Vedrørende Appiah: ”We’ve identified three kinds of disagreement about values: we can fail to share a vocabulary of evaluation; we can give the same vocabulary different interpretations; and we can give the same values different weights. Each of these problems seems more likely to arise if the discussion involves people from different societies.” (Appiah, 2006, p.66) Appiah on Cosmopolitanism “So there are two strands that intertwine in the notion of cosmopolitanism. One is the idea that we have obligations to others, obligations that stretch beyond those to whom we are related by the ties of kith and kind, or even the more formal ties of a shared citizenship. The other is that we take seriously the value not just of human life but of particular human lives, which means taking an interest in the practices and beliefs that lend them significance.” (Appiah, 2006, p.xv) But the universalism of cosmopolitanism raises a second question of comprehensiveness: how much of our lives should be regulated by universal principles? Appiah’s version of cosmopolitanism is limited in a number of significant ways: “Because there are so many human possibilities worth exploring, we neither expect nor desire that every person or every society should converge on a single mode of life. What ever our obligations are to others (or theirs to us) they often have the right to go their own way.” (Appiah, 2006, p.xv) Additionally, Appiah wants to argue that while we have universal responsibilities, there are some responsibilities that we have only to our countrymen. That is, that being a member of a country or a nation or a culture, can generate duties that are a) not generated by being a member of the human race, and b) directed only at the other members of the country, nation or culture: “…the one thought that cosmopolitans share is that no local loyalty can ever justify forgetting that each human being has responsibilities to every other. Fortunately, we need take sides neither with the nationalist who abandons all foreigners nor with the hard-core cosmopolitan who regards her friends and fellow citizens with icy impartiality. The position worth defending might be called (in both senses) a partial cosmopolitanism.” (Appiah, p.xvii) Appiah on lack of cosmopolitan empathy (nationalist only empathy?) empirically wrong, because: “Some American Christians send money to suffering fellow Christians in Southern Sudan; writers, through PEN International, campaign for the freedom of other writers, imprisoned around the world; women in Sweden work for women’s rights in South Asia; Indians in the Punjab worry about the fate of Punjabis in Canada and Britain. I care about some people in other places, people whose oppression would engage me particularly, just because I have read their philosophical writings, admired their novels, seen them play spectacular games of tennis on television. So, if we change the examples to suit the case, do you. […] the great lesson of anthropology is that when the stranger is no longer imaginary, but real and present, sharing a human social life, you may like or dislike him, you may agree or disagree; but, if it is what you both want, you can make sense of each other in the end.” (Appiah, 2006, 98) “Then, as I said at the start, we cosmopolitans believe in universal truth, too, though we are less certain that we have it all already. It is not skepticism about the very idea of truth that guides us; it is realism about how hard the truth is to find. One truth we hold to, however, is that every human being has obligations to every other. Everybody matters: that is our central idea. And it sharply limits the scope of our tolerance.” (Appiah, 2006, p.144) Appiah - From tolerance to obligations to strangers: “If cosmopolitanism is, in a slogan, universality plus difference, there is the possibility of another kind of enemy, one who rejects universality altogether. “Not everybody matters” would be their slogan. The fact is, though, that, whatever may have been the case in the past, most people who say it now don’t really believe it. Bernard Williams wrote in Ethics and the limits of Philosophy that “morality” – in the sense of norms that are universally binding – “is not an invention of philosophers. It is the outlook or, incoherently, part of the outlook of almost all of us.” […] The real challenge to cosmopolitanism isn’t the belief that they don’t matter very much. It’s easy to get agreement that we have some obligations to strangers. We can’t do terrible things to them. Perhaps, if their situation becomes completely intolerable and we can do something about it at reasonable cost, we may even have a duty to intervene. Perhaps we should stop genocide, intervene when there is mass starvation or a great natural disaster. But must we do more than this? Here’s where easy assent starts to fray.” (Appiah, 2006, p.151ff) Appiah, in arguing for his limited cosmopolitanism, objects to the universalist principle of consequentialism: “All this talk of mandarins and foreign children can make it seem that Unger’s paradox is a special problem for cosmopolitans. It is not. Forget the starving children of Africa and Asia if you can. Wherever you live in the West, there are children’s lives to be saved in your own country. […] The problem with the argument isn’t that it says we have incredible obligations to foreigners; the problem is that it claims we have incredible obligations. Whatever has gone wrong, you can’t blame it on us cosmopolitans.”(Appiah, 2006, p.159f) To explicate the alleged error, he turns to another drowning example, concerning a small child drowning in a pond and the ruination of your suit in the process of rescuing it. This is in response to Peter Singer and Peter Unger, and Appiah raises two points: first that Singer’s consequentialist principle 1 does not respond well to the drowning example, because leaving the child to drown and spending the time and Appiah sums up Singer’s arguments in the following principle, dubbing it the ”Singer principle”: ”If you can prevent something bad from happening at the cost of something less bad, you ought to do it.” (Appiah, 2006, p.160) This is a fairly standard formulation of the principle found, with small variations, in different types of consequentialist ethics. 1 money lost in saving it to help children in Africa, Asia or wherever would create better consequences. The second is that actually figuring out which potential action will lead to the best consequences is literally impossible. Both are stock objections to consequentialist ethics, but not easy to maintain when combined with some form of cosmopolitanist ethics. The first in addition seems to involve a strange confusion about consequences: if the situation literally involves a choice between saving one child or saving many, e.g. if you were on your way to the office of an NGO with a cheque, and knew (somehow) that delivering the cheque would save the lives of 10 children, but that it will (somehow) be destroyed in the rescue attempt, then wouldn’t it be reasonable to accept that rescuing the 10 children is more important than rescuing the one? It’s a strange hypothetical scenario, and an uncomfortable conclusion, but it would seem absurd to support an ethics that allowed us to kill 10 people tomorrow to save one today. In reality, it is a scenario that is unlikely to occur. Most of the time we are more likely to be obligated to do both than we are to be in a situation, in which we have to choose which of our obligations to meet, because of circumstance outside of our control. The deeper difficulties in defending both cosmopolitanism and a limited universalism become obvious when we look at the principle that Appiah suggests as an alternative to the Singer principle: “If you are the person in the best position to prevent something really awful, and it won’t cost you much to do so, do it.” (Appiah, 2006, p.160) Apart from the obvious difficulties of determination that it shares with the consequentialist principle,2 it just isn’t very obvious why either of the two significant changes are justified. Why does the fact that I am only the second-best person qualified to help alleviate my moral responsibility to do so? To stay with the drowning example, would we really accept as a legitimate excuse for not trying to help the child that “there was another guy who was closer to the water than me. He didn’t do anything, and the child drowned, but he was in a better position than I to help it, so I didn’t have any moral responsibility.” That doesn’t seem reasonable. Particularly if, as is the case with the global problems we are discussing here, the person(s) who are in a better position than I to help either can’t or won’t solve the problem. At least not solve all of it. Either because they simply do not have the resources to solve them, or because they refuse to assume moral responsibility. As for the second major change, it seems no less obvious that we can justify that the cost to myself has to be insignificant compared to the evil I am preventing. Why? Would we accept an excuse from the potential rescuer that he was on his way to an important business-meeting, and that stopping to rescue the drowned child would have cost him an enormous sum of money? It might provide some understanding of his psychological motivation for failing to rescue the child, but it could hardly excuse his negligence to do so in moral terms. How do figure out who is “the person in the best position to prevent something really awful”, how bad does something have to be to qualify as “really awful” and how much is “it won’t cost you much to do it”? It seems that the difficulties of determination may be even greater for this principle than for the Singer principle. 2 Unfortunately, Appiah is brief on the subject, and does not provide supporting arguments. Barring that, Appiah falls back on moral intuitionism: “I have no doubt at all that I should save the drowning child and ruin my suit. […] There are many arguments that I might make in defense of this view, especially to someone who was seriously convinced that he was free to let the child drown. But I am less certain of most of those arguments than I am that I should save the child.” (Appiah, 2006, p.162) Not only does Appiah fail to provide an explanation of why these changes are justified, it seems doubtful that a persuasive explanation of this type is even possible. It seems, instead, that he succumbs to a common problem for defenders of intuitionism: Because our empathy works stronger for people and events that we witness personally, intuitions tend to make smaller demands of us when dealing with strangers. But until it can be demonstrated that the lack of empathy in a given situation is a valid disqualifier of moral responsibility, this invalidates intuitionism and supports the use of moral principles, rather than the other way around. For a society of states/limited cosmopolitanism: “…the primary mechanism for ensuring these entitlements remains the nation-state. There are a few political cosmopolitans who say they want a world government. But the cosmopolitanism I am defending prizes a variety of political arrangements, provided, of course, each state grants every individual what he or she deserves. […] Accepting the nation-state means accepting that we have a special responsibility for the life and the justice of our own; but we still have to play our part in ensuring that all states respect the rights and meet the needs of their citizens. If they cannot, then all of us – through our nations, if they will do it, and in spite of them, if they won’t – share the collective obligation to change them; and if the reason they fail their citizens is that they lack resources, providing resources can be part of that collective obligation. That is an equally fundamental cosmopolitan commitment.”(Appiah, 2006, p.163f) Vs. global state/cosmopolitanism: “A global state would have at least three obvious problems. It could easily accumulate uncontrollable power, which it might use to do great harm; it would often be unresponsive to local needs; an it would almost certainly reduce the variety of institutional experimentation from which all of us can learn.”(Appiah, 2006, p.163) Limited cosmopolitanism: Singer offers four additional constraints on cosmopolitanism: 1) “Each of us should do our fair share; but we cannot be required to do more. This is a constraint, however, inchoate, that the Shallow Pond theorists do not respect. The Singer principle just doesn’t begin to capture the subtlety of our actual moral thought. […] Our ordinary moral thinking makes distinctions the principle doesn’t capture.” (Appiah, 2006, p.164) 2) “Even if we could get everyone to agree on the virtues of the plan; and even if we could determine how each of us, depending on our resources, should contribute his or her fair share, we can be pretty confident that some people would not give their fair share. That means there would still be some unmet entitlements. What is the obligation of those who have already met their basic obligation?” (Appiah, 2006, p.164f) 3) “Whatever my basic obligations are to the poor far away, they cannot be enough, I believe, to trump my concerns for my family, my friends, my country; nor can an argument that every life matters require me to be indifferent to the fact that one of those lives is mine.” (Appiah, 2006, p.165) 4) “Any plausible answer to the question of what we owe to others will have to take account of many values; no sensible story of our obligations to strangers can ignore the diversity of the things that matter in human life. […] Would you really want to live in a world in which the only thing anyone had ever cared about was saving lives?” (Appiah, 2006, p.165f) In support of this, Appiah criticizes two of the premises of consequentialist arguments: “Part of the strategy of Unger’s argument is to persuade us that not intervening to save someone because we have something else worth doing is morally equivalent to killing him in the name of those other values. We should resist the equation.” (Appiah, 2006, p.167) Why the two are not morally equivalent and we should therefore resist the equation is, unfortunately, not well-explained. It seems to rest on a combination of intuitionism and the argument of relations alleviating responsibility; that is, because we intuitively feel more morally responsible for the people close to us, and more responsible for actions we take that directly affect people than actions we take that indirectly affect them, the equation doesn’t hold. Unless we accept the principle of intuitionism this obviously does not hold. The second is a variation and combination of two previous points on the difficulty of evaluating consequences and the critique of narrow conceptions of the good: “Death isn’t the only thing that matters. What matters is decent lives. And if what you save [the dying children] for is just another month or another year or another decade of horrible suffering, have you really made the best use of your money? Indeed, have you really made the world less bad?” (Appiah, 2006, p.167) and he continues: “When you spend your dollars – or Euros or Pounds – isn’t it worth also spending a moment or two to ask whether they are being spent intelligently? However much you give, doesn’t it matter that none of it is wasted? Part of the trouble with Peter Unger’s focus on those starving children is that it blocks thought about the complexity of the problems facing the global poor. Ask the people OXFAM and UNICEF whether they think that all that matters is keeping children alive a while longer.” (Appiah, 2006, p.171f) Conclusion: ”If we accept the cosmopolitan challenge, we will tell our representatives that we want them to remember those strangers. Not because we are moved by their suffering – we may or may not be – but because we are responsive to what Adam Smith called “reason, principle, conscience, the inhabitants of the breast.” The people of the richest nations can do better. This is a demand of simple morality. But it is one that will resonate more widely if we make our civilization more cosmopolitan.” (Appiah, 2006, p.174) But the universalism of cosmopolitanism raises a second question of comprehensiveness: how much of our lives should be regulated by universal principles? Appiah’s version of cosmopolitanism is limited in a number of significant ways: “Because there are so many human possibilities worth exploring, we neither expect nor desire that every person or every society should converge on a single mode of life. What ever our obligations are to others (or theirs to us) they often have the right to go their own way.” (Appiah, 2006, p.xv)