1 Logic 1.1 Logical vs. Material equivalence: 1.1.1 “Two wffs (statements) are logically equivalent if they necessarily have the same truth-value. The are materially equivalent if they have the same truth-value.” (Susan Haack, philosophy of logics 246). 1.2 Logical truth: “A wff is logically true in L iff it is true in all interpretations of L.” (Haack, p.248) 1.3 Contrary: “Wffs (statements) A and B are contrary if they can’t be both true but may be both false.” (Haack 244). Extension/intension “Reference (extension) versus sense (intension) of an expression. For a singular term, the extension is its reference, for a predicate, the set of things it is true of, for a sentence, its truth-value. Two expressions with the same extension are co0-extensive. Related terminology: Dedeutung (- extenson) versues Sinn (intenson) of an expression (Frege); denotation versus connotation (Mill); extensional versus intentional contexts. (Haack 246). See the same page for a good definition of extensional/intensional contexts. 1.3.1 Richard Kirkham: “The extension of an expression is the object or set of objects referred to, pointed to, or indicated by, the expression…The extension of a predicate is the set of all objects to which the predicate truly applies….The attempt to produce such a noncircular description of the set of all trueh things (the extension of the prediate ‘is true’) is what I shall call the extensional project.” (Kirkam, Theories of Truth, p. 4) 1.3.2 “Imagine someone in the process of learning English. He has learned the meaningof, and hence the extension of, ‘vertebrate with a liver’, but he does not yet know the meaing of ‘vertebrate with a heart’. By informing him tha the extension of ‘vertebrate with a heart’ is identical to the extension of ‘vertebrate with a liver’, we have effectively specified for him the extension of the former. (We shall no, however, have completely explained the meaning of ‘verbrate with a heart’ until we have accounted for the other component of its meaning, its intension.) [This demonstrates that meaning has two components, sense and reference].” Kirkham, 5. 1.3.3 “Put in a very general way, the intension of an expression is the informational content of the expression, as distinct from the set of objects deonted by the expression…the intension of ‘the morning star’ can be worded as ‘the star visible around dawn’, while the intension of the ‘the evening star’ is ‘the star visible around sunset’. But being visible around dawn is not the same things as being visible around sunset, so whle ‘the morning star’ and ‘the evning star’ are extensionally equivalent, they are not intensionally equivalent. They convey different information. And since intension is one component of meaning, the two expressions do not mean the same thing, despite the fact that they both anme the same planet. (9) …¶ One implication of the intensional equivalence of x and y is that we can substitute y for x in any English sentence in which the latter appears without changing the meaning or, hence, the truth value, of the sentence. This principle does not hold good in cases of mere extensional equivalence. [Are ‘heart’ and ‘blood-pumping organ’ intensionally equivalent. I can see one would say no, since the latter focuses the mind on more fine-grained properties of the heart. Certainly, they are extensionally equivalent expressions. Modes of representation may be in play here as well. How is ‘heart’ presenting itself to me, as a blood-pumping organ? No, just a 3-dimensional shape that is red in color.] (Kirkham, Theories of Truth) 1.3.4 George Bealer “Fine-grained type-free intensionality” 1.3.4.1 (178) “An item x is an extensional entity if fit satisfied all relevant principles of extensionality. Principles of extensionality come in two forms. First, let ‘R’ be any copula (‘is’, ‘is an instance of’, ‘is related by’, ‘is a member of’ ‘is a part of’, ‘has’, ‘falls under’, etc.) and let the item x be in the same ontological category as some item in the range of R. Then for all y in the same ontological category as x: (z)(zRx ↔ zRy) x = y. Second, let ‘T’ be any verifier (‘is true’, ‘is so’, ‘obtains’, ‘holds’, ‘happens’, ‘occurs’, etc.) and let the iterm x be in the same category as some item that is an instance of T. Then for all y in the same cateogory as x: (Tx ↔ Ty) x = y. With this definition of extensional entity we may define intensional entity: an item x is intensional if it is not extensional. That is, an item x is intensional if it fails to satisfy one or more of these extensionality principles. 1.4 See p. 247 for definition of material vs. strict implication. 1.5 Oratio Obliqua “Indirect (reported) speech, as ‘s said that p’ (Haack 249). 1.6 Port Royal Grammar/Logic 1.6.1 Chomsky, Language and Mind, (16): 1.6.1.1 It seems that one of the innovations of the Port-Royal Grammarof 1660—the work that initiated the tradition of philosophical grammar—was its recognition of the importance of the notion of the phrase as a grammatical unit. Earlier grammar had been largely a grammar of word classes and inflections. In the Cartersian theory of Port-Royal, a phrase corresponds to a complex idea and a sentence is subdivided into consectutive phrases, which are further subdivided into phrases, and so on, until the level of the word is reached. In this way we derived what might be called the “surface structure” of the sentence in question. To use what became a standard example, the sentences “Invisible God created the visible world” contains the subject “invisible God” and the predicate “created the visible world,” the latter contains the complex idea “the visible world” and verb “created,” and so on. But it is interesting that although the Port-Royal Grammar is apparently the first to rely oin a fairly systematic way on analysis into surface structure, it also recognized the inadequacy of such analysis. According to the Port-Royal theory, surface structure correspons only to sound— to the corporeal aspect of language; but when the signal is produced, with its surface structure, there takes place a corresponding mental analysis into what we may call the deep structure, a formal structure that related directly not to the sound but t o the meaning. In the example just given, “Invisible God created the visibile world,” the deep (17) structure consists of a system of three propositions, “that God is invisible,” “that he created the world,” “that the world is visible.” The propositions that interrelate to form the deep structure are not, of course, asserted when the sentence is used to make a statement; if I say that a wise man is honest, I am not asserting that men are wise or honest, even though in the Port-Royal theory the propositions “a man is wise” and “a man is honest” enter into the deep structure. Rather, these propositions enter into the complex ideas that are present to the mind, though rarely articulated in the signal, when the sentence is uttered.” (Chomsky, Language and Mind) 1.7 Intensional Logic 1.7.1 Bealer and Mönnich, “Property Theories”. 1.7.1.1 (138) “It appears, therefore, that failure of substitutivity is indeed the best criterion to use in characterizing intensional logic.” 1.7.2 Bealer “The Logical Status of Mind” 1.7.2.1 (234) ¶ “there have been two prevalent conceptions of intensional entities in the history of logic and philosophy. On the first conception, intensional entities are taken to be identical if and only if they are necessarily equivalent. … ¶ The second conception of intesniaonal entities imposes far stricter conditions on what it takes for a definition to be correct. On this conception, when an intensional entity is dfined completely, the result is unique and noncircular. … ¶ The first conception underlies the currently popular possible-worlds treatment of intensional entites, and it also underlies Alonzo ?church’s “Alternaitve (2)” formulation of Frege’s theory of sense. This conception is parituclarly well suited to the treatment of the modalities (Necessity, possibility, etc.), probability statements, counterfactuals, and so forth. The second conception has a rather livelier history. It underlies Leibniz’s doctrine of simple and complex properties and russell’s doctrine of logical atomism. And when intensional entities are identified with ideas (concepts, thoughts), we see that this conception was adopted at least implicityly by neary all modern philosophers from Descartes and Locke thorugh Kant. … (237) ¶ … Though the concept of being a triangle and the concept of being a trilateral are distinct, they correspond to the same quality of things in the world. The reason is that qualities, unlike concepts, are identical if there is no possibility of an object haiving one of them but not the other. Qualities (and connections) are what fix the actual conditions in the world, and they do not exhibit distinctions finer than necessary equivalents. Concpets, on the other hand, pertain to thinking and to reason; it is here that finer intensional distinctions show up. Thus, we arrive at the accompanying picture of the types of intensional entities.