The principle of subsidiarity Marta Staniszewska November, 14th 2007 The Prime Minister (Mr John Major): “…There is a tendency for the Community to want to legislate over a wide area. That tendency needs to be curbed. That is the essence of what hasbecome known as subsidiarity. I am aware that different people view it in different ways, but what subsidiarity must mean is that, if a problem can be dealt with at national level, it should be.” Despite the fact, that the principle of subsidiarity may be seen from two different points of view (see below), here I will focus upon its connection with the European Union and its legal provisions. 1. Origin and context of subsidiarity1 In studying the origins and context of subsidiarity it is possible to distinguish two extrinsically related steps. First, subsidiarity has a religious origin, or even a specifically Catholic origin. Second, it has another origin within the ongoing discussions concerning the construction of the European Community or the European Union. Subsidiarity reflects originally a specifically Catholic preoccupation and a well determined historical reflection as both the outcome and the answer to the political climax that preceded World War II. In a narrow political and institutional sense it could be thought that the effort to think out and to make subsidiarity possible responds to three well defined challenges: 2 the defense of the church’s authority in a political situation ever more hostile, the reconciliation of Catholicism with the goals of social progress and the state’s political policies, and the analysis of the lay Catholics’ commitment in an ever more secular or laicized political order. But the broader and real concern of the encyclicals was to save place for persons and their group exercise of responsible freedom in the face of the countervailing emergent polarization of various forms of totalitarian and liberal threats to social participation. The concept of subsidiarity in these circles appears first in the encyclical Quadragesimo Anno from Pope Pius XI, and is found in all subsequent related encyclicals up to the present date. 3 These original conditions have become much more elaborate as can be seen from subsequent writings by both Catholics and non-Catholics, believers and atheists, religious and lay people. 1 http://www.crvp.org/book/Series05/V-5/chapter_iv.htm Cf. A. Adonis and S. Jones, Subsidiarity and the Community’s Constitutional Future, Discussion Paper No. 2 (Center for European Studies; Oxford: Nuffield College, 1991), pp. 4 ff. 3 Nature and Future of Episcopal Conferences, H. Legrand, J. Manzanares and A. Garcia y Garcia, ed. (Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, Washington, D.C., 1988. 2 The Synod of 1985 was called to study the applicability of the principle of subsidiarity inside the Catholic Church herself.4 Only in the 1980s did the concept of subsidiarity acquire a place of its own in the language of the European Community.5 We can thus speak, but only methodologically, of a second origin of the concept of subsidiarity. In the context of the formation of the European Community or European Unity 6 the concept of subsidiarity is set in the center and clarified as such, alongside the main concepts and problems from social and political philosophy. In this way, subsidiarity has become increasingly associated with the elucidation of the problems concerning common interests, democracy and federalization. Or, to put it the other way round, what is discussed in terms of subsidiarity generally are problems of decentralization of power and decision making, federalism and even the sub-sequent confederalism, and the concept of the common good. Inside the process of European construction, Jacques Delors has been one of the main sources and promoters of discussion regarding subsidiarity. On the basis of Canadian, American and German experiences, each with their own cha-racteristics, subsidiarity supposes the distinction of two spheres: the private on the one hand, and the state on the other, and the distribution of tasks among those different levels of political power. From this point of view, according to Jacques Delors himself, subsidiarity encompasses two essential aspects: on one level, the right and/or duty of everyone to exercise his or her responsibilities so as to be able 4 These are, among others: Non Abbiamo Bisogno, also from Pius XI, and Mater et Magistra (1961) and Pacem in Terris (1963) by John XXIII. The Second Vatican Council also makes reference to subsidiarity, particularly in the field of education. The subsequent writings of by Paul VI and John Paul II contain specific room for subsidiarity. In any case, here these indications have only indicative value. Those with other interests or purposes might wish to trace back the Vatican documents in order to determine whether there are linguistic or other changes between one document and another, or between one period and another, for instance, between one Pope and another. 5 There is an evident though unmentioned historical presupposition concerning the multiple connections between earlier Catholic and, in a very broad sense, Christian history up to its recent generic extension to the construction of the European Community or Union. Beyond the merely economic preoccupation of responding to the strong pressure of Japanese economic, commercial and financial power, on the one hand, and their American counterparts, on the other, there is as well a desire to become an independent world block. In this there has been strong influence from Christian Democracy as well as from Catholicism itself in forming the European Community or Unity. This should not be taken as if the influence of liberal and Social-democratic forces were necessarily minor. The point is rather to make a bridge between the "religious" and the "lay" origins of subsidiarity. Both origins correspond to one and the same vector, and there is really much more of a continuity between the two. The Liberal, Socialist and Social-democratic forces came to contribute to that process of formation after the first efforts and pillars had been established particularly by Christian Democracy. 6 There is a difference between the concepts of European Community and European Unity which consists in an ascending path from the first to the second. For reasons of language economy the two concepts will be used here without discrimination, especially as the immense majority of texts about subsidiarity refer to the construction of the European Community. Only after the Maastricht Treaty and the Agreements from Schengen has the second concept come to be more widely used over the first one. This reflects the strengthening of the European Unity. But as this is a unity in progress other concepts can be added afterwards; hence the use of those concepts here is less categorical and more denotative to act in the best way; on another level, the obligation the public authorities to provide all with the means to develop and reach their own capacities.7 In any case, the history of subsidiarity in the framework of European construction is neither lineal nor uniform. On the contrary, it is an issue in whose discussion different interests converge with equally multiple goals. The comprehension and application of subsidiarity is really a story of multiplicities, rather than of simple unity. 8 In such a state of affairs the clarification of subsidiarity is a task which lies ahead. In this task clearly there are two groups. On the one hand, there are those who believe that it is necessary to define what subsidiarity is, not only for its actualization but as the most expeditious way to clarify the range of its possible applicability. On the other hand, there are the understandings of subsidiarity not so much in juridical and constitutional, but in sociopolitical, terms, as for example in the ecologists’ positive concern for subsidiarity. From this point of view, it is not so much an already established and determined concept, but a leading principle or a guide to action. The former is an objective or objectivist de-finition of the problem; the latter is a subjective or subjectivist reading of the concept. The issue of subsidiarity lies in the ten-sion between both positions, to which for the immediate fu-ture there is no foreseeable simple solution. This is typical of the specific tension found in liberal Western democracies. 2. Subsidiarity: the beginning The principle of subsidiarity9 then has a quite determined place, date, author and situation of origin. There is general agreement that its political and philosophical roots can be traced back without doubt to the work of Proudhon and J. Stuart Mill;10 others would trace its antecedents as far back as St. Thomas Aquinas and Aristotle. 7 Cf. J. Dolors, The Principle of Subsidiarity: Contribution to the Debates," in Subsidiarity: The Challenge of Change. Proceedings of the Jacques Delors Colloquiums (Maastricht, The Netherlands: European Institute of Public Administration, 1991), p. 18. 8 Cf. among others, Subsidiarity within the European Community, A. Duff (Ed.) (Federal Trust for Education and Research, 1993), and A. Tyrie, "Subsidiarity -- What Should The Government Do", in Subsidiarity as History and Policy, op. cit.; R. Sinnott, "Integration Theory, Subsidiarity and the Internationalization of Issues: The Implications for Legitimacy", in Working Paper RSC, No. 94113, (Florence: Euro-pean University Institute, Robert Schuman Center). 9 As used here, the expression "principle of subsidiarity" is really a generic designation used without as-signing to it further ontological or logical consequences. However, a principle is generally a guide to meaning or action. In this sense, it is perhaps implicit that the principle of subsidiarity contains a reference to a series of theoretical and practical tasks. 10 By Proudhon, cf. Du principle federatif et la necessité de reconstituer le parti de la revolution (1863). Usually there is agreement in stressing the importance Proud-hon gives to subsidiarity understood as a contractual principle for establishing and guaranteeing the social and political coherence of social and political life. -- As for J. Stuart Mill, cf. Consideration on Representative Government (1872). When it comes to the European Union, talk of subsidiarity was introduced in the late 1980s through the initiative of the European Parliament, Britain and Germany in response to fears of centralized power by placing the burden of argument with integrationists. Britain feared European federalism, and the German LaEnder sought to maintain their exclusive powers enjoyed in the German Federal Republic.11 The explanation for the principle of subsidiarity ought to be sought in answering the question: how should legislative power be divided between the Community and the Member States? The answer, it is suggested, is that power needs to remain with the Member States except where there is a good reason why it shall be given to the Community. In other words, Member-State action should be the norm, Community action the exception- for which clear justification is required in each instance. The word subsidiarity is derived from the Latin word subsidiarius and has its origins in Catholic social teaching. The concept or principle is found in several constitutions around the world.12 In Community parlance, this principle is known as “ subsidiarity”, a word imported into English from German, so that the concept could be discussed with reference to the Community. Although the word is new in English, the idea is well-known: Americans claim that it is the principle on which their constitution is based. In the Community context, subsidiarity first began to attract attention about twenty years ago and it was eventually laid down as a principle of Community law in the Maastricht Agreement ( known also as Treaty on European Union).13 3. Definition The Oxford English Dictionary14 defines subsidiarity as the idea that a central authority should have a subsidiary function, performing only those tasks which cannot be performed effectively at a more immediate or local level. Subsidiarity is the principle which states that matters ought to be handled by the smallest (or, the lowest) competent authority. This means that the primary responsibility and decision- 11 Andreas Féllesdal, Survey Article: Subsidiarity, The Journal of Political Philosophy: Volume 6, Number 2, 1998, pp. 190±218 12 http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Subsidiarity 13 Trevor C Hartley, Constitutional Problems Of The European Union 14 The Oxford English Dictionary (OED), published by the Oxford University Press (OUP) in 2005 making competence are supposed to rest with the lowest possible level of authority of the political hierarchy. The concept is applicable in the fields of government, political science, cybernetics and management. Subsidiarity is, ideally or in principle, one of the features of federalism.15 When it comes to European Union Law it’s a fundamental principle. Though its legal effects may be slight, its symbolic significance is enormous: it is a declaration of the vision of Europe shared by the authors of the Treaty and enshrined in that document.16 According to this principle, the European Union may only act (i.e. make laws) where Member States agree that action of individual countries is insufficient.17 Moreover, subsidiarity reduces the risk for members of being overruled in common decisions, by limiting the common agenda. Thus, it means that the Member States remain responsible for areas which they are capable of managing more effectively themselves, while the Community is given those powers which the Member States cannot discharge satisfactorily. In the context of the EU, principles of subsidiarity have been introduced precisely to quell fears of centralization. The Union was established to enhance and complement domestic sovereignty in areas where common action was necessary. The European level of governance ensured beneficial cooperation, regulation of externalities and options for collective actions.18 According to N.W Barber, 19 subsidiarity is a principle about the functioning of democracy, even if it is not a principle of democracy. It helps shape the structures within which democracy can operate, but does not require or presuppose the agreement of individuals within these structures. Most obviously, the European principle of subsidiarity is concerned with the allocation of powers to pre-existing institutions: for instance, whether a decision should be taken within the institutions of the European Union or should be allocated to the Westminster Parliament. It will be suggested that the principle can also provide an argument for the creation of new democratic institutions, both at the sub-state and at the supra-state level. 15 http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Subsidiarity N. W. Barber, The Limited Modesty of Subsidiarity, European Law Journal, Vol. 11, No. 3, May 2005, pp.08–325 17 http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Subsidiarity 18 Follesdal, Andreas, Subsidiarity, Democracy and Human Rights in the Constitutional Treaty of Europe, Journal of Social Philosophy, Volume 37, Number 1, Spring 2006 , pp. 61-80(20) 19 N. W. Barber, The Limited Modesty of Subsidiarity, European Law Journal, Vol. 11, No. 3, May 2005, 16 pp.08–325 Legal Basis 20 4. 1) The principle was enshrined in the 1992 Treaty of Maastricht and is contained within the proposed new Treaty establishing a constitution for Europe. However, at the local level it was already a key element of the European Charter of Local Self-Government, an instrument of the Council of Europe promulgated in 1985 . Subsidiarity was established in EU law by the Treaty of Maastricht, article 3b (signed on 7th of February 1992 and entered into force on 1st of November 1993). The present formulation is contained in Article 5 of the Treaty Establishing the European Community (consolidated version following the Treaty of Nice, which entered into force on 1 February 2003): The Community shall act within the limits of the powers conferred upon it by this Treaty and of the objectives assigned to it therein. In areas which do not fall within its exclusive competence, the Community shall take action, in accordance with the principle of subsidiarity, only if and in so far as the objectives of the proposed action cannot be sufficiently achieved by the Member States and can therefore, by reason of the scale or effects of the proposed action, be better achieved by the Community. Any action by the Community shall not go beyond what is necessary to achieve the objectives of this Treaty. Under this article, there are three preconditions for Community action in accordance with the principle of subsidiarity: 21 the area concerned must not fall within the Community's exclusive competence; the objectives of the proposed action cannot be sufficiently achieved by the Member States; the action can therefore, by reason of its scale or effects, be implemented more successfully by the Community. 2) The principle of subsidiarity has not just applied since its incorporation in Article 5 ECT. As long ago as 1951, Article 5 of the ECSC Treaty stipulated that the Community should 20 http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Subsidiarity#European_Union_law 21 http://www.europarl.europa.eu/facts/1_2_2_en.htm exert direct influence on production only when circumstances so required. And although it was not expressly so defined, a subsidiarity criterion was included in Article 130r EECT, on the environment, by the Single European Act in 1987. However, the Court of First Instance of the EC ruled in its judgment of 21 February 1995, ECR II-289 at 331, that the subsidiarity principle was not a general principle of law, against which the legality of Community action should be tested, before the EU Treaty entered into force. 3) Without changing the wording of the subsidiarity criterion in Article 5, second paragraph, ECT, the Treaty of Amsterdam (signed on 2nd of October 1997, and entered into force on 1st of May 1999) incorporates the ‘Protocol on Application of the Principles of Subsidiarity and Proportionality’ into the European Treaties (agreed in Edinburgh in 1992). 22 The first issue dealt with by the Protocol on subsidiarity is that of the institutions which are bound by the principle. The first provision of the Protocol on subsidiarity address the question when it specifically establishes that ‘each institution shall ensure that the principle of subsidiarity is complied with’. It follows that all Community institutions which have powers to dictate legally binding acts, and not only the Community institutions sensu stricto23 are obliged to observe the principle of subsidiarity when they act. The provision also makes clear that the ECJ has competence to review acts on the basis of subsidiarity. The second issue addressed by the Protocol is that of the relationship between subsidiarity and the pillars supporting the Community’s constitutional edifice. The Protocol stays clear about it: the implementation of the principle of subsidiarity does not call into question any of the elements that are inseparable from the ‘Community’s constitutional charter’ (ECJ). This matter is resolved in provision 2 of the Protocol, although provisions 3 and 8 are also relevant. Provision 2 establishes that both the Community’s acquis and the principle of institutional balance shall be respected by Community institutions when they implement subsidiarity. The same provision states that the implementation of subsidiarity shall not affect the principles developed by the ECJ- this clearly refers to the principles of supremacy, direct effect, Member States’ liability for not implementing Community law, and legal certainty. Finally, provision 2 indicates that the implementation of the principle of subsidiarity shall take into account the ‘ principle of sufficiency means’, according to which ‘ the Union shall provide itself with the means necessary to attain its objectives and carry out its policies’. 22 23 Antonio Estella, The EU Principle of Subsidiarity and Its Critique That is, those listed in Art. 7 ECT (ex Art. 4) When it comes to Provision 3, it states that ‘the principle of subsidiarity does not call into question the powers conferred on the European Community by the ECT, as interpreted by the ECJ. Provision 8 recalls the principle of loyal co-operation when subsidiarity is implemented. In those cases in which the Community considers that it should not act, the Member States will be free to do so.24 However, the correlation between subsidiarity and loyal co-operation established by provision 8 means that Member States’ intervention may not call into question the objectives of the ECT and the other obligations contracted by them with the European Community. The Protocol also attempts to clarify the definition of subsidiarity, particulary in provision 3. This provision states that subsidiarity is a principle regulating the exercise of Community competences, since it ‘provides a guide as to how the Community’s powers are to be exercised at the Community level’. This is an Amsterdam innovation. The provision also establishes that the principle of subsidiarity is a ‘dynamic’ concept, which essentially means that subsidiarity allows Community action ‘when the circumstances so require’ and, conversely, that it allows Community action to be restricted or even ‘discontinued’ where it is no longer justified.25 5. Objectives The principle has a two-fold purpose in Community law:26 a) to assess the need for Community action; even though Community objectives are set in general terms by the EC Treaty, specific Community action must be justified wherever the community has current competence with Member States b) to control the exercise of power by the Community once the need for action has been established; it’s connected with a principle of proportionality. According to the well established caselaw of the Court a proportionate action is one which is no more than is appropriate and necessary to achieve its desired goals. The principle of subsidiarity is intended to guarantee a more efficient Europe, closer to its citizens and more respectful of local and national identities. The essential idea is that Leaving aside the question of whether the Community’s competence is exclusive or not. From a strictly legal standpoint, if we take into account the silence of the ECT in this regard, it seems more appropriate to speak here of ‘pre-emption’ than of exclusivity. If the field is already entirely occupied, this will hinder Member States’ interventions. See Goucha Soares (1998) 25 Antonio Estella, The EU Principle of Subsidiarity and Its Critique 26 United Kingdom Association for European Law, University Association for Contemporary European Studies, “Legal Issues of the Maastricht Treaty”, edited by O’Keeffe, Twomey 24 decisions should be taken closest to where they will have their impact and be brought as close to the citizen as possible.27 6. Justification for the principle28 The justification for the principle is easy to see. The Community covers an area of considerable geographical, economic, political, social, religious and cultural diversity. A policy that works well in, for instance, Greece might be unsatisfactory in Denmark. In principle, it makes sense for the Greeks to make laws for Greece and for the Danes to make laws for Denmark: diverse conditions need diverse legislation. Community legislation should be adopted only when there is a specific need. 7. Defects of the principle 29 We may find four kinds of such deffects: 1. article 3b (5) cannot be used to question the granting of powers to the Community, but only the exercise of those powers by the passing of specific pieces of legislation.30 This means that the principle of subsidiarity does not determine when the Community has competence to intervene. According to this principle, the Community may act only when it has explicitly been granted competence. Therefore, subsidiarity enters the scene only when it is clear that the Community has competence to act. In other words, this principle regulates the exercise, does not hold, of Community competence. 31 2. article 3b (5) applies subsidiarity only in those areas which do not fall within the exclusive competence of the Community- the text laid down in this article applies only where the Community shares the concurrent powers with the Member States. Unfortunately, the Treaty nowhere specifies which those areas are.32 The Comission has issued a list of areas 27 28 Miroslaw Matyja, Subsidiarity: A Tool for Gender Equality in an Enlarged EU Trevor C Hartley, Constitutional Problems Of The European Union Trevor C Hartley, Constitutional Problems Of The European Union 30 This follows from the fact that Art. 3b (5) is simply a Treaty provision like any other; consequently, it cannot affect the validity of other provisions of the Treaty. See also Art. 3 of the Protocol on the Application of the Principles of Subsidiarity and Proportionality (annexed to The EC Treaty by the Treaty of Amsterdam) 31 Antonio Estella, The EU Principle of Subsidiarity and Its Critique 32 Commentators have expressed divergent views. Toth considers that all the areas of power granted to the Community under the EEC Treaty as originally concluded are exclusive: Toth, “The Principle of Subsidiarity in the Maastricht Treaty” (1992) 29 CMLRev.669 at pp. 1091 et seq.; Steiner, on the other hand, suggests that the 29 which it regards as falling within the exclusive competence of the Community and therefore outside the scope of the doctrine.33 3. subsidiarity is difficult to apply in practice because different views could be held as to when Community action is necessary.34 In attempt to meet this objection, the Member States agreed in the Treaty of Amsterdam to add a Protocol to the EC Treaty, the Protocol on The Application of the Principles of Subsidiarity and Proportionality. This makes clear that both requirements in the definition in Article 3b (5) have to be met: it must be established that the objectives of the proposed action cannot be sufficiently achieved by the Member States and that they can be better achieved by action on the part of the Community.35 The Protocol also lays down guidelines for determining whether these conditions are fulfilled. They indicate that this is likely to be the case where: - the issue under consideration has transnational aspects which cannot be satisfactorily regulated by action by Member States - actions by Member States alone or lack of Community action would conflict with the requirements of the Treaty or would otherwise significantly damage Member States’ interest - action at Community level would produce clear benefits by reason of its scale or effects compared with action at the level of the Member States These guidelines make the principle easier to apply, but the fact remains that it is a really matter of political judgment whether an issue can be ‘satisfactorily’ regulated by the Member States, whether lack of Community action would ‘significantly’ damage Member States’ interests or whether action at Community level would produce ‘clear benefits’36 only areas in which the Community has exclusive competence for the purpose of Art. 3b (5) are those in which it has already legislated: Steiner, “Subsidiarity under the Maastricht Treaty”, in David O’ Keeffe and Patrick M Twomey, Legal Issues of the Maastricht Treaty (1994), p.49 at pp. 55-58; see also Emiliou, “Subsidiarity: Panacea or Fig Leaf?” ibid., p.65 at pp. 74-75; Schilling, “A New Dimension of Subsidiarity: Subsidiarity as a Rule and a Principle” (1994) 14 YEL 203 at pp. 217 et seq. (this last analysis is probably the most closely reasoned) 33 See The Principle of Subsidiarity, Com. Doc. SEC(92) 1990, 27 October 1992, p.5 34 Lord Mackenzie- Stuart, a former President of the European Court, has called the definition of subsidiarity in the Treaty a “prime example of gobbledygook”: letter to The Times 15 June 1992. This is an over-reaction, but there can be no disguising the fact that it is not easy to apply in practice. See, further, Mackenzie-Stuart’s article in The Times 11 December 1992 35 Art. 5 of the Protocol. This means that if the objectives can be sufficiently achieved by the Member States, the Community is not allowed to act even if it could achieve them better. Moreover, even if they cannot be satisfactorily achieved by the Member States, the Community cannot act unless it is established that it could do better than the Member States. 36 A close Reading of the Protocol suggests that some Member States regarded the principle with suspicion and were anxious that it should not restrict Community powers too much. Thus, Art. 2 specifies that the application of subsidiarity must respect the acquis communautaire, thereby seemingly preventing it from applying to legislation passed before the European Court on the relationship between Community law and national law, one such rule being that Community law is supreme over national law. Art. 3 says it must not call into question the 4. as things stand in present, it is far from certain that the European Court will be prepared to strike down measures which infringe subsidiarity. In view of the Court’s centralizing philosophy, it will probably be reluctant to do so. However, if the Court is not willing to act, the principle may in time become a dead letter.37 8. Where the principle applies We may distinguish 2 levels where it applies: 1) during the Intergovernmental Conference,38 which is the formal procedure for negotiating amendments to the founding treaties of the European Union; it is a legal-political criterion delineating those areas where the Community should and should not act. In practice, the concept is frequently used in a more informal manner in discussions as to which competences should be given to the Community, and which retained for the Member States alone. 2) as a constitutional principle 39 - applies to all the Community Institutions. The rule has practical significance for the Council, Parliament and Commission in particular. The Court's decisions are also bound by Article 5, second paragraph, ECT. Citizens of the Union cannot derive any rights directly from this provision. 9. Subsidiarity before the Court The competence to review legislation has been granted to the European Court of Justice. According to Article 230 ECT, the ECJ ‘…shall review the legality of acts adopted by the European Parliament and the Council, of acts of the Council, of the Commission and of the powers conferred on the Community by the Treaty “as interpreted by the Court of Justice”, apparently a reference to the doctrine of implied powers developed by the European Court. 37 Art. 1 of the Protocol added by the Treaty of Amsterdam provides that, in exercising the powers conferred on it, each institution “shall ensure that the principle of subsidiarity is complied with”. Since the European Court is an institution, this appears to require it to use its judical powers to ensure that the other institutions respect the principle, if necessary by annulling legislation that conflicts with it. See also the Conclusions of the Presidency,European Council in Edinburgh (11-12 December 1992), Annex 1 to Part A, p. 4. In view of this, the most likely outcome is that the Court will hold subsidiarity to be justicable, but will annul measures only in the clearest cases. For more detailed analysis, see Toth “ Is Subsidiarity Justicable?” (1994) 14 ELRev. 268; and Emiliou: “Subsidiarity: An Effective Barrier against ‘the Enterprises of Ambition’?” (1992) 17 ELRev.383, at pp. 402-405 38 http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Intergovernmental_Conference 39 http://www.europarl.europa.eu/facts/1_2_2_en.htm ECB, other than recommendations and opinions and of acts of the European Parliament intended to produce legal effects vis-à-vis third parties’.40 Although the text of that article speaks of ‘legality’, and not of ‘constitutionality’ ,its second paragraph indicates that one reason for which the ECJ may declare a legislative act void is infringement of the ECT. If Community legislation may be annulled by the ECJ on the ground of Treaty infringement, this amounts to constitutional review of legislation, at least in national contexts.41 Subsidiarity gives a new argument for the Court to annul measures adopted by the Council. The Court has adopted a very prudent approach regarding subsidiarity. Up to now, it has never declared void a legislature measure because it contradicts subsidiarity. Beyond descriptive analysis, it is also important to understand why the Court is not implementing subsidiarity to its fullest. I am going to develop this matter later, for now I would just like to mention that there are two kinds of explanations to account for the Court’s attitude. The first has to do with the legitimacy of the Court. The argument is that the Court is not currently implementing subsidiarity because, given that the principle is devoid of clear legal content, the Court could be putting its own legitimacy at risk if it decided to do so. The second explanation is connected with the Court’s vision of its own role in Community integration. The argument is that the Court has its own political agenda, and that this agenda is dominated by the idea of integration. The Court’s perception that subsidiarity, an antiintegration principle for the Court, puts its own integrationist agenda in real danger could also explain its prudent approach to the principle.42 10. The Court’s doctrine on subsidiarity 43 The word which best summarizes the Court’s doctrine on the principle of subsidiarity is prudence. Here prudence means restraint on the part of the Court. The Court could have used the opportunity offered by subsidiarity to check whether the Community legislature is going astray. The Court’s acting may be explained by taking into consideration two main variables: 40 Antonio Estella, The EU Principle of Subsidiarity and Its Critique Alonso Garcia (1994) notes that Art. 230 does not differentiate in reality between ‘legality’ and ‘constitutional’ control. This may create some confusion as to the existence of constitutional review of legislation in the EC context, at least for those lawyers educated in the continental tradition, which is in general characterized by the distinction between ‘legality’ and ‘constitutionality’ controls, each being performed by different courts 42 Antonio Estella, The EU Principle of Subsidiarity and Its Critique 43 Antonio Estella, The EU Principle of Subsidiarity and Its Critique 41 - the Court’s own legitimacy as an institution - the Court’s political agenda The Court’s Legitimacy (concerns the non-implementation of material subsidiarity). It’s well known that the Court of Justice has moulded its case-law to the canons of classical legal reasoning. It could not have done otherwise. The Court wished to exercise objectivity and neutrality in its case- law, in common with courts on the continent, and beyond. Courts are not generally elected bodies, and when they are elected it is not in the same sense as politicians. Courts are essentially technical bodies. If they do not want their decisions to be challenged they must be seen to be simply interpreting and applying a technical instrument: the law. The European Court of Justice has gained legitimacy through its insistence on appearing to legal practitioners. The Court knows that its survival as an institution, and the extent to which its decisions are accepted, depend on its continuing to convince observers that its decisions are based strictly on the interpretation and application of European Community law, and not merely a matter of preference expediency. The Court’s Political Agenda (concerns the non-implementation, or lack of full implementation, of procedural subsidiarity). What the Court actually does as far as procedural subsidiarity is concerned is merely to apply its case-law on article 253 ETC (ex Article190). That is, it exercises minimum control over the statement of reasons , or the requirement to give reasons, as far as the Community legislature is concerned. The Court is satisfied if the legislature merely makes a general statement of why it considered Community action to be necessary. This stance cannot be explained by the Court’s legitimacy variable, since a procedural subsidiarity assessment clearly fits within a legal assessment. Conclusion. Concerning the material side of the principle, the Court stance seems to be clear. This stance is that, save in cases where the Community legislature has commited a manifest error, the Court will not review a Community legislative norm on grounds of subsidiarity. Therefore, the Court will generally avoid, even on grounds of the principle of subsidiarity, substituting an assessment by the Community legislature. Regarding the exceptions to that rule, it is difficult to see in which cases the Court could conclude that the Community legislature had committed a manifest error. It should be noted that the Court’s case-law on manifest error is not especially clear.44 It seems to apply a sort of rule here. It takes each case on its own merits, and analyses whether the Community measure is reasonable as regards the 44 See Case C-34/95 [1998] ECR I-4355 objectives pursued by the measure. In those exceptional cases in which it is patently clear that the measure is not reasonable compared to the objectives, then the Court will annul it. However, it is obvious that this approach is closer to proportionality than to subsidiarity. On the other hand, as far as procedural subsidiarity is concerned, the attitude of the Court is very flexible here as well. The Court is satisfied if the preamble of a measure briefly mentions the reasons why the Community legislature deemed it appropriate to act. Furthermore, the Court does not require that the Community legislature mention subsidiarity expressly. In this respect, the stance of the Court does not differ much from its stance on Article 253 ECT as far as legislative measures are concerned. In particular, the Court seems to require the Community legislature to state reasons why, from the perspective of three standards ( dimension or scale of the action, effects, and sufficiency) it considers that it is better suited to act than the Member States. However, the way in which the Court reviews the obligation to state reasons is very superficial: a mere mention of the tree criteria in the measure’s preamble seems to be sufficient. 11. The early warning system in the new Constitutional Treaty 45 Early Warning System ( EWS), featured by the Protocol on the Application of the Principles of Subsidiarity and Proportionality, annexed to the Constitutional Treaty, 46 means that EU institutions are obliged to inform National Parliaments at all stages of the legislative procedure. The establishing of an “early-warning” system regarding respect for the subsidiarity principle will enable National Parliaments to ask the Commission to review a legislative proposal if they consider that it violates the principle.47 According to the Constitutional Treaty, the Commission’s proposals for European legal acts shall be sent to the national parliaments at the same time as to the Council and the European Parliament. The national parliaments also receive the European Parliament’s drafts and amendments as well as drafts from groups of Member States and the other EU institutions. 45 Margherita Poto, Democracy and Europe: New Times, Old Dilemmas 2. Protocol on the application of the principles of subsidiarity and proportionality, in Official Journal of the European Union, C-310/207, 16 December 2004, also available on <www.eur-lex.europa.eu>. 47 http://europa.eu/scadplus/glossary/subsidiarity_en.htm 46 Each parliament then has the opportunity, within six weeks of transmission of the proposal, to submit a reasoned opinion in which the parliament explains why, in its opinion, the draft in question violates the principle of subsidiarity. The Commission, the Council and the Parliament are obliged to take the opinion into account and, if one third of the national parliaments complain that a specific EU bill violates the principle of subsidiarity, the draft must be reconsidered. The Commission may then decide to uphold its proposal, to amend it or to withdraw it. The decision must be justified. Where this relates to drafts concerning the politically sensitive area of judicial cooperation in criminal matters or police cooperation, the draft must be reconsidered if just one quarter of the national parliaments issue a reasoned opinion. The final part of this procedure gives to the Court of Justice jurisdiction to hear actions for annulment brought by any Member State for violation of the principle of subsidiarity: Article 8. The Court of justice of the European Union shall have jurisdiction in actions on grounds of infringement of the principle of subsidiarity by a European legislative act, brought in accordance with the rules laid down in Article III-365 of the Constitution of Member States, or notified by them in accordance with their national Parliament or a Chamber of it. Amongst the benefits that should derive from this mechanism, if only it were in force, some authors point out the possibility of improving compliance of EU regulation and of alleviating the ‘democratic deficit’, but noting in any case that there is one important element missing: ‘it empowers national parliaments to review EU legislation for conformity with subsidiarity but not with proportionality, its “sister principle”.48 12. The early warning system in the Reform Treaty 49 When it comes to the Early Warning System in the Reform Treaty, national parliaments will be given a greater role in any reform of the EU Treaty (new Article 33 replacing Article 48) and in responding to new applications for membership (new Article 34 replacing Article 49). National parliaments will be able to veto measures furthering judicial cooperation in civil matters (new Article 69d). 48 49 See I. Cooper, The Watchdogs of Subsidiarity, cit., 283. http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Reform_Treaty#The_European_Parliament_and_National_Parliaments Article 8c: National Parliaments shall contribute actively to the good functioning of the Union: (a) through being informed by the institutions of the Union and having draft European legislative acts forwarded to them in accordance with the Protocol on the role of national Parliaments in the European Union; (b) by seeing to it that the principle of subsidiarity is respected in accordance with the procedures provided for in the Protocol on the application of the principles of subsidiarity and proportionality; (c) by taking part, within the framework of the area of freedom, security and justice, in the evaluation mechanisms for the implementation of the Union policies in that area, in accordance with Article 64 of the Treaty on the Functioning of the European Union, and through being involved in the political monitoring of Europol and the evaluation of Eurojust's activities in accordance with Articles 69k and 69h of that Treaty; (d) by taking part in the revision procedures of the Treaties, in accordance with Article 33 of this Treaty; (e) by being notified of applications for accession to the Union, in accordance with Article 34 of this Treaty; (f) by taking part in the inter-parliamentary cooperation between national Parliaments and with the European Parliament, in accordance with the Protocol on the role of national Parliaments in the European Union. Protocol 2 provides for a greater role of national parliaments in ensuring that EU measures comply with the principle of subsidiarity. In comparison with the proposed Constitution, the Reform Treaty allows national parliaments eight rather than six weeks to study European Commission legislative proposals and decide whether to send a reasoned opinion stating why the national parliament considers it to be incompatible with subsidiarity. National parliaments may vote to have the measure reviewed. If one third (or one quarter, where the proposed EU measure concerns freedom, justice and security) of votes are in favour of a review, the Commission will have to review the measure and if it decides to maintain it, must give a reasoned opinion to the Union legislator as to why it considers the measure to be compatible with subsidiarity. 13. Subsidiarity and the Human Rights policy 50 The first essential element in building a new EU human rights policy is to establish that such a policy lies within the constitutional competence of the Community and that it would not violate important principles such as that of subsidiarity. It seems sometimes to be assumed that the application of this principle requires that responsibility for matters dealing with human rights should remain at the national level. But this is a false assumption which actually undermines the objectives of the principle. Consistent with the principle, Community-level action is warranted if the objective in question cannot be adequately achieved by Member State action alone and if the scale or effects of the proposed measures favour Community action. Clearly where the measures in question are taken by the Community within the field of Community law it makes no sense to argue that individual Member States are best placed to ensure not only that those measures do not violate human rights but that they do whatever they can to promote respect for them. Moreover, the guidelines contained in the Protocol on subsidiarity attached to the Amsterdam Treaty correctly emphasize that Community action might be necessitated by various factors, including the transnational dimensions of an issue and the existence of treaty obligations. Thus a Community human rights policy is not only consistent with the principle of subsidiarity, but is in some measure a necessity required by that principle. 14. Conclusion 51 The European principle of subsidiarity is important because it is one of the key constitutional principles that serve to set the character of the EU. As a legal principle, a justiciable constraint on the power of the Community Institutions, subsidiarity has had little obvious effect. Perhaps daunted by the complicated political assessments the principle entails,52 or, less charitably, perhaps disinclined to develop a principle that limits the centralisation of power,53 the European Court of Justice has not made use of the 50 51 http://www.jeanmonnetprogram.org/papers/99/990109.html N. W. Barber, The Limited Modesty of Subsidiarity, European Law Journal, Vol. 11, No. 3, May 2005, pp. 308–325 See generally: A. G. Toth, ‘Is Subsidiarity Justiciable?’, (1994) 19 European Law Review 268 53 See: J. Bednar, W. N. Eskridge and J. Ferejohn, ‘A Political Theory of Federalism’, in J. Ferejohn, J. N. Rakove and J. Riley, eds, Constitutional Culture and Democratic Rule (Cambridge University Press, 2001). 52 principle. The degree to which subsidiarity has indirectly affected the measures advanced by the Community is unclear. But the principle stands as a declaration of how the EU perceives itself, and as the sort of political community the authors of the Treaties intended it to be. In particular, it represents a commitment to democracy, to de-centralised power and, most importantly, opposition to nationalist ideals of state legitimacy.