6 Conclusion: Another encounter with the “event”? Having explored political as well as ethical dimensions of the production of “events” in the previous chapter, this chapter will look further at what an ethical encounter with the “event” might look like, and also how such an encounter can be understood in relation to the politics of producing “events”. In the first part of the chapter I will do this, first by returning to the example of “9/11” and by looking at some alternative ways of responding to questions about what has happened and what is going to happen, and second by discussing how such alternatives can be understood in relation to the politics of producing “9/11” through practices of response. In the second part of the chapter I will conclude this thesis, first by providing a summary of each chapter, then by discussing what it has achieved and what contributions it has made, and finally by pointing to different areas of future research. 6.1 The politics and ethics of encountering “events” So far in this thesis we have only seen how “9/11” is produced along more rigid lines, either as a clear-cut change in history that has introduced us to a new social and political order, or as a reproduction of certain values and traditions of U.S. foreign policy and identity politics. This (re)production emerges from the discourse on response and in relation to questions and problems of how to respond to what has happened. However, the ways in which these questions and problems are raised and dealt with in this context can be seen as both limited and exclusionary. From the disruption of everyday life and reality, including the horrific images of planes crashing into the WTC and of people jumping out of the windows, we are merely left with questions and problems of how to develop a strategy to respond with 209 even more violence. Thus, in order to find an alternative way of encountering “9/11” it also seems necessary to move away from the violence and simplicity of reducing questions of what has happened and what is going to happen to a political imaginary that is purely based on questions of war and security.1 But the question, then, is how it might be possible to do so. Confronting the outside Following one of the main points that was made in the previous chapter, in order to challenge the dominant actualization of forces in the social field it is first necessary to be exposed to, as well as to actively engage with, the space from which those forces emerge. This space is the space of the outside, where different forces combine and connect and where different lines are constantly in the process of being drawn, lacking a calculable model or formula as well as a pre-determined goal or direction. This notion of the outside can, moreover, be understood as a space that conditions the production of different “forms” in the social field, forms of content and expression, as well as the relationships that are established between those forms. To be exposed to the outside thus involves a confrontation with the lines and forces that have not yet found their way into any particular forms and are still waiting to be actualized. There are two different examples of such a confrontation that I wish to highlight here. The first is a documentary called 7 Days in September, a collaborative work that consists of images and stories of 28 individuals on the day of and week following September 11, 2001.2 The main part of this film shows how people are coming together in various ways, demonstrating a sense of unity and collective identity. However, what to me stands out the most is a scene of intense confrontation that took place in the middle of In a similar way Jenny Edkins has argued that we need “a way of responding that attempts to avoid a rapid return to previous forms of security, safety and sovereign power.” (…) “…a form of response that does not re-enter the same cycle of security and trauma.” See Edkins, “Forget Trauma? Responses to September 11”, International Relations, 16 (2), 2002, p. 254. 2 7 Days in September: A Powerful Story About 9/11, directed by Steve Rosenbaum, 2002, available on the DVD 24 Hours at Ground Zero / 7 Days in September, Castle Home Video, 2004. 1 210 Union Square on Friday, September 14. In the documentary, a witness describes this scene by saying that “it wasn’t just one argument that happened at Union Square; it was argument after argument after argument, breaking out between people who would not even talk to each other on the street”. People were confronting each other with questions and arguments, demonstrating a profound sense of disagreement. The scene begins with a man writing “THE AMERICAN FLAG PROPAGATES VIOLENCE” on the ground, followed by angry people who are shouting that this is unacceptable, while others try to argue that in America everyone has the right to express themselves. We then get to see several clips of people arguing about a whole range of issues, including the role and meaning of American values, religion, whether to respond with war and bombs, or whether not to respond at all. The discussion is fierce and people are yelling in each other’s faces. It presents a total break from previous scenes in the film, where people are coming together to mourn, hold hands, and bring food to the workers at Ground Zero. All of a sudden the peaceful atmosphere is replaced by a strong sense of antagonism. Eventually, however, as the arguments continue and more and more people are getting involved there is also a sense of confusion over why they are fighting. This confusion is illustrated by the confrontation between a man and a woman. As the man is shouting to the people around him to “shut up”, informing them that he was “there on the first two days…pulling body parts”, the woman confronts him by screaming: “So was I, on the first night”. The man then asks: “So what are we arguing about?”, “I don’t know. You came here telling everyone to shut up”, says the woman. The man waits a couple of seconds, then he replies by saying: “I don’t know; I am in fucking pain, because I have never seen heads, body parts, anything like that…I don’t know how to process this.” The scenes at Union Square express confusion as well as confrontation. And what makes the film’s presentation of these scenes so powerful is that it does not try to bring them together in order to form a unity, nor does it tell us who was right or wrong. The film lets the scenes speak for themselves, 211 highlighting their ambiguity as well as their heterogeneity. In this way, it also moves away from a process of trying to represent one single “event”. It points instead to the problems and paradoxes that subsist in the singularity of events, problems of coming to terms with questions about what has happened and what should happen next. We see of course different attempts to actualize these problems. But the most interesting aspect of the film is not the actualizations themselves but rather how the problems underlying those actualizations are revealed; problems to which there are, as Deleuze puts it, “no ultimate or original responses or solutions…only problem-questions, in the guise of a mask behind every mask and a displacement behind every place”.3 Hence, in relation to these problem-questions there is not just one way of responding but always a multiplicity of ways. By revealing the indeterminacy and ambiguity of these questions the film stays in touch with the space of the outside, where different forces are still in the process of interacting with one other without yet corresponding to any actualized forms. As such, it also expresses the potential for other actualizations yet to-come, being limited neither by an overarching structure nor a definite framework that tries to tie everything together. The second example is a short film by Alejandro Gonzales Iñárritu. The film forms a segment of a series of 11 short films that were made by 11 directors from around the world after September 11, 2001.4 Although many of these films are definitely worth watching it is Iñárritu’s contribution that to me stands out as the most remarkable one. In contrast to many of the other films, this one does not try to present a story or a narrative. In the beginning and during the main part of it we are merely faced with a black screen. In the background there are different sounds emerging: several layers of voices talking, but with no distinguishable utterances or words; a man that appears to be on TV talking about a “splendid September day”; sounds of planes 3 Gilles Deleuze, Difference and Repetition, translated by Paul Patton, (London: Continuum, 2004), p. 132. 4 “Mexico”, written and directed by Alejandro Gonzales Iñárritu, in 11’09’’01 September 11: A Film by 11 Directors, produced by Alain Brigand, A Galatée Films/Studio Canal Production, 2002. 212 crashing into buildings and people screaming; several voices speaking in different languages and on top of each other; some people trying to describe what is happening, either by referring to explosions in the towers or to bodies falling to the ground; we hear other ones calling their family members and friends from what appears to be either inside the WTC or in one of the hijacked planes, leaving messages on answering machines saying goodbye and expressing their love; we also hear a man saying “we should hit every country that harbours terrorists … I want their fathers to be hit, I want their mothers to be hit, I want their children to be hit”. In the middle of these and countless other voices and sounds there are sudden and very short video clips of people falling down from the buildings. They appear only for a second or two before the black screen returns yet again. Towards the end there are also images of the two towers collapsing, but without any sound, just complete silence. Without a narrative or a story to follow it is not clear exactly how the images should be linked to the voices and the sounds. The film presents voices and sounds on the one hand and images one the other, with no bridge between them. In this sense, the sounds and the images can be analysed as two different modes of dispersion. Whereas words are dispersed in a black void, images are dispersed through a series of irregular cuts with no point of reference that can tie them together into a homogenous movement. There is, furthermore, no clear temporal order available, which makes it difficult to determine the order of images and sounds in accordance with a linear timeline. For example, we do not hear the man talking about a “splendid September day” until first having seen images of people falling down from the buildings. Everything seems to be in flux and perpetually decentred, with no clear beginning or end, and no ultimate point of view, according to which the order of events can be determined. In this way, the film does not present itself as a whole, nor does it create the image of what has happened in terms 213 of a whole. It presents only a series of cutting and sequencing of images and sounds, which, through their irregularity disrupt the very notion of a whole.5 Lacking a whole as well as a coherent order, Iñárritu’s film can also be said to confront the outside as the limits one arrives at when trying to speak of the “unspeakable”. The voices we hear from the telephone calls, for example, express very strong emotions, yet there is a sense in which they are also facing a limit, trying to convey a message that is simply too powerful to be grasped. In the film there is no attempt to determine what these messages represent, for instance by providing a voiceover or illustrating images. Accompanied only by the black screen and irregular cuts, the limits of language and communication are maintained as such. In the chaotic mixture of images and sounds, voices are disappearing into the black screen or the void of the outside. The film leaves us with this void and does not attempt to provide a closure or sense of agreement. As such, it also opens up to a process of folding, or a process of actively making connections between images and words. In brief, it allows us to experiment with different ways of seeing and speaking about what has happened without being limited by an overall framework or a system of representation. Iñárritu’s film creates an encounter with something ambiguous and indeterminate, which no doubt is closer to the problems and paradoxes that subsist in the singularity of events than to the uniformity of an “event”. This idea of disruption can also be found in Deleuze’s analysis of modern cinema, which, he argues, is characterised by its ability to alter perceptions of life. This ability can be explained more specifically by the role of “time” in modern cinema. Rather, than being subordinated to “movements” or translated into specific temporal orders time presents itself as such, or as a virtual element that is independent of an actualized world or a coherent movement. “The direct time-image is the phantom which has always haunted the cinema, but it took modern cinema to give a body to this phantom. This image is virtual, in opposition to the actuality of the movement-image.” Gilles Deleuze, Cinema 2: The TimeImage, translated by Hugh Tomlinson and Robert Galeta, (London: Continuum, 2005), p. 40. Claire Colebrook has explained this idea of the “time-image” in the following way: “In the time-image the image is no longer perceived as an image of this or that. It is the image in its singularity, so we see imaging as such, not yet incorporated into a viewpoint, not yet ordered into a line of time. The irrational cuts do not allow images to link together to form moving things, and in so doing we are presented with imaging itself, both in its production of movement and its production of connection.” Gilles Deleuze, (London: Routledge, 2002), p. 53. 5 214 In relation to these two examples it is also possible to understand how the problems and paradoxes of events are travelling in different directions without being linked to a determinable centre. The very force behind these problems and paradoxes lies in the indeterminacy of movements rather than in determinable objects or states of affairs. Here, Deleuze’s approach to time and temporality can be seen as particularly useful because it sees the dispersion of time as an integral part of reality and experience. In order to become worthy of this reality it is therefore necessary to actively confront a plurality of temporalities and movements, without trying to link everything together in a neatly composed narrative order. Thus, it also becomes necessary to refuse the practices of locating “9/11” within such an order, as well as those that situate “9/11” within the space of a violent politics of response and that define “9/11” as a particular kind of “event”. Instead of such a notion of the “event”, it is more useful to think of “9/11” in relation to the indeterminacy of problems and questions whilst refusing to incorporate them into a particular context or framework. It is then possible to think of “9/11” as something other than just an historical “event” or a particular kind of “event”. 6 And we have to affirm another reality for thinking about the “event”, a reality that involves different encounters with time, life and becoming. Crucially, these encounters should not be seen as imaginary or simply the work of dreams. On the contrary, they have to be seen as something real, a real part of our ongoing processes of experience and becoming. Specifically, they can be used to highlight the ambiguities of becoming – ambiguities that illustrate the indeterminacy of life itself – not The life, but A life, as Deleuze puts it: Timothy Rayner has made a similar argument in relation to “9/11”, also from a Deleuzian perspective. According to Rayner: “Ordinarily, when we think of an event, we think of something that takes place within the flow of history. To have an understanding of “events” in these terms if to follow “current affairs” – the kind of everyday occurrences that are recorded by journalists, and documented in the daily news. (…) But does this do justice to the event itself? Not at all. For the most part, this viewpoint elides the event itself. For here the event is represented as an objective circumstance – something which takes place “out there in the world,” requiring us only to be present on the scene to capture the moment with our cameras, sum it up in a sound bite.” Timothy Rayner, “Time and the Event: Reflections on September 11, 2001”, Theory & Event, 5:4, 2002. 6 215 A life is everywhere, in all the moments that a given living subject goes through and that are measured by given lived objects: an immanent life carrying with it the events or singularities that are merely actualized in subjects and objects. This indefinite life does not itself have moments, close as they may be one to another, but only between-times, betweenmoments; it doesn’t just come about or come after but offers the immensity of an empty time where one sees the event yet to come and already happened, in the absolute of an immediate consciousness.7 A life is present in specific moments and in relation to given subjects and objects, but it also exceeds those moments. And in a similar way, it can be argued that A life is constantly caught up in the production of “events” through different practices of response whilst also exceeding that production. The task of philosophy in this context should be to affirm the existence of an indefinite life, to extract its virtual potential from the current state of affairs and thereby experiment once again, in favour of another becoming and another set of lines. Where or how those lines should be drawn cannot be fully known or calculated. In fact, we cannot even be sure that they will not return to a more violent form of “being”, or turning into “lines of abolition, of destruction, of others and of oneself”.8 How do you draw the line? And how will you be able to know if that line is the right one, or at least the most productive one? To submit thought to lines of flight and rupture is both risky and dangerous. It involves opening oneself up to experimental ways of thinking and becoming, without having any perceptible lines to fall back on. The process of experimentation will always and necessarily be unpredictable. It is a “dice-throw”, or an affirmation of chance as well as an affirmation of the necessity of chance.9 7 Gilles Deleuze, Pure Immanence: Essays on A Life, translated by Anne Boyman, (New York: Zone Books, 2005), p. 29. 8 Gilles Deleuze and Claire Parnet, Dialogues II, translated by Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam, (London: Continuum, 2006), p. 105. 9 Gilles Deleuze, Nietzsche and Philosophy, translated by Hugh Tomlinson, (London: Continuum, 2006), p. 24. 216 Lines of politics and ethics As was noted in the previous chapter, what signifies a favourable way of experimenting with thought and creating concepts is how well those concepts manage to speak or release the event and thereby open up to something “new, remarkable and interesting” that is replacing “the appearance of truth”. 10 Without any references to “truth”, however, there seems to be a problem of knowing which events should be released in the first place, or which events that are more important and valuable compared to others. In this respect, as Paul Patton has noted, Deleuze’s conception of philosophy “cannot offer criteria for judging the importance of events, nor rules for the attribution of events to states of affairs”.11 The importance or value of events cannot for example be determined by pointing to criteria such as truth and falsity, but neither is it possible to use any other sorts of criteria. According to Deleuze, it is simply not philosophy’s task to determine the value of events in terms of their essence or in relation to some static and independent criteria, nor is it philosophy’s task to come up with rules for how events should be actualized. Philosophy’s only task is to create concepts, which have the capacity to release the event from a state of affairs and in that way also enable other actualizations to occur. To determine in advance either the value of specific events or how they should be actualized would not only undermine their indeterminacy but also their openness to that which is always in a sense eternally yet to-come. The value of events thus lies neither in some supposed essence nor in the outcomes of actualizations. Rather, their value has to be linked to an intrinsic quality of constantly opening up to more outcomes and actualization. For this reason, it is also necessary to maintain a certain distinction between events and “events”. Whereas the latter refer to the outcomes of particular actualizations, the former relate to a continuous movement that remains independent of any such outcomes or actualizations. This does not mean, 10 Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari, What is Philosophy?, translated by Graham Burchell and Hugh Tomlinson, (London: Verso, 1994), p 111. 11 Paul Patton, “Introduction”, in Paul Patton (ed.), Deleuze: A Critical Reader, (Oxford: Blackwell, 1996), p. 14. 217 however, that the two should be seen as fully independent and separate from one another. Rather, it means that whilst it is important to examine their continual interaction it is also important to emphasise that the value of events refers to something quite different from the values that are attached to what we commonly refer to as “events” in the social field. Whereas the value of the latter has to be understood in relation to the political practices of producing the meaning of “events”, the value of the former has to be linked to something that eludes as well as challenges those practices. The value of events, in this sense, can also be defined in terms of their capacity to challenge the dominant actualization of forces in the social field; not so much by trying to go “beyond” this actualization but to actively confront it, and in doing so also reveal their violent and contingent nature. In this way, creating concepts and becoming worthy of the event cannot simply be detached from the politics of producing “events”, nor can it be separated from the political imaginaries and social frameworks that define us as subjects and set the conditions for how it is possible to act as such. Rather, creating concepts and becoming worthy of the event must always be understood in relation to the politics of actualizing forces in the social field, as well as in relation to the value- and meaning-producing practices that tell us what an “event” really is and how we should deal with it. Following this understanding of the relationship between an ethics of the event and the politics of the “event” it is also possible to analyse further the scenes of confrontation that took place at Union Square. On the one hand, these scenes illustrate an active process of challenging the emergence of a politics of response; they move away from a single conception of the “event” in favour of a much more ambiguous and indeterminate sense of what has happened and what should happen. But it can also be argued that these scenes eventually become part of a more official discourse on discourse, which instead of maintaining a sense of ambiguity and indeterminacy seeks to offer us clear lines to follow, lines that separate “good” from “evil”, “us” from “them”, etc. Through the discourse on response everyone is expected to become part of the same story, and everything must be subordinated to the 218 same inscription of values and identities. We are constantly informed of how to think about the significance of what has happened but also what has to be done in order to move forward. In this sense, the process of thinking has already been made for us. The task of doing so belongs solely to the state; it falls under the state’s authority to determine how the story should be told, how the lines should be drawn and what kind of strategy has to be developed. Here, the hope must be that there will be more attempts to raise questions and problems that manage to highlight elements of uncertainty and ambiguity, and thereby also reveal the radical contingency and inherent violence of speaking about “9/11” in the context of a politics of response. The value of Deleuze’s concept of the event, I would argue, is precisely that it enables a powerful way of thinking about the possibility of such attempts. It shows that there is something other than just social and historical “events”, a movement that happens underneath or within, which has the potential to undermine, disrupt, and produce another life and another becoming. Where such a movement will take us has to remain unknown because it is on the very basis of its indeterminacy and uncertainty that the potential for another encounter with the “event” rests. 6.2 Conclusion In order to see what has happened in the process of addressing the questions that were raised in the introduction to the thesis I will now look back at each chapter and provide a summary of them. I will then discuss what the thesis as a whole has achieved and what contributions it has made. Finally, I will point to some problems and issues that have not been fully explored but hopefully will be explored in future research. Summary In the introduction to the thesis it was pointed out that according to what appears to be a dominant way of understanding the “event” in International Relations (IR), the “event” is seen as an independently existing object or a coherent whole, which refers to something specific that has happened in a 219 particular moment in time. As such, the “event” can also be said to constitute an important reference point in time, which is used to trace out continuities as well as changes in international politics. However, whilst the “event” constitutes an important reference point in time it also tends to remain passively in the background. In this way, it is often referred to only in passing, without any serious attempts to question what it actually means to speak of “events” in the first place or how it is possible to determine the content and meaning of those “events”. There is, in this sense, an implicit assumption regarding the meaning of “events”, an assumption that can be linked to the idea of re-presenting “events”, as well as to the idea of representing a world of international relations. On the basis of this assumption, the “event” is treated as something that is more or less already given, something that belongs to an independently existing reality that is just waiting to be discovered through the use of language and concepts by a subject located in a position that is external to that reality. The aim of this thesis was to challenge the idea of representing the meaning of “events”, as well as to show how it is possible to think about the “event” as such, without merely seeing it as a passive object or a coherent whole, whose content and meaning is already given. This aim was articulated in the context of so called critical or poststructuralist approaches to IR. According to those approaches, representation has to be seen, not as a method that can provide a faithful image or copy of the world, but rather as a form of practice that is constitutive of how we speak and even think about the world. Following this understanding of representation as a practice, the question of how to understand the production of “events”, or how to understand the “event” in terms of an outcome of different forms of representational practices was raised. It was noted, furthermore, that this question does not only concern the constitutive impact of representational practices but also the lines, processes and movements that underlie or condition those practices. In order to develop a deeper understanding of this question, chapter 1 began with a further discussion concerning the problems and limits of 220 representation. By examining the respective work of Jacques Derrida, Michel Foucault and Deleuze, representation was analysed as a form of “illusion”, which lacks an ultimate ground or foundation and therefore has to be regarded as a method that relies on that which is always and necessarily absent: a signified content, a pure presence of objects, an autonomous subject, etc. The question of whether it might be possible to think “outside” this illusion was then raised. When addressing that question I turned exclusively to the philosophy of Deleuze, and specifically to Deleuze’s concept of “transcendental empiricism”. It was noted that according to this form of empiricism it is possible to refuse the subject/object dualism of representation and instead think of knowledge and experience in relation to a “plane of immanence” or a “transcendental field” of singularities, in which there is neither a prior distinction between the internal and the external, nor between the subject and the outside world. There is only a pure flow of experience, which is active and creative rather than reactive and representational. The main objective following this idea of experience is not to identify and represent resemblances and similarities between separate cases, nor is it to connect experience with the identity of someone who experiences. Thus, it is crucial that empiricism never begins with some abstract unity, such as the One, the Whole, or the Subject, which then is given the task of explaining. Instead of letting the abstract explain, Deleuze argues, it is the abstract, or the One, the Whole, the Subject, that itself has to be explained. For this reason it is also important not to treat the “abstract” as some kind of origin but rather as an effect. It is an effect that emerges from the plane of immanence and the transcendental field of singularities, which constitute the flow of life and experience. Against the backdrop of this understanding of empiricism, I returned to the problem of thinking about the “event”, suggesting that the “event” too can be thought of in terms of an abstract unity or a whole. Consequently, instead of trying to represent the meaning of the “event” in terms of a unity or a whole the important task should be to examine the ways in which the “event” is produced. So, rather than beginning with an abstract notion of the “event” and then looking at 221 what it refers to or represents, it is necessary to begin by looking at how the “event” itself is produced, and specifically to examine the processes, lines and movements that condition the “event” and make it possible for it to emerge in the first place. In order to articulate such a starting point for thinking about the “event” I turned to Deleuze’s own concept of the event in chapter 2. According to Deleuze, the event can be referred to as something that has always already happened and is eternally yet to come. It is a movement that follows the incorporeal line of Aion and travels in the directions of both past and future without being linked to a dominant present or the being of the subject. As such, the event can also be described as a singularity, or as a preindividual and impersonal instant, which is independent of any personalised form of being. However, in addition to this understanding of the event there is also what Deleuze refers to as the “actual” side of the “double structure” of the event. This side of the event can be understood more precisely as the outcome of “actualization”, which refers to the process of actualizing and translating the event as a singularity into a state of affairs or what is. Following this process, the incorporeal lines of Aion are replaced by the regularizing present of Chronos, which measures the movements of bodies and envelops past and future into a homogenous movement that always goes from the past to the future. In relation to these two sides of the “double structure” of the event it was suggested that the notion of the “event” as an abstract unity or a whole can be analysed in terms of the “actual”, or as an outcome of the process of actualization. The “event”, in this sense, can be referred to as “the moment in which the event is embodied in a state of affairs, an individual, or a person, the moment we designate by saying ‘here, the moment has come’”. 12 As such, it follows the process of moving away from the singularity of events and inscribing an actualized state of affairs, thereby resolving the paradoxes and problems that are expressed by those events. What we have in this sense 12 Gilles Deleuze, The Logic of Sense, translated by Mark Lester, edited by Constantin V. Boundas, (London: Continuum, 2004), p. 172. 222 is a notion of the “event”, which is located in a particular moment in time, in relation to a well established subject and against a particular background or context. However, it was also pointed out that the “event” should not be understood as a final end or product, which exists independently of the processes from which it is produced. Rather, the production of “events” has to be grasped as an ongoing and continuous process of becoming, which always remains open to change and transformation. This point was made specifically by drawing upon Deleuze’s concept of “counter-actualization”, which refers to a process whereby the singularity of events is abstracted from an actualized state of affairs. According to Deleuze, actualization and counter-actualization should never be grasped independently of one another, nor should they be linked to some final point of completion. Rather, they should always be understood in relation to one another, as two different processes that constantly interact with one another. For that reason it also becomes increasingly difficult to think of the “event” as an independently existing object or a coherent whole. There is always a process that has the potential to disrupt such a notion of the “event”, a process of counter-actualizing the “event”, which brings it back to something much more uncertain and indeterminate. This point was further developed by discussing the process of “formalizing” the content and meaning of “events” through the use of language and concepts. Drawing upon Deleuze and Guattari’s ideas about the role of language in the social field, and specifically what they refer to as the interaction between form of “content” and form of “expression”, it was noted that the “event” can be understood as a form of content, which is intervened in, refigured and reterritorialized through different forms of expression. And as something that is constantly exposed to a process of reconfiguration and reterritorialization, the “event” thus belongs to an ongoing and continuous process of becoming, which despite different attempts to formalize it, continues to change and transform in various ways. Having developed this understanding of the production of “events”, the question of how it might be possible to put the theory to work and thereby 223 explore the actual relevance of it was raised. To address this question, chapters 3 and 4 examined the production of “9/11” as an “event”. Whereas the main purpose of chapter 3 was to examine the two different sides of the “double structure” of the event as well as the relationship between them, the aim of chapter 4 was to examine how that relationship becomes formalized and translated into a single conception of the “event”. In chapter 3 I looked at newspaper- and TV-material, including eyewitness accounts and newspaper commentaries. In this material it was possible to map the emergence of two different processes. The first related to the immediacy of events, illustrated by people jumping, planes hitting the WTC and buildings collapsing, but also by a sense of disruption and dislocation of life and reality – an instantaneous and incorporeal transformation. Expressing different kinds of problems and paradoxes whilst at the same time lacking any straightforward answers, these examples highlighted the agonizing aspect of events. As such, they pointed to the indeterminacy and uncertainty of events, always going in different directions without a unifying point of view or a dominant present. The second process studied in chapter 3 related to different attempts to actualize the indeterminacy and uncertainty of events into a state of affairs or what is. Such attempts could for example be found in practices of inscribing specific points in time, according to which the uncertainty of movements was translated into the certainty of moments. But they could also be found in practices of imposing particular understandings of everyday life and reality and in that way resolve some of the paradoxes and problems created by the sense of disruption and dislocation. Although this latter process implied a clear movement away from the singularity of events it was pointed out that the two processes must be seen as co-existing and mutually implicated rather than simply excluding one another. Consequently, despite different attempts to replace one with the other it was argued that they continue to interact with one another. The relationship between the singularity of events and the actualization of events should thus not be seen as finalised or complete. As they continue to interact with one another, the questions of how “we” should 224 interpret and understand what has really happened and what kind of value “we” should attach to it always in a sense remain open. In response to this openness, chapter 4 looked at different attempts to formalize the content and meaning of what had happened. It did so by examining policy documents and speeches by President George W. Bush and Secretary of Defense Donald Rumsfeld, focusing in particular on how the question of “response” was addressed in those documents and speeches. The point of doing so was to see how response could be analysed as a practice of formalizing the content and meaning of what had happened and thereby also of producing ideas about “9/11” as an “event”. In this context it was possible to map the emergence of two main forms of response. Whereas the first form consisted of attempts to respond to what had happened in the past, or to what “really” happened on September 11, 2001, the second form was concerned with responding to what might happen in the future. And whereas the former implied a practice of reproducing familiar themes of U.S. national identity and a traditional geopolitical imaginary of sovereign nation-states, the latter implied a more novel attempt to create a way of thinking about a social and political order that could deal with elements of the new and the unfamiliar. In relation to these two forms of response it was possible to see how “9/11” emerged as a central reference point in time, which was used to legitimise certain ideas about how to respond to the past as well as to the future. Thus, the content of “9/11” was filled with elements of the past and the future, the familiar and the unfamiliar, the old and the new, certainty and uncertainty, safety and vulnerability, etc. In this way, it was pointed out that it becomes extremely difficult to think of “9/11” only in terms of change or continuity, as well as to determine the actual content and meaning of “9/11” as such – as an externally existing object or a coherent whole that exists in a fixed point in time. A more useful approach is to think of “9/11” as a mixture or a “multiplicity”, in which different lines, processes and movements are at work as well as a co-existence of various becomings. “9/11”, in this sense, belongs to an ongoing and continuous process of becoming, which always remains open to change and transformation. 225 Following chapters 3 and 4 there was one particular issue that had to be addressed. This issue related to the politics of producing “events” and specifically to the question of how to understand the forces underpinning that production. In order to address this question, chapter 5 returned to a closer examination of Deleuze’s philosophy, focusing in particular on the concepts of “force”, “folding”, and “micropolitics”. In relation to these concepts it was argued that politics has to be understood, not only by taking into account what happens in the realm of the actual, but also what happens in the space of the virtual. It is in relation to this latter space that the real forces of politics can be grasped, where different forces combine and connect, and where the actualization of particular “forms” in the social field is made possible. Hence, the forces of politics do not belong to already established patterns and systems but rather to elements of the unknown and the unfamiliar, which are always in the process of taking shape. It is through an encounter with those elements that politics proceeds, not by encountering already established forms. This happens, moreover, not by relying on a calculable model or formula but rather through an active process of experimentation. For example, the production of “events” proceeds by experimenting with different ways of seeing and speaking, without ever being able to calculate or predict what the process of doing so might involve or lead to. This incalculability and unpredictability can also be explained by the immediacy of the singularity of events. According to that immediacy, nothing is ever static or given; everything is constantly in flux, thus making every attempt to deal with questions about what has happened and what is going to happen in a coherent manner increasingly difficult and unpredictable. When examining Deleuze’s discussion of politics it was also noted that there is a closely related normative commitment in Deleuze’s philosophy. This commitment is expressed most explicitly in Deleuze’s, and Deleuze and Guattari’s, definition of what philosophy is and what role it should play. According to their definition, philosophy has a close affiliation with the experimentation of thought and experience, as well as with the creation of new concepts. These concepts should be created, not in order to represent or 226 reflect upon an independent reality but rather to speak or release the event and in so doing actively produce a life and a becoming that eludes the static and formalized states of affairs. The aim of philosophy, in this sense, should always be to become worthy of the event. However, as was also noticed, this aim implies a risk as well as a potential, both of which can be linked to an unpredictable process of constantly drawing new lines without having any perceptible lines to fall back on. There is only a pure line of becoming that is forever in the process of being drawn and that cannot simply be reduced to either of the two sides of the “double structure” of the event, the virtual or the actual. As such, this line can also be linked to the space of the “outside”, which expresses the limits one arrives at when trying to speak of the unspeakable. In order to deal with this space, as well as with the pure line of becoming, it is necessary to invent different ways of folding. Doing so has the potential to open up to something new, interesting and remarkable, but it can also lead to an inevitable disintegration. Since the process of folding has to be invented and since there are no pre-established lines to fall back we cannot know for certain what the outcome of this process will be. It is a process that both relies on chance and affirms the necessity of chance. In order to explore what the implications of this process might be for thinking about the production of “events”, the present chapter returned to “9/11” and looked at some alternative ways of encountering “9/11” as an “event”. It was argued that what distinguishes these encounters is precisely their capacity to create different ways of thinking about what has happened, not by providing specific answers, but rather by expressing the paradoxes and problems that exist in the singularity of events. And instead of trying to link those paradoxes and problems to one single conception of the “event”, the paradoxes and problems are retained as such. The point was also made that these kinds of alternative encounters do not just happen independently or by themselves but always in relation to the politics of producing “events”. And this is precisely what makes Deleuze’s concept of the event so important and valuable; it offers a way to actively challenge the dominant actualization of forces in the social field by pointing to the existence of 227 another life and another becoming, the potential of which always remains open despite different attempts to close it down. Adding to reality Drawing upon the philosophy of Gilles Deleuze as well as various sources and empirical material relating to what happened in New York City and Washington D.C. on September 11, 2001, I have argued that the “event” can be understood in terms of an ongoing and continuous becoming, which always remains open to a process of change and transformation. To think about the “event” along these lines can in many ways be said to differ from the dominant understanding of the role and meaning of “events” in international politics. According to the latter, “events” are often assumed to follow one another within a particular narrative order and a linear timeline that always goes from the past to the future. In relation to that order, the “event” is given a clear beginning and a final end, and its meaning is determined by its presupposed static location in time – as an independently existing object or a coherent whole located between the past and the future. In this thesis I have developed a completely different way of thinking about “events”, one that emphasises various aspects of the production of “events” rather than the being of “events”. Crucially, this emphasis does not imply that the “event” should be seen as something that is constructed as an object or a whole. It rather implies seeing the “event” as something that is made up of a mixture of lines, processes and movements. The “event”, in this sense, does not exist as a constructed “thing”, the role and meaning of which can be reduced to the level of language and representation. It also has to be grasped in relation to that which exceeds that level, for example by pointing to thought, sense and experience as elements that cannot be represented but still play an important role in the production of social phenomena and political “events”. By taking these elements into account the thesis has shown how it is possible to think about the production of “events” in terms of a mixture of different lines, processes and movements, which interact with one another without following a particular narrative order and without 228 adding up to a coherent “event”. The relationship between those elements and the notion of an “event” is therefore not in any way given or causally determinate. It follows a non-causal order, or a chaotic mixture of lines, processes and movements, where the path always remains open to different kinds of unpredictable experimentations, the outcome of which is uncertain and indeterminate. In this way, the “event” cannot simply be located in a specific moment in time and between the past and the future; nor can it be said to have a clear beginning and a final end. The “event” is a multiplicity that moves in different directions depending on the forces that underpin it. Thinking about the production of “events” along these lines is, of course, to a large extent inspired by Deleuze’s own concept of the event, and specifically by the connections he makes between the event, singularity and the virtual. In Deleuze’s philosophy, all of these concepts point to an understanding of reality that eludes the order of representation, as well as the corporeal presence of bodies. They point instead to the reality of the unrepresentable and the incorporeal. In this sense, it can also be argued that Deleuze’s philosophy differs somewhat from many other “poststructuralist” approaches. What distinguishes Deleuze’s philosophy is that whilst being highly critical of different attempts to inscribe particular notions of reality, it still seeks to retain a notion of reality. Moreover, the way in which Deleuze does this is not by abandoning a systematic conception of philosophy, or by avoiding the metaphysics of thought and experience. Rather, it is precisely by creating a system that takes the metaphysics of thought and experience as its main starting point that Deleuze seeks to retain a notion of reality. In this way, as Patton has argued: “Unlike many of his contemporaries, Deleuze remained committed to the classical idea of philosophy as a system. The novelty of Deleuzian thought does not lie in its refusal of any systematic character but in the nature of the system envisaged.”13 And in a similar way, when discussing Deleuze’s approach to time and temporality, Kimberly Hutchings has argued that “Deleuze’s approach still permits a lateral kind of theorising in which multiple, parallel and interacting presents may be 13 Patton, “Introduction”, pp. 1-2. 229 understood in relation to one another, in this sense it is systematic as well as pluralist”.14 The novelty of Deleuze’s system can thus be explained by its refusal of a hierarchical structure, according to which different presents are claimed to follow one another. But it can also be explained by its refusal to determine the value of events in relation to a transcendent normative horizon. Lacking a hierarchical structure, as well as any aspiration to transcend the meaning of thought and experience, the only guiding principle of the system Deleuze envisages is that of multiplicity itself. According to that principle, then, the aim of philosophy is to construct a systematic understanding of life, in which difference, change, and the co-existence of becomings are prioritised over the static being and hierarchical structure of things. Thus, it is also possible to conceive of the system as nothing but a multiplicity – made up of differential elements of thought and experience, which are constantly transformed in various ways without being incorporated into a determinate structure and without adding up to a coherent whole. When emphasising the importance of multiplicity it is also necessary to consider the process of writing as an integral part of it. Consequently, this process should not be seen as a calculable or static procedure whose ultimate aim is to represent an independent reality. Rather, the process of writing should be treated as an active and creative process, which hopefully can contribute to a way of thinking that also adds something new to reality. This is also what I have tried to do in this thesis when writing about the production of “events”. Hence, my aim in so doing so has not been to provide a faithful representation of what this production involves, nor has it been to mirror an independent reality. Rather, what I have tried to do is to create a way of thinking about this production, and in that way also add something new to reality. And in a similar way, instead of trying to reflect upon the objective nature of “9/11” as an “event” I have tried to create a way of thinking about “9/11”, mainly by showing how it can be conceived of as an open-ended multiplicity that is constituted by intersecting lines, processes Kimberly Hutchings, “Happy Anniversary! Time and Critique in International Relations Theory”, Review of International Studies, 33, Special Issue: Critical International Relations Theory after 25 Years, 2007, p. 88. 14 230 and movements. Finally, rather than treating Deleuze’s philosophy as a complete and unitary whole I have experimented with various concepts and ideas in Deleuze’s work. Thus, instead of just letting it remain the “same” I have shown how it is possible to take Deleuze’s philosophy of the event further by adding the concept of the “event” and in that way explore how the former is relevant for thinking about the production of the latter. I have also shown how it is possible to experiment with other concepts in Deleuze’s work, such as the “fold” and the “outside” in order to think about the politics as well as the ethics of encountering “events”. Future connections The connections that I have made in this thesis when developing a way of thinking about the production of “events” have mainly been between various concepts and ideas in Deleuze’s philosophy, media sources, political speeches and policy documents. These connections, however, do not form an exhaustive list of what could be done in order to think about the production of “events”. To begin with, there are various aspects of Deleuze’s work that have not been explored in this thesis, for example his work on art, literature and cinema.15 Even though I would argue that many of the key ideas of this latter work can be found in his earlier books (most notably in Difference and Repetition and The Logic of Sense), there are definitely elements of it that are worth exploring and that might also contribute to a slightly different way of thinking about the production of “events”. Moreover, these elements could be used in order to examine different kinds of sources and empirical material, including novels, art practices and films. In this way, it would also be possible to broaden the study of the production of “9/11” as an “event”, and 15 In relation to art Deleuze’s main contribution is Francis Bacon: The Logic of Sensation, translated by Daniel W. Smith, (London: Continuum, 2003). Regarding literature there are two main books, one on Marcel Proust and one on Franz Kafka (co-written with Guattari), see Gilles Deleuze, Proust and Signs, translated by Richard Howard, (London: Athlone, 2000), and Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari, Kafka: Toward a Minor Literature, translated by Dana Polan, (London: University of Minnesota Press, 1986). Regarding Deleuze’s work on cinema, I have already referred to his concept of the “time-image” and its connection to “modern cinema” earlier in this chapter. In addition to this, Deleuze has also written about the role of “movement” and “early” cinema in Cinema 1: The Movement-Image, translated by Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam, (London: Continuum, 2005). 231 to include a lot more material than this thesis has managed to do. Focusing solely on newspapers, speeches and policy documents means that other sources have been left out, sources that might give a different understanding of what happens in the production of “9/11” as an “event”. It would thus be interesting to continue examining this production by making another series of connections, between various concepts and ideas in Deleuze’s philosophy and different kinds of sources and empirical material. When developing a way of thinking about the production of “events” it would of course also be possible to study the production of different kinds of “events”. By using “9/11” as the guiding example, this thesis has mainly focused on questions surrounding the production of big or global “events”, questions that can be linked in particular to the temporal dimension of those “events”: how they constitute central reference points in time and how those reference points seem to have a crucial impact on how we think about international politics more generally. If the aim was to explore further this role of “events” it would definitely be interesting to study other big or global “events”, including catastrophes and environmental disasters such as the 2004 Boxing Day Tsunami and the 2005 Hurricane Katrina. But it would also be interesting to study the production of other “events”, such as for example elections, international conferences, EU and UN summits, the Olympic Games, etc. In discourses on international politics there seem to be few, if any, areas that do not highlight different kinds of “events” as important elements of what really happens within those areas. The very content of the international politics, in this sense, consists to a large extent of different kinds of “events”. The problem, however, is that they often tend to remain unchallenged and uncontested. It is therefore important to continue questioning exactly what is meant by these “events”, how they emerge in the first place, what it is that conditions them, and how their production can be analysed in relation to different kinds of practices and force relations. In conclusion, then, there are always more connections to be made. The ones I have made in this thesis are only a small sample of what could be done. The important task is to continue on an explorative path to politics and 232 philosophy, to make more connections and more constellations of various concepts in order to create new ways of thinking about different issues. In this way, it is possible to challenge the concepts and frameworks that have already been given to us and to experiment one more time, for another purpose and in relation to another thought, which once again will have the potential to alter our thinking. 233