences of this dissolution of opposites; and finally, the fourth chapter, ‘The Critique of Morality and the Affirmation of Life’, groups together four articles that survey the connection between Nietzsche’s critique of language and, as its title suggests, the life affirming aspects of his philosophy. From this chapter, Marta Faustino’s paper on the indefinite meaning of health in Nietzsche work is of most interest. However, as compared with the other chapters, there is a definite lack of cohesion amongst these closing essays and, furthermore, they do not seem to deal any more specifically with Nietzsche’s critique of morality nor the life affirming aspects of his philosophy than many of the other preceding essays in the volume. Structurally, then, one finds the volume at its weakest in its final quarter. It is not here possible to provide an overview and analysis of each of the volume’s eleven papers; however, by examining at a small selection, one can obtain a fairly clear picture of the argumentative movement that characterises the collection taken as a whole. A good place to start is with Patrick Wotling’s contribution in the volume’s second chapter, ‘What Language do Drives Speak?’ Wotling is less interested in what would ordinarily be referred to as language – i.e. conscious, verbal, human communication – so much as the so-called ‘language’ of the drives. The central argument is that, for Nietzsche, individual conscious thoughts are, contrary to our phenomenological experience, not causally connected. Rather, they are each the superficial effect of deeper processes, rearrangements and struggles occurring within the infra-conscious community of the drives. To summarise, Wotling’s thesis is that an ‘originary’ form of communication between the drives is a precondition of such interaction and that, indeed, that this necessity was something of which Nietzsche was well aware. Going into further detail, Wotling argues that the interaction of the drives is almost exclusively orientated toward their self-hierarchicisation, and that the resulting network of command and subordination, since it is imposed immanently, requires some form of communication (p.76–7). Finally, since this communication is based on the ‘feeling’ of respective power statuses, is it therefore, says Wotling, affective as opposed to verbal. Wotling’s paper, however, leaves a number of questions unanswered (if not further complicated). The first concerns the precise meaning of the term ‘language’ – an issue that in fact pervades the volume as a whole. Whereas the often overlooked differences between Nietzsche’s use of Triebe and Instinkte is carefully drawn in Nietzsche on Instinct and Language, the distinction extant between language proper and non-linguistic communication is not. Nietzsche undoubtedly strives to renaturalise both language and reason in a way that tries to leave Descartes behind; however, in the interests of clarity and philosophical rigor, we ought to retain an important distinction identified by the latter and also quite rightly sustained by contemporary psychologists and linguists alike – viz., that existing between linguistic and non-linguistic forms of communication.1 Of course, not all communication is linguistic, and the drive communication which Wotling indexes, is certainly not. In his defence, Wotling explains that he has only chosen to call this originary, affective species of communication ‘language’ in a metaphorical sense, and indeed throughout the volume, ‘language’ is often placed in quotation marks when used to refer to these infra-conscious levels of communication (see e.g. p.78, 100, and xviii). Nonetheless, the indubitable uniqueness of the socio-cultural phenomenon of language proper is eroded without a clear differentiation of these two forms of communication. It is understandable that the editors 1 See e.g. Descartes (1861), p.53–4 and Hauser et al. (2002). and authors of the book may not have wanted to separate language from other forms of communication since doing so may reinforce its transcendent or supra-natural appearance. Such a move, however, would need to be explicitly justified. In any case, it is surprising that, in a book in which ‘language’ is such a key term, the noun so consistently eludes precise definition. There is then the issue of the ‘causal’ relation between language and conscious thought on the one hand, and the instincts and drives on the other. According to Wotling, it is the originary communication of the drives that renders possible language proper (p.78). Yet, as Wotling emphasises, this relation ought not to be thought of in terms of causality, since, as is well known, Nietzsche was highly critical of our tendency to fabulate such facile causal connections. But the passages that Wotling cites in order to ground this claim are specifically directed against the idea of the human will as a unified causal force and, thus, the idea that conscious thoughts are the cause of subsequent conscious thoughts (NL 2[103] KSA 12.112; NL 15 [13] KSA 13.414). So, although Wotling argues very competently that, for Nietzsche, there is no horizontal causal relation between conscious thoughts, he does not adequately demonstrate that there is none between, on the one side, the activity of the drives and, on the other, the phenomenon of conscious thought and language proper. NL 6[264] KSA 9.266, quoted by Wotling (p.65) and also once earlier in the volume (p.41), is a note that demands closer exegesis than it is subject to in Nietzsche on Instinct and Language; especially the following lines: Auch dem feinsten Gedanken entspricht eine Verhäkelung von Trieben. – Die Worte sind gleichsam eine Claviatur der Triebe, und Gedanken (in Worten) sind Akkorde darauf. Is Nietzsche painting a vertical model of mental causation here – i.e. are language and conscious thought merely higher descriptive levels of the activity of the drives. Are these two levels therefore synchronic manifestations of the same activity as opposed to distinct links on a causal chain (after all, this is a relation of Entsprechung as opposed to Kausalität)? Thus, striking the correct combination of keys would not cause the chord, they would be the chord described from one perspective, and the sound its description from another. Unfortunately, these questions are left unanswered by Wotling. João Constâncio, in the book’s fourth essay, ‘Instinct and Language in Nietzsche’s Beyond Good and Evil’, also engages with this elliptical interrelation of language, conscious thought and the drives. Whereas both Wotling and, in the volume’s opening essay, Bertino (see p.30) both present a unidirectional account of this interrelationship starting with the drives and ending with conscious thought, Constâncio contends that: If we had to think of the relations between conscious and unconscious mental states and processes in terms of causality, we would have to conceive of a bi-directional path of causality, for although conscious mental states are always ‘caused’ and sustained by unconscious mental processes, they also influence and change the life of the unconscious drives. Strictly speaking, however, Nietzsche conceives of such relations in terms of sign- and power-relations’ (p.97). For Constâncio, then, the desires of conscious reason (‘caused’ by the activity of the drives) strive to become physiologically incorporated or, in other words, instinctual. However, in spite of Constâncio’s rather cursory mention of sign- and power-relations, along with the quotation marks he places either side of ‘caused’, he nonetheless fails to explain sufficiently the relationship between the conscious realm of language and the infra-conscious domain of the drives without reference to a fairly traditional conception of causality. Perhaps, in a Nietzschean fashion, it could be argued that, at present within our culture, it is verging on impossible to linguistically articulate a non-causal relationship since the grammatical structure of Indo-European languages (subject- verbobject) is condemned to describe the world in terms of causality. Yet this is not argued, and, additionally, since there is no dialogue between the stances of Wotling, Bertino and Constâncio, readers are left none the wiser as to the precise interrelation of these respective levels. Having outlined the descriptive aspect of Nietzsche’s philosophy of language, Constâncio dedicates the final section of his paper to its normative dimension. This concerns the genesis of a ‘neue Sprache’ (JGB 4). Indeed, Branco (p.51) and Hay (p.255) similarly attempt to illumine some of the features of Nietzsche’s own ‘new language’ – that is, the ‘language’ he suggests ought to replace the diction of the Wissenschaftler he censures so polemically. The consensus between these three analyses is that this ‘new language’ is one that rejects the demonstrative, logo-centric mode of philosophical presentation and chooses, instead, to embrace the creative potential of a wholly rhetorical, non-representational model of language. But again, though this ‘new language’ can, in one sense, be referred to as a ‘language’, it cannot replace language proper (ordered systems of signs and syntax), which is what Nietzsche is actually often criticizing when he speaks of language. His ‘new language’ is, rather, as Katia Hay points out, a new style; it is a new manner of speaking about the world by means of the existing linguistic framework. For this reason, says Constâncio, Nietzsche’s ‘new language’ is ‘not entirely new’ and ‘does not lead to an alternative grammar of “becoming”’(p.110). To be sure, Nietzsche’s stylistic novelty is less a radical emancipation from our grammatical-linguistic fetters (which we need to survive and make sense of the world) so much as a far tamer rejection of a certain academic approach. Referring to Nietzsche’s new style as ‘language’, then, I would argue, is misleading since it is something quite distinct from what is meant by language elsewhere in Nietzsche on Instinct and Language. Once again, then, one finds no consistent definition of ‘language’ (used with or without quotation marks).Yet the flaws of the book do not stop at its failure to make important conceptual distinctions; it also lacks a thorough critical examination of the efficaciousness of this ‘new language’. If it is grammar and the structure of language proper that governs our metaphysical Weltanschauung and philosophical approach toward that world, how effective a force can Nietzsche’s new fluid style be against the imperial dominance of our linguistic edifice. In this way, then, the more pressing critical questions go unasked, and indeed, the book is left with a tone that is almost naively celebratory with respect to Nietzsche’s fearless, revolutionary iconoclasm and innovation. What is more, owing to the volume’s overall lack of substantial structure and the enormous quantity of repetition between papers, the text’s birth from an overly concentric collection of conference papers is unfortunately palpable throughout. Finally, for a book edited by such esteemed Nietzsche scholars and published by De Gruyter (as part of it’s Nietzsche Today series) it must be said that the sheer abundance of spelling and grammatical errors tarnishes the content of the collection. Notwithstanding, the volume makes comprehensive use of existing secondary material, and so, in this respect, this volume certainly represents an indispensible tool for anyone following a similar line of inquiry. In addition to this, most of the essays, taken on their own, are interesting and insightful; thus, the book remains a worthwhile addition to the Anglophone literature on Nietzsche, especially since his thoughts on language per se tend to be treated as secondary to both his conception of the world qua text and the role played by interpretation in his later works. But, in particular, it is the way in which the connection of language and physiology has been scrutinized in such a sustained manner that represents the most original aspect of the text. Despite the major discrepancies between Bertino’s, Wotling’s and Constâncio’s papers (see above), they nevertheless effectively argue that any serious study of Nietzsche’s physiology – which currently happens to be the subject of so much critical attention – ought to be considered inseparable from his thoughts on language (and, of course, vice versa). References Descartes, Discours de la Méthod (Paris: Eugène Belin, 1861) Marc D. Hauser, Noam Chomsky and W. Tecumseh Fitch, ‘The Faculty of Language: What Is It, Who Has It and How Did it Evolve’, Science, 298 (2002), 1569-1579