Simon Amey U4423598 A850/04 What matters in survival? I will argue for Parfit’s view that psychological connectedness is what matters in survival. Psychological connectedness consists of the sharing of mental modes, such as a belief in God, an intention to exercise, or a love of dogs. This radical view opposes both Cartesian Dualism and using the condition of bodily continuity. Dualism’s flaws, such as communication between the substances, are described elsewhere, and I will not revisit them here. To reach Parfit’s conclusion I will first argue for bodily continuity as the condition for survival, then show that that reasoning is flawed. I will describe the difference between psychological continuity and connectedness and show that psychological connectedness can provide a coherent response to two puzzling thought experiments. Finally I will show that it is incompatible with personal identity. Personal identity is the theory that you are identical to the person as you were yesterday, and identical to the person you will be tomorrow. We all hold the relationship of identity to ourselves over time. While this might sound simple enough, identity’s attributes as a one-to-one relationship, an allor-nothing relationship and a transitive relationship means that it leads to paradoxical results when applied to cases more complicated than those met in everyday life. To Parfit’s excellent exposition of this subject, I will only add a thought as to why our intuitions, which authors such as Wiggins place great store on, might be misled: that it is evolutionarily successful for us to care for this body in which we inhabit. Williams presents a very convincing case for the importance of bodily continuity in the following thought experiment. Two people, A and B, enter a body-swapping machine. This machine will record both their brain states, then alter the A-body-brain to be like B, and the B-body-brain to be like A. A and B enter the machine, and when they come out the A-body person acts like and thinks that they are B, and vice versa. While there might be problems if the bodies were radically different, which I will pass over here, it feels as though we would be quite happy to accept that nothing is lost in this exchange, and that the two persons have swapped bodies. But Williams then asks us to consider what it would feel like if you were person A. You would be told that you were going into the machine, which would act in a number of stages: (i) (ii) (iii) (iv) (v) (vi) A is subjected to an operation which produces amnesia; amnesia is produced in A, and other interference leads to certain changes in his character; changes in his character are produced, and at the same time certain illusory ‘memory’ beliefs are induced in him; these are of a quite fictitious kind and do not fit the life of any actual person; the same as (iii), except that both the character traits and the ‘memory’ impressions are designed to be appropriate to another actual person, B; the same as (iv), except that the result is produced by putting information into A from the brain of B, by a method which leaves B the same as before; the same happens to A as in (v), but B is not left the same, since a similar operation is conducted in the reverse direction. Williams, in The Self and the Future pp21 Looking down the gradual changes, it is hard to pin-point where you would stop being you. Williams highlights this by saying that the A body will be tortured after the operation; the question is, who should be worried by that, person A or person B? In Simon Amey U4423598 A850/04 the first, objective description, we might have thought that B should worry, since B was being transferred into A’s body which would then be tortured. But looking at the second, personal description it feels as though you should worry, because you are person A, and even if your mind has been altered, it will still be you being tortured. As Williams points out, if you are to be tortured, it makes no difference if you are also given amnesia before hand. So it seems that our body is necessary survival: the programming of someone else’s brain does not matter at all because they would not be you; and your body is also sufficient for survival: that whatever changes your brain might undergo, you will still in there, caring about what happens to your body. Try to applying the language of identity seems to reach two different conclusions here, depending on the viewpoint we take to the experiment. From the objective view of person A and B going into the machine and having their minds swapped, identity seems to be swapped with them. But considering the machine’s actions occurring on your own mind suggests that even despite the changes to your brain, your identity remains with your body. Williams suggests this means that the body is the better candidate for the condition of identity, and hence of survival. Having put the case for bodily continuity, I will now attack it, before moving on to Parfit’s own thought experiment and the conclusions he draws from it. First, bodily continuity is not nearly so simple as it appears. Our cells are constantly dying and being replaced. After seven years, almost every atom in our body has been lost. In just the same way as Theseus’ ship1, someone could collect up these atoms, and rebuild a model of us. If perfect, this model would be alive, and would have a greater claim to bodily continuity than we do. Clearly, literal, physical continuity is not what is really important. The ongoing, functioning body that we inhabit is what matters, and that is what is meant by bodily continuity. However, the body has lots of functional parts, and they do not all matter for our survival… So, secondly, consider that all not body parts are equal. We can lose a finger and we are still ourselves. We can lose a limb, and we are still ourselves. In fact it seems that we can lose almost all our body, and still be ourselves. The part that really matters must be our brain. And so, and this is still consistent with Williams’ thought experiment, it is the ongoing functional brain that is really important, and that must be the criterion for bodily continuity and survival. But, thirdly, we must consider that the brain is not one simple entity (not once dualism has been rejected). How much of the brain must survive in order that you survive? Is there some special part of the brain that makes you, you? Cases of brain damage indicate that there is not. It seems that the measure of ourselves, like so many things in the world, exists only on a sliding scale. With some brain damage, you might be a very much like yourself, but with a few differences. As the injury increases, so will the difference between ‘you’ before and ‘you’ after. Is there a magic percentage that must be present so that you are still you? Any percentage must be chosen 1 As described by Hobbes, paraphrased here: Theseus sails from Athens to Crete. On the way his ship is constantly falling apart, and by the time he lands every plank has been replaced. A Cretan travels along behind him collecting all his discarded planks, and recreates his ship from them. There are now two ships in Crete, but which is Theseus’ ship? This might be considered conceptually undecidable, as our concept of a ship cannot cope with this sharp division between physical and functional continuity. Simon Amey U4423598 A850/04 arbitrarily, and be a conventional decision rather than shed any conceptual light. So bodily continuity comes down to a debate of percentages of brain mass. The only percentage that could conceivably have a deeper meaning is 50%, but Parfit shows that this case is in fact the strongest argument for a psychological criterion for survival in his thought experiment of division: Our brains consist of into two hemispheres. As a treatment for epilepsy, the links between the hemispheres are sometimes separated. Once they are, under laboratory conditions, two independent consciousnesses can be evinced, each seeing through one eye and controlling one hand. Normally there is a division of labour within the brain, with one hemisphere specialising in mathematical reasoning, and the other dealing with speech, but either hemisphere can learn either skill. Following Parfit, consider the case of a person, P, without any division of labour within their brain, where either hemisphere can take over the complete functioning of the brain2. This brain is divided and one half is transplanted into a waiting body. The other half is thrown away. Has P survived? They are psychological and physically continuous with the person before the operation, and are unchanged in disposition or outlook. By all measures P seems to have survived. But what if the other half of the brain was not thrown away, but was similarly transplanted into another waiting body? Now P seems to have survived as two people, P’s identity has been split. Can we say that only one person exists after the operation? We cannot pick that one person to be one of the bodies, because there is nothing to choose between them. If we say that the left-brain-body is where P survives, this gives us no grounds for saying why the right-brain-body has not survived. Clearly both have survived, or neither. Might we say that P survives in neither body? But when only one half of the brain was transplanted, P had survived. If we say that the dual transplant is not survival, then the left-brain-body should stop the second transplant at all costs, because it will destroy their survival. Clearly that is ludicrous; it breaks the intrinsic requirement that the survival of one person cannot depend on what happens to a second person. To conclude, after the dual transplant, we cannot say that P did not survive, and we cannot say that they survived in only one body. We must conclude that P survived in both bodies. As identity is necessarily a one-to-one relation, this gives no plausible response for what has happened to P’s identity. How can the two different descriptions of Williams’ body-swapping machine and survival in the case of division be reconciled? With a new criterion for survival: psychological connectedness. Psychological connectedness involves holding the same hopes, desires, fears, intentions etc. over time. Each individual is nothing more than the sum of these mental states, and these states are constantly evolving. We can now see why division poses no problems for survival, connectedness can easily split and continue in two bodies. In the first half of Williams’ thought experiment, where A and B walk into the machine and emerge in each other’s bodies, connectedness has been transferred, and survival continues in another body. And we can now draw a line in Williams’ 6 stages of transference where survival stops. At stage 2 your character is altered. There psychological connectedness is broken, there you cease to survive. 2 As well as the hemispheres, there is also a lower part of the brain that is not dual-redundant. For the purposes of this thought experiment, that is ignored. Simon Amey U4423598 A850/04 Psychological connectedness is subtly different from psychological continuity. Continuity is not sufficient for connectedness: consider the strange case of Dr. Jekyll and Mr. Hyde; that although they shared memories and were psychologically continuous, they had completely different outlooks and were not psychologically connected. Nor is continuity necessary for connectedness. Psychological continuity might be broken by amnesia, but the psychological connectedness might remain, with the same intentions and beliefs, even though their formation was not remembered. While psychological continuity is transitive, psychological connectedness is not. You might be strongly connected to yourself five years ago, and youself five years ago might be strongly connected to yourself ten years before that, but it does not follow that you are strongly connected to yourself fifteen years ago. Most importantly, psychological connectedness is not identity. While identity is sufficient for connectedness, connectedness does not imply identity. First, as division shows, connectedness can branch and hold a one-to-many relationship. Since identity is always a one-to-one relationship, this means that identity does not always hold where there is connectedness. Secondly, connectedness is always a matter of degree. You almost perfectly connected with you from yesterday, but there have been some changes. Over the years these changes will be very great. Contrast identity, which is an all or nothing relation. Thirdly, identity is transitive while connectedness, as described above, is not. Connectedness is a much more versatile and enduring condition, that can explain survival in the thought experiments described without contradiction, and with less implausibility than trying to apply the idea of identity. Why might concern for identity, Cartesian Egos, and our bodies be so prevalent? Even while I am writing the logical arguments for what matters in survival, I can barely shake off the belief that I am within this body, that this is what I should take care of, and be damned with psychological connectedness. I believe the start of the answer is evolution. Those creatures who fought for themselves the hardest, who looked after themselves best and who reproduced most were those who harboured the delusion that what mattered to their survival was their body. Wiggins identifies this instinctive drive to protect ourselves as an animal, but fails to question it. Evolution, whether through nature or nurture, should strongly favour that instinct, but that does not make it true, or even valuable. Indeed, from a moral point of view excessive concern with ourselves could be highly damaging. To conclude, the thought experiment of division gives strong evidence that what matters in survival can have a one-to-many relationship, and hence what matters is not identity. Bodily continuity is flawed because it cannot draw a reasonable line in the possible spectrum of degrees of bodily survival, but the condition of psychological connectedness surmounts this by not being an all-or-nothing relation, and saying instead that our survival is always a matter of degree. Therefore psychological connectedness is what matters in survival. Word Count: 2241 Simon Amey U4423598 A850/04 Bibliography: Course Notes, chapter 4. Williams, B., 1973, The Problems of the Self, reproduced in the course notes. Parfit, D., 1971, Personal Identity, reproduced in the course notes. Wiggins, D., 1991, The Concern to Survive, reproduced in the course notes. Parfit, D., 1984, Reasons and Persons, Oxford University Press Broks, P., 2003, Into the Silent Land, Atlantic Books