Generalism and Particularism: Are the Folk Particularists? Jen Wright Generalism and particularism are seen as competing theoretical approaches to ethics.1 Roughly speaking, generalism holds that the identification of general moral truths that are capturable in the form of moral principles is fundamental to the development of an adequate ethical theory. Particularism, on the other hand, is skeptical about the importance (and even the existence) of such general moral principles.2 Why are particularists skeptical about general moral principles? One driving motivation for this skepticism is the particularist’s commitment to holism. Holism plays a role in particularism in two ways: the particularist considers both the favoring relation of moral reasons3 and the right/wrong-making relation between grounding4 and moral features to be “holistic”: that is, according to particularism, the valence of moral reasons (i.e., counting for, against, or neither) and the rightness/wrongness of moral features is determined by the presence/absence of a wide range of other features in the context in which they arise, and thus, is capable of shifting. It is typically believed that insofar as generalism holds that we can locate favoring and right/wrong making (what I will call the moral status making) relations that are insensitive to contextual factors, it cannot accommodate the full force of holism5: to be a generalist, you likewise have to hold that at some level moral status making relations are atomistic (i.e., you have to hold that, at 1 The generalism/particularism debate is currently raging on many fronts. See, just as examples, Asher & Bonevac (1997), Audi (2004), Dancy (1993, 2004), Dreyfus & Dreyfus (1991), Hooker and Little (2000), Little (2001), McDowell (1998), McKeever & Ridge (2005), Shafer Landau (1997), Stratton-Lake (2000), Väyrynen (2004), Varela (1999). 2 This is admittedly a bit of a gloss on the debate: there are many different versions of particularism and generalism presented in the literature (see, for example, McKeever & Ridge’s, 2006 discussion of different versions, ch.1). 3 And, indeed, reasons generally. 4 Grounding features can be either non-moral or moral. 5 Most particularists and generalists agree with this point. However, there are some generalists (e.g., McKeever and Ridge, 2006) that argue that generalism can accommodate holism (so long as it is a codifiable form of holism). some level, reasons and grounding features “carry their particular valence around from place to place”6). Consider the following moral principle: “lying is wrong”.7 Clearly, there are exceptions to this (for example, when lying saves someone’s life). Generalists typically deal with such exceptions in one of two ways: they either accommodate the exceptions into the principle itself by generating qualified principles (e.g., “lying is wrong except when it saves lives”) or they stipulate that it is a prima-facie (or pro-tanto) principle that simply fails to generate an actual duty (or an all-things-considered reason against acting) in these sorts of circumstances. Both of these approaches share the view that the valence (that is, the “wrongness”) of lying is invariant: it’s just that either the grounding feature that gives rise to the wrongness has been restricted (“lying-other-than-to-save-lives”) or the wrongness has been overridden by other considerations. Particularists would say, on the other hand, that in cases such as these, lying is no longer wrong. In these cases its valence has shifted, thereby making it right, as well as making it a reason for (rather than a reason against) action. I. Empirical Studies There are many thorny philosophical issues surrounding this debate – many of which I have tried to grapple with elsewhere – but for the purposes of the current project, I will leave more or less aside. My goal here is actually quite modest: I simply want to explore empirically whether people’s judgments tend to look more holistic or atomistic (so, really I should have titled my paper “Are the Folk Holists?” but it didn’t seem as catchy). The studies that I will report here 6 Dancy (2004), p. 7. As I state elsewhere, I take moral principles to be propositions that (i) are (necessarily) true, (ii) contain both (what we might call) grounding and moral concepts, (iii) are normative (i.e., they entail certain prescriptive imperatives – e.g., “tell the truth”) (iv) are (robustly) generalizable, (v) are theory-grounded (i.e., non-arbitrary), and (vi) are specified (or specifiable) in advance (i.e., not ad hoc). 7 represent very preliminary and exploratory attempts to begin an investigation into this question. Investigating this question will hopefully be the first step in a much longer project to empirically explore whether people tend more towards generalism or particularism in their thinking in the moral domain. I started my research off by presenting participants (n = 117; 46 males) with the following set of scenarios (which were counterbalanced in their presentation), all of which involve the morally relevant grounding feature of lying: Bob and Joe are roommates. Bob asks Joe if he has seen his new iPod. Joe did recently see it under a pile of papers on the bookshelf. But Joe lies to Bob, telling him that he hasn’t seen it. He thinks that if Bob doesn’t find it on his own in a day or two, he can take it down to the pawn shop and get $50 for it. Suzy is three years old. On Christmas morning, Suzy is opening her Christmas presents from “Santa Claus”. Suzy remembers hearing some older children talking at pre-school earlier in the week, saying that Santa Claus isn’t real. Suzy turns to her parents and asks them “Did Santa Claus really bring me these presents?”. Her parents lie to her, assuring her that yes, Santa Claus did bring them to her – from the North Pole on his sleigh. Hilda hides her Jewish neighbors in her basement during the Nazi occupation of France. A German soldier comes to her door one afternoon and asks her if she knows where her neighbors have gone. Hilda lies to the soldier, telling them no, she hasn’t seen them recently, but she believes that they left the country to visit family. Participants were asked the following questions on 0 (positive) -8 (negative) Likert scales: Whether lying in each situation was “good, bad, or neither good nor bad”. Whether lying in each situation was “the right thing to do, the wrong thing to do, or neither right nor wrong”. Whether the person who lied in each situation was “praiseworthy, blameworthy, or neither praiseworthy nor blameworthy” for lying. Even though it is reasonable to expect participants’ all-things-considered answer to the question “Should x lie?” to differ between the scenarios regardless of whether they are atomists or holists, nonetheless atomism and holism would suggest different sorts of answers to the above questions. Specifically, as atomists we should expect the valence of lying for each of the answers to be consistent across the different scenarios. As holists, we should expect quite the opposite: we should see a clear valence shift (from negative to neutral to positive) across the scenarios. What I found was as follows: JOE lying good/ bad JOE lying right/ wrong JOE praise/ blame for lying SUZY PARENTS lying good/ bad SUZY PARENTS lying right/ wrong 7.49 7.53 7.40 3.39 3.45 Table 1. Means for each question in LYING scenarios. SUZY PARENTS praise/ blame for lying 3.74 HILDA lying good/ bad 0.66 HILDA lying right/ wrong 0.63 HILDA praise/ blame for lying 0.78 Participants’ answers clearly differed with respect to the reported valence of lying’s badness and wrongness, as well as on the blameworthiness of the person who lied across the different scenarios. Joe’s lying was viewed as very bad, very much the wrong thing to do, and Joe was judged to be very blameworthy for doing so; Hilda’s lying was viewed as very good, very much the right thing to do, and Hilda was judged to be very praiseworthy for doing so; the lying of Suzy’s parents was viewed as more or less neutral (neither good/bad, nor right/wrong) and Suzy’s parents were judged to be neither blameworthy nor praiseworthy for doing so. This difference in judgments between scenarios was quite strong – indeed, the changes in judgment based on changes in the vignettes explained 91% of the variance in participants’ answers. When the means were compared with paired-sample t-tests, the analyses showed significant differences for each question across the scenarios. In other words, the means for the Joe case were significantly higher than the means for the Suzy case and the means for the Suzy case were significantly higher than the means for the Hilda case. Paired sample comparisons JOE lying G/B - SUZY lying G/B SUZY lying G/B - HILDA lying G/B JOE lying R/W - SUZY lying R/W SUZY lying R/W - HILDA R/lying W JOE P/B for lying - SUZY P/B for lying SUZY P/B for lying - HILDA P/B for lying Table 2. Paired sample t-tests for LYING scenarios. t value (df 116) 23.11 13.71 23.33 14.13 23.89 17.42 p value 0.00 0.00 0.00 0.00 0.00 0.00 In summary, there is a significant shift in the reported valence of the grounding feature (lying) between the Joe case, in which it was reported to be bad, wrong, and the liar found blameworthy, the Suzy case, in which it was reported to be morally neutral, and the Hilda case, in which it was reported to be morally good, right, and the liar found praiseworthy. Of course, it could be that this particular morally relevant grounding feature (lying) was not the best feature to test: perhaps lying is not the sort of feature we should consider to be invariant. To look at this, I employed a much more classic example of an invariant grounding feature: namely, promise keeping. Promise keeping is considered to be a perfect duty by Kant and a primary prima facie duty by Ross, so one would think that it should not be subject to any valence shifting. To examine this, I gave participants (n = 71; 24 male) the following scenarios (which, once again, were counterbalanced in their presentation): Stan promises his girlfriend that he will meet her for lunch at 12pm on Wednesday at their favorite café. Wednesday at 11:45am, on his way to the café, Stan runs into his friend, who is on his way to a baseball game. He has an extra ticket, and invites Stan to join him. Stan decides to go with his friend to the game, even though he knows that doing so means that he will be breaking his promise to have lunch with his girlfriend. Pam promises her son that she will be back in 5 minutes: she is just going into the grocery store to buy a gallon of milk. Pam enters the store and heads for the milk aisle. After grabbing a gallon, she walks to the register. The lines are much longer than she expected. She guesses that she will probably have to wait in line for about 10 minutes. Pam decides to wait in line to purchase the milk, even though he knows that doing so means that she will be breaking her promise to be back in 5 minutes. Fred promises his girlfriend that he will meet her for lunch at 12pm on Wednesday at their favorite café. Wednesday at 11:45am, on his way to the café, Fred runs into his grandfather, who is out for a stroll. They exchange hellos, and then suddenly Fred’s grandfather clutches his chest and falls to the ground unconscious. An ambulance arrives minutes later to take Fred’s grandfather to the hospital. Fred accompanies his grandfather to the hospital, even though he knows that doing so means that he will be breaking his promise to have lunch with his girlfriend. Participants were asked the following questions on 0 (negative) -8 (positive) Likert scales: : Whether the breaking of a promise in each situation was “good, bad, or neither good nor bad”. Whether the breaking of a promise in each situation was “the right thing to do, the wrong thing to do, or neither right nor wrong”. Whether the person who broke the promise in each situation was “praiseworthy, blameworthy, or neither praiseworthy nor blameworthy” for breaking a promise. The results were as follows: STAN break promise good/ bad STAN break promise right/ wrong STAN praise/ blame for break promise PAM break promise good/ bad PAM break promise right/ wrong PAM praise/ blame for break promise 6.99 7.23 6.94 3.75 3.58 3.99 Table 3. Means for each question in PROMISE KEEPING scenarios. FRED break promise good/ bad FRED break promise right/ wrong FRED praise/ blame for break promise 1.04 0.65 1.08 Once again, participants’ answers clearly differed with respect to the valence of the promise breaking’s badness, wrongness, as well as the blameworthiness of the person who broke his/her promise across these different scenarios. Stan’s promise breaking was viewed as bad, the wrong thing to do, and Stan was judged to be blameworthy for breaking his promise; Fred’s promise breaking was viewed as good, the right thing to do, and Fred was judged to be praiseworthy for breaking his promise; Pam’s promise breaking was viewed as morally neutral and Pam was viewed as neither blameworthy nor praiseworthy for breaking her promise. The difference in judgments was again quite strong – this time the change in judgments based on changes in the vignettes explained 82% of the variance in participants’ answers. And paired sample t-tests revealed, once again, that the means were significantly different for each question across scenarios. In other words, the means for the Fred case were significantly higher than the means for the Pam case and the means for the Pam case were significantly higher than the means for the Stan case. Paired sample comparison STAN break prom G/B - PAM break prom G/B PAM break prom G/B - FRED break prom G/B STAN break prom R/W - PAM break prom R/W PAM break prom R/W - FRED break prom R/W STAN P/B for break prom - PAM P/B for break prom PAM P/B for break prom - FRED P/B for break prom Table 4. Paired sample t-tests for PROMISE KEEPING scenarios. t value (df 70) 19.38 15.42 17.33 13.48 16.44 14.83 p value 0.00 0.00 0.00 0.00 0.00 0.00 So, once again, there was a significant shift in the reported valence of the morally relevant grounding feature (this time, promise keeping) between the Stan case, in which it was reported to be bad, wrong, and the promise breaker found blameworthy, the Pam case, in which it was reported to be morally neutral, and the Fred case, in which it was reported to be morally good, right, and the promise breaker found praiseworthy. The purpose of these studies was to explore not whether people’s all-things-considered judgments vary from scenario to scenario, but rather whether people judge the valence of a particular morally relevant grounding feature involved in the all-things-considered moral status to be variant or invariant – that is, whether or not people judge the valence of one morally relevant grounding feature to shift depending on the other sorts of features that are present. One worry for these studies that might therefore arise is that since participants were not given an opportunity to express their all-things-considered judgment, what looks like valence-shifting may really be just a reflection of just such a judgment. One way to address this worry would be to give participants the chance to answer questions not only about the grounding feature of interest, but also about the moral status of the action as a whole. Therefore, another group of participants were given both the LYING and PROMISE KEEPING scenarios, but were asked a new set of questions before being asked the questions for each scenario already considered above. For example, participants (n = 61; gender not collected) were asked (on 1-7 Likert scales) whether Joe’s plan to sell Bob’s iPod: was good, bad, or neither good nor bad was the right thing to do, the wrong thing to do, or neither right nor wrong As well as whether, for planning to sell Bob’s iPod, Joe: was praiseworthy, blameworthy, or neither praiseworthy nor blameworthy should feel good, bad, or neither good nor bad (new question added) In addition, participants were asked the same set of questions about: Suzy’s parents telling Suzy that Santa brought the presents Hilda’s protecting her neighbors Stan’s going to a game with a friend Pam’s taking 10 minutes to purchase the milk Fred’s accompanying his grandfather to the hospital Not only should we expect participants’ answers to reflect some all-things-considered differences, but insofar as participants are being given the opportunity to judge that Hilda did the right thing in protecting her neighbors even if they believe her lying to be invariantly wrong, we should expect the presence of these additional questions to help free participants up express their atomism about the grounding features of interest (should they have any). The results showed the following: JOE plan good/ bad 6.30 STAN game good/ bad 5.71 SUZY PARENTS praise/ blame for story SUZY PARENTS feel good/ bad for story 6.43 6.16 6.23 4.23 4.23 4.07 Table 5a. Means for “all-things-considered” questions for LYING scenarios. 5.71 JOE plan right/ wrong JOE praise/ blame for plan JOE feel good/ bad for plan SUZY PARENTS story good/ bad SUZY PARENTS story right/ wrong HILDA protect good/ bad STAN PAM STAN STAN feel PAM PAM PAM feel game praise/ good/ milk milk praise/ good/ FRED right/ blame bad for good/ right/ blame bad for ambulance wrong for game game bad wrong for milk milk good/ bad 5.75 5.71 5.77 4.08 3.73 3.98 4.15 2.54 Table 5b. Means for “all-things-considered” questions for PROMISE KEEPING scenarios. HILDA praise/ blame for protect HILDA protect right/ wrong 1.93 1.80 FRED ambulance right/ wrong 1.67 2.02 FRED praise/ blame for ambulance 2.37 What we find, not surprisingly, is that participants’ all-things-considered judgments in the LYING scenarios were context sensitive. Joe’s plan to sell Bob’s iPod was very bad, very much the wrong thing to do, Joe was very blameworthy and should feel very bad for doing it; Suzy’s parents telling her a story about Santa was generally morally neutral (with the exception that participants judged that Suzy’s parents should feel bad about telling her the story); Hilda’s protecting of her neighbors was considered good, the right thing to do, and Hilda was praiseworthy and should feel good for doing it. And we find the same general trend for the PROMISE BREAKING scenarios: Stan’s going to the game with a friend was very bad, very much the wrong thing to do, and Stan was very blameworthy and should feel very bad for doing so; Pam’s standing in line for 10 minutes to buy milk was judged to be morally neutral; Fred’s riding in the ambulance with his grandfather was considered good, the right thing to do, and Fred was praiseworthy and should feel good about doing so. Paired sample t-tests revealed the means for each same questions across scenarios to be significantly different: ts(55) between 7.6 and 13.0, ps < .001. HILDA feel good/ bad for protect 2.29 FRED feel good/ bad for ambulance 2.63 Given the opportunity to express their all-things-considered judgments about the scenarios, the question of interest is: did participants express a more atomistic view with respect to the moral valence of lying and promise keeping? It appears that they did not: JOE feel JOE JOE JOE good/ SUZY SUZY lying lying praise/ bad PARENTS PARENTS good/ right/ blame about lying lying right/ bad wrong for lying lying good/ bad wrong 6.38 6.41 6.04 6.23 4.32 4.09 Table 6a. Means for questions in LYING scenarios. SUZY PARENTS praise/ blame for lying 4.02 STAN STAN STAN STAN feel PAM PAM PAM break break praise/ good/ break break praise/ promise promise blame bad promise promise blame good/ right/ for break about good/ right/ for break bad wrong promise promise bad wrong promise 5.65 5.77 5.69 5.67 4.04 3.71 3.92 Table 6b. Means for questions in PROMISE KEEPING scenarios. SUZY PARENTS feel good/ bad about lying 4.07 PAM feel good/ bad about promise 4.17 HILDA lying good/ bad 2.02 FRED break promise good/ bad 2.50 HILDA lying right/ wrong 1.64 FRED break promise right/ wrong 1.92 HILDA praise/ blame for lying 1.96 HILDA feel good/ bad about lying 2.36 FRED praise/ blame for break promise 2.46 FRED feel good/ bad about promise 2.83 Again, lying and promise keeping were judged to change valence in several different respects across the scenarios – this time with an additional question about how the person who lied or broke a promise should feel about doing so. There was no difference between the valenceshifting of the all-things-considered questions and the moral feature questions (p = .88). 80% of the change in participants’ judgments was explained by the change in vignettes and paired sample t-tests revealed that the means for each question across the scenarios were once again significantly different: ts(55) between 6.1 and 13.7, ps < .001. (Note: Though the means may look a bit lower than those presented above, this is largely because the Likert scale used here was 1-7 instead of 0-8). The changes in the means seen above appear to support a sort of holism in the moralstatus-making relation of moral features. To get more directly at the holism of the favoring relation of reasons, participants in this group were also asked one final question at the end of each of the scenarios: they were asked whether or not the fact that the action in the scenario (e.g., planning to sell an iPod, protecting one’s neighbors, going to a game with a friend, etc.) involved lying or promise breaking counted as a reason for, against, or neither for nor against engaging in the action (1-7 Likert scale with 1 = strongly for; 7 = strongly against). The results were: BOB SUZY HILDA STAN REASON REASON REASON REASON 4.90 4.14 3.55 5.52 Table 7. Means for reasons question. PAM REASON 4.21 FRED REASON 3.83 Participants reported that the fact that it involved lying counted significantly more against Bob’s planning to sell iPod and significantly more for Hilda’s protecting her neighbors than Suzy parents’ telling Suzy that Santa brought the presents (which was reported as neutral). Likewise, participants reported that the fact that it involved promise breaking counted significantly more against Stan’s going to the game with his friend and significantly more for Fred’s going to the hospital with his grandfather than Pam’s standing in line for 10 minutes to buy milk. So, even here, when directly asked about the valence of reasons, participants’ answers suggest a holistic view. t value Paired sample comparison (df 55) p value JOEREAS – SUZYREAS 3.84 0.00 SUZYREAS – HILDREAS 3.35 0.00 STANREAS – PAMREAS 6.39 0.00 PAMREAS – FREDREAS 2.93 0.01 Table 8. Paired sample t-tests for reasons question. II. Generalist Response What sort of response to these data might the generalist have? If their objective is to come to the defense of atomism, then it seems to me there are two main potential responses: First, the generalist could maintain a pro-tanto principles position (namely, that the wrongness of the moral feature remains, but is overridden) and try to explain away the fact the findings reported here are in definite tension with this view. Second, and more interestingly, the generalist could reply that the reason that we get different sorts of judgments about lying and promise breaking across the different scenarios is because people are actually applying different invariant qualified principles. In the LYING cases, these would be something like “lying-to-profit-oneself is wrong”, “lying-in-socially-acceptable-circumstances is morally neutral”, and “lying-to-savelives is right”. The principles, then, identify three distinct grounding features (that is, three distinct types of lying), which each have a different invariant moral status. This seems like a reasonable explanation: thus the generalist can explain what looked like valence-shifting in the data I have presented while remaining true to (a more nuanced form of) atomism. Yet, the generalist is not home free. For even with these revised grounding features we may be able to demonstrate valence shifting. Consider, for example, the following three scenarios: Hilda hides her Jewish neighbors in her basement during the Nazi occupation of France. A German soldier comes to her door one afternoon and asks her if she knows where her neighbors have gone. Hilda lies to the soldier, telling them no, she hasn’t seen them recently, but she believes that they fled the country. Hilda hides her Jewish neighbors in her basement during the Nazi occupation of France. A German soldier comes to her door one afternoon and asks her if she knows where her neighbors have gone. They are wanted by the Germans for bombing a German-only schoolyard and injuring a number of German children. Hilda lies to the soldier, telling them no, she hasn’t seen them recently, but she believes that they fled the country. Hilda hides her Jewish neighbors in her basement during the Nazi occupation of France. A German soldier comes to her door one afternoon and asks her if she knows where her neighbors have gone. They are wanted by the Germans for bombing a German-only schoolyard and injuring a number of German children after the Germans had bombed one of the local synagogues, killing and injuring local men, women, and children. Hilda lies to the soldier, telling them no, she hasn’t seen them recently, but she believes that they fled the country. Let’s assume that the grounding feature we are working with now is lying-to-save-lives. If the generalist explanation given above is correct, then we should expect to see invariance with respect to this particular grounding feature. Yet, when I gave this series of vignettes to a group of participants (n = 34; 14 males), along with the same set of question as before (both all-thingsconsidered about Hilda protecting her neighbors and then questions specific to lying), this is what I found: Protecting Protecting Feel guilt Protecting right/ praise/ for good/bad wrong blame protecting HILDA1 6.59 6.81 6.89 7.04 HILDA2 2.96 3.07 3.19 3.33 HILDA3 4.56 4.67 4.63 4.63 Table 9. Means for expanded HILDA LYING scenarios. Lie good/bad 5.89 3.00 4.30 Lie right/ wrong 6.37 3.00 4.33 Lie praise/ blame 6.26 3.22 4.41 Feel guilt for lying 6.96 3.41 4.52 Lying reason for/ against 5.44 2.78 4.00 Participants viewed Hilda’s lying-to-save-lives in the first scenario as good, very right, and Hilda as very praiseworthy for doing so. They also felt that Hilda should feel not-at-allguilty for having lied. When the neighbors whose lives Hilda is saving are implicated in a bombing that injured German children, however, suddenly participants judged her lying-to-savelives to be somewhat bad, wrong, and Hilda somewhat blameworthy for doing so. In addition, they judged that she ought to feel somewhat guilty for doing so. Finally, when the neighbors whose lives Hilda is saving are implicated in a bombing that injured German children that was in retaliation for previous bombing that had killed Jewish citizens, participants judged her lying-tosave-lives as somewhat good and right again, as well as Hilda somewhat praiseworthy for doing so. They also judged that Hilda ought to feel somewhat not guilty for doing so. Finally, when it came to whether or not the fact that it involved lying-to-save-lives counted as a reason for, against, or neither Hilda’s protecting her neighbors, in the first scenario it counted significantly more for her action, in the second scenario it counted more against her action, and in the third scenario it was considered to be neutral. The effect that the different vignettes had on participants’ judgments was once again quite robust, accounting for 65% of the variance in their judgments. Paired-sample t-tests show that the means for each of the questions were significantly different across scenarios. t value (df Paired Sample Comparison 33) p value H1ProtectG/B - H3ProtectG/B 6.19 0.00 H2ProtectG/B - H3ProtectG/B -3.91 0.00 H1ProtectR/W - H3ProtectR/W 6.29 0.00 H2ProtectR/W - H3ProtectR/W -3.92 0.00 H1ProtectP/B - H3ProtectP/B 8.24 0.00 H2ProtectP/B - H3ProtectP/B -3.05 0.00 H1ProtGUILT - H3ProtGUILT 6.19 0.00 H2ProtGUILT - H3ProtGUILT -2.92 0.01 H1LieG/B - H3LieG/B 4.32 0.00 H2LieG/B - H3LieG/B -3.45 0.00 H1LieR/W - H3LieR/W 6.62 0.00 H2LieR/W - H3LieR/W -3.16 0.00 H1LieP/B - H3LieP/B 6.12 0.00 H2LieP/B - H3LieP/B -2.54 0.02 H1LieGUILT - H3LieGUILT 6.09 0.00 H2LieGUILT - H3LieGUILT -2.33 0.03 H1Reason - H3Reason 3.89 0.00 H2Reason - H3Reason -4.16 0.00 Table 10. Paired sample t-tests for expanding HILDA LYING scenarios. (Note: I also did a variation on the Joe “lying-to-profit-oneself” question that showed some interesting variance, but I don’t have time to go over that here.) So, it seems that the generalist would have to accommodate yet additional variance in order to get to their invariant moral principles (such as “lying-to-save-lives-implicated-inharming-innocents is wrong” and “lying-to-save-lives--been-implicated-in-harming-innocentsin-retaliation-for-the-harming-of-other-innocents is right”…or something along those lines”). And this strikes me as an undesirable approach – it seems a high cost to pay for moral principles. In addition, it strikes me as problematic for another reason: namely, that in order to take this route the generalist would have to provide justification for why the grounding feature of lying can be legitimately broken down into these distinct grounding features in the first place. That is, the generalist would have to identify what the relevant differences between each of the instances of lying are that warrants them being treated as distinct grounding features, each with their own invariant moral valence, rather than as just one grounding feature with variable moral valence. My suspicion is that the only real difference between them is going to be that of their moral relevance. But then, if this is the case, then I fail to see what reason the generalist has given us to adopt the former, rather than the latter view. One other response that may be open to the generalist is to embrace holism, but to argue that morality is still context-insensitive enough to make general moral principles possible.8 Whether or not this approach can be made to work in the end is hard to say – but even if it did, I’d say the generalist would be giving up a lot of ground in doing so. And I worry about exactly what sort of explanatory role such principles would ultimately be able to play. IV. Conclusion What sort of conclusion can we draw from the findings reported above? I’d say at this juncture, any conclusions we draw must be extremely modest. Nonetheless, the data presented here do suggest that a case could be made for valence shifting in people’s moral judgments about certain grounding features (lying and promise breaking). Importantly, people are not only not reporting the valence for these grounding features to be fixed and/or overridden, they are, more strongly, reporting that the same grounding features are both morally good and right in some contexts while morally bad and wrong in others. Does this count as definitive evidence for holism in the folk? No, not really. Alternative explanations are clearly possible and need to be considered. In addition, more experimental research exploring the various issues needs to be conducted. But, nonetheless, I think the studies I’ve reported represent a humble start in the right direction. 8 This is the approach taken by McKeever & Ridge (2005).