Notes on Utilitarianism 1. Consequentialism refers to a variety of ethical theories that hold that rightness and wrongness is not an inherent feature of actions – rather, it is a function of the consequences of actions. Loosely, actions that have good consequences are right – actions that have bad consequences are wrong. As a result, on consequentialist theories we can’t tell what is right until we first decide what is good, because for the consequentialist rightness (and wrongness) is a function of the goodness (and badness) that actions cause. As Rawls puts it, for the consequentialist goodness is prior to rightness. 2. Utilitarianism is a type of consequentialist view, differing from other consequentialist views chiefly in how it defines goodness, or, in what amounts to the same thing, in how it identifies which consequences matter. The consequences that are morally relevant to the utilitarian are those that relate to happiness. Whose happiness? The happiness of any and all beings affected by the action – for this reason Boatright describes utilitarianism as universalistic. 3. But what is happiness, according to utilitarianism? The two great Classical Utilitarians, Bentham and Mill, think happiness is solely a function of pleasure and the absence of pain. That makes their view hedonistic. According to them, a happy life would be one with great and many pleasures and few pains. They disagreed, though, about the value of particular pleasures. For Bentham, all that matters is a pleasure’s quantity (it’s intensity, duration, etc.) Take two pleasures, say, the pleasure of eating potato chips and the pleasure of figuring out a subtle and difficult math problem. (Even if you don’t generally like math, figuring out a problem can still be pleasurable!) For Bentham, so long as these two pleasures are felt with equal intensity, last equally long etc., they’re equally valuable. Hence his saying that other things being equal, "pushpin is as good as poetry." ('Pushpin' is a children's game, analogous to tic-tac-toe.) But Mill disagreed. He thought pleasures also differed in terms of quality – some are worth more because of the kind of pleasures that they are. Solving a difficult math problem gives a “higher” and more valuable pleasure than eating chips, even when the pleasures are equally intense, last equally long, etc. Hence his saying that it’s better to be Socrates dissatisfied than a pig satisfied – because the few “higher” pleasures that a dissatisfied Socrates enjoys are much more valuable than the many “lower” the pig has. It’s an interesting philosophical issue as to who’s right here about pleasure, but not something we’ll need to be particularly worried about. Most contemporary philosophers and economists who defend Utilitarianism abstract from this dispute about pleasures altogether, and simply write about what satisfies preferences, regardless of the object of people's preferences. 4. The Principle of Utility is this: An action is right if and only if it produces more happiness (more pleasure and less pain) for all concerned than any alternative action. In addition to being consequentialist, universalistic, and hedonistic, the principle of utility is also a maximizing principle. This means that in order to know an action is right it’s not enough just to know it produces much pleasure in many people – we have to also know that it produces more pleasure and less pain overall than any alternative action would have produced. Alternatively, to know an action is wrong, we need to know more than the fact that it produces much pain in many people, since maybe any action in that situation would have produced much pain. (Think of President Truman’s decision to either drop the atomic bomb on Japan or let the war drag on – either way, many people die.) We would need to know that an alternative action would have produced less pain and/or more pleasure. Further, despite the slogan, “the greatest good for the greatest number,” it doesn’t follow that an action is right just because it positively affects more people than the alternatives. We also need to know how much it affects them – what matters is not the number of people but the overall amount of pleasure and minimization of pain produced. 5. Two complications: First, because a person thinks she is doing something that maximizes happiness (and minimizes unhappiness), it doesn’t follow that the person does the right thing. What matters is the reality, not someone’s perceptions or motivations. If you’re trying to help, but still doing something sure to lead to disaster, it’s still wrong, according to the Utilitarian. Second, there’s a debate among Utilitarians about whether it’s the actual consequences or the reasonably expected consequences that count. On the actual consequences view, an action could turn out to be wrong because it had some disastrous but totally unexpected consequences that the agent couldn’t have foreseen, or for that matter, right because of some wonderful and yet entirely accidental consequences. This makes the theory less plausible, generally, and for this reason we’ll stipulate that it’s the reasonably expected consequences that count. (Reasonably expected consequences are still different from what the agent may actually expect.) But how then do we take merely possible consequences into account? Multiply the possible consequences by their likelihood. (Something with a 10% chance of producing 100 units of pleasure, for example, goes on the scale as .1 x 100, that is, 10.) 6. So far, we’ve been talking about what’s called Act Utilitarianism, because we’ve been speaking as though what makes the action right or wrong is the (reasonably expected) consequences of that action, and no other. But there are good reasons for Utilitarians not to be Act Utilitarians. For one thing, it seems quite possible for actions to be wrong and yet still have maximally beneficial consequences, and vice versa. One way around this is to shift to what’s known as Rule Utilitarianism. For Rule Utilitarians, particular actions are right or wrong depending on their relationship to justified moral rules. Thus, if an action is bribery, and there’s a justified rule that says, “Never bribe,” the action would be wrong even if the consequences of this particular action were better than any alternative. What makes the view Utilitarian is the idea that rules are justified if the general observance of that rule has better overall consequences (with respect to happiness) than any other rule. This view is still consequentialist, maximizing and universalistic, but only indirectly so, since these are aspects of evaluating particular rules, not individual actions. Another way to express the contrast with Act Utilitarianism is to say the Rule Utilitarian is concerned not with particular actions, but with action types.