Back to Realism Applied to Home Page Australian Book Review, November 1979 Negative_rev.doc Importance of negative results Sutcliffe J. P. (ed.) Conceptual Analysis and Method in Psychology Essays in Honour of W.M . O'Neil Sydney University Press, 216 p., $10.00 ISBN 0 424 00055 5 By Jim Mackenzie This collection of essays by his former students marks the retirement of Bill O'Neil, who has been Professor of Psychology m the University of Sydney since 1945, though in the last twelve years or so he has been occupied more with university administration than with leaching or psychology, as he tells us in a brief and frank autobiographical essay included in the book. The authors of the other papers are his former students, now holding distinguished academic positions in Australia, Canada, Britain and America. The lest of a teacher is the achievement of the pupils, and on conventional criteria O’Neil’s pupils have done well A more searching test, however, is not in terms of their positions, but rather in terms of their work, and it is samples of this which we are invited to peruse. J. R. Maze gives a rather garbled presentation of the eroticist theory of morality, known to its opponents as the "Groper" theory- that moral judgements such as ‘Abortion ought (or ought not) to be legalised’ arc to be understood not as malting statements but as expressing internal stales such as ‘Legal abortions prr (or, grr)’ He concludes with the remarkable statement that moral beliefs are ‘a mental construction in much the same sense that a delusion is a mental construction’ — or perhaps, one might interject, in the same sense as non-Euclidean geometries are mental constructions — but that ‘Moralism (the holding of moral beliefs and passing of moral judgements) is of course, extremely widespread, and characterises enormous numbers of persons who would not be described as mentally disturbed by any orthodox set of psychiatric criteria’ I can find no hint that this was intended as a joke In the next paper Terence McMullen puts to one side most ‘psi’ phenomena (such as telepathy), and endeavours to Show that two particular kinds, precog nition and retrocognition, are logically incoherent. His discussion of what he calls the philosophy of time is rather brief, which is just as well because it seems to rule out Einstein's theory of relativity as unstable. He also denies, without explaining his grounds, the apparent disanalogy between precognition (knowledge of the future) and retrocognition (of the past). Certainly some form of retrocognition seems possible, for since sunlight takes time to reach us the sun we see directly is the sun of several minutes ago. Thus though it is unlikely that visual information from (say) ancient Babylon may still be around to be picked up, it is not self-contradictory. Jean Jones discusses personal identity, a hoary favorite among philosophers though she refers to no philosophical writings more recent than 1949. She rejects what she calls c-identity, meaning absolutely unaltered in any respect, as a criterion for ‘being the same person’ (as contrasted with ‘He’s quite a different person now’). I cannot believe that c-identity is anything more than a straw man. Roderick McDonald argues that a statistical method advocated (jointly and separately in different writings) by himself and his mate S. A. Mulaik is not subject to certain objections raised by those who prefer a rival method. He seems more concerned with the danger of saying that something is there when it isn't than with the danger of saying that something isn't there when it is. Not having followed the debate of which it is a part, 1 didn't find his paper easy reading, but his conclusion, in which he argues that stability from one sample to another is the crucial factor for judging between the two methods seems to me correct. Many of O'Neil's students are interested in vision. John Ross reports some rather unsurprising experiments designed to decide between two accounts of how it is that we can see movies. Barbara Gillam gives a fascinating analysis of the illusion of the double-headed and double-tailed arrows, which is marred by the omission of two of the diagrams referred to in the text (6.6c and d). Max Coltheart addresses the important, question of what goes on when we read. His approach of concentrating on single words ignores the facts that reading requires sentences — lots of illiterate Kids can identify single words from advertising slogans — and that proofreading (spotting typographical errors in a text) is difficult. He describes experiments in which people have to identify a row of letters as being or not being a word, and provides three arguments that the process involved cannot be wholly phonological. One — that English contains ideographs like the numerals and pound — doesn't follow, for these signs could be treated as representing sounds (as in 'Car 4 sale’), and anyway isn't relevant since his experiment did not include any. The second, that we can distinguish meet, meat and mete, isn't relevant either, since his subjects didn't need to distinguish them. They could have answered by finding (a) is it pronounceable' (b) is it misspelt? His third argument, that English spelling is irregular so that a given letter combination can b§ pronounced several ways, ignores the possibility that a phonological strategy which tries several ways of making the combination pronounceable might work. This is not to say that his conclusions are false, but only that he fails to prove them. M. J. Meggitt, who has turned from psychology to anthropology, reports on relationships between the myths and the family structures of some people in Papua New Guinea, eschewing the extremes of Freud or Levi-Strauss. He has a tendency to alliteration — the 'perambulating punitive penis' and the 'vagrant voracious vulva' take central roles. Bob Lockhart argues for what he calls ecological validity, which he explains and distinguishes clearly from social relevance, in the investigation of memory. Peter Wenderoth and Cyril Latimer argue against the reduction of the psychology of perception to physiology. They erroneously claim that, as a matter of logic, no term can appear in the conclusion which did not appear in the premises, and neglect completely the voluminous literature on reduction, theory-change and meaningchange by students of science published since their authority Nagel (1961). Ray Over argues persuasively that investigators' preconceptions about vision have impoverished their experimental research. His argument links up with the independent remarks of Lockhart on ecological validity. Alison Turtle contributes a scholarly Australian Book Review, November 1979 essay on the origins of the functionalist theory of mind, and its relevance is not in doubt for she contradicts the account given in recent literature. One hopes that she has nipped an illfounded myth in the bud. Ali Landauer provides another paper on perception, with interesting historical resonances, but his statement of his conclusion is appallingly banal. R. A. Champion points out some o! the ambiguities and different patterns of use of technical terms such as 'backward conditioning' between clinical and experimental psychologists. This sort of confusion also bedevils the physical sciences, and it is helpful to have the dangerous cases explained, but Champion wanders off this important topic on to more general criticisms of the experimental methods used in behaviour therapy. Peter Sheehan discusses various attempts to place experimentation on a collaborative footing instead of the impersonal, authoritarian one traditional in psychology, though inconclusively. The last paper, by the editor, Sutcliffe, deals with the concept of progress. He begins pedantically, brightens up to resuscitate Turing's Imitation Game (to what extent can a machine imitate a person0), but seems not to have digested the arguments of Kuhn (whom he cites) about the theory dependence of problems. His prose has a tendency to degenerate into mind-paralysing sequences of questions. The paper I have not yet mentioned is by J. Furedy on the importance of negative results. Journal editors and referees, he claims, reject or advise 'de-emphasis' of papers which report failure to find anything (even when there is adequate evidence of sensitivity of the procedure to the sought effect), or which report results inconsistent with those obtained by others Furedy argues with cogency and wit for the need to change this absurd and antiscientific policy. His paper is informed by a considerable understanding of the philosophy of science and recent work in that field This is a splendid and timely paper, and should be required reading for anyone advising graduate students in psychology. I have dealt with the papers in such detail because they are such a mixed bag. Some are decidedly disappointing. But overall, Bill O'Neil has reason to be proud of his students. Jim Mackenzie teaches Wollongong University. philosophy at