The Problem of the Relevance of Global Perspectives: an analysis of Sen’s solution Daniela Goya Tocchetto Federal University of Rio Grande do Sul UFRGS daniela.gt@terra.com.br Keywords: Amartya Sen, Global Justice, John Rawls Introduction In The Idea of Justice, Amartya Sen present us with a whole world of practical and useful information about how to effectively address the injustices of contemporary societies; a world mostly ignored by political philosophers before Sen. His work sheds a new light into a long tradition in philosophy of approaching such a complex subject as justice in a transcendental manner; consequently deserving serious attention by all those interested in political philosophy. The first and fundamental insight is that, on the one hand, humans apparently have widely shared judgments about the flagrant injustices currently present in our world. On the other hand, individuals seem to have endless disagreements about what constitutes a perfectly just society. In face of these facts, why should we keep insisting in the elaboration of a theory of justice able to provide us with the ultimate description of a just society? Sen suggests that perhaps the most natural way to proceed would be precisely the opposite: start from widespread assessments of what constitutes cases of manifest injustice, and from these assessments build a wide consensus1 about which injustices should be addressed. Accordingly The Idea of Justice represents a major contribution to the attempt of putting together a consistent theoretical structure capable of affording viable solutions to real cases of injustice in the world. Sen’s departure point for the construction of his theory of justice is clearly Rawls’s theory of justice as fairness. He dedicates an entire chapter of his book to the discussion 1 Not necessarily complete. Indeed, Sen exposes his belief in the impossibility of a complete ordering of individuals judgments on matters of justice. both of his debt to the rawlsian theory and of the points he believes to be problematic – to which his work intends to provide a feasible alternative. The purpose of this paper is to evaluate Sen’s alternative to one of this supposedly problematic points in Rawls’s theory of justice; the problem of the relevance of global perspectives. In order to properly assess Sen’s proposal we shall proceed in the following manner. Firstly, we will elucidate in what exactly the problem consists of. Secondly, we will analyze the ways in which both the theory of justice as fairness and Sen’s comparative theory tackle the issue. Lastly, we will critically examine the two options, so as to better understand how good a solution Sen’s approach is able to provide to the problem in hand. 1. The problem of the relevance of global perspectives Sen exposes this problem in the third chapter, Rawls and Beyond; under the section ‘Difficulties that need fresh investigation’. At the outset the problem consists in the obstacles posed by the device of the rawlsian original position in obtaining principles of justice able of avoiding the influence of parochialism, through the allowance of globally different perspectives on matters of justice. According to Sen’s interpretation of the original position, its foundation in the social contract tradition is incompatible with the participation of individuals from outside the borders of a given community in the choice of the principles of justice that will rule its basic institutions. Amartya Sen also mentions, under this same section, the problem of global justice, stating that Rawls’s original position is so problematic for a conception of global justice that it would ultimately render it impossible2. Following this remark, Sen seems to argue that the impossibility of global justice would undermine the utmost relevance of regarding the views of persons from outside a country’s borders in the assessment of justice inside its borders. Yet we must recognize here the existence of two apparently distinct problems: (i) the problem of the relevance of global perspectives; and (ii) the problem of global justice. The first problem is related to the difficulties involved in preventing the influence of vested interests and parochial beliefs in the formulation of the principles of justice; while the second problem concerns the difficulties in arriving at a globally shared set of 2 This impossibility was disclosed by Thomas Nagel (2005), in ‘The Problem of Global Justice’. justice principles and an institutional structure able of enforcing these principles around the world. The main point here is that one could solve the problem of the relevance of global perspectives, while having no answer for the problem of global justice. If the original position is in fact, as Amartya Sen claims it is, unable to avoid the influence of parochial beliefs, we could build another instrument able to take global perspectives into account without being able to supply globally accepted justice principles neither global institutions that resemble a State. Still that Sen treats both these problems as intertwined indicates some important aspect about his perspective of justice. He is not developing a theory of justice similar in scope to Rawls’s theory. While Rawls’s theory of justice is intranational, applied solely to the rules governing the basic institutions of a given society geographically limited; Sen is aiming at global justice, as applied to the rules governing both intranational and international3 relations, i.e., the relations between sovereign countries. Thus, his approach is consistent with the view that that one could solve the problem of the relevance of global perspectives, while having no answer for the problem of global justice; but the opposite does not follow. Amartya Sen presents two main reasons for his insistence on the necessity of a global framework for justice. Firstly, in the globalized world in which we live what happens inside one country has unavoidable consequences on the other countries. Every rule or policy a country adopts inside its borders may affect the lives of other people around the globe. The American response to the threat of terrorist attacks is a plain example; but any other economic or trade policy could also potentially affect entire populations. Secondly, Amartya Sen emphasizes that each society has its own parochial beliefs, which may call for more global scrutiny. Every society would take huge advantages from a global debate about its internal rules and policies; a debate that would enlighten the local views and the existence of unreasonable convictions. Global deliberation can transform our ideas 3 The distinction between intranational and international justice was introduced by Thomas Pogge (2003), in ‘What is Global Justice’. because it can broaden the class and type of questions that are considered in that scrutiny, and because the factual presumptions that lie behind particular ethical and political judgments can be questioned with the help of the experiences of other countries or societies. 4 Hence the problem of the relevance of global perspectives and the problem of global justice are treated as inexorably interrelated in the contemporary world. Countries around the world are strongly politically and economically connected in a way that an action by one country inevitably affects the others. These connections arouse the necessity for a global debate on justice. Additionally the issue of local parochialism calls for the importance of allowing for the views from distinct perspectives. Consequently a constructive theory of justice cannot but provide a realistic alternative for these problems. 2. Possible alternatives: justice as fairness and Sen’s comparative approach Sen develops a comparative approach to justice intrinsically global in scope; diverse from the lines of Rawls theory of justice as fairness, specifically aimed at the construction of just institutions for a geographically limited society. Rawls elaborates his global theory of justice separately, in a latter work, namely The Law of Peoples. This later theory still relies in the device of the original position, only adapted to be constituted not of individuals of a given society, but of world leaders. Nonetheless Sen’s critique is directly addressed at the device of the original position as originally formulated in A Theory of Justice. Sen argues that if Rawls is unable to solve the problem of the relevance of global perspectives in his treatment of justice within sovereign states, it follows that he will be inevitably incapable of providing a treatment of justice between these states. Thus if Sen is correct in asserting that the original position does not effectively address the problem at hand, then it becomes unnecessary to extend the discussion to Rawls’ approach to global justice – given that his theory will have failed in a previous stage. In order to better evaluate Sen’s claim we will discuss both his’ and Rawls’ possible solutions to the problem in the next couple of subsections. 4 Amartya Sen, The Idea of Justice, 2009, page 71. 2.1 The original position The original position and the veil of ignorance constitute the basic rawlsian framework for thinking about justice as the result of a procedure that is fair – hence ‘justice as fairness’. Rawls conceives this thought experiment as a natural way of arriving at basic principles of justice capable of accounting for our intuitive ideas of impartiality in fair judgments and of the existence of an equal value of human beings as moral persons5. In this manner the original position comprises an initial situation of equality among individuals of a given society, where all those features irrelevant to justice are ruled out by the veil of ignorance. The veil of ignorance excludes from deliberations about the basic principles of justice such characteristics as personal income, social class, natural abilities, and all other biased influences on our judgments. Thus it is the instrument through which Rawls guarantees the impartiality of the basic principles of justice. As he puts it “The idea here is simply to make vivid to ourselves the restrictions that it seems reasonable to impose on arguments for principles of justice, and therefore on these principles themselves.”6 The main critique of Sen to the original position, in respect to the problem of the relevance of global perspectives, is the fact that Rawls includes in this initial position only the persons within a given society, thereby excluding the views of others from distinct social environments. As previously discussed, this exclusion undermines the theory of justice as fairness since (i) it opens the possibility for the influence of parochial beliefs in the formulation of the basic principles, and (ii) it is incapable of recognizing the global scope that any theory of justice should inevitably aim at in the contemporary world. 2.2 The idea of justice Amartya Sen recognizes the utmost importance of impartiality in any deliberation about justice, but discards the original position in the face of its inherent flaws. He proposes 5 As defined by Rawls: “(…) the purpose of these conditions is to represent equality between human beings as moral persons, as creatures having a conception of their good and capable of a sense of justice. The basis of equality is taken to be similarity in these two respects.” (p. 19) 6 Rawls, A Theory of Justice, 1971, p. 18. the use of a different device for thinking about justice, the so-called ‘impartial spectator’ as developed by Adam Smith in the Theory of Moral Sentiments. Smith explains our morality as a system ultimately founded in our natural moral sentiments. These moral sentiments of approval or disapproval of our own and other’s actions are explained through the mechanism of what Smith refers to as sympathy. This sympathy can be understood in modern terms as the feeling of empathy, the ability to put ourselves in the place of another individual and share his feelings. Yet to accurately feel what a third party is feeling in a given situation we must have information about how the situation came about, “(…) our sympathy depends on our ability to approve of another’s behavior because it is appropriate to the situation. Until we understand the context of another’s behavior, we cannot know whether our own emotional response will be one of positive sympathy or negative revulsion, of approval or disgust.”7 Thus in order to make sense of our moral sentiments and explain the system of morality we must have (i) the ability to feel sympathy, (ii) the relevant information about the situation, and there is still a third fundamental characteristic of the smithian approach: impartiality. We cannot judge an action based on personal interests, we must always evaluate a situation from a distance, as a third uninvolved party would evaluate it. The veil of ignorance is effective in ruling out the influences of personal interests in the elaboration of the principles of justice; but it is still unable to bring into the deliberation in the original position the opinions of individuals from outside the focal group. For Sen, the impartial spectator is able to overcome not only the influences of personal interests, but also the influences of local conventions of thought. As Sen puts it: Smith invoked the reflective device of the impartial spectator to go beyond reasoning that may be constrained by local conventions of thought, and to examine deliberately, as a procedure, what the accepted conventions would look like from the perspective of a ‘spectator’ at a distance.8 7 Theory of Moral Sentiments, page 58, in The Essential Adam Smith, edited by Robert Heilbroner, 1987. 8 Amartya Sen, The Idea of Justice, 2009, page 125. Sen establishes the distinctions of closed impartiality and open impartiality to elucidate the main difference between the original position and the impartial spectator. Closed impartiality is defined as a geographically limited impartiality, in the sense that only the views of the members of a given society are taken as relevant in deliberations of justice inside that society. In contrast, open impartiality is defined as global impartiality, in the sense that the views both form inside and from outside a given society are taken as relevant in debates about justice. The original position provides, in Sen’s interpretation, only an ‘identity blackout’ in the individuals who are members of a society. Yet “Something more than an ‘identity blackout’ within the confines of the local focal group would be needed to address this problem. In this respect, the procedural device of closed impartiality in ‘justice as fairness’ can be seen as being ‘parochial’ in construction.”9 Another aspect of the relevance of global perspectives in Sen’s approach to justice is his emphasis in the need to take the idea of justice beyond the scope of sovereign states. He affirms that “(…) no theory of justice today can ignore the whole world except our own country.”10 He bases this need in three main reasons: (…) assessment of justice demands engagement with the ‘eyes of mankind’, first, because we may variously identify with the others elsewhere and not just with our local community; second, because our choices and actions may affect the lives of others far as well as near; and third, because what they see from their respective perspectives of history and geography may help us to overcome our own parochialism.” 11 Sen also calls attention to three main points of difference between the rawlsian approach and the smithian device of the impartial spectator: “(…) first, Smith’s insistence on what is being called here open impartiality, accepting the legitimacy and importance of the ‘enlightenment relevance’ (and not just ‘membership entitlement’) of views from others; secondly, the comparative (and not just transcendental) focus of Smith’s investigation, going beyond the search for a perfectly just society; and thirdly, Smith’s involvement with social realizations (going beyond the search only for just institutions).12 9 Amartya Sen, The Idea of Justice, 2009, page 126. Ibid., p. 173. 11 Ibid., p. 130. 12 Ibid., p. 134. 10 3. Critical analysis Sen’s central argument is that the original position is (i) unable to filter the influence of parochial beliefs in the construction of the basic principles of justice and (ii) is also unable to account for the interests of other societies that are inevitably affected by the institutions of any given country. I believe the first criticism to be misguided and the second to be appropriate. The parties in the original position only know certain very general facts about their society, namely, “that it exists under the circumstances of justice, both objective and subjective, and that reasonably favorable conditions making a constitutional democracy possible obtain”13. Beyond that, when identifying principles of justice (as opposed to just institutions), the parties in the original position do not know more particular information about their society – and, in particular, they do not employ the kinds of country or society-specific beliefs that would give rise to concerns about ‘parochialism.’ Sen seems to be conflating the original position, in which principles of justice are selected, with the ‘constitutional stage,’ at which point the parties apply the principles of justice to the constitutional structure of a particular society, while remaining ignorant of the particular place of the people whom they represent within that society. Furthermore Rawls does not intend the original position to represent a gathering of all actual or possible persons. He stresses that To conceive of the original position in either of these ways is to stretch fantasy too far; the conception would cease to be a natural guide to intuition. (…) it is important that the original position be interpreted so that one can at any time adopt its perspective. It must make no difference when one takes up this viewpoint, or who does so: the restrictions must be such that the same principles are always chosen.14 In the above passage it is clear that Rawls intends the original position to function as a possible (and the more appropriate, he argues) perspective for addressing issues of social justice. In addition, the restrictions imposed by the veil of ignorance cover all aspects that would render a judgment partial; there is no suggestion in justice as fairness 13 Rawls, Justice as Fairness: a restatement, 2001, p. 87. 14 Rawls, A Theory of Justice, 1971, p. 139. that we should not think of parochial beliefs as an aspect that is ruled out by the application of the veil of ignorance. Another way of ruling out social conventions such as racism is explicitly and effectively addressed in A Theory of Justice; racist principles are not only unjust under the lights of justice as fairness, they are also irrational. The following passage magnificently expresses the argument: Those born on a sunny day might be blessed with a happy temperament, and for some positions of authority this might be a qualifying attribute. But such distinctions would never be proposed in first principles, for these must have some rational connection with the advancement of human interests broadly defined. The rationality of the parties and their situation in the original position guarantees that ethical principles and conceptions of justice have this general content. Inevitably, then, racial and sexual discrimination presupposes that some hold a favored place in the social system which they are willing to exploit to their advantage. From the standpoint of persons similarly situated in an initial situation which is fair, the principles of explicit racist doctrines are not only unjust. They are irrational. 15 Given this irrationality, such principles as racism do not fall into the category of moral conceptions; they are merely means of suppression. In Rawls’s theoretical construct, conceptions of right are not empty: they have substantive content and are thus able to exclude arbitrary principles. Turning now to the second major criticism of the original position, namely its inability to account for the interests of individuals from other societies, I believe Sen actually presents some appealing justification for the need of improving Rawls’ theory. The justification has already been presented in the preceding sections, and rests in Sen’s assertion that the scope of any talk about justice in the contemporary world is unavoidably global. One cannot discuss justice for a given country confined within the interests just of its own citizens. The actions taken by one country affect the lives of persons all around the world. This influence works not only through means of the deliberate use of force, like in the invasion o Iraq in 2003; but also through the indirect impacts of commerce and trade. As Sen remarks 15 Rawls, A Theory of Justice, 1971, p. 149. We do not live in secluded cocoons of our own. And if the institutions and policies of one country influence lives elsewhere, should not the voices of affected people elsewhere count in some way in determining what is just or unjust in the way a society is organized (…)? 16 In this respect Rawls’ separate treatment of justice within a country and between countries seems insufficient in a world where it does not make sense to talk of justice confined within a country’s borders. Hence Sen’s insistence in the relevance of the ‘views from everywhere’ is not to be discarded without serious reflection. The Idea of Justice is capable of enlightening the philosophical debate in a number of ways, especially in what concerns the focus on practical results and on the possibility of global deliberation. However philosophers will have to work out the foundations of Sen’s view regarding the possibility of a comparative approach to justice, given that in many ways it seems to be ‘political in the wrong way’17. Sen wants to ‘diagnose’ particular instances of injustice in a way that allows for ‘plural grounding’ on the basis of multiple, conflicting ‘evaluative criteria’; apparently without a serious concern with the reasons for why an injustice is to be considered as such. He argues that “Agreements on particular justice-enhancing moves are material enough for public action (what was described earlier as ‘plural grounding’), and for that guidance, unanimity on the nature of the perfectly just society is not needed.” 18 Nonetheless, this is merely asserting that whatever judgments persons under global deliberation arrive at are to be taken as correct; and this is far from sufficient for justifying a given notion of neither justice nor injustice. 16 Amartya Sen, The Idea of Justice, 2009, page 130. 17 In Part V of the Restatement, Rawls asserts that political liberalism seeks a kind of consensus that is different from ‘consensus politics’. The latter aims to identify a particular policy that can gain sufficient political support in a particular time and place, without seeking agreement concerning the justification of the policy (and allowing the balance of power between various groups to influence the decision). For example, one might hope to reach agreement on the ‘diagnosis’ that X is unjust, without first (or ever) identifying why X is unjust. In contrast, Rawls’s view is political not because it bypasses the question of justification, but because it deals with that question in a political way. 18 Amartya Sen, The Idea of Justice, 2009, footnote page 135.