Three Kinds of Rhetoric The Three Basic Issues From Thank You for Arguing, by Jay Heinrichs Before you begin arguing, ask yourself the question: What’s the issue? According to Aristotle, all issues boil down to just three (the Greek were crazy about that number): Blame Values Choice You can slot any kind of issue involving persuasion into one of these categories. Who moved my cheese? This, of course, is a blame issue. Whodunit? Should abortion be legal? Values. What’s morally right or wrong about letting a woman choose whether or not to end the budding life inside her own body? (My choice of words implies the values each side holds—a woman’s right to her own body, and the sanctity of life.) Should we build a plant in Oaxaca? Choice: to build or not to build, Oaxaca or not Oaxaca. Should Brad and Jen have split up? Values—not moral ones, necessarily, but what you and your interlocutor value. Were they just too cute to separate? Did OJ do it? Blame. Shall we dance? Choice: to dance or not to dance. Why should you care which question slots into which core issue? It matters because you will never meet your goals if you argue around the wrong core issue. Watch a couple as they in their living room, reading books and listening to music. She: Can you turn that down a little? He: You’re the one who set the volume last. She: Oh, really? Then who was it blasting “Free Bird” all over the place this afternoon? He: So that’s what this is about. You hate my music. What does she want out of this argument? Quiet. It’s a choice issue. She wants him to choose to turn the music down. But instead of choices, the argument turns to deal with blame, then values. Blame: You’re the one who set the volume last. Values: So that’s what this is about. You hate my music. It’s hard to make a positive choice about turning the volume knob when your argue about a past noise violation and the existential qualities of “Freebird.” The examples I gave of the core issues—blame, values and choice—show a certain pattern. The blame questions deal with the past. The values questions are in the present tense. And the choice questions have to do with the future. Blame = Past Values = Present Choice = Future If you find an argument spinning out of control, try switching the tense. To pin blame on the cheese thief, use the past tense. To get someone to believe that abortion is a terrible sin, use the present tense. The future, though, is the best tense for getting peace and quiet in the living room. Aristotle, who devised a form of rhetoric for each of the tenses, liked the future best of all. The rhetoric of the past, he said, deals with issues of justice. This is the judicial argument of the courtroom. Aristotle called it forensic rhetoric, because it deals with forensics. Our music-challenged couple uses the past tense for blaming each other. He: You’re the one who set the volume last. She: Then who was it blasting “Free Bird”? If you want to try someone on charges of volume abuse (not to mention bad taste), you’re in the right tense. Forensic argument helps us determine whodunit, not who’s-doing-it or who-will-do-it. Watch “Law and Order,” and you’ll notice that most of the dialogue is in the past tense. It works great for lawyers and cops, but a loving couple should be wary of the tense. The purpose of forensic rhetoric is to determine guilt and mete out punishment; couples who get in the habit of punishing each other usually end up miserable or divorced. How about the present tense? Is that any better? It can be. The rhetoric of the present handles praise and condemnation, separating the good from the bad, distinguishing groups from other groups and individuals from each other. Aristotle reserved the present for describing people who meet a community’s ideals or fail to live up to them. It is the communal language of commencement addresses, funeral orations, and sermons. It celebrates heroes or condemns a common enemy. It gives people a sort of tribal identity. (We’re great, terrorists are cowards). When a leader has trouble confronting the future, you hear similar tribal talk. Aristotle’s term for this kind of language is demonstrative rhetoric, because ancient orators used it to demonstrate their fanciest techniques. Our argumentative couple uses it to divide each other. He: So that’s what this is about. You hate my music. You might say that the man bears sole blame for switching tenses from past to present. But let’s not get all forensic on each other, okay? The man may be right, after all; perhaps the argument has to do with the guy’s thing for Lynyrd Skynyrd and not the volume knob. In any case, their dialogue has suddenly turned tribal: I like my music. You hate it. If the man happened to be a politician he would find it hard to resist adding, “And that’s just wrong!” We use the present tense to talk about values. That is wrong. This is right. Detesting “Free Bird” is morally wrong. If you want to make a joint decision, you need to focus on the future. This is the tense that Aristotle saved for his favorite rhetoric. He called it deliberative, because it argues about choices and helps us decide how to meet our mutual goals. Deliberative argument’s chief topic is “the advantageous,” according to Aristotle. This is the most pragmatic kind of rhetoric. It skips right and wrong, good and bad, in favor of expedience. Present-tense (demonstrative) rhetoric tends to finish with people bonding or separating. Past-tense (forensic) rhetoric threatens punishment. Future-tense (deliberative) argument promises a payoff. You can see why Aristotle dedicated the rhetoric of decision-making to the future. Our poor couple remains stranded in the present tense, so let’s rewind their dialogue and make them speak deliberatively—in the future tense, that is. She: Can you turn that down a little? He: Sure, I’d be happy to. Wait. Shouldn’t he say “I’ll be happy to”? I will, not I would? Well, sure, you’re probably right. He could. But by using the conditional voice—would instead of will—he leaves himself an opening. He: But is the music too loud, or do you want me to play something else? She: Well, now that you mention it, I’d prefer something a little less hair-bandy. Ouch! He plays nice, and she insults the entire classic rock genre. That makes him feel justified to retaliate; but he does it moderately. He: Something more elevatorish, you mean? That doesn’t really turn me on. Want to watch a movie? By turning the argument back to choices, the man keeps it from getting too personal—and, possibly, keeps her off balance, making her a bit more vulnerable to persuasion. She: What do you have in mind? He: We haven’t seen “Terminator 2” in ages. She: “Terminator 2?!” I hate that movie. As he well knows. This is a little off topic, but I can’t resist giving you another rhetorical trick: propose an extreme choice first. It will make the one you want sound more reasonable. I used the technique myself in getting my wife to agree to name our son after my uncle George. I proposed lots of alternatives—my personal favorite was Herman Melville Heinrichs—until she finally said, “You know, ‘George’ doesn’t really sound that bad.” I kissed her and told her how much I loved her, and notched another argument on my belt. Back to our couple. He: Well, then, how about “Lawrence of Arabia”? He knows she would prefer a different movie—the desert just isn’t her thing— but it doesn’t sound that bad after hearing the first choice. She: Okay. “Lawrence” it is. Which happens to be the movie he wanted in the first place. Three Kinds of Rhetoric / Aristotle The Greek word for topic, "topos," literally mean "a place." In rhetoric, a topics are those places where a speaker can look for the available means to persuade his audience (Kennedy 45). Having stated that there are three different genres of rhetoric, Aristotle now proceeds to describe those topics in each of the different kinds of rhetoric that will be of use to the speaker. rhetoric dialectic topi special topi common topi The study of speaking and writing persuasively. Contains the study of both what is communicated and how communication takes place. (“R” means the study of classical rhetoric; “r” means the study of rhetoric more broadly) Distinct from rhetoric (yet sometimes considered a companion to rhetoric), dialectic is logical (syllogistic) argumentation concerned with reason to approach probable truths. Audience or context is not a consideration in dialectic argumentation. Logical appeals can be invented/composed by using rational arguments that fit within known topics (topi). The topics of invention have basic categories of relationships of ideas. Topi service as a heuristic for discovering things to say and how they can be said about a subject. Topi are the “places to find things” to create an argument. Rhetorical arguments fall into one of the three specific (or special) topi which would direct the rhetor to a heuristic for developing a special argument. See Silva for a list of special topi. (The three special types of topi are Judicial, Deliberative, and Ceremonial.) Rhetorical arguments might fall into one of these more general (or common) topi which would direct the rhetor to a heuristic for developing a common type of argument. See Silva for a list of common topi. epideictic speech forensic speech deliberative speech One of three principle kinds of classical public speech. Epideictic is ceremonial/demonstrative speech. A eulogy would be an epideictic speech. One of three principle kinds of classical public speech. Forensic is judicial/legal speeches. The purpose of forensic speech was originally for defending or accusing a person. Today, debate is often called forensics picking up on the notion of one team speak for (defending a position) and one team speaking against (accusing of flawed reasoning). One of three principle kinds of classical public speech. Deliberative is political/legislative speech. The primary concern of deliberative speech is to move people toward future action (laws/policies that would affect the future of society). Deliberative rhetoric is argumentation for or against future action. B&H pg. 3; Silva B&H pg 3; Silva B&H pg. 3; Silva Aristotle: 3 types of rhetoric: Blame = Past 1. Forensic --Forensic rhetoric defends or prosecutes in legal proceedings. The forensic process argues for the innocence or guilt of a single person for events of the past. Topics for Forensic Rhetoric (1.10-15) The aim of forensic rhetoric is either accusation (kategoria) or defense (apologia). o To accuse or defend someone, the rhetoric must first have an understanding of the definition of injustice (adikia) o We must understand what injustice is, what its motives are, and what the state of mind is of someone who commits an unjust act. Aristotle defines Injustice as "voluntary illegal harm." (1.10). An act of injustice, therefore, is always: 1. a voluntary act (i.e.,, it is done freely and knowingly) 2. an act that causes harm (i.e.., injury or damage to another's property to person) 3. an act that is illegal (i.e., it is done in violation of the laws of one's country) o o If I want to accuse someone of an act of injustice I must first demonstrate that the act was done voluntarily, that it caused some harm/damage, and that it was in violation of the law. Conversely, if I want to defend someone against a charge of injustice, then I must first prove that either (a) the act was not voluntary (e.g., because the accused was insane at the time he committed the act of injustice), or (b) that it produced no real harm (e.g., consentual S & M), or (c) that the act was not, in fact, illegal (e.g., because it was done in self defense?) There are seven causes of all human action: chance, nature, force, calculation, habit, anger, desire. o Based upon the specific cause of an act, we can determine whether an act has been done voluntarily or involuntarily: Involuntary Acts are those that are due to: 1. chance (no observable cause: e.g., spontaneous brawl at a soccer game) 2. nature (cause is within and determined: e.g., mental illness or retardation) 3. force (against one's own desire: e.g., Patty Hearst) Voluntary acts are those that are due to: 1. 2. 3. 4. calculation (done with deliberation and planning: e.g., first degree murder) habit (done through the repeated performance of an act: e.g., drug use) anger (done out of the desire for revenge: e.g., retaliating against an insult) desire (done for the sake of something pleasant: e.g., rape) Values = Present 2. Epideictic [epi-deck-tick] --Epideictic speeches aim to censure or honor someone or something. The epideictic process praises or censures people or things in the present. Epideictic Speech Topics Examples of speeches with epideictic speech topic elements are praising, blaming or celebrating a birthday, wedding roasts and toasts, eulogies or funeral speeches, farewell addresses, political and Fourth of July orations. All praise or blame the virtues, feelings and values of exceeding boundaries, achieving, justice, overcoming obstacles, condemnation, commendation or mourning. Ten sample specific thesis purposes you can work out: Praise: person Rosa Parks for her act of protest against the segregation on city public transit vehicles which strengthens the America's civil rights movement. group Sessions of meditation groups in order to transmit powerful spiritual energy for the benefit of humanity. idea Praise in public and criticize in private, as Russian empress Catherine II teached. Blame: person Britney Spears for attracting aggressive news paper paparazzi in down town Los Angeles because of her behavior. organization Blame the commercial and investment banks that are responsible for the ongoing financial meltdown. theory The idea of correcting injustices of governments in history, because it will causes modern problems. Celebrate: person Nobel Peace Prize 1983 winner Lech Walesa, the Polish worker from the Gdansk Shipyard who negotiated the transition from communism to democracy. group Wedding ceremony attendees generate feelings of closeness and community. idea Sharing grief is the best recipe for emotional healing. value The best Thanksgiving speech topics praise and welcomes the feeling to be surrounded and supported by close friends at the dinner table. Topics for Epideitic Rhetoric (1.9) The end of epideitic rhetoric is the exhibition of a noble or base subject. We, therefore, need to define what we mean by noble and base. o Aristotle defines the noble as that which is intrinsically good (i.e., good in itself; desired for its own sake) and praiseworthy o Since virtue is intrinsically good, it must be a noble thing. o Therefore, the possession of such virtues as justice, courage, self-control, generosity and prudence makes a man noble. Since justice and courage are among the most praiseworthy of the virtues, the possession of these virtues in particular makes a person even more noble. To put it in simple terms, the possession of virtues makes a person noble in character and worthy of praise, while the possession of vices makes him base and worthy of disapprobation. Amplification of Character: to effectively praise a subject, it is often necessary to amplify his/her qualities. He can do this in either of two ways: 1. magnification of a person's virtues (e.g., moderate courage becomes tremendous courage) 2. transforming vices into virtues (e.g., a stubborn man becomes determined; a drunk becomes a fun-loving guy) Exercise: Aristotle's recommendations on how amplify character are used quite effectively in Anthony's speech in praise of Caesar in Shakespeare's play, Julius Caesar. Keep in mind that in the scene right before this one, Brutus, one of Caesar's murderers, has just convinced the crowd that Caesar was a tyrant and deserved to be assassinated. By the end of his speech Caesar has been declared a villain and Brutus the savior of the Roman Republic. Anthony's task is to persuade his audience that they are completely mistaken about Caesar---that is was in fact a truly swell guy---and that Brutus is the real villain. How does he use amplification of character to achieve this end? Read Anthony's Speech Choice = Future 3. *Deliberative --Deliberative concerns policy-making speeches that affect items in the future. Aristotle elevated the deliberative process above forensic and epideictic. The deliberative process addresses future issues, which have impact on a greater number of people. For example, persuading Corinth to allow Athenian merchants access to a particular trade route would use the deliberative process. Topics for Deliberative Rhetoric (1.4-8) In 1.4 Aristotle observes that it is not necessary for the speaker to have familiarity about every conceivable topic. Things that happen through necessity (e.g., the laws of physics) and what happen at random (matters of good or bad luck) are not subject to debate. The topics that he must familiarize himself with are those in which human action can make some difference (1359b). In deliberative rhetoric these topics are generally of two kinds: Political and ethical. 1. Political Topics (1.4): General Political Topics Sub-Topics revenue source of revenue, expenses of the state war and peace own strength, strength of neighbors, similarities and differences national defense size and deployment of one own military resources trade items that can be produced at home and those that must be imported general legislation different kinds of government, advantages and disadvantages of each Remember Deliberative Rhetoric is concerned about future actions that are either advantageous or disadvantageous. In the political realm, why does the speaker need to have a least some familiarity with the above topics in order to be able to persuade his audience? 2. Ethical Topics (1.5-7): One might ask why we have a discussion of ethics in this section? Aristotle's argument for this move can be stated in the following way: o The end of deliberative rhetoric is what is advantageous. o What is advantageous is what is good for human beings. o Happiness (eudaimonia) is universally recognized as the supreme good for human beings o Therefore we need to understand what happiness is before we can persuade anyone of what is advantageous to them. Aristotle's understanding of happiness can be summed up in the following way: o happiness is nothing more than virtue along with the possession of certain external goods o These external goods include: health, wealth, family, friends, good looks, reputation, comfort in one's old age, etc. Aristotle understands these goods to form a natural hierarchy [with some goods being more excellent than others] o all rational human beings, he believes, would recognize this hierarchy. Therefore, knowing which goods are recognized as superior to others can help you to persuade an audience to follow a particular course of action (1.6-7) Exercise: Many of the topics treated in Aristotle's Rhetoric 1.4-7 are used by Thucydides in his description of a debate that was held in 427 B.C. between Cleon and Diodotus in the Athenian Assembly. The subject of discussion was whether to follow though on a vote that was previously held which called for the execution of all the men of Mytilene for their defiance of Athenian authority. What specific topics do the speakers make use of in their attempt to persuade the members of the Athenian assembly to support their position? Whose arguments do you feel are the more persuasive? Read Thucydides' Text Using the enthymeme (non-rational decisions based on values and opinions held by the audience) and artistic proofs (logos, ethos and pathos) as vehicle, the audience is transported through the substance from the position in time to the conclusion. This is the art of rhetoric that creates persuasion. Aristotle’s idea for rhetoric is that it is mainly used in the public assemblies in order to advance the political, cultural and social goals of the Greek polis, where one can only be a spectator or a judge. Aristotle remarks that rhetoric can be defined “as an ability, in each [particular] case, to see the available means of persuasion.” Aristotle limits rhetoric to the confines of the Greek political assemblies and law courts where a final judgment had to be made. Rhetoric can help settle situations where the probable needs to be converted to a decision (such as whether someone is guilty or not, or whether a particular course of political action needs to be taken); therefore, rhetoric can only work in cases where an underlying truth is capable of being uncovered. In contrast, dialectic is used for arriving at logical decisions in philosophical discussions. In dialectic, judge and spectator are combined because decisions will have to be made in context of an on-going argument in order for the argument to continue. Dialectic’s purpose is given in terms of its qualities in carrying on a conversation in order to advance philosophical truths where no practical outcome is needed. enthymeme example metaphor ethos pathos A syllogistic argument in which the conclusion is based on a “probable” premise; thus, leading to a probable conclusion. Sometimes referred to as “informal” or “truncated” syllogism, the enthymeme was not/is not always considered sound because a premise is implied rather than proven. Specimen or sample. Example is related to the topic of invention. An “example” is used to strengthen a point by a true or contrived example. Metaphor is related to invention and is a comparison that is made by referring to something as another thing. Metaphor is an implied comparison. (Life is like a box of chocolates.) One of three forms of persuasive appeal. Ethos is concerned with the persuasive appeal of one’s character. One’s character can bestow upon one, in the minds/hearts of the audience, the right to make an argument and thus the ability to make an argument. One of the three forms of persuasive appeal. Pathos is concerned with the persuasive appeal to emotion. Emotional appeals, according to classical rhetoricians, can come at the expense of logical (logos) appeals. Thus, pathetic appeals should be used prudently. B&H pg. 4; Silva Silva Silva B&H pg. 4; Silva B&H pg. 4; Silva logos One of the three forms of persuasive appeal. Logos is concerned with the persuasive appeal to reason or logic. Aristotle hoped that all rhetoric could be based on reason alone, but humans were not capable of such “pure” reason. B& H pg. 4; Silva