A discussion of Glenn W. Most’s ‘Nietzsche gegen Aristoteles mit Aristoteles’ Nietzsche-seminar 2nd October 2009 A reflective report By Bas Nabers Introduction During the Nietzsche-seminar on October 2 2009, Glenn W. Most presented his text ‘Nietzsche gegen Aristoteles mit Aristoteles’. In it, Most analyses the relation between Nietzsche’s use of the word ‘Entladung’ in Die Geburt der Tragödie, and Bernays’ interpretation of the Aristotelian concept katharsis. The text was primarily written within the context of a series of conferences on katharsis. According to Most, Bernays made a crucial contribution to our understanding of katharsis on which Nietzsche was to draw. By explaining Aristotle’s notion of katharsis in medical instead of moral terms, Bernays raised a whole series of issues which are still relevant today. Moreover, he translated katharsis with ‘Entladung’, and ‘Entladung’ is a key word in Die Geburt der Tragödie. In this reflective report, I will first give a summary of the text. Then I will give an account of the main issues that were raised during the discussion. Finally, I will conclude with a critical reflection on both the text and the discussion. 1 1. Summary of the text Most’s analysis of the relation between Nietzsche’s use of the word ‘Entladung’ and Bernays’ interpretation of the Aristotelian concept katharsis starts with the observation that Nietzsche rarely uses the word katharsis; even at those places where one would expect him to do so, the word is lacking (51). In order to explain this absence, Most draws attention to §22 of GT, where Nietzsche joins the recent philological debate, taking implicitly position against Bernays. Bernays had rejected Lessing’s moral interpretation of katharsis, as well as Goethe’s aesthetic one, and offered an understanding of Aristotelian katharsis in medical terms. Nietzsche argues against both moral and medical interpretations of Greek tragedy. Doing so, he leaves it unclear which position recent scholars have adopted, thereby adding to the impression that there is confusion among them. Neither the struggle of the hero with his fate, nor the victory of the moral order, nor the ‘Entladung von Affecten’ can define the tragic (52-53; GT 22). With Goethe Nietzsche argues that the tragic should be understood as an aesthetic phenomenon. According to Most, Nietzsche deliberately uses Bernays to argue against the moral interpretation of Greek tragedy, but only before rejecting Bernays’ position as well (53-54). However, against whom does Nietzsche argue here? Against Aristotle? Or against a specific interpretation of the Greek philosopher? This is not altogether clear according to Most (55). He writes that no satisfactory explanation of Greek tragedy has been given since Aristotle, leaving it unclear whether ‘since’ includes or excludes Aristotle. Further, it remains obscure whether Nietzsche found it important that the recent philological theory of katharsis is conceptualized in moral or medical terms. Only years after Die Geburt der Tragödie Nietzsche takes an unambiguous position against Aristotle. In 1888 he writes that tragedy is life-enhancing, whereas tragedy appears to be life-negating if we follow the Aristotelian interpretation. But Most doubts whether we should understand Nietzsche’s position in Die Geburt der Tragödie simply in terms of this self-understanding (56). Is there really such a strong opposition? Most will argue there is not. As a student Nietzsche already tried very hard to oppose Aristotle’s theory of katharsis. For, refuting the great thinkers of the past would make him famous. With respect to content, Nietzsche’s early struggle with Aristotle mainly concerns the role of the choir, which is crucial for Nietzsche but ignored by Aristotle. When Nietzsche does value Aristotle’s theory of katharsis, he does so merely because Aristotle’s analysis indicates that the Greeks were deeply touched by the tragic music (56). In all his published works Nietzsche’s critique of Aristotle, Most states, often remained 2 somewhat superficial. In the Nachlass, however, Nietzsche takes Aristotle more seriously. In one of his notes Nietzsche writes about the necessity of ‘Entladung’ or katharsis, which was characteristic of the Greek soul (57). In Die Geburt der Tragödie itself Nietzsche differs mainly from Aristotle with regard to the role of the choir and the nature of the mimesis in tragedy (57). In Most’s view this suggests that Nietzsche tries to replace rather than to invalidate Aristotle’s position. And this seems to be the reason why Nietzsche suppresses the presence of Aristotle in GT (58). However, Nietzsche’s own position is characterized by a very active, even energetic ‘Aristotelismus’ (59). Indeed, Nietzsche does oppose Aristotle, in so far he rejects pity, fear and morality as crucial in an explanation of tragedy, but there remain many traces of Aristotle in Nietzsche’s own ideas (59). This especially holds true with regard to the Bernaysian interpretation of Aristotle’s concept of katharsis. Bernays had translated katharsis with ‘Entladung’, which Nietzsche takes over, bringing the whole Aristotelian conceptualization of katharsis into play (61). In a Dionysian phase emotions are stimulated and reinforced; and after their intensity has reached a certain height, there is an ‘Umschlag’ in a totally different dimension, one of apollonian visualization and vision. In other writings (like Nietzsche’s lecture about the ‘Geschichte der griechischen Literatur’) other ideas related to ‘Entladung’ and katharsis pop up again and again (60). Most argues, then, that the central idea in Die Geburt der Tagödie could only have come into existence out of Bernay’s concept of ‘Entladung’. Only by paying attention to Bernays’ understanding of katharsis as the background of Nietzsche’s own views on Greek tragedy, can Die Geburt der Tragödie be properly understood (62). 3 2. The discussion of the text 2.1 Katharsis and Entladung until Bernays In order to sketch the background of the views presented in the text, Most first elaborates on his own understanding of katharsis, and the development the notion has undergone. According to Most the history of the notion can be divided in four phases. During the first Plato set the problem, by posing the question why people derive pleasures from the horrible scenes of tragedy. Plato’s answer has to do with his idea that our emotions are always trying to get control of us, putting our reason to the test. Now, in tragedy our emotions get so strong that we get insane. The pleasure we derive from tragedy is the pleasure we derive from the total victory of one part of the human psyche over the rest. Aristotle’s account of tragedy, indicating the second step in the development of katharsis, was still confined within Plato’s framework, but also gave a twist to Plato’s account. By means of the imitations of actions where pity and fear are involved, tragedy aims to realize a katharsis of these feelings. Tragedy stimulates emotions, making them stronger and stronger, in order to realize a turning point, after which the reason is clarified. Since these observations lack a well defined theoretical basis (at least in the texts we have today), interpretations of Aristotle’s katharsis remain hypothetical reconstructions. Until Bernays katharsis was understood in moral terms. Tragedy taught people to be better by showing bad things. The purification of immoral emotions which katharis was assumed to imply was part of this process. Bernays offered a new interpretation of Aristotle’s katharsis. He adopted a medical approach and drew attention to Aristotle’s comparison between katharsis and female menstruation. According to Aristotle, the female body is wet and cold and, therefore, produces too much blood. By means of katharsis or menstruation the female body gets rid of too much blood, allowing her to be healthy again. In a similar way, emotions would increase while attending a Greek tragedy, leading to a turning point (Bernays uses the word ‘Umschlag’). Professor Most is asked whether this intensification of emotions is for Bernays, as it is for Nietzsche, not only a matter of quantity, but also of acceleration. Most states that this acceleration is not particularly thematized. But the fact that Aristotle emphasized that tragedy takes place in a one day time might point into that direction. It is asked why the word ‘Umschlag’ is applied to Nietzsche’s notion of ‘Entladung’. In Nietzsche’s account ‘Entladung’ entails the recreation of an older substance into something new, whereas Bernays, when using the word ‘Umschlag’, does not speak of recreation, but of the sudden 4 loss of feeling. Most states that he used the word ‘Umschlag’ in order to indicate the suddenness of the ‘Entladung’ in Nietzsche. After having clarified the history of katharsis, Most turns to the meaning of the word ‘Entladung’. He discerns four basic meanings before Nietzsche. First, ‘Entladung’ was used with respect to a weapon which discharges itself. Secondly, it related to sexual energy, which is frustrated and ‘entlädet’ itself in an orgasm. Next, it could describe a sudden discharge of some electrically charged body. And finally, it could refer to unloading a boat or truck. Most emphasizes that Bernays used the term in order to oppose the moral interpretation of katharsis, and drew especially on the scientific, electric, but also on the sexual meanings of ‘Entladung’. 2.2 A critical discussion of the text 2.2.1 Nietzsche’s and Aristotle’s use of ‘Entladung’ Most questions focus on the relation between Nietzsche’s use of ‘Entladung’ on the one hand, and Bernays’ on the other. Is Nietzsche’s use of the term ‘Entladung’, in this case, not far too small a basis for the similarity claimed in the article? In Nietzsche’s work ‘Entladung’ has to do with production. Aristotle’s account of katharsis, on the other hand, only focuses on the perception of tragedy. The fundamental role which music played in Nietzsche’s account of Greek tragedy, driving passions to an overflowing abundance, rather than his discussion with Aristotle seems to be the motivating ground for Nietzsche’s usage of ‘Entladung’. Is the BernaysianAristotelian account of tragedy not far too psychological to be the framework for Nietzsche’s metaphysical account, involving the expression of Dionysian energy in visual images? And does not Nietzsche’s description of this process in terms of ‘Entladung’ owe more to Schopenhauer and Wagner than to Bernays? And if so, does Nietzsche really use the word ‘Entladung’ as an interpretation of katharsis? A similar remark draws attention to a passage in Götzendämmerung (‘Was ich den Alten verdanke’). In this text Nietzsche uses the word ‘Entladung’ to describe Aristotle’s view, while defending an account of Greek tragedy, which is expressed by means of the word ‘Entladung’ elsewhere. This suggests that Nietzsche consciously uses ‘Entladung’ in at least two very different ways. One usage is associated with the ‘Reinigung’ of dangerous or disturbing emotions, which is judged to be necessary by an outside rationality. The other usage connotes fullness, ‘überfliessen’ and an inner, creative necessity to express feelings. Nietzsche’s diverse use of ‘Entladung’ is stressed in an even stronger way. In Nietzsche’s ‘Lesung zur griechischen Literatur’ the word seems to pop up everywhere. Can all these 5 usages be covered by the meaning Bernays ascribes to ‘Entladung’? From still a different angle, it is stated that ‘Entladung’ can relate to both positive and negative freedom (as a freedom from…, and a freedom to…), or as a means to loose yourself and find yourself. All these remarks tend to revolve around the same basic question: can’t ‘Entladung’ be a keyword in Die Geburt der Tragödie, without forcing it to work within the constraints of a Bernaysian-Aristotelian framework? To these questions Most replies that Bernays was so central a figure in Nietzsche’s days that we should assume that Nietzsche was working with Bernays’ interpretation of Aristotle. And while responding to him, Nietzsche, like Bernays, assumed that emotions, through Greek tragedy, get stronger and stronger until they reach a point where they are being replaced by Apollonian visions. Nietzsche wanted to develop an interpretation of tragedy superior to Aristotle’s, but he could do this only by adopting the word ‘Entladung’ as a translation of katharsis and using Bernays’ interpretation of Aristotle. In that sense Nietzsche was writing ‘gegen Aristoteles, mit Aristoteles.’ In response to this explanation of the title, it is again argued that Nietzsche uses the word ‘Entladung’, but in a very different way. The word may be the same, but the attached concept is totally different (as is the case in §22). This would mean that Nietzsche is only in a very weak sense ‘mit Aristoteles’ in GT. Nonetheless, Most argues, it is important that Nietzsche used Bernays’ term, and developed it in his writing. The interesting thing is that he could not have written his treatise without Bernays’ influence. In order to fully address Nietzsche’s relationship to Bernays, two things have to be done: to show that the text could not have been written without Bernays, and to reveal the differences between them. In the article the first aim is realized. Again it is stressed, however, that the accumulation of Dionysian energies, according to Nietzsche, leads to a transformation in images. This move has nothing to do with Bernays. Most argues, on the other hand, that Nietzsche’s account is similar, insofar he applies the word ‘Entladung’ to Greek tragedy. Most claims to reveal nothing more than a hidden discussion between Nietzsche and Bernays. Though he admits that it may be possible to find other influences on Nietzsche’s use of the term, Most argues that this still has to be done and that this was not his aim. This reply seems to be unsatisfactory, since the question is rephrased: what needs to be explained is how images are born out of emotional intensity; what needs to be clarified is the significance of ‘Entladung’ in Nietzsche. In addition to this question, it is argued that Nietzsche’s view about an excess of pain (and not only of emotion) producing a 6 state of harmony and pleasure can not be derived from Bernays. Where, then, does it come from? Most agrees that this latter idea does not seem to stem from Bernays, though one should keep in mind that the Greek word for emotion could also mean pain. As for the first objection, Most argues that Nietzsche might well have read Bernays and interpreted the word in another way, inspired by Schopenhauer. Nietzsche surely read Schopenhauer, but it is also interesting to read Nietzsche as someone who has read Bernays. The influence of Bernays is again challenged, by the remark that Wagner also used the word ‘Entladung’. Most replies that he does not deny other influences on Nietzsche’s use of the word, but emphasizes that Bernays’ influence should not be overlooked either, since he applied ‘Entladung’ specifically to Greek tragedy. With respect to the question about Nietzsche’s focus on production, opposing Aristotle’s focus on the spectator, Most stresses that exactly the creative aspect of the reception of Greek tragedy is central in Nietzsche’s aesthetics. Another question concerns the notion of ‘Umschlag’ in the article. Is this a term of Bernays? And can it be applied to Nietzsche’s views, in the sense that Dionysus ‘entlädt’ itself into a different, Apollonian realm? Wouldn’t this mean that Apollo is of less importance than Dionysus? The term is indeed from Bernays, but Most states that he used the word ‘Umschlag’ in order to indicate the suddenness of the ‘Entladung’ in Nietzsche. And while addressing the question whether this would mean that Appollo replaces Dionysus (that is, whether we should speak, in Most’s view, of replacement instead of recreation), Most argues that Nietzsche himself is ambivalent on this point. At least at some points Nietzsche suggests that Apollo has won in a work of art (becoming too Apollonian, therefore, is the permanent danger for art). 2.2.1 Aristotelian katharsis as life-negating and rationalistic Some of the questions concern Nietzsche’s view that Aristotelian katharsis was life-negating and rationalistic. Why did Nietzsche think so? Most explains Nietzsche’s negative view on Aristotle’s analysis of tragedy, by stating that Aristotle saw emotions as unhealthy, as something you have to free yourself from, whereas Nietzsche judged them to be vital. And Aristotle turned out to be too rationalistic for Nietzsche, because he, unlike Plato, thought it was easy to deal with them. 7 2.2.3 Nietzsche’s act of concealment Questions are raised concerning Most’s suggestion that Nietzsche was deliberately suppressing Aristotle in his published work. In his text Most argued that Nietzsche took Aristotle more seriously in the Nachlass, while concealing his influence elsewhere. The implicit way of referring to other authors, however, is a much used strategy in Nietzsche’s work. Is there any ground for suspicion in this specific case? Did Nietzsche misuse Aristotle in any sense whatsoever? Were Nietzsche’s views less different from Aristotle’s than Nietzsche himself made us deliberately believe? Did Nietzsche, in his published works, pretend to say more than he was actually saying? In general, Most argues, Nietzsche was not trying to interpret Aristotle, but was trying to pose a counter model based on the scholarship back then. Nietzsche, in this sense, uses (the Bernaysian interpretation of) Aristotle in order to interpret tragedy anew. But this is not to say, Most continues, that he tries to attack Nietzsche or that he sees any reason to be suspicious of Nietzsche’s writing in particular. Nietzsche is not deliberately concealing something, there is no dishonesty in Nietzsche’s style of writing. It is rather a procedure of rewriting texts which deserves attention here. In a draft for Unzeitgemäße Betrachtungen, for example, Nietzsche quotes Leopardi; in the next version the quotation is still there, but Leopardi’s name is gone; in the published text only a rephrased version has remained. This is no example of plagiarism, but the product of a process of reworking an idea over and over again, until Nietzsche made these ideas his own. Most explains that he is merely suspicious about how a text comes about generally. And Nietzsche is especially interesting, since he was a brilliant writer and a tactical reader, and, secondly, much material has survived which enables us to intercept this process in action. 2.2.4 Concluding remark At the end of the discussion Most once more stresses that he only added one more ingredient to the analysis of Nietzsche’s view on Greek tragedy. When it is asked whether Schopenhauer had a greater influence than Bernays, Most replies that both Bernays and Schopenhauer were important, and that the article was primarily meant to add to our understanding of katharsis, and did not aim at a full understanding of Nietzsche’s account of Greek tragedy. 8 3. Critical reflection on the text and the discussion Given the emphasis laid by scholars on Wagnerian and Schopenhaurian elements in Nietzsche’s Die Geburt der Tragödie, Most’s approach to this work is an interesting one. The author sheds light on unknown influences, by drawing attention to Nietzsche’s implicit discussion with Bernays and to Nietzsche’s interpretation of Aristotle in Bernaysian terms. The discussion, moreover, revealed that katharsis or ‘Entladung’ in both Nietzsche and Aristotle does not have a single or clear cut meaning. Most’s position, however, remains problematic. What I find most striking is the difference between the author’s defense of the text on the one hand, and the view expressed in the text itself on the other. To put it more critically: the author avoided some of the critical questions by adopting a different position. As has already been noted, Nietzsche uses ‘Entladung’ in different ways, of which at least two are crucial here. When he uses ‘Entladung’ to express his own view, the term mainly has to do with the creative side of tragedy. Music drives to an overflowing abundance of Dionysian energies into Apollonian images. Nietzsche sees this process of overflowing as the expression of a fullness of life, which enjoys life even in its absurd and painful aspects. This fullness is associated with health. In the Bernaysian-Aristotelian view on katharsis or ‘Entladung’ in Greek tragedy the focus lies on the reception of tragedy, which is then performed in order to get rid of unhealthy emotions. Now, while defending his article Most said only to shed light on the facts that Nietzsche understood Aristotle in Bernaysian terms, and that Nietzsche used a word developed by Bernays in order to express his own view on Greek tragedy. As I will argue below, Most tried to make a much stronger claim in his article. Besides, the fact that Nietzsche adopted a word from Bernays in order to express his own view on Greek tragedy may not be as interesting as Most suggests. Why would we trace the words used by Nietzsche back to their origins, if this does not reveal anything about the meaning of these words in Nietzsche’s text? Nietzsche’s adoption of a word is only interesting if it either carries some conceptual content with it (in which case the analysis reveals strong conceptual similarities), or implies an important shift of meaning brought about by Nietzsche (in which case the relevant analysis reveals important dissimilarities). During the discussion Most admitted that the similarities are minimal, while still focusing on these minimal similarities. Most states that the article has originally been written in order to add to our understanding of katharsis as such. But then it remains equally unclear why so little attention is paid 9 to dissimilarities. Besides, as the title clearly suggests, the article turned out to be an article on the meaning of Nietzsche’s text. The author, however, does argue (in his article at least) that there is an important Bernaysian-Aristotelian conceptual framework at work in Nietzsche’s use of ‘Entladung’. According to the article, Nietzsche’s refutation of Aristotle did not merely make use of a ‘word’ derived from Bernays, nor did Nietzsche solely interpret Aristotle in Bernaysian terms. Rather, Nietzsche partly adopted the conceptual framework which he sought to reject (or rather, which he sought to replace). ‘Gegen wen kämpft Nietzsche eigentlich in diesen vielen Äußerungen zu Katharsis und Aristoteles? Gegen Aristoteles selbst?’ (55) At first this remains unclear. Nietzsche often adopts a polemical tone against Aristotle, but he takes Aristotle in the Nachlass more seriously according to Most. Why? Because Nietzsche argues that ‘die Notwendigkeit der Entladung, der Katharsis, ein Grundgesetz des griechischen Wesens ist’. (57) So, while using the term ‘Entladung’ Nietzsche takes Aristotle seriously, that is, partly works within an Aristotelian framework. Most does mention several important dissimilarities between Aristotle’s and Nietzsche’s view, but these do not receive the main attention. Moreover, Nietzsche’s critique of Aristotle, which suggests strong dissimilarities, is described as ‘bisweilen oberflächlich und manchmal etwas simple.’ Most argues, on the other hand, that we find in Nietzsche ‘einen zwar verschwiegenen aber dennoch durchaus aktiven, ja sogar virulenten Aristotelismus.’ (59) And again, one of the main arguments for this view concerns ‘Spuren des aristotelischen katharsis-Begriffs in der Interpretation Jacob Bernays’. Der Beweis liegt in Nietzsches merkwürdig auffälliger und häufiger Verwendung des Wortes ‘Entladung’ als deutende Übersetzung für den aristotelischen Terminus katharsis.’ (60). Most quotes several passages of Nietzsche’s works, and argues not only that Nietzsche uses the word ‘Entladung’, ‘sondern auch, daß dabei die ganze Begrifflichkeit der aristotelischen Katharsis mit im Spiel ist.’ (61) In a concluding remark, Most states that the ‘Grundidee von Nietzsches Buch nur aus Bernays’ Begriff der ‘Entladung’ heraus entstehen konnte und erst vor dessen Hintergrund voll verständlich wird.’ (62) So, the author clearly argues for a strong conceptual similarity between Nietzsche and (the Bernaysian) Aristotle. The whole point of the article seems to be that, though Nietzsche seems both to ignore and to replace Aristotle’s view, and refuses to use the word katharsis in GT, he does make use of the Bernaysian-Aristotelian framework, because of his use of the word ‘Entladung’ (as a translation of Aristotelian 10 katharsis). The questions mentioned above tend to undermine such a position. Secondly, one cannot measure the influence of Bernays on Nietzsche’s use of ‘Entladung’ in isolation of other influences, as Most suggests. One cannot simply add one more ingredient to our understanding of Nietzsche, without considering how other ingredients determine its scope. Most argues that the Aristotelian framework is to some extent at work in Nietzsche’s work, because Nietzsche derived the word ‘Entladung’ as a translation of katharsis from Bernays. If Nietzsche, in contrast, derived the word from Schopenhauer or Wagner this does not follow. Even the weak similarities Most defended during the discussion (Nietzsche derived a ‘word’ from Bernays) could then be undermined. During the discussion Most stated that ‘Nietzsche might well have read Bernays and interpreted the word in another way, inspired by Schopenhauer.’ Even if Nietzsche originally derived the word from Bernays, what this means depends on the way Schopenhauer influenced Nietzsche in using the word. Thirdly, Most said he is only suspicious about how texts come about generally. However, in the article, Most does seem to argue that Nietzsche deliberately hides his Aristotelian perspective. He takes Aristotle more seriously in his unpublished works. Moreover, Most writes: ‘Denn man verdrängt nur, was einem wichtig ist, und je mehr man die Geburt der Tragödie studiert, desto mehr entdeckt man in dieser Abhandlung einen zwar verschwiegenen, aber dennoch durchaus aktiven, ja sogar virulenten Aristotelismus.’ (59) It is not altogether clear in what sense Nietzsche suppresses Aristotle in his work, but he does suppress him, and not only ‘im psychoanalytischen, metaphorsichen Sinne’. (58) Aristotle’s absence in Nietzsche’s writing, then, is the result of an act of concealment, and this act does not seem to be performed wholly unconsciously. Most offered an original approach to Nietzsche’s text and many interesting insights in the problem of katharsis in general. However, it remains unclear what precisely Nietzsche owes to Bernays or Aristotle, and how exactly Nietzsche’s critique of Aristotelian katharsis relates to his own view on Greek tragedy and his use of the word ‘Entladung’. In order to fully address Nietzsche’s relationship to Bernays’, according to Most, two things have to be done: to show that the text could not have been written without Bernays, and to reveal the differences between them. But these issues cannot be considered separately. Or rather, the question to what extent Bernays enabled Nietzsche to develop his own analysis of Greek tragedy involves the question to what extent he did not, that is, to what extent the two frameworks differ. 11